THOMAS AND THE UNIVERSE STANLEY L. JAKI Seton Ha,ll Uni1;ersity South Orange, New Jersey F EW SUBJECTS MAY appear so discouragingly vast as Thoma's and the Universe. Few have pmduced a work vaster, let alone deeper, than did Thomrus. As to the universe, its Viastnessas well as its depth ·are succinctly stated in Newman's Idea of a University:" There is but one thought greater than that of the universe, and that is the thought of its Maker." 1 There is in aiddition the vastness of the history of the notion of the universe and the .large number of Thomas' interpreters, not all of them immune to prolixity. At any rate, Thomas' best known interpreters offer, as will be seen shortly, at most a brief chapter or a subsection of it on Thomas and the universe with very little on the universe as such. A possible reason for this is that in rthe vast writings of Thomas there is no chapter or question on the universe as suoh. By as such I mean the very core of the notion of the universe, or its 'being the totality of consistently interacting things and their very unity. Thomas, as will 1be seen later, is not iat all silent on this point. Brut if one tries to focate his relevant dicta hy looking through the detailed fables of contents in, say, the Para:na edition of his works, one is not given much guidance. No different is the cruse when one looks through the subject indices. Entries under "universum" are almost as scarce as hen"s teeth. As to entries under " mundus," they .are of no great help on the worild or universe as such. Authors who let their publishers undertake the compilation of the subject index of their books will p11obably agree that the 1J. H. Newman, The Idea, of a, University Co., 1888), p. 462. 545 (London: Longmans, Green & 546 STANLEY L. J AKI result is very unsatisfactory in most cases. Few reaiders can really sense the nuances of an author's real concerns, especially if, like Thomas, he has many important concerns. There is in addition the effect of the climate of thought. Under ordinary circumstances one does not pay attention to the air one hreathes in, and much less writes about it extensively, though one still can make incisive though brief references to it. In the intellectual atmosphere surrounding Thomas, the reality o[ the universe :as such 'Was taken to he a most obvious fact. There were debates whether the universe was eternal or temporal; whether it was uncreated or created out of nothing or out of some prime matter; whether any creature could he given a creative power; whether the unive11se was governed providentially; whether it was properly ordered; whether anything occurred in it :by chance or thy accident; whether it was absolutely or relatively the best; whether it could have been otherwise; whether it was necessarily spherical; whether it could move or not-but nobody .felt the need to discuss ·at length whether there was a universe, .that is, a totality of consistently intemcting things 1aH of which verged toward unity. Democritus' claim aibout a large number of universes was, of course, known, but just a;s well known was the illogicality of it. Either those universes interructed with one ,another, and in that oase they clearly formed one :single universe, or they were unknowaible to one another in the 'absence of such interaction. 'lihe arguments Aristotle offered 2 on behalf of the unicity of the universe were widely adhered to even in the latter half of the 17th century. The idea of the plurality of worlds that came then into vogue l1ested largely on taking planets and stars for worlds, though hardly ever with the intent of destroying the notion of the universe as a totality. The spontaneous acceptance of a real universe remained part and parcel of Western consciousness until Kant's Critique of Pure Reason began to make a real impact through the rise of Neo-Kantiani:sm fil'om the 1870s on. Reaction to that impact 2 Aristotle, On the Heavens, Bk I, ch. 8-9. THOMAS AND THE UNIVERSE 547 within Catholic philosophical circles, ·and in particular -among the Thomists and their freshly born N eothomist kind, is a subject still to he studied in detail. It seems, however, that no close look W:as taken in those circles at the centrality which Kant's attack on the validity of the notion of the universe occupies in his ,strategy of agnosticism. Usu.ally ignored in the same cireles we:ve ;also the "scientific" threats posed to the unity of the universe in precisely those times or the five decades between 1870 and 1920.8 The scientific situation, though not the scientists' perception, drastically changed in the 1920s, or the very decade during which General Relativity :became widely known. Even today there is no strong awiareness of the fact that Einstein's chief a;chievement in General Relativity was to restore credi1hilityto the notion of the universe. He did ·so hy providing the first contmdiction-free scientific account of all gravitationally interacting things in the concluding or fifth memoir on General Relativity published in 1917. Einstein himself paid no immediate attention to the that in •a sense he discovered for science the universe as ·such, ;and that hy the same stroke he disoredited Kant's claim that science was the ohief disproof of the credi!hility of the notion of the universe. 4 This pivotal 1 s .A case in point is the· Oosmologie by D. Nys, of the lnstitut Superieur de Philosophie in Louvcain, which grew between 1903 and 1929 from a onevolume work into a four-volume opus and influenced many Neothomist writers. The book is a philosophical account of the scientifically investigiated processes in the universe but wholly void of any reference to astronomy, let alone to the cosmos as such. Far less imitated was another major Catholic work from that period, K. Gutberlet's Kosmos (Paderborn: F. Schoningh, 1908). Though it contains interesting discussions on the optical paradox of an infinite universe, the universe as such is not discussed there. Such is hardly a progress from Christian Wolff's Oosmologia (1730), the first major work with that title which, in spite of its Leibnizian biases, influenced for the rest of the eighteenth century many Catholic writers of textbooks of philosophy as well as their Protestant counterparts sympathetic to Scholasticism. 4 Einstein revealed only around 1950 his awareness of the foct that the cosmology of General Relativity may be supportive of natural theology. See for details my Oosmos and Oreator (Edinburgh: Scottish .Academic Press, 1978), pp. 51-3. 548 STANLEY L. J AKI oontriibution of General Relativity was equally ignored hy Eddington, Born, Pauli, Weyl, and other foremost early interpreters of Generial Relativity for the broader scientific public. Wearing the opaque glasses of the Kantian categories, they could hardly see the new cosmologica.1landscape for what it really was. Something very different should have come from first-rate Cathnlic on relativity, such as the Abbe George Lemaitre and Sir Edmund Whittaker. Had they pointed out the bearing of General Relativity on the notion of the universe, better-grade Thomists would have taken notice. This is especially true of Pius XII who in writing his famous address of 1951 on modern science and the proofs 0£ the existence of God 5 was advised by Whittaker, a prominent member of the Pontifical Academy of Sciences. The pope, who quoted from Whittaker's Space and Spirit, credited modern science not for its having reinstated the universe into intellectual respectability; rather, the pope praised modern science for its ha.ving, "in a marvelous degree, fathomed, verified, deepened beyond all expectation" the "wonder of being of the world around us," namely, "the mutrubility of things, including their origin iand their end; and the teleological order which stands out in every corner of the ·cosmos." 6 As happens all too nften, the focusing of attention on particulars, however valuable and telling, distracted from perceiving the overriding importance of the whole. The pope made much of entropy, galactic red-shift, and radioactive decay .as supports o.f the creation of the universe in time. Such a support ean never amount to a strict argument. Physics can never infer from any actual physical state, however remote in the past, to a state which is nothing. Not that the pope offered a strict argument. He would have been the last to abandon Thomas' .standpoint about the impossibility to prove or dis5 The Proofs of the Flwistenoe of God in the Light of Modern Science (Washington, DC: National Catholic Welfare Conference, n. d.). 6 Ibid., p. 5. AND THJ!l UNIVERSE prove either the temporality or the eternity of the universe. But the thrust of his address was unmistakably in favor of the view that physical science strongly suggests a temporal beginning for the cosmos about 5 billion years ago. That today cosmologists speak of rn or 18 billion years is by far the least important change to note. Already a difference of a mere million years or two is beyond human susceptibility. The same is even more true when it comes to very short time spans such as ,a hundredth of a second, to say nothing of a millionth of a second. Yet it is on processes taking place in time units far shorter than a millionth of a second that modern scientific cosmology focuses its investigations. The phases most intensely scrutinized are in the range between 10- 35 to 10-43 seconds, and if the gravitational force will be quantized, research might push beyond the present barrier of 10- 43 seconds or Planck's time. In other words one of the most important facets of modern scientific cosmology is that by spanning almost 70 orders of magnitudes ralong the space-time parameter it is very suggestive of an over-arching totality underlying a vastness that defies imagination. What all this has to do with Thomas will he clear shortly. For a moment let us take a look at some of Thomas' best known interpreters. There is a chapter on" God and the Universe" in Fr. D' Arcy's well known presentation of Thomism hut the chapter contains not a wo1.1d about the universe as such. 7 Even more tantalizing is Fr. Copleston's Aquinas. There the ,chapters" The World and Meta.physics" and " God and Creation " cover eighty pa:ges, almost a third of the entire hook. But a mere look at the index, which does not contain the words "universe" and "world," should be enough of ,a warning that the chapters in question would also be void of those two topics. The warning is folly justified by Copleston's sentence that concludes the chapter "The World 1 1 7M. C. D'.Arcy, Thomas Aquinas (London: Ernest Benn, 1930), pp. 177-90. The first subsection, entitled "The Physical Universe," (pp. 191-7), of another chapter, "Nature and Man," is mostly a discussion of hylemorphism. 550 STANLEY L., JAKI and Metaphysics," a phrase that emphasizes Aquinas' destruction of the world as ·a, " quasi-entity," as a " pseudo-Absolute," and not his commitment to " things which in their inter-reiatedness form the world." 8 To he sure Aquinas had to .battle many doctrines for which the ,world was 'an •aJbso1ute. But did he say ras little rubout the interrelatedness of things that forms the world as Fr. Copleston's neglect Oif that Thomist ·worLd would suggest? Or did that neglect have for its source Fr. Copleston's sympathies for Fr. Marechal ·and for the latter's reading-astonishingly aprioristic reading--of Kant, Fichte, and Hegel? None of these luminaries were rea1ly in .fove with the universe, unless it was the universe of their own ideas. A re1w tantalizing glimpses into the universe as such were offered to the English-speaking world in Fr. Sertillanges' Founr da:tiom of Thomistio Philosophy ,as he :brought his chapter on crea.tion to a close with 1a 1oo:uple of pages on the unity oi£ the universe. There he quoted Thomrus' ,argument :from the Summa (I, 47, 3) that things that come from God must have a relation with one another. He also mentioned Thomas' rejection of the multiplicity of universes on the ground that numbers as such are valueless, whereas a oreated universe must have the v.alue of a single overriding purpose. 9 By comparison, Maritain's St. Thomas Aquinas: Angel of the Sohools, given to the English readership in the same year of 1931, should seem very disappointing. It contains a chapter on Thomas the "Wise Architect," hut ha11dly a wol\d about the all-encompassing ·a;rchitecture which is the universe. Maritain's remark there that "the world which is struggling to be, •struggling to emerge in the future, is not a world of positivism ibut .a world of meta.physics," is not followed by a discussion of the manner in which Thomas makes the physical world ap1 s F. C. Copleston, Aquinas (Penguin Books, 1957), p. llO. Foundations of Thomistic Philosophy, tr. G. Anstruther (London: Sands & Co., 1931), pp. 129-30. 9 A. D. Sertillanges, 551 THOMAS AND THEJ UNIVERSE pear in a. metaphysical light, 10 possibly because Thomas is silent on a struggling and emerging universe. Even more disappointing is Gilson's The Spirit of Thomism, the distillation of half-a-century-long reflections of a great Thomist. The second of its chapters is entitled, " The Master Plan of Creation." There Gilson states: "The Universe is an ordered whole, a hierarchy of heings, and 1although each particular being is good in ,itself, their general order is better still, since it includes, over and wbove the perfection of each individual thing, that of the whole." 11 This is indeed an accurate paraphrase of what Thomas states in Part II, ch. 45, of the Summa contra Gentiles:" For each thing in its nature is good, hut all things together are V'ery good, hy reason of the order of the universe which is the ultimate and noblest perfection in things." 12 Possibly, in his The Spirit of Thomism, four .fairly popular lectures, Gilson wanted to spare his audience some deeper aspects of Thomas' dictum in that chapter about the "plurality of :goods" as !being "better than a single finite good." Yet Thomas' views on the unity or profound coherence of those goods, so ·Large in number, is not given justice in Gilson"s larger syntheses of Thoma;s' thought. Surprising as it may seem, in Gilson's The Christian Philosophy of St. Thom,a,s Aquinas the chapter entitled "The Universe of St. Thomas " contains not a word about the universe as such. There Gilson recalls that aiooording to Thomas the uniV'erse is not the best possible world, that it is not eternaJ, that it is not necess acy, but 1 1 1Q J. Maritain, St. Thomas Aquinas: Angel of the Schools, tr. J. F. Scanlan (London: Sheed and Ward, 1931), p. 61. Maritain had little use for cosmology as he discussed the bearing of modern physical science on metaphysics in his chief work, The Degrees of Knowledge. ·See my article, " Maritain and Science," New Scholastiaism 58 ( 1984), pp. 267-92. 11E. Gilson, The Spirit of Thomism (New York: Harper Torchbook, 1966), PP· 40-1. 12 Quoted from On the Truth of the OathoUc Faith. Summa contra Gentiles, Book Two: Oreation, tr. J. F. Anderson (Garden City, NY: Doubleday, 1956), p. 139. STANLEY L. JAKI he ignores Thomas' emphatic assertions 'about the unity of the universe. The chapter on " The Corporeal World," though it contains the tantalizing phra;se, " The entire world is but a unique instrument in the hands of the Creator," is about substantial fo:rims, change, :and secondary causality. Noil' does Gilson exploit the enormous hearing on the cosmological argument of Thomas' dictum (which he quotes there) that "to underestimate the actions proper to things is fo slight divine goodness." 13 No more :satisfactory in this :respect is Elements of Christian Philosophy, :which contains his most detailed discussion of Thomas' five ways of proving the existence of God. There he notes at the very start that because the " proof is not necessarily tied up with it [Aristotle's own cosmography], it" applies to 'any universe wherein there is some change perceptible to sense." Gilson is quick to assert rubout the first wiay from motion that " it is independent 0:f any scientific hypothesis" :as to the structure of the universe. 14 He amplifies his distancing the five ways from science with the remark that " science simply takes the existence of the world for granted." 15 But then, although he states in the same breath that " the existence of a world of changes in itself is a problem and that it is up to the metaphysician to formulate this problem, to discuss it, and to solve it," he does not extend this precept to the universe as a totality. To see the importance of this latter point, one should only think about the crucial role which the impossibility of a regress to infinity holds in any of the five ways, but in particular in the first and thfod ways that together constitute the cosmo13 E. Gilson, The Ohristian Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas, tr. L. K. Shook (New York: Random House, 1956), pp. 180 and 182. The quote is from SOG III. 27. 14 E. Gilson, Elements of Ohristian Philosophy (Garden City, NY: Double· day, 1959), p. 67. 15 Ibid., p. 68. There is practically nothing on the universe as such in Gilson's The Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas, tr. E. Bullough (1937; New York: Arno Press, 1978), 55$ THOMAS AND THE UNIVERSE logical rargument. For is the impossibility of an actually realized infinite quantity a mere scientific hypothesis? Furthermore, can the regress to infinity he made independent of the notion of an rall-enoompassing tot1:1Jlityand still he used as part of proofs that must first prove that totality to he real if the metaphysical inference f:vom it should really reach the Ultimate Reality? In justice to Gilson, Thomas insists very much on the hierarchical,organization o.f all things, which is, of course, an aspect o;f their unity. Thomas delights in referring to the ascending ladder leading from mere matter through plants and animals to humans and to pure spirits. Gilson is right in emphasizing that Thomas' universe is man-centered and for strictly theological reasons. It shows 'Something of Gilson's intellectual courage that he was not ashamed of restating those reasons at a time, 1968, when astronomers delighted in slighting man as an insignificant .1:1Jccidentin an even more insignificant corner of the universe. The quick and complete turn-around of the scientific consensus on man's position in the universe (through the fol'IIllulation of the anthropic principle, 0if which more later) was not yet visible in the early 1970s when Gilson could have ihad a golden opportunity to il'escue Thomas' man-centered universe from ·scientific obloquy with a reference to that principle.16 Nothing, of course, can or should he done about Thomas' geocentric universe, or t11bout his emphatic endorsement of the Aristotelian subordination of sublunary to superlunary matter. Thomas ·speaks approvingly o.f the empyrean heaven as the highest form of purely material entity. The physical universe of Thomas is fully consonant with Aristotelian physics and a faithful mirror of Ptolemaic astronomy and and cosmology. Thomas sees no difficulty in reconciling Gen1 1 1 16 In a lecture series given by Gilson around 1970 on teleology and modern science published subsequently as D'Aristote a Darwin et retour (1974). See English translation by J. Lyon, with my introduction, From Aristotle to Darwin and Back Again (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1987). 554 STANLEY L. J AKI esis I with the Ptolemaic world view,17 a point noted also by Gilson.18 Of course, the universe as seen by Thomrus, the metaphysician, is .anything but Aristotelian or Ptolemaic by necessity. That God had a free choice among an infinitely large number of possible universes is a very clear teaching of Thomas, but no less clear is that he sees the Ptolemaic universe as a universe that exists most fittingly. He goes along with Aristotle' s claim that it is best for the universe to be spheric.al and, as is well known, tries valiantly to make it appear that Aristotle did not really mean that the universe was necessarily spherical and eternal. Tha.t Thomas nowhere dwells iat length on the totality or unity of things ,as 'Such has obviously much to do with the fact that he lived before the telescope. The pre-telescopic universe as seen by the naked eye appears very much a unity, a spherical totality. This is not to suggest that the telescope immediately disposed of :a neatly visua.Iizable totality of things. Long after his first great successes with the telescope that showed enormous quantities of stars everywhere, Galileo still advocated the idea of ,a spherical universe enclosed within a fairly wide ,shell of istars.19 Such 1a picture of the universe, and even more so the one pivoted on the idea of a sphere of fixed stars, readily evoked •a comprehensive system in which all ve1'ged into unity. For 'Such is the mentaJ impruct 0£ an over•all physical situation confined to a sphere. All this graphically illustrates both the ,advantaiges and the disadvantages of living in •a particular age or phase of intellectual or 'Scientific history. Our respective advantaiges 1and disadvantaiges with respect to the universe will be discussed later. 17 As shown by Thomas' lengthy commentary on the six-day creation in the Summa theologiaa by his much shorter "Postilla seu expositio aurea in Librum Geneseos" in Opera omwia (Parma edition), vol. XXIII, pp. 1-133. 1s Gilson, The Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas, p. 187. 19 See Dialogue Oonaernilng the Two Ohief World Systems-Ptolemaic and Ooperniaan, tr. S. Drake (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1962), pp. 325-6. THOMAS AND THE UNIVERSE 555 As for Thomas, the view natural to him of the universe as a closed sphere offered the adv1antage of never doubting rubout the whole or totality as suich. The disrudvanta;ge was that he did not extensively discuss it as he almost took it for granted. Almost, in a restricted sense of course. As a Christian, as a saint, Thomas knew that the universe was the greatest of all gratuitous gifts. Not surprisingly, his most penetrating discussion of the unity of the universe is, as will be seen shortly, theological with an emphasis, 'as one may ,expect, on knowing truth, which is always to know unity in diversity. While this hardly appeals to modern minds fascinated hy what appears on the sufilruce (quantities in particular) , it alone can rescue modern scientific iciosmologistsfrom taking the universe for a creation of their minds. rt is one thing to be right rubout the manner in which true knowledge resolves the problem of the one versus the many; it is another to make things known, and especially the vastness of things insofar as they constitute a real universe. The restricted sense tin which Thomas seemed to take the universe for granted concerned its obviousness. And he could assume the same on the part of any and 1all, Christian, Jew, and Muslim. Herein lies the source of not an essential, hut still a strategic, weakness of his five ways. '.Dhey do not contain explicit emphasis on the totality of contingent things, whether they move, display their limited perfections, or ,act for a purpose. In this respect even Aquinas' ibest students failed to go heyond their master 1as they systematically ignored important pointers given hy him whereby those ways can he endowed with ·a strength strategically meaningful for the modern mind. Owing to that lack of emphasis a potential threat was in store to his proofs when the sphere of the fixed sta;rs, or at lerust an imaiginary spherical shell .containing all stars, proved to be an illusion. This was still to happen when in 1616 John Donne coined the phrase" all coherence gone." 2 ° For ·almost its first 1 1 1 20 J. Donne, An Anatomie of the World. The First Anniversary: all in peeces, all cohaerence gone; All just supply, and all Relation." "'Tis 556 STANLEY L. JAKI hundred years, Copernican.ism stood for a spherical universe. The incoherence of things haid been celebrated for at least fifty years for politico-social reasons 21 before the vision of a univ:erse with no distinct licitly states that a multiplicity of universes cannot he truly created, has two aspects. 34 One relates to the rationality of God's creative action, which no less than any rational human ·action, must have a specific end that cannot he on hand in the case of a multiplicity equivalent to aibsolute disconnectedness. The other aspect is that matter is not a separate object of creation. It is co-created with the things or substances. ]'or Thomas corporeality is ne-ver a substantial form. He warns in fact against the reification of pure extension as a substance, while he retains dimensional quantity as the principle of individuation. With this he cuts off the possibility of a world-building 1 1 s3 These passages are from ST I, 47, 1. I follow the discussion of L. J. Eslick, 'The Thomistic Doctrine of the Unity of Creation," New SoholastiaWm 13 (1939), pp. 49-70. S4 Here THOMAS AND THE UNIVERSE 561 either in the Cartesian or in the Hegelian manner. Those unable to appreciate the -abstractness of Thomas' distinctions should at least admire them against the very concrete debacles which Cartesian 1and Hegelian wodd-huildings unfailingly triggered and are still triggering, ·as will ibe seen shortly, within scientific cosmology. Now something 1aibout the gems that sparkle about the universe as such here and there .in Thomas' vast writings. They should have been noticed by Thomists of the stature of Garrigou-Lagrange though not hy that new brand of them who call themselves transcendental Thomists. Were they called Aquikantists, hecause of their delusion that Aquinas and Kant can he :£used together, their disinterest in the real universe would more readily give itself away. To find those gems one may he 1greatly helped by the over 50 volumes, each huge in itself, of the computer-produced Index Thomisticus. A mere look at the more than 3000 entries there under universum and mundus 35 ·should .at least suggest that the universe was not at all secondary in Thomas' thinking where the decisive perspective is always theological. Severed from that perspective not a few of his statements on the universe may even appear as markedly lacking in originality. He was not original in saying that the universe was created out of nothing and in time, that God oould have created a better universe, that 1oreation implied infinite power which was therefore not communica,ble to any creature. Others before him had insisted that creation did not require the pre-existence of any kind of matter, that creation was an instantaneous act and related to the ·entire being of any existent, that rea1Son could demonstrate the fact of creation, that the universe was truly 1a totality of all existents other than God, and that it was fully harmonious and created for the sake of man. Thomas, of course, said all these things with extraordinary incisiveness 1 35 See vol. 14 and 22 of Section II in Indw Thomistious, ed. R. Busa (Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: Frommann-Holzboog, 1975). 562 STANLEY L. JAKI and with an unfailing ·ruwareness of the fact that the truth 1about the universe is also 1a truth about God. In view of Thomas' notion of theology as an articulation o[ the authoritative eoclesial message, no surprise should be felt at his emphatic reference, at the ,start of his commentary on Genesis,36 to the definitions, dogmatic and disciplinary, of Lateran IV, or the Decretalia as he called them. Although " in principfo " could mean hoth the principle which is God who makes heaven and earth, as well as a strict temporal beginning, the ":fumiter credimus" of the Decretalia settles for Thomas the choice for the latter interpretation. Thomas' special commentary on the Decretalia 37 that hegin with a formal Creed is probably the most .informative contemporary appreciation 0£ the dogmatic weight Catholic consciousness attriibuted from the very start to that document. He would have as little patience with present-day Catholic " murmuring " against taking the temporal :beginning of the universe for less than a dogma as he had with :some of his crypto-eternalist contemporaries. At any rate, in Thomas' eyes the temporality 0£ the universe strengthens, as win he seen shortly, the unicity of the universe. And so does the Decretalia' s special insistence on the unicity of the Creator which took care, according to Thomas, of the Manicheans, Catha.rs, and others, who claimed also a creator of evil. There is an infinite separation ,between the Creator as meant by Thomas and the imperfect evolving God of Whitehead 1and of process theologians following in his £ootsteps, who, precisely because they themselv:es are evolving with everything else, can ;provide no fimn footing for any statement, including the one about the evolving of everything. The immediate creation of all ,by God, as stated in the Decretalia 1 answered, according to Thomas, the Menandrians, who attri1 ss" Postilla seu expositio aurea in Librum Geneseos," in Opera, vol. XXIII, pp. lff. ar "In Decretalem. vol. XVI, pp. 303-4. Expositio ad Archidiaconum Tridentinum,'' in Opera, THOMAS AND THE UNIVERSE 563 1buted to •angels the creation of this wodd, and also answered Origen for whom the creation of the material world came only when a place of punishment wa:s required for rebellious spiritual creatures. The provision rubout creation in time answered Aristotle's claim about the eternity of the world and Anaxagoras, (Plato's?) views according to which this world was created in time hut matter existed since eternity and was not made by God. Hence also the Decretal,ia's clause de nihilo. Thomas' exposition of the Apostle's Creed is characteristic of his fondness for quoting the Scriptures in the manner of a. friar zealous in preaching. His personal excitement about the subject is usually conveyed through scriptural quotations, but not always. Only a thinker thoroughly seized hy the beauty, dignity, and goodness of the universe because of its having oome out of the hands of an infinitely wise and good Artificer would say, as Thomas does, that it is to he rbelieved that all these things are from one God " who giv;es his own being and norbility to each thing." 88 In speaking of the nobility of each thing ·and of the universe, Thomas is once more true to his prructice, difficult to •appreciate in this age of inflated phraseology. Whereas a modern author would fill 1a chaipter or two with unusual nouns, verbs, and adjecti\i;es to celebrate the universe, Thomas, to do the .saime, uses hut a ,few words, taking each, ihoweV'er simple and familiar, in its fullest significance. Only a mind •seized by the goodness of God could feel a sort of transport on hearing the universe presented as the best because it was a whole, though its parts represented different degrees of goodness. 39 Thomas' universe included not only man but purely spiritual rbeings too, yet he also held that all lower creatures were essential for the goodness, beauty, and perrfection of the universe. It wrus rubout that entire universe that Thomas stated: "The perfection of the totality (universitas) of creatures consists in its similitude to God," a similitude which could not he meaningful if it lacked a thorough unity. 40 1 S8 "In Symbolum Apostolorum ex:positio," in Opera, vol. XV, p. 401. 89 ST I, 47, 2. <10 BOG- II, 46 and 45. 564 STANLEY L. J AK1 According to Thomas, God's own intrinsic order and harmony was reflected in the order pervading the universe which was its very perfection. The unity of the universe was in Thomas' very words, the effect o[ the unity o[ God's mind! 41 This is why the order of the universe could not be a result of chance but had to ,be intended and willed by God himself.42 For Thomas the univ;erse as God's work was so comprehensiv;e that "outside" it there was only God's own eternity. 43 Since, therefore, the universe was the only manifestation of the one God, there could be nothing inordinate, that is, non-unitary, in it. God's single purpose for the universe could not be undermined hy moral evil,44 and much less by physical evil. The latter's handling by Thomas is characteristic of his readiness to see matters, however particular or trivial, in that br:oa;dest perspective which is the foll cohesiveness of the univ:erse. Thus, in commenting on the passage in Matthew's gospel on the nominal price of sparrows as a symbol of their expendability, he brings up the inte11dependence of animal species, with the feeding of cats on mice as an exa;mple, which takes plaice, Thomas declares, " for conserving the good of the universe. It is the order of the universe that one animal should live on another." 45 Rodent exterminators would not he wrong in choosing Thomas for their patron saint in witness to his universal relevance. That the universe loomed supreme in Thomas' thought can be gathered from his statement that all creatures were proportionate to the universe itself. 46 The creation of the entire universe together was, according to Thomas, a view more consonant with the perfection of God, as well as with the unity of the universe, than successive creations. 47 For this reason 41 Comm. de Div. nom. cap. 13, in Opera, vol. XV, p. 401. 42 BOG II, 39. 43 SOG II, 32. 20, 1, in Opera vol. VII/I, p. 210. in Matt. ev., cap. X, 2, Opera, vol. X, p. 104. 46ST I, 56. 47 Quest Disp. Pot. 3, 18, in Opera, vol. VIII, p. 74. 44 3 Sent 45 Oomm. THOMAS AND THE UNIVERSE 565 afone, the idea of a steady-state universe, in which hydrogen atoms are steadily emel'ging out of nothing (without a Creator, of course) as well as the Popperian idea o[ 1an "open universe" 48 (where endless universes successively " realize " themselves) would have ibeen an abomination for Thomas. He would tear his garments and oo¥er his head with ashes on being told about mathematical tricks whereiby entire universes are claimed to have been produced in the ba;sement of laboratories.49 On hearing the related claim that the" Universe could ibe the last free lunch," 50 he would cry " blasphemy " especially for the failure of most Catholics WTiting about cosmology to protest 1against a 1colossal sacrilege. Countless are the passages in which Thomas t11aces the goodness of the universe to its ordel"liness and harmony. While praise of the incomparable value of the universe as uttered by Pla.to, Aristotle, and Plotinus is suggestive of cosmos-worship, Thomas' encomiums of the universe are expressive of the depth of his worship of the God of the universe. Being a genuine worship, its object's reality implies the reality of the universe as a supreme pointer to God. This is why Thomas most naturally makes the distinction between the " universe as a. mere name and as a thing " 51 in ol"der to cut short a priori objections. Clearly, he would know how to cope with those for whom God himself is no more than an idea of their own, because in Kant's aprioristic istyle they take the universe for a mere regulative idea that, in fact, regulates nothing and noibody. Perhaps their sole interest in Thomas' dicta on the universe would be the logical force with which he al"gued time and a.gain that the universe has to be one as long as one meant what one said by uttering that word. In that ·respect Thomas was fully at one with Aristotle, with 1 48 K. R. Popper, The Open Universe: An Argument for Determiinism (Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield, 1982), pp. 129-3(}. 49 .A. H. Guth of MIT as quoted in M. M. Waldrop, "The New Inflationary Universe," Science 219 (Jan. 28, 1983), p. 337. 50 .A. H. Guth as quoted in The New York Times (.April 17, 1987), p. C4. 51 I Sent 44, 1, in Opera, vol. VI, p. 354. 566 STANLEY L. JAKI whom he was so reluctant to disagree as to suggest that Aristotle did not perhaps categorically hold the world to be eternal. Equally polite was Aquinas' disagreement with Aristotle on the creation of each individual soul. Thomas was not ready to deny categorically that Aristotle's Prime Mover was deprived of aJl personal character. No favorruble interpretation could, of course, he given by Thomas of Aristotle's denial of creation out of nothing. Apart from these four pivotal points Thomas readily espoused Aristotle's teachings, philosophical and scientific. But no particular page in Aristotle could inspire what may be the most intriguing pages Thomas has written on the universe. To be sure, the muple of pages, or the ·body of article 17 of q. 3 in De potentia,52 are suffused throughout with deep respect for the nature of things and therefore distinctly Aristotelian. Aristotle's middle :voad in epistemology imposed respect for reality. In Thomas• case that respect was immensely strengthened by his viewing each and every thing as endowed with a nobility that 1aocrued to it through its having been created .by God himself. Those pa1ges also show a Thomas who .for the sake of truth is ready to concede as much as possible to his. opponents. In answering in general the objections, thirty .altogether, aimed at proving the eternity of the world, Thomas ibegan, of course, with a reference to the truth of the Catholic £aith ·which states "we must hold firmly that the world has not always existed." Being a l'evealed truth, it cannot be "effectively a.ttacked by any demonstration based on phyisics " nor by any philosophical argument. Were an al'!gument of the latter kind possible, it would intl'!oduce into God a necessity other than the one which alone is compatible with God, namely, his cons.istency. It is the free choice of God's will in producing such and such a thing that assmes its ·existence in .all its specificity. The validity of this last consideration seems at first to be contradicted by Thomas with respect to the universe. He states s2 See English translation in On the Power of God, tr. English Dominican Fathers (Westminster, Md. 1952), vol. I, pp. 219-34, especially pp. 225-28. THOMAS AND THE UNIVERSE 567 that whereas a particular thing has always a correlation to other particular things, the universe cannot be correlated to another universe. What is therefore the source of the specificity of the universe ,as such? Thomas first 1ooncludes that the Creator's will is the ,sole reason why " the heaven is of such and such a sire and not greater." He invokes ,the aiuthority of RaJbbi Moses (Maimonides) to the effect that " no reason can ibe assigned to account for the great distance of this star from that one, or for any other phenomena that may be observed in the disposition of the heavens, except the design of God's wisdom." Thomas may seem to have momentarily overlooked the fact that stars and other phenomena of the heavens were not the universe itself and therefore subject to the method of correlation which he had just used a:s the explanation of the ructual quantity or suchness of things. Actually, he is quick to admit the sam.e a1bout the universe itself which he had just put in a class different from particular things in proof of his enormous reverence for the uniqueness of the universe. Thus Thomas declares: "We should grant that the nature 0if heaven is not wholly indifferent to quantity, or that it has no capacity for any other than its present quantity." He seems to he content with the p:mviso that ,even if ,a specific quantity is suited to the particular actually existing universe, that universe still cannot ,be necessary. This proviso, which manifests Thomas' eagerness to do justice both to the empirical and the metaphysical, should scientific cosmolseem prophetic in the light of ogy. In the latter, extraordinarily narrow margins are recogniz·ed for the viariability of the total mass of the universe if it is to issue in the actually observed one and not in something unimaginably different. Those narrow margins for the quantity of total mass imply nothing less than that even the specific time-span of the universe is part of its actual nature or suchness. 1 1 568 L. J'AXl'. What is particularly scientific, 1as if :by anticipation, in Thomas' remarks is that he was more willing to grant a natural quantity to the universe than a time natural to it. For him time, together with place, was, unlike quantity (or mass), "ext:mneous to a thing." Such was one of Thomas' reasons for arguing that the finiteness or infinity of the time-span of the universe could not be demonstrated. In Thomas' eyes cosmic time depends more immediately on God's free choice than does the quantity of cosmic matter as the latte,r is mediated by the material nature chosen by God for the cosmos. The balance tilted in favor of cosmic time over cosmic matter will appear to he subtly present even in the concluding phrase of the body of the article under discussion, provided the place where Thomas puts the words, "the mere will of God," is not taken for a mere accident: "The appointing of a [cosmic] measure to time depends on the mere will of God, who decreed that the world should not exist forever but should have a. temporal beginning, just as He willed that the heaven should not he greater or smaller than it is." The objection that this intentional imbalance is contrary to the equal footing on which space and time are put in relativity can easily be answered. The impotence of physics, relativistic or not, to handle but a very narmw aspect of the reality of time was admitted, however reluctantly, by none other than Einstein a:s he tried in 1922 to cope with Bergson's objection in terms of 'a rather lame ·excuse that what he had said about time he had said merely as a physicist. 53 Years later he was brooding over the plain ina;bility of physics to cope with the reality of the Now and refused to- iaccept Carnap's facile solution that time centered on the Now was a purely subjective experience.54 1 53 A discussion with leading French philosophers at the Sorbonne, April 6, 1922, see Bulletin de la Societe frangaise de philosophie 17 ( 1922), pp. 101-2. 54 See Carnap's recall, in his " Intellectual Autobiography " of his conversations with Einstein during 1952-54, in P.A. Schilpp (ed.), The Philosophy of Rudolf Oarnap (La Salle, Ill.: Open Court, 1964), pp. 37-8. THOMAS AND THE UNIVERSE 569 Physicist-cosmologists who today try to fathom the moment of creation and even peek heyond it by mere physics, provide startling evidences of the fact that time su:btly escapes as the now, so important an element of time, escapes the ,framework of physics. Those physicists who would not hand over to metaphysics the moment of creation out of nothing have to fall back on a nothing which is not really penfect vacuum that precedes nothing. I mean the in some cosmological theories the Big Bang. Once more the Copenhagen pseudophilosophy of quantum mechanics is called upon to do the trick. All laymen will be dazzled by technical references to the creation and annihilation of virtual particles in that vacuum. Laymen with some sensitivity for logic may not readily ,swallow references to statistics as proofs that the foregoing process will assure the riandom accumulation of virtualities so great as to spill over into realities equivalent to an entire universe. Any layman should blame only himseH if he feels no contempt ,for the blunt phrase of a leading cosmologist: "Perhaps the reason that there is something instead of nothing is that [the] nothing is unstable." 55 Clearly, when the nothing is to be taken for something and vice versa, one is faced with a flippancy that is nothing short of plain intellectual anarchy or of rank hubris. The sixty or so years of modern scientific cosmology that witnessed not a few contemptuous remarks rubout what is truly 1beyond the material world have, not illogically, also witnessed not a few cases of a rudely high-handed attitude toward material reality. Compared with that high-handedness the old materialistic insistence on the eternity of matter should seem an almost reverential attitude steeped in humility. Thomists will be able to cope with this situation only if they emulate Thomas in his reverence for reality. Above all they 55 Quoted in J. S. Trefil, The Moment of Oreation (New York: Macmillan, 1983), pp. 205-6. The physicist in question is Frank Wilczek of the University of California at Santa Barbara. 570 STANLEY L. J AKI should ha'V'e very clear notions of the sinistrous threats posing as so many supports. The chief of these threats is the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics that has grown into a cosmic philosophy tantamount to an all-pervasive climate of thought. Within its milieu either the nothing is turned into something, or thel'e will be as many worlds as there are observers, or all things fade into the grey gamut of irrational randomness. This last remark owes something to Chesterton, who saw deeper than anyone else into the true repulsiveness of Darwinism insofar as it is distinct from mere ibiological evolution. The really repulsive thing on visiting a zoo after reading Darwin was, so Chesterton a,rgued, not the possibility that one might encounter one's paternal or maternal ancestors, but the realization that all things could vanish into the grey gradations of a universal twilight. 56 That there are things or substances has always been the ,standing or falling p11opositionof Thomism, the only philosophy truly geimane to that touchstone of Catholic faith which is the dogma of transubstantiation. 1 Almost at the same time when the marvelous science of quantum mechanics was and straitjacketed by its Copenhagen philosophy, Chesterton 'Wl'Ote his St. Th01nas Aquinas, still the finest portrayal of Thomism. There he offered not only 1a plethom of penetrating insights about Thomism but also a cosmic diagnosis and a cosmic prophecy. He did not, of 'course, know about quantum mechanics but he certainly knew that if one diagnosed basic ,symptoms, one could sharpen one's vision for diseases not yet catalogued. The true nature of complementarity, the guise in which the antiontologisrn of the Copenhagen philosophy of quantum mechanics is often presented, was in fact described in that book which made a Gilson think that there was nothing more for him to write on 56 G. K. Chesterton, The Everlasting Man (New York: Dodd, Mead, 1925), p. xvii. THOMAS AND THE UNIVERSE 571 'f.homas and Thomism, 57 a book that contains the prophetic passage: I have pointed out that mere modern freethought has left everything in a fog, including itself. The assertion that thought is free [of truth] led first to the denial that will is free; but even about that there was no real determination among the Determinists. In practice, they told men that their will was free though it was not free. In other words, Man must live a double life; which is exactly the old heresey of Siger Brabant about the Double Mind. In other words, the nineteenth century left everything in chaos; and the importance of Thomism to the twentieth century is that it may give us back a cosmos.58 But if Thomism is. to live up to that challenge, Thom.is.ts must not imitate the best interpreters of Thomas in treating modern scientific cosmology as if it did not exist. They should try to be experts in it, or at least appreciate the crucial ·contributions: it can make on behalf of that Thomism whose sole purpose is to serve the Catholic faith. 59 By .achieving a contra.diction-free account of the totality of gravitationally interacting things, modern scientific cosmofogy implicitly discredits the wry heart of Kantian agnosticism, the calling into doubt of the intellectual respectability of the notion of the universe. In addition, by showing over the mind-boggling span of 70 orders of magnitude .a most specific universe, modern scientific cosmology provides a, powerful illustration of the contingency of the universe. Like any specific thing, the specific univ;erse, too, has to be the result of a choice among a great many possibilities. But since the universe is the totality of things, the choice for its specificity can only be looked for " outside " that totality where only God can he found. Finally, within that cosmology there emerged the an1 1 57 For quotations of Gilson's statements from 1929, 1933, and 1966 see my Ohesterto-n: A Seer of Soienoe (Urbana, Ill.: University of Illinois Press, 1986), pp. 19 and 126-7. 58 G. K. Chesterton, St. Thomas Aquinas (New York: Sheed & Ward, 1933), p. 204. 59 See my God and the Oosmologists (Edinburgh: Scottish Academic Press; Washington: Regnery-Gateway, 1989). STANLEY L. JAKI thropic principle, a most reluctant recognition of man's centrality in the universe. Therefore even some Thomists, overly apprehensive about sounding unpopular, should no longer hesitate to echo their fearless master's dictum 60 that the universe was created for the purpose that many may praise the Creator. Once Thomists have .familiarized themselves with these great •contributions of modern scientific msmology, they will ibe able to do what is intellectua.lly far easier .but morally far more difficult. It is to resist academic and cultural pressures, the lure of pleasing their secularisrt peers. They must guard aigainst beooming opportunists if they are to seize their great historic opportunity which is to save the cosmos from many scientists, led alone from countless trendy theologians capable of talking only of their steadily shrinking anthropocentric world. They can confidently appeal to many a statement of Thomas as they proclaim the unique reality of the universe, that supreme witness of the One God. ao Analyzed by Gilson with customary finesse in The Spirit of Thomism, pp. 40-41. CREATOR AND CAUSALITY: A CRITIQUE OF PRE-CRITICAL OBJECTIONS ANDREW BEARDS University of Oalgary Calgary, Alberta I N SOME QUARTERS arguments ias to the existence or non-existence of God are still regarded as intellectually respectaible. Indeed, interest in such arguments is not restricted to those with a strictly philosophical or theological training. Every so often one may observe some specialist from the physical sciences taking an interest in the philosophical discussion of cosmological issues. Such has been the case with the recent contributions of the physicist Paul Davies. 1 However, such contributions are likely to invite from the philosopher the response that the generalized notions which the scientist attempts to transpose from the particular field of his scientific interest are the very notions which feature in the current debates on the philosophy and methodology of the sciences. Such debates bring into question the status of these scientific notions and therefore render any putative generalized or even metaphysical application of them problematic. Discussions of natural theology, then, often appear to be conducted in a manner which tends to take too much for granted with regard to the terms employed. The notion of causality, central to such ,argumentation, is a case in point. Often enough a simple ":billiard hall" image of causal interaction seems to he all that one is required to keep before the mind in order to follow the lines of argument involved, he they or aiga.inst the postulation of a First Cause. Thus, in the often referred to r:adio .debate on the existence of God between 1 Paul Davies, God and the New Physics (New York: T'ouchstone Books, 1984). 573 574 ANDREW BEARDS Bertrand Russell and Fl1ederick Copleston, Russell simply averred that he did not feel compelled to accept that a causal chain extended heyond the ·World to some First Cause. For, indeed, if one imagines a line of billiard halls transmitting momentum one to the other, there is nothing unintelligible about picturing a first !billiard hall initiating the process apparently unaided. Hume has surely taught us that much. If one is to heed the present debates raging in that arena known as the philosophy of science (by which term one can understand epistemology, metaphysics and virtually ·any other topic tr:aditiona1ly designated philosophical), then one can .be forgi¥en for asking how the question as to the existence of God could he raised in an intelligiible manner. For if one is to agree with Richa1d J. Bernstein's assertion that contemporary philosophy manifests, in the ma.in, 1a rebellious attitude to the "father figure,, of the methodical Descartes, 2 then one can be equally well impressed by the fact that this " rebellious spirit" is no Jess informed iby a respect for the Kantian attempt to descry the parameters of valid human knowing. And was it not the Kantian achievement to have dispelled the oibfuscation of metaphysics, thereby eliminating the grounds which were helieved to have substantiated a rational affirmation of the existence of God? The term 'Pre-Critical ' in the title of this essay is, therefore, intended as an e¥ocation of the Kantian demand for a critical v;alidation of the terms employed in philosophical argumentation. However, I shall attempt to advance the thesis that the Kantian enterprise does not, in fact, result in a happy resolution of the problems which it sets for itself. This is, of course, a thesis which could 'be proposed f.rom a number of divergent philosophical standpoints. It is my intention to argue here, however, that the work of the philosopher Bernard Lonergan provides ,a more satisfactory method for the carrying through of the critical endeavour to validate epistemologi2 Richard J, Bernstein, Beyond Objectwism and .Relatwism (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1983), p. 18. CREATOR AND CAUSALITY 575 cally the philosophical ,statements we propose. I believe it is the merit of Lonergan's work to have developed positions on the hasis of an explication of the exigences operative in criticism itself, such that any criticism of this explication will he rbut an example of an incoherent criticism ,attempting to invalidate its own procedures. 3 In what follows I shall attempt to develop the above-mentioned argument to the effect that Kant, for all his effort to carry through the critical programme, must, for the most part, ,he regarded a:s " Pre-Critica1l" in terms of the position adopted here. In the mur:se of this 1argrnmentI will outline a notion of causality which, I suggest, does succeed in validating a rational a:ffirmation of God's existence . .Awa.re of Kant's propensity for 1the use of geographical metaphors in the description of his philosophical aims, we may say that the critical validation of philosophical terms which he envisaged was to ,be made on the basis of the terrain most directly ruccessihleto us; the terrain of our own cognitional procedures. By the care£ul mapping out of this native territory Kant hoped to curtail forays into the distant and fantastic domains of metaphysics which miuld not he shown to be critically verifiable on the hrusis of any experience aiccessi!bleto us. Kant's Transcendental l!dealism has come in ,for criticism from philosophers as diverse ais Hegel, Bolz,ano, Straw:son and Lonergan. However, these philosophers have not denied the validity, in principle, of what Kant attempted to do, ,as might, say, a devotee of the later Wittgenstein. Their criticism has been directed, rather, at indicating points at which Kant has not succeeded in his attempt to 'gl1ound critically philosophical assertions on the basis of cognitional data immediately accesssible to us. One example of this is position on our ability to affirm the existence of a transcendental ego that is distinct s The most compendious exposition of Bernard Lonergan's philosophy is to be found in his book, Insight: A Study of Human Understandilng (London: Darton, Longman and Todd, 1957). 576 ANDREW BEARDS from the other objects of our experience which, Kant informs us, we can 1affirm as existing but not know the nature of. The problem here is that if we cannot know anything rubout the nature of the transcendental "I", then how are we to affirm rationally that the noumenon which is the source of our experiences of >the phenomenal ego is itself to ;be designated "ego", and thereby he differentiated fmm the unknowruble things-inthemselves of the outer world? Richard Rorty has recently made a great deal of the fact that most of Western philosophy's 1atJtempts to set forth an account of human knowing have 1been dominated by the idea that ·knowing is a kind of 'looking' or mirroring. This, of course, is also an observation made hy Heidegger. Less well known, perhaps, is the stress placed on the danger of understanding knowing on the analogy af looking iby such philosophers ias J. Mareohal, E. Col'eth and Lonergan. These writers would argue rthat the " knowing as looking'' notion became particularly well established through the wo11k of Duns Sootus and othel'ls: in the Middle Ages and that it has remained the dominant epistemological model since that time. And Kant, according to 1this Hne of argument, was in no way exempt from the influence of these mediaev1rul developments. The result of this type of critique would, however, not ibe an account of knowing purely in terms of its cultural and social foundations, critique, hut would aim at providas is the case with ing a validated critical .realism (which would, on Lonergan's account at any mte, still give due weight to the historical and social factors involv·ed) . While I cannot hope to reproduce here in •any detail such arguments regard[ng the effect the "looking " analogy has had on Kant'1s epistemology, I will ruttempt to indicate some incoherences which arise in his position .which, I believe, are on further analysis trareable to the operation of that analogy in his thinlcing. It may ibe ·questioned whether Kant differentiates clearly enough between ' objectivity ', in our knowing, as !l."ational as- CREATOR AND CAUSALITY 577 sent and 'ohjectivity ' as the sensiblie experience of objects. For some cruder forms of empiricism, of oour:se, there is not much of a. distinction to be made. But whatever Kant was he was icertainly not a crude empiricist. Kant, that something is: the case, that it exists, is known by the understanding when there is some filling of the empty forms of space and time. The understanding may then make the type of judgement which is not the merely logical, analytical judgement, which refers. to the union of. swbjeot and predicate in the concept of the object, but a synthetic judgement which relates the concept to the o:bject given in the, previously, empty form of spaiceand time. According to Lonergan, however, Kant's account does not explicate clearly enough the factors involved in a rational act of affirming something to be the case. There is insufficient attention given to the criteria which we spontaneously employ in order to answer such questions as "is it so?", "am I ·sure?", "is iit probaibly, or certainly the case?" In contemporary science we stiU require the data presented to our senses in order to perform any investigation and to verify any hypothesis. However, the entities, the existence of which is claimed to be probrubly verified by the modern scientist, are entities which could not be the objects human sensible experience. There is an inferential process at work, often long and complicated, which hegins froon the evidence of the data, or objects of sense, and moves towards a, normally, probable verification of the existence of certain entities, systems and the 1ike. The Kantian would, no doubt, argue ·at some length that such fructors may, in some modified fashion, he included within Kant's scheme of things. But to provide a test case, as it were, to show the inadequacy of Kant'.s notion of objectivity we may briefly point to an incoherence within the Kantian account itself. Kant avers that, in a very limited way, we can lmow what is the case. For we can know that things-in-themselves exist. But it is obvious that for Kant it is no less the case that we cannot know what these things-in-themselves are. For Kant 578 ANDREW BEARDS it is a fact that our knowing is thus restricted. Hut if this is the ease, is a fact, how does this fact itself ·become known in the way in which a fact has to ·become known for Kant: by a filling of the empty categories of time and space? How could this fact of the limitation of human knowing " show up " as some kiind of sensible datum in these categories? This 1brings me to the topic of a self-destructive incoherence which Lonergan, 1among others, helieves can he identified at the heart of the Kantian enterprise. For Kant, as I have just stated, we can know the existence of things-in-themselves but not what these things are. We are incapable of knorwing the nature of 'anything. But this position lands itself in incoherence. For in making the judgement that we can know that there are things hut not what they are, we are affil'IIIlingsomething to be the case with regard to our knowing. We are asserting something about the nature of human cognition. However, the solution here is not to tum to the Hegelian critique of Kant since that position merely compounds Eant's incoherence. The Hegelian affirmation that we only know appearance, not what is so, is itself a claim to know what is the case; it is 1a claim to have Ibid., p. 1. 11 But see note 5 above. JULIAN HARTT AND AUSTIN FARRER 603 I. The Uniqueness of Hartt and Farrer In a recent encydopedia entry, David Kelsey arranges a useful chart of contemporary theology according to the answers given to " the array o:f decisions theologians must make in the course of doing theology." 12 According to Kelsey, theologians must decide the subject matter o:f theology, the importance o:f cultural context, the 1wudience, the significance of the theologian's vantage point, the goals o:f theology and the best means o:f accomplishing them. For our purposes o:f identifying Hartt and Farrer, however, we need concentrate only on the first and the last-the question o:f subject matter and the question o:f the hest means £or attaining theological ends. The latter (being the last question the theologian must face) best :identifies the overall mind o:f the theologian at work. Thus, against the standard answers given here, I shall try to place Farrer. The former, being the furthest removed from actual practice, is the best gauge for reading Hartt's mind on method. According to Kelsey, theologians on the springboard of ruction choose to be either " :foundationalists " or " antifoundationalists." The former, as the badge implies, requires that the " network oif Christian theological proposals " be grounded in a theologically neutral and self-evident proposition in order to convince those outside the faith (as well as those within it) that the faith is intelligible, coherent, and/or true (whatever the goal may be) .18 Antifoundationalism is a bit more of a misnomer. This party is not so much opposed to " :founding " or grounding a system of discourse as it is against the prejudice that nothing, especially religious .belief, is sufficiently accounted for until a bedr:ock of neutral and self-evident fact is :uncovered. Drruwing on the work of cultural anthrnpologists, linguistic philosophers and historians of science, antifoundationalists ·argue that systems of disoourse a:ve not rooted in a 12 'Method, Theological,' The Westminster Dictionary of Christian Theology, eds., Alan Richardson and John Bowden (Philadelphia: The Westminster Press, 1983), p. 363. la Ibid., p. 366. 604 WILLIAM M. WILSON common soil of adjudication, but rather are internally coherent, sustained by a. " deprth grammar " which is unique to them. Like the child who can never point to the moment it began to learn its native tongue, so the ·Christian cannot point to the clear md distinct fact which sprung his £aith. As learning is a function of languaige, so the ability to indicate things which are clear and distinct is a function of the system in question. Farrer stands in neither camp. Agruiust foundationalism, he claimed that the " founding, steadying, invigorating, illuminating and enriching" light of [aith is a result of "assuming God's existence in relating (one's) life to· Him." 14 Children are not taught the terms of an ancient oriental religion and then shown its cogency against a background of disinterestedness; they al'e "smiled aind talked" into it by their "sainted grandmothers." More to Farrer's point, foundationalism is based on a viciously circular argument: In order to begin the search for foundations, one must already have posited the truth of the reality in need of support or else the claim that the foundation is solid-is true in a basic way for a.U people-will itself be in need Oif foundation. It is a game, Farrer said, which mrbelief can play e:reellently and at the expense of theism. A doctrine of substance, for instance, is the proper foundation for a worild taken to be a hierarchy of substantial causes, but if the world is assumed to be a mere " uninspired simplicity," then a doctrine of phenomena-ol'dered-hy-rule is all the support which is needed, and is, so to speak, more clear and distinct, more irreducible, than one of substance. 15 But these remarks do not -rule out the kind of account .foundationalists seek, e.g., a rational account (as Farrer put it) of what is" there for the mind." 16 His co:ntention is simply that, given the strategic role played by •such •accounts, the 14Faith and Speculation (New York: New York University Press, 1967), p. 11. 15 Finite and Infinite, p. 9. ::t6 Ibid. JULIAN HARTT AND AUSTIN FARRER 605 theist cannot pretend to be neutral in his rendition. Indeed, against all manner of anti-foundationailism, Farrer went on to argue that the theist must offer such an account and he must "exhibit his account ... so that others may recognize it to be what they themselves apprehend.''1 7 He need only he cautiorus and have let the "rabbit of theism" out of the "ha,t" of ·an allegedly impartial cosmology. But why a" rational acooUIIlt" at all if it is not to have the force of unanswerruble proof? Because, Farrer argued, God is unique; unique not only in the sense that he possesses a singular set of characteristics, but in the sense that all the characteristics he has are unique to him. If God is known, then, the knowledge must have .been gained through an .apprehen•sion of him existing through, in and with all else. In other words, whereas a foundationalist contends that a constrnal of the world as finite " supports " the idea of the infinite, Farrer argues that in the very idea of the infinite, some definitive ordering of the finite world must already be bound to it or else the infinite cannot be said to be known at all. To put the case in antiffioundationalist terms, if there is a infinite, then a rendition of rfinitude must he ·its "internal structure." Thus, even though we are " smiled and trulked " into faith, the theologian must assume, said Farrer, that the believer has "mrude ·an assumption" about the world, 1better, has run implicitly the course of a " grid of hard thinking " 18 a.bout the world, if the thought of God has become so second nature. Accordingly, Farrer argued, the 'l'ole of the theologian is to explicate these " 1believingthoughts " and attempt to show that the world !hound to theism is cogent, and, finally, the only one we know. This last task indeed will involve a bout with rival systems on all foonts, but the battle cannot be won on the assumption that the theist's world is in and of itself irreducible or clear and distinct. For it is a world of definitively theistic construal; its intelligibility is a function of its 1being the struc11 Ibid. isQ-odlsNotDead (New York: Morehouse-Barlow Co., 1966),p.125. 606 WILLIAM M. WILSON ture which demonstrates the manner in which God is apprehended. The goal of theology, then, is not to "guarantee assent " .but to augur run apprehension. From this quick account of Farrer's thought we can see that he .bears the earmarks of the current options hut finally eludes them both. He is after a bedrock of hard fact in theism, but he acknowledges that this account is not the " support" of belief but rather its internal grid. Like the foundationalists, Farrer stakes coo.viction on this kind of rudimentary evidence, but unlike these theologians, he does not pretend that it will. guarantee assent. Instead, he is more like an antifoundationalist in strategy, decreeing that assent is a function of the faith. Nonetheless, his claim that theism is bound to a definitive metaphysical system results in a denial of the antifoundationalist's basic premise that systems of discourse are mutually integral and exclusive: " Theism is not just one of several ways of construing the same phenomena rwhich other systems exclude." The hegemony of foundationalism is not lost on Farrer: " This extra term, God, implies a certain system in the rest which are ordered towards Him as the garden at Hampton Court is ordered towards the central window of the rpalace."19 We can see that Hartt arrives at the same vision of the theo1o·gicaJenterprise ood policy for achieving goals by attending to his critique of matters closer to the concerns of method-the subject matter of theology. Under this heading Kelsey lists again two candidates: the doctrines of the faith which command obedience and the symbols or narrative through which God is enoountered. 20 Ha.rtt's reading of the options is roughly the same. He separates doctrine and obedience into distinct categories with "encounter," then, being a third. 21 But either list will have Hartt as a footnote, for he cites them to argue that these options must entail each other as parts of Finite and Infinite, p. 9. Theological," p. 364. 21 Theofogicai Method and Imagination 1977), Chapter 3, pp. 45-83. J.9 :20 " Method, (New York: The Seabury Press, JULIAN HARTT AND AUSTIN FARRER 607 one larger subject. For instance, according to Hartt, if God is to be obeyed one must have already encounte11edhim, and if the encounter is to result in something more than the report, in words, " I'm all shook up hut in a wonderfully creative way," 22 then ooe must know something of the doctrines concerning him. In a more serious vain, Hartt argues that the first candidate, doctrine, concerns the " grand patterns " of God's historical action: God is the Lord of a covena111t; He is the Lord in His Kingdom. Under such patterns, dogma holds, God's 'action through time is witnessed. But the patterns are not, says Hartt, simply heuristic devices for church teaching; they are historical; they are the patterns of an agent. Thus, if a pattern is seein, God "speaks"; an agent, a personal intention, is encountered. The second option, then, is at work integrally in the first. Our ensuing obedience (the third option) to the oom.mandments made by God registers that we have in fact claimed the relationship between .patterns and agent to be real. As Hartt puts it, the question which follows encounter, "What must I do now?", signals the recognition (say) " God wa:s i111 Christ;" " and he dwelt among us." 23 This "obediential truth claim," then, is an ontological assertion. The three forms of faith outline a " situation," a "state of affairs apprehended as having certain structural features," which is unique to singular faith as the bind of the three .fonns.24 Had Hartt limited his concepti001 of faith to any one of the three forms then he could not make this claim, :for then faith would he simply a teaching believed, a meeting acknowledged or a person trusted. In other words, the event of .faith would have been but one eveint in an ontological struc22 Ibid., p. 50. 23 "Theological Investments in Story: Some Comments on Recent Developments and Some Proposals." Journal of the American Academy of Religion, L/II (April, 1984), p. 123. 24 "The Situation of the Believer," from Faith and Ethics: The Theology of H. Richard Niebuhr, ed. Paul Ramsey (New York: Harper Bros. 1957), p. 235. 608 WILLIAM M. WILSON ture of the world availrubleto anyone. But he has linked worldly patterns to the divine agent. Thus, we do not first hear other things, other voices and then the . . . voice of the Lord. We do not move from a situation defined as [emphasis interfinite into a situation defined as mine]. 25 No, the finite-infinite structure is original and absolute, and it must be known to be so, not me11ely presumed or thought to be so-or else the overlap of the three forms constitutive of the subset (" person who believes ") would make no sense and we would once a1gain have three diverse notions of faith. Faith in the singular can only .be an actual construal of the world or a viewing of things by incessantly relating " all things in ways appropriate to their belonging to God " 26 ••• that is, by oibediooce. Thus Hartt and Farrer differ from their colleagues in similar ways. What Farrer claimed we must assume as apologists, Hartt has .found to be the very subject matter of theology. Both claim that belief and a definitive construal of the world go hand in hand and cannot be separated with impunity. To the importance of their brand of theism we now turn. First we will hear Hartt's counsel on method to theologians at work, foundationalists as well as their adversaries. Then we will consider theology as a "response" to Hartt's voice. 1 II. Julian Hartt's Theological Method The state of the current controversy between foundationa1ists and antifoundationalists, against which we will read Hartt, is best reached, perhaps, by noting a change in one of the names. If " antifoundationalism" implies more of a reaction against something than a movement with an appeal of its own, then the new name, "post-liberalism" implies that what it reacted against has now been surpassed or moved beyond. pp. 235-236. The Restless Quest, p. 90. 2s Ibid., 26 JULIAN HARTT AND AUSTIN FARRER 609 Indeed, the post-liberal progr:am in many ways seems to have taken Alasdair Macinty.re's recent metaphorica:l prophecy that in the ruins of Western civilization we a.wait a "new St. Benedict" 27 quite literally. Stanley Hauerwas, for instance, has written that " Christian ethics should not begin with an attempt to develop strategies designed to make the world more just, but with the formation of a society shaped and informed by the truthful character of the God we find revealed in the stories of Israel and Jesus." 28 In doctrinal theology, George Lindbeck claims that doctrines do not primarily register independent and universal truths nor symbolize the inner feelings of a general " authentic " human life. He holds, instead, that doctrines are the rules or grammars constitutive of communal speech and action. Doctrines, for Lindbeck, mean what they make. They do not represent trnths which can he stated more precisely in philosophical terms; they render, and thus as .statements :they represent, a community. 29 This concern for closure is not lost on the apologist. On the contrary, Ronald Thiemainn has recently argued that the woeful history (if not the forgotten project) of apologetics is largely a result of ignoring just these sorts of non-foundational claims. The theologian who spends as much time examining the nature of faith as devising a strategy to spread it should see, according to Thiemann, that God is not " extrinsically related to Christian helief and practice." 30 God does not, so to speak, do things which could prove the gospel; what he does is the gospel, and so it follows, for Thiemann, that one may discover the coherence of the faith only amidst the interrelations of such claims already rut work. Thus the " post-liberals " do not advocate an inward turn 21 After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theology (Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press, 1981), p. 263. ·28 A Oommunity of Oharaoter: Towards a Oonstruotive Ohristiwn Social FJthio (Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press, 1981), p. 92. .29 The Nature of Doctrine (Philadelphia: The Westminster Press, 1984.). ao Revelation and Theology: The Gospel of Narrated Promise (Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press, 1985), p. 81. 610 WILLIAM M. WILSON at the of the biblical command to render the faith intelligible to any interested outsider. Rather, they advocate the turn so that a faith which is irreducibly communal may be properly rendered. But it remains that along with this correction goes a serious veaippraisal, perhaps a tempering, of the traditional goals of apologetics. For if faith is a badge of membership, ii belief is a grammar and the mission an acquired :skill, then " spreading " the faith is,. according to Thiemann, a matter of " rational persuasion," 31 or according to Lindbeck, "a matter akin to catechesis. 32 Il belief is a function of practice, then any case designed for the non-beHever must admittedly be, a.s Barth would have it, a "secular parable " of the actual route of assent. It must be ad hos analyzed. BETTI AND THE HERMENEUTICS OF DOGMA THOMAS GUARINO Seton Hall University South Orange, New Jersey I. The Traditional Response to the Question of Historicity. I T IS BY NOW a truism to· speak of historicity as the horizon within which both theological thought and languaige 'emerge. The finitude of the inquirer, the forestructure of understanding, and the historical distance between text and interpreter ·are themes: which dominate contemporary Catholic thought. '.Dhis, however, is not an entirely new phenomenon. Since becoming aware of the invariant structures of temporality, Catholic theology has sought to develop some rapprochement between the apparent antinomies of the universal truth-claims proffered .by the Church's dogmatic statements and the necessary constraints and " localizations " dictated by the realities of culture, time and language. The question has ibeen: How can the Church continue to ho1d for the actual cognitive penetration seemingly called for hy her dogmatic statements 'given the ,striking limitedness of the philosophical, sociological, linguistic and cultural horizons within which such statements are wrought? The solution to this question has, from the nineteenth century onwards, taken the form of some type of distinction between plurality of context and identity of content, between a variety of oonceiptual frameworks a:nd a single undergirding affirmation. This accommodation may he found, in an anticipated sense, in Newman's notion of the subsistent Idea as well as in theological formulation of unity amidst multiplicity.1 Unfortunately, this incipient distinction was quickly 1 Cf. J. H. Newman, An Essay on the Development of Ohristian Doctrine, 635 636 THOMAS GUARINO lost to Catholic theology. In the first place, Aeterni Patris" defined " a particulair eonoeptual system as optimum, thereby reducing the possibility of seeing the distinction actually " exercised ". Secondly, the plurality of conceptual systems, as argued for by Modernism, served only to enervate dogmatic statements of actual cognitive penetration. This essentially pragmatic understanding of doctrinal formulations caused a suppression of the emerging attempt to handle the difficulties involved in the reconciliation of theological plurality with the unity of faith. The entire issue re-emerged in the Forties with the so-called "nouvelle theologie ". The distinction made ,by Henri Bouillard between representations and affirmations was an attempt to preserve the stable determinacy of fajth across a variety of conceptual frameworks. For example, Bouillard argued that despite linguistic, philosophical and cultural differences, the Johannine, Augustinian, Thomistic, Tridentine ·and post-Tridentine theological anthropologies contained one starble affirmation of faith: Grace is a free 1gift of God iby which man is truly justified and empowered to do the good.2 This attempted rapprochement between historical contingency and uni'V'ersal truth-claims was greeted only cautiously by Humani Generis. By the time of Vatican II, however, the distinction :between a multiplicity of conceptual representations and an undergirding affirmation of faith was unqualifiedly sanctioned. 3 Theologically, this fundamental refinement haid been honed and ¥a:riously expressed in the works of Rahner, Lonergan and Schillebeeckx. 4 The distinction was forcefully (London: Longmans, Green and Co., 1900), and J . .A. Mohler, Die lilinheit in der Kirche, (Mainz: Matthias-Grunewald Verlag, 1925), sections 35-48. 2 Cf. Henri Bouillard, Conversion et grflce chez S. Thomas d'Aquin: liltude historique, (Paris: .Aubier, 1944), pp. 212-224. s The relevant passages are Gwudium et Spes # 62, Unita,tis Redintegra,tio # 4, and Unita,tis Redintegra,tio # 6. 4 Cf. K. Rahner, "Considerations on the Development of Dogma", in Theologica,l Investiga,tions v. IV, trans. by K. Smyth, (Baltimore: Helicon Press, 1966), pp. 3-35. .Also, Rahner, "What is a Dogmatic Statement", in TI, v. HERMENEUTICS OF DOGMA 637 promoted hy the Declaration Mysterium Ecclesiae and, most recently, the Final Statement of the Extraordinary Synod of Bishops.5 The greatest theological effect of this con.tent/context, affirmation/representation distinction has been the emergence in Catholic theology of a variety of conceptual systems. The theoretical possibility of dogmatic re-conceptualization has given rise to numerous theological methodologies. Process theology, liberation/praxis methodology and feminist hermeneutics, simply to name three systematic aipproaches, owe their present vibrancy in Catholic thought to the identity/ multiplicity principle. II. Criticisms of the Identity /Plurality Distinction. The 'solution to the problem of contingency/universality, originally proferred theologica.lly and finally sanctioned :by the Magisterium, has itself spawned questions. The chief issue is the epistemological presuppositions which govern the entire affirmation/repl'esentation proposal. For the entire solution rests precisely on the ability of the theologian (or, in the case of final dogmatic validity, the Magisterium) to 1) reconstruct the intended meanings of theological systems, hoth ancient or modern, as these ·a:re embodied ·in varying texts; and 2) " abstract" the undergirding affirmation from the differently developed conceptual frameworks. The chief contention of those questioning the affirmation/ representa;tion distinction is that reconstructive and abstracV, trans. by K.-H. Kruger, (Baltimore: Helicon Press, 1966), pp. 42-66. B. Lonergan, Doctrinal Pluralism, (Milwaukee: Marquette Univ. Press, 1971). .Also, Method in Theology, (London: Darton, Longman and Todd, 1971), pp. 324-326. E. Schillebeeckx, "Towards a Catholic Use of Hermeneutics'', in God the Future of Man, trans. by N. D. Smith, (New York: Sheed and Ward, 1968), pp. 1-50. 5 For Mysterium Jlloolesiae, cf. AAS, v. LXV, p. 396fi. For the Synodal Report, cf. Origins, v. 15, (Dec. 19, 1985). The Declaration makes the distinction between dogmatic unity and a plurality of changeable conceptions. The Synod distinguishes between unity and a proper theological pluriformity. 638 THOMAS GUARINO tiV'e acts, ,as called for by the proposal, do not take OO:equate account orf the ·radical demands of historicity. Especially critical of the proposed solution are those theologians influenced by the Gadamerian current of hermeneutical phenomenology. David Tracy, for example, in his significant attempt to estahfoh a "public " criteriology for systematic thought, rejects any notion of the fusion of horizons (Horizontverschmelzung) which is re-cognitive or re-:productive in kind. A reoonstructive interpretation of the hermeneutical moment represents, for Tracy, a misguided forgetfulness of the structures of tempora.lity. Following Gadamer, Tracy understands interpretation as mediative or c11eative rather than 1:1erproductive. The fusion of horizons, then, ibetween interpreter and text not only the extraction orf content from context, it necessitates the production of •an understanding which is essentially diV1erse from that of the original text. It is precisely the radical epistemological consequences of historicity which cause Tracy to deem the reconstructive act of the identity /plurality distinction to ,be illusory. It follows, naturally enough, from the exclusion of reconstructive interpretation, that Tracy would find the "abstractive " act, i.e., the search for an undergirding affi.rmation within ,a variety of conceptual systems, to he gratuitous. Since the structures of temporaJity characteristic of context are inextricably linked to the content itself, there is no epistemological ibasis for the possible extraction of a singular affirmation. For Tracy, the rfundamental identity which manifests itself in hermeneutica.l theory is not that, in various interpretations, the same thing is affirmed; rather, identity is manifested in the [act that the same (classic) text continues to make a" claim" thereby releasing itself to interpretation. The various trajectories of interpretation will themselves differ widely, subject as they are to the historicality of understanding. 6 Ultimately, for its own sake, and he 6 Tracy, of course, does not advocate plurality seeks to establish public criteria for the adjudication of conflicting theological claims. Ultimately, however, Tracy's thought, based as it is on the HERMENEUTICS OF DOGMA 639 then, Tracy finds the affirmation/representation distinction to rest on the unfounded epistemological presuppositions which Heidegger's ana:lysis of the " world " should have laid to rest. Edmund Farley is another significant systematic theologian who sees a misguided understanding of finitude in the identity /plurality distinction characteristic of much Catholic theology. Farley slowly estaiblishes his case hy presenting an archeology of knowledge in which the various axioms and presuppositions of Revelation are exposed. 7 The fundamentail axis upon which Revelation turns is the principle of divinehuma.n identity. This simply means that an identity-syn.thesis between the divine will and human understanding has heen traditionally rpredicated of the Scriptures, conciliar statements aind dogmatic formulations in general. These loc-i are theologically categorized as "vehicles orf secondary representation," i.e., it is by means of these texts and statements th.at original events are transmitted. For example, the dogmatic statements of the early Christological councils have been theologically understood as secondary representations of the actual inner Trinitarian life. According to Farley, the revelatory "event " has here been " levded " to its secondary form. As a result of this " leveling '', the theological foous is no longer the original event (in this case, Jesus), and the event's validity, hut the vehicles (in this case the conciliar statements) and their validity. The inexorable consequence of the Principle of Identity and the axioms of secondary vepresentation and leveling is the process of de-historicization. If the vehicles of secondary representation are to be worthy of the divine/human nexus, they can ·hardly he relative and errant. On the contrary, dogmatic formulations can only perdure if 1 Heideggerian/Gadamerian understanding of temporality, allows for a variety of interpretations, even conflicting ones. The author may speak of this as an ' analogical' imagination because of his unique interpretation of both the ground and function of analogy which, in the last analysis, is highly dia· lectical. Cf. The Analogical Imagination, (New York: Crossroad, 1981), pp. 319ff, 372ff. Fortress Press, 1982). 1 Cf. Edmund Farley, Eoolesial Reflection, (Phila.: 640 THOMAS GUARINO they are always a.nd everywhere valid and true. Farley concludes, therefore, that the process of de-historicization gives rise to the axiom of Immutability. The principle of Identity along with the axioms of secondary representation, leveling and immutability are seriously challenged hy the awareness of the radical historicity of thought and language. According to Farley, recent Catholic theology has sought to rescue these constitutive axes of Re¥efation theology hy resorting to the context/content, affirmation/representation distinction. " The search is on to focafo that about dogma, that element in dogma, beneath the relativity and errancy of the time-bound and human £ormulat:ions, which is inerrant." 8 To that end, Catholic theologians generally admit that dogmas are formulated in particular languages, philosophical frameworks and cultural horizons. It is conceded that the epistemofogical constraints imposed by these historical factors never allow dogmas to 1be absolutely precise cognitive statements. As such, dogmas always retain their status as true hut severely restricted attempts. Nevertheless, while Catholic theology acknowledges a relativity to the expressi.on of the content of faith, it also claims to recognize an "immutable" element, which is the content itself. It may hold, therefore, by way of example, that one may express the content of the homoousion without utilizing the language of Chalcedon. Like Tracy, Farley sees this identity /plurality distinction as a naive answer :to historical requisites. He accepts as valid what he calls the epistemological presupposition of contemporary philosophy: " Every entity occurs in an ever-changing situation and is itself ... an ·ever-changing situation." 9 From this ip'l'inciple,Farley infe'l's that the re-cognitive and abstractive identity assumed 'by the affirmation/representation distinction is unattainruble. One may not conclude that an equivalent meaning rperdures in new conceptual frameworks. To do so is to igno11e the historica;l situationality of all understands Ibid., p. 96, note # 19. p. 138. 9 Ibid., HERMENEUTICS OF DOGMA 641 ing. Conciliar and dogmatic statements are determinate historical responses, intel'pretative in kind, of a pre-dogmatic faith which inexorably seeks cogniti¥e expression. Faith, then, is always linguistic in character. However, the structures of temporality dictate that the cognitive expressions of faith attain to no universal or immutable validity. Ultimately, for Farley, the epistemological archai of historical consciousness have de-constructed the principle of Identity and the axiom of immutability on which the content/context, affirmation/ representation distinction rests. 10 III. Emilio Betti: Historicity and Interpretation Theory. The hermeneutical theory of Emilio Betti presents theology with one major alternati¥e to the current of thought which claims that the content/context, affirmation/representation solution to the history/doctrine question is an ,illusory construct. Betti is not himself a theologian and is not primarily interested in theological questions; howe¥er, his extensive work on hermeneutical theory and its epistemological presuppositions qualifies him as a potential contributor to the theological discussion. As with most recent Catholic systematic theology, Betti is acutely concerned with assessing the relationship hetween historicity and understanding.1 1 10 It should be noted that Farley is not as immediately dependent on Hediegger/Gadamer as is Tracy. Ultimately, however, he embraces the notions of historicity and understanding as developed by hermeneutical phenomenology. He cannot, therefore, subscribe to the type of recognitive and re-productive interpretative acts necessary for the gnoseological support of the content/context distinction. While both Tracy and Farley seek a more "public" systematic theology, their uses of contemporary hermeneutical theories differ. Farley implies that the notion of "claim" could develop into an individualism which ignores man's social, intersubjective existence and, a, fortiori, his ecclesial existence. This would undercut his attempt to establish theology as a "more rigorous " discipline on the basis of the evidential appresentation of redeemed social existence. 11 Betti's work has been more fully discussed on the Continent than in the English-speaking world. Summaries of his thought may be found in THOMAS GUARINO In his two ¥olume work,. Betti presents an exhaustive phenomenology of the hermeneutical situation. 12 The cornerstone on which his work rests is the determined and invariant structure of the interpretative act. This movement is triadic in nature, involving 1) the interp11eterwho is called to understand the meaning of texts, symbols, monuments, etc. These products of the creative spirit are called Representative Forms or, less frequently, Objectifications of the human spirit; fl) the "other " spirituality who calls and speaks to the interpreter through the Representative Form; and S) the Representative Form itself. Betti offers a detailed analysis of each of these constitutive elements. In all noetic situations, the interpreter finds himself before a Representative Form. This Form or Objectification may he defined as perceptible material (whether text, musical notation or work of art), mediating a spiritual endowment which is embodied within it. Through the Representative Form, one spirituality calls to another. The Form thereby serves as the inaugurator of a colloquy between the interpreter and the spiritual endowment now living within the Objectification. This correlation hetween the message fixed within the form and the interpreter to whom it calls marks the beginning of an actual historical dialogue. Where Betti differs from several contemporary hermeneutical theorists is in his analysis of the message embodied in the Representative Form. Betti emphasizes both the sta.ble deRichard Palmer, Hermeneutics, (Evanston: Northwestern Univ. Press, 1969), pp. 54-60; Josef Bleicher, Contemporary Hermeneutics, (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1980), pp. 27-50; and, briefly, Randy Maddox, " Contemporary Hermeneutic Philosophy and Theological Studies", in Religious Studies, v. 21 (Dec., 1985), pp. 521-522. i2 Betti's opus magnum is Peoria G-enerale della Interpretazione, (TG-I), (Milan: Dott . .A. Giuffre, 1955). The work was translated into German as Allgemeine .Auslegungslehre als Methodik der G-eisteswissenschaften, (Tiibingen: J. C. Mohr, 1967). This later edition included an evaluation of Gadamer's Wahrheit und Methode. Also important is Betti's response to Gadamer in Die Hermeneutik als Allgemeine Meth-Odik der G-eisteswissenschaften, (Tiibingen: J. C. B. Mohr, 1962). HERMENEUTICS 643 OF DOGMA terminacy of meaning affixed within the Form and, more strikingly, the possibility of its re-cognition by the historical interpreter. The Representative Form embodies a meaning and messa:ge which has been objectified ;by the creative act of an "Other". The process of re-cognition involves the reconstruction and of precisely that spiritual endowment now mediated through the Form. For Betti, the very possiibility of such re-cognition and re-construction is undergirded by the commonness of human nature and the cognitive " openness" of the historical given.18 The re-oognitive act of the interpreter seeks to be as faithful as possible to the spirituality eJq)ressed in the Representative Form. Precisely insofar as the interpretative act succeeds the creative act, interpretation properly called demands some type of controllable subordination of the interpreter to the Representative Form itself. Only this interpretafiv;e fidelity and subordination to the Objectification of the human spirit protects the hermeneutical axiom, "Sensus non est inferendus, sed efferendus." 14 Along similar lines, the subordination of the interpreter to the Representative Form emphasizes the objectified "Otherness " before which the interpreter stands. It is, of course, precisely this otherness, the voice of a different human spirit calling, which engenders the hermeneutical project. However, the very " otherness " affixed in the Representative Form must be protected from attempts to level its message to the horizon and self-understanding of the interpreter. Once the canons of subordination and fidelity to the Representative Form are ignored, the "otherness" of the spiritual endowment is forgotten and there looms a temptation to validate understand1 is For Betti, shared humanity allows for an inversion of the creative and hermeneutical moments. For his reliance here on Husserl and especiall!)'" Nicolai Hartmann, cf. TG:I, pp. 260-262. 14 This phrase is repeated by Betti throughout his work and serves as an epigrammatic clue to his entire hermeneutical project. 644 THOMAS GUARINO ing by means of a framework which is imposed subjectively and a priori.15 For Betti, however, the "otherness" of the Form does not stand as a barrier to the re-cognition of its affixed spiritual endowment. Precisely because of the humanity the interpreter shares with the "other" who speaks, the interpreter is able to re-construct the other's thought in a retrospective sense. It is, of course, precisely at this point that the entire weight of contemporary philosophy is brought to bear on Betti's hermeneutical project. Is not Betti's work merely a reprise of historically naive systems? Does his re-cognitive pvoject take into account the undeniable fact that both thought and language come to light within history? Must it not he recognized that the finitude of the interpreter necessarily obviates the repro-' ductive element of the hermeneutical task and transforms it into a creative one? Betti emphasizes that he is not ignorant of the demands of historicity and temporality. His very stress on the noema/ noesis correspondence excises any possible myopic dogmatism. He prefers, however, to speak of the unique visual angle of the interpreter and the manner in which this undergirds the multiplicity of interpretations vis-a-vis the stab1e determinacy of meaning of the Representative Form. A phenomenology of epistemic .action reveals that man always interprets from his unique perspective. It is precisely this perspectival character of knowing and the distinctiveness of each visual angle which issues forth in a plurality of interpretations. However, the proper understanding of interpretative plurality must not be 15 Since a true sense of " otherness " must exist in every truly hermeneutical act, Betti holds that the act of "understanding" may be applied only analogously to cognitive activities such as " interior " experiences. Along similar lines, Betti thinks that speculation concerning the major themes of existence, life and world may be called "interpretation" only in a wide sense. Lacking Representative Forms in which spiritual endowments are affixed, and to which the canons of fidelity and submission may be applied, these themes necessarily lend themselves to hermeneutically ' uncontrollable' speculation. Betti's hermeneutical (rather than metaphysical) concern here is simply the imposition of alien conceptual frameworks. HERMENEUTICS OF DOGMA 645 confused with those theories which conclude from the perspectival character of knowing to the essential relativity of every perspective. The logical inference therefmm is the rejection of re-cognitive interpretation. Betti claims that there are always two demands accompanying the hermeneutical task: 1) objectivity, i.e., re-cognition and representation must he faithful :bo the "otherness " of the determinate meaning of the Representative Form; fl) mediation, i.e., such objectivity is possible only inasmuch as the interpreter perceives the Fomn fmm his unique visual angle. Each interpreter necessarily "interprets" within an original context. For Betti, however, it is a misunderstanding to conclude that .context so go-verns content that ·any search for the stable determinacy of meaning of the Representative Form within the multiplicity of interpTetations is illusory. This is to confuse the essentially re-constructive and mediative tasks of interpretation with the creative and productive tasks characteristic of creation.16 it should be noted that Betti is not opposed to " productive" and "creative" readings, which he calls "speculative" interpretation. He simply claims that such a procedure must be distinguished from a. hermeneutical methodology which, although recognizing that understanding is necessarily determined hy the given forestructure of the unique visual angle, seeks to protect the struhle determinacy of the Representative Fo:mn. This latter methodology is concerned to safeguard the " otherness " and the " autonomy" of the spiritual endowment affixed in the Representative Form. Speculative interpretation, on the other hand, is not concerned with mediating 16 Those who, given their notion of historicity, understand interpretation as primarily creation are necessarily locked into a constraining particularism. "The existential limitation of understanding, which ignores the spiritual basis of interpretation within common humanity, leads to the inhuman and barbaric result of raising insuperable barriers among circles of men reciprocally excluding them and attributing an absolute basis to particularism." TGI, p. 262. For Betti, this is simply the unavoidable collapse of the sensus efjerendus into the sensus inferendus. 646 THOMAS GUARINO and re-producing the " alien " thought objectivated in the Form; it seeks to interpret given events and Representative Forms from the a priori framework of a chosen conceptual system. 11 IV. Hermeneutical Canons. The invariant triadic structure of the hermeneutical process gives rise to four methodological canons which, according to Betti, govern the properly interpretative moment. 18 1. The Autonomy of the Text (Representative Form) This canon merely serves to affirm and preserve the " otherness" affixed in the Representative Form. As such, the Form must not be interpreted by way of any heteronomous or extrinsic standard. All tendencies to reduce or relativize the text to one's own horiwn must be suppressed. The Representative Form stands alone with its own objectivated spirituality; it bears within it a stable and determinate meaning. As such it must he considered and studied according to its own internal coherence, rationality and necessity. 2. Reciprocal Illumination The canon of reciprocal illumination calls .attention to the correspondence hetween the whole and the parts of the Representative Form. The interp·reter, respecting the Form's autonomy, must e:XJcavate from individual elements the meaning of the whole and understand the individual elements themselves in function of the whole. According to Betti, this is merely another way of calling attention to the autonomy of the text. By stressing the critical norms of totality and internal coherence, Betti hopes to avoid the deficiencies of contemporary hermeneutical "extrinsicism ". 17 .Although not explicitly stated, this is certainly how Betti would interpret Heidegger's readings of the thought of Ka.nt and Nietzsche as well as Gadamer's work on Plato and Hegel. is TGI, pp. 305ff. HERMENEUTICS OF DOGMA 647 3. The Actuality (Topicality) of Understanding The emphasis in this third canon is markedly on the side of the interpreter's contribution to the noetic moment. The interpreter always approaches the "otherness" of Representative Forms with his own interests, concerns and mental categories. The Representative Form constitutes an embodied spiritual endowment which the interpreter must reconstruct and re:produce in acco11dancewith his own sensibilities and intelligence. According to Betti, it 'Would be absurd to aspire to strip oneself of one's sll!bjectivity; on the contrary, the subjectivity of the interpreter is the indispensable condition for the possibility of hermeneutical reconstruction. 19 4. The Canon of Hermeneutical Consonance In this [oorth canon, Betti posits a certain hermeneutical " congeniality " which must exist between the interpreter and the Representative Form. Betti refers to this as ,a " fraternal disposition " which must exist between the interpreter Mld the spiritual endowment. 20 It '.l.'epresents a sense of pieta:s before true humanita:s. This disposition, however, is not some ".affective" element covertly introduced within hermeneutical methodology. The attitude of ,empathy is meant to underscore the necessary excision of prejudices in the interpreter's confrontation with the Representative Form. It serves to accent the fact that, if spirit is to speak to spirit, then a true transportation must take place. The interpreter must understand the objectified spirit precisely as he intends to speak. 21 19 "While it is true that the office of interpreter is that of researching and understanding the meaning of the ' other ', this can hardly mean that the interpreter is an inert recipient with a passive and mechanical operation." TGI, pp. 315-316. However, Betti again rejects the inference that the dimension introduced by the subjectivity of the interpreter vitiates the recognitive goal of interpretation. 20 Betti notes that this is something akin to what is found in Nietzsche, Die Frohliohe Wissensohaft, # 339, 334, 310, 305. 21 This canon, then, must be understood as another safeguard against the epistemological bias which blurs the horizon between interpreter and inter- 648 THOM.AS GUARINO V. The Achievement of Interpretation. For Betti, the end or goal of interpretation is, in the first place, re-cognition of the spiritual endowment affixed in the Representative Form. However, as he also makes clear, this re-cognition is never simply imitation, but is reproduction in a wider sense. This is necessarily the case since the new Representative Form achieved by the interpreter reflects a distinct visual angle. Further, in its didactic character, a reproductive understanding is meant for a new circle of hearers. Therefore, its very purpose is to re-express an original meaning in a diverse dimension, accessible to a new " audience ". Interpretation, then, never results in simple identity. This would be impossible given the two horizons which confront each other in the hermeneutical situation. However, Betti notes, some theorists confuse identity and correspondence. The former, outside of mathematics, is epistemologically impossible. It assumes that the consonance between two spiritual totalities could result in a rigid identity. The latter, however, is the achievable telos of interpretation. Betti describes correspondence as an equivalency of meanings in various Representative Forms. 22 This consonance may not be understood as an anti-dialectical identity which ignores the two horizons; rather, it represents the highest goal of interpretation, viz., a dialectical unification. Precisely because the process of re-cognition and re-construction can only be in accord with the education, culture and mental categories of the interpreter, the preted. The " congeniality" called for represents, in a positive sense, the necessity of "bracketing" prejudices vis-.a-vis the novum confronted in the objectified Form . .A misunderstanding of the last canon, which does borrow elements from the thought of Schleiermacher, Boeckh and Dilthey, has occasioned the criticism that it endorses a naive immersion into the culture, Lebensioelt, etc. of the authors of the various Representative Forms. This has caused some hermeneutical theorists to dismiss the realistic epistemology which undergirds Betti's hermeneutics as mere nineteenth century Romanticism. Notice the perceptive comment on this point in W. Hill, The Three-Personed God, (Washington: CU.A Press, 1982), p. 246. 22 TGI, p. 324. HERMENEUTICS OF DOGMA 649 new understanding achieved will be equiv