THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN RES SIGNIFICATA AND MODUS SIGNIFICANDI IN AQIDNAS'S THEOLOGICAL EPISTEMOLOGY GREGORY RoccA, O.P. Dominican School of Philosophy and Theology Berkeley, California S T. THOMAS AQUINAS often refers to the distinction between res significata and modus significandi. He asserls that, whie the :absolute and analogical predicates of positive theology may be pveditcated of God with regard to their RS,1 they mrust ,be denied of God with regard to their MS. 2 The distinotion, then, is an imporlant element in his sake I will refer to res significata, by RS and to modus 1 For brevity's significand.i by MS; I will also speak of the res/modus distinction. The following abbreviations for Aquinas's works will be used: BDH =Flropositio in librum Boethii De hebdomadibus (Marietti ed., 1954); DA=the disputed question De anima (ed. J. H. Robb [Toronto: PIMS, 1968]) ; DDN =Flropositi<> super librum Dionysii De divinis nominibus (Marietti ed., 1950); DP=De potentia (Marietti ed., 1949); DSS=De substantiis separatis (Leonine Commission, vol. 40, 1969); DV=De veritate (Leonine Co=ission, vol. 22, 197276); Herm.=Sententia libri Peri hermeneias (Marietti ed., 1955); John= Leotura super Johannem (Marietti ed., 1952); Meta.=Sententia libri Metaphysioorum (Marietti ed., 1950); Phys.=Sententia libri Physioorum (Marietti ed., 1965) ; Quod. = Quaestiones quodlibetales ( Marietti ed., 1956) ; BOG= Summa contra gentiles ( Marietti ed., vols. 2-3, 1961) ; SDO =Eropositio super librum De causis (Marietti ed., 1955) ; SS=Scriptum super libros Sententiarum (Paris: Lethielleuro, 1929, 1933, 1947); ST=Summa theologiae (Alba/ Rome: Editiones Paulinae, 1962). The English translations are my own. For Thomas's positive theology of the divine names, see Gregory Rocca, "Analogy as Judgment and Faith in God's Incomprehensibility: A Study in the Theological Epistemology of Thomas Aquinas" (Ann Arbor: University Microfilms International, 1989) 540-615. text: "In every name predicated by us [of God], im2 A characteristic perfection is found with respect to the name's mode of signifying [MS], 173 174 GREGORY ROCCA, O.P. theological epistemology and onomatofogy .3 For some, however, the distinction wou1d ultimately lead us back to the univocist camp of Duns Scotus,4 for they see it as hiding within itself a latent core of univocity. One writes that the predication involved in 1anafogy of attribution is both univocal and equivocail: " It is univocal, insofar as it ai1ways denotes the siame proprietas rei; it is equivoca,J since, through a differrent modus significandi, it •connotes ' a different existentiail mode of the denoted proprieta.'J."5 Another writes, in simil.ar fashion, that "the :same property is signifi·ed, hut the way in which the property inheres in the subject is different." a Another contends tha;t the idis:tinJCtionbetween RS and MS is a" bogus distinction between what words realily mean and what they mean to us." 7 If the res/niodus distinction is an im1 which does not belong to God, though the thing signified [RS'] is suitable to God in some eminent manner " ( SOG l.30.277) ; the same sentiment is found in many other texts such as SS L35.LL ad2 and ST l.13.3. Thomas often explains the saying of Pseudo-Dionysius, that negations about God are true while affirmations are vague, by claiming that affirmations are true as regards their RS but not as regards their MS (SS l.22.l.2. adl; l.4.2.l. ad2; SOG l.30.277; DP 7.5 ad2; ST l.13.12. adl; SDO 6.161). a Hampus Lyttkens, however, thinks the distinction plays no essential role in Thomas's theory of the divine names (" Die Bedeutung der Gottesprltdikate bei Thomas von Aquin," N eue Zeitschrift fur systematisahe Theologie und Religionsphilosophie 6 [1964] 277-80). Klaus Muller claims the application of the res/modus distinction to the divine names " says really nothing at all" (Thomas van Aquins Theorie und Praxis der Analogie. Der Streit um das rechte Vorurteil und die Ana,lyse einer aufsohlussreichen Diskrepanz in der "Summa theologiae ", Regensburger Studien zur Theologie 29 [Frankfurt am Main/Bern/NY: Peter Lang, 1983] 100). 4 See Richard Swinburne, The Coherence of Theism (Oxford: Clarendon, HJ77) 78-80. s Jan Pinborg, Logik und Semantik im Mittelalter: liJin uberblick, Afterword by H. Kohlenberger, Problemata 10 (Stuttgart/Bad Cannstatt: Frommann0Holzboog, 1972) 101; but cf. G. Scheltens, "Die thomistische Analdes Duns Skotus," Fra,nziskanisohe ogielehre und die Univozitatslehre Studien 47 ( 1965) 323. e Jonathan Kvanvig, "Divine Transcendence," Religious Studies 20 ( 1984) 378. r John Morreall, Analogy and Talking about Goit: A Critique of the Thomistic Approach (Washington, D.C.: University Press of America, 1978) RES SIGNIFICATA AND MODUS SIGNIFICANDI 175 portant component in Aquinas's theology of the divine names and if it 11ests ultimately on univocity--either because the names we predicate of creatures and God really have the same meaning or hecaiusethe reality they refer to is really the samethen Thomas's contention that the 1abso1ute names of positive rtiheology1a11e predicated anafogiically of God cannot be upheld, and therefore God's transcendence will be sJighted by all divine predication. This investigation of what Thomas means by the distinction between res significata and modus significandi begins by looking at ;the actual historieal genesis of the terminology. I. Historical Background Thanks to rthe combined efforts of several scholars, today we have a fairly good picture of the W e:stern ancestry of the term modus significandi, which began its ual'eer in grammar but was later incorporated into logic and epistemology and whlch in its later ioontexts was distinguished from the res significata.8 114. For Morreall, the RS is what the word really means, but we do not know what that is; the RS is a "core meaning" that has picked up limited connotations by being applied to creatures for so long; supposedly, after stripping away the " encrustations of the MS, we are left with the "pure" meaning or RS. But at this point no one can describe that pure meaning, and so in the end it is no meaning at all. s See Charles Thurot, Emtraits de divers manuscrits latins pour servir a l'histoire des doctrilnes grammaticales au moyen age (Frankfurt: Minerva, 1964; repr. from Notices et emtraits des manuscrits de la Bibliotheque Imperiale, vol. 22/2 [Paris, 1868]), especially pp. 148-60; Ueberweg-Geyer, Die patristische und soholastische Philosophie, vol. 2 in Grundriss der Geschiohte der Philosophie, 11th ed. (Berlin: Mittler, 1928), section 37, especially pp. Geistesleben, 3 vols. (Munich: 455-60; Martin Grabmann, Mittelalterliches M. Hueber, 1926; 1936; 1956), especially vol. 1, chap. 4, and vol. 3, chaps. 3 and 12; M.-D. Chenu, "Grammaire et theologie aux XIIe et XIIIe siecles," Archwes d'histoire dootrinale et litteraire du moyen ,age 10 ( 1936) 5-28; idem, La theologie au douzieme sieole, Preface lly E. Gilson, :Etudes de philosophie medievale 45 (Paris: Vrin, 1957) ; Franz Manthey, Die Sprachphilosophie des hl. Thomas von Aquin und ihre Anwendung auf Probleme der Theowgie (Paderborn: SchOningh, 1937); Brendan O'Mahoney, "A Medieval Semantic: The Scholastic Tractatus de modis signiffoandi," Laurentian-um 5 176 GREGORY ROCCA, O.P. The remote foun:dations of the term are to be found :in Aristotle, Boethius ( , and the Latin grammarian Prisoian, a contemporary of Boethius. Chapters two .and thl"'ee of Aristoble's On Interpreta.tion teach that rthe noun and verb "signify" (semainein) something, and that the verb" signifies time in addition" (prossemainein chronon): e.g., health is a noun and is healthy a verb, the fatter s1ignifying in aiddition (to whait the noun signifies) ithat cthe health is now presently existing. In his commenta.ry on Aristotle's On Interpretation, Boethius understands the Philosopher to mea:n that while the noun may signify (signifioare) ·time in one sense (in words Hk!e today or tomorrow) , only the veTb neoessarily and as pairt of its very naturre consignifies (consigniffoare) time according to its" proper mode'' (proprius modus) .9 Boet:hius's consignificare is very olose in meaning to Aristotle's prossemainein, and the Boetihian ve11b consigni:fies time aocol'ding to a modus .10 Finally, in his Institutiones grammaticae Priscian refers to the "semantic properties'' (proprietates significationum) of the v;arious parts of discourse, wh1oh by the middJe of the twelfth century will be disicussed under the term modi significandi. In the ea:rly middle ages, from the eighth to the beginning (1964) 448-86; idem, "The Medieval Treatise on Modes of Meaning," Philo· sophioal Studies 14 ( 1965) 117-38; Geoffrey Bu:rsill-Hall, Speculative Grammars of the Middle Ages, Approaches to Semiotics ll (The Hague/ Paris: Mouton, 1971) ; Jan Pinborg, Die Entwicklung der Spraohtheorie im Mittelalter, Beitrage zur Geschichte der Philosophie und Theologie des Mittelalters 42/2 (Munster: Aschendorff, 1967) : idem, Logik und Semantik im Mittelalter: Ein Uberblick (Stuttgart/Bad Canstatt: Frommann-Holzboog, 1972); idem, "Speculative Grammar," in The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy, ed. A. Kenny, N. Kretzmann, J. Pinborg (Cambridge: Cambridge University, 1982) 254-69; for the old logic of the Middle Ages, see The Cambridge History 101-57, and for the logic of the high Middle Ages, see section four of the same work; other relevant literature may be found in E. J. Ashworth, The Tradition of Medieval Logic and Speculative Grammar from Anselm to the End of the Seventeenth Century: A Bibliography from 1836 Onwards (Toronto: PIMS, 1978). 9 In librum Aristotelis De interpretatimie, 2nd ed., "De nomine" ( PL 64:421D-422B); cf. idem, De divisione (PL 64:888D-889A). io Cf. Pinbo:rg, Die Entwicklung 30-45. RES SIGNIFICATA AND MODUS SIGNIFICANDI 177 of the twelfth century, grammar-in conjunction with dialectic and rhetoric, the other two parts of the trivium-was taught in the cloister and cathedral siohools, mainly as a commentary on Priscian and Donatus. In its middle third, however, the twelfth century experienced a logicizing of grammar, under the influence of the translations of Aristotle's logical organon, especiaMy as it was interpreted by the commentaries and logical treatises of Boethius and by other Arabic commentaries. 11 This logicizing took p1ace especially at the hands of Peter Abela11d (d. ll4Q) 12 and Peter Helias, a professor ait Paris around 1140 who is actually the founder of the medieval logic of language, exp1aining Priscian',s I nstitutiones grammatiaae through Aristotle's Categories and On Interpretation. 13 He teaches that the parts of speech ail'e distinguished from one another by their modi sigriificandi, which is his understanding of Priscian's proprietates significationum. A part of speech is a sound indicating the mind's conoept, i.e., it is a way (modus) of signifying or consignifying something. Thus, the noun is that which signifies "srnhstance with quaility." He a.rgues for seven parts of speech-noun, verb, participle, pronoun, adverb, preposition, and conjunction---,on the grounds that there are only seven modes of signification and rejects the interjection since it does not have a per se mode of significakion. The "essentirul modes" are what pertain always and univcersa11lyto the parts of speech as 'Such, and the " 'aicc1dental modes " are either species of the essentiaJ parts of speech (a noun may he eiither appellative or proper) or something seicondary to the 11 For Boethius's influence on medieval logic, see Ohenu, La theologie, chap. 6. The early period of medieval logic, which runs from the beginning of the twelfth century to about 1230, is sometimes called logiaa antiqua and further subdivided into logica vetus and logiaa nova: the former is founded on Porphyry's lsagoge, .Aristotle's Categories and On Interpretation, and Boethius's logic treatises; the latter is founded on the remaining treatises of .Aristotle's logical organon. 12 Note that .Abelard distinguishes the nomen from the verbum by the way (modus) each signifies time (see Thurot 150) . 1a For the very early logic before .Abelard and Peter Helias, see Grabmann, 3:94-113. 178 GREGORY ROCCA, O.P. essential mode as such (e.g.• the Single or plrural number of a noun) .u The thirteenth century deepened the logical advance with treatises dealing with sentence and enunciation, the properties of terms (like supposition and distribution) , and the syncategorematicals, which are various connective, modaJ, or numeral ·terms (like omnis, totus, non, et, an, necessario, etc.). The most famous treatise of this period is Peter of Spain's Summulae logicales (ca. 1240-45) ,15 FinaHy, from 1270-1350 a new genre flowe11ed, known as grammatica speculativa, whose works were commonly called Tractatus de modis significandi or Summae modorum significandi,16 and whose authors were named Modistae. Relying on Aristotle's logicail corpus (as interpreted by Boethius), Priscian, Donatus, and Peter Helias, the M odistae treatises merged grammar with logic ·and even metaphysics, aittempting to construct a philosophy of language that could describe a universal linguistics and grammar that are isomorphic with and dependent upon common reality. The Modistae take for granted a realistic epistemofogy, especiai1ly in the celebrated triad of modus essendi, modus intelligendi, and modus significandi, the first of which grounds :the res, which is represented by the conceptus (grounded in the second) , which is signified by the dictio (grounded in ·the third). A physical noise (vox) becomes a woro (dictio) and part of speech (pars orationis) by hamg a determinate modus significandi within the language, ibut this latter is directly conditioned by the wiay in which intell.ecilU'rul knowl,edge gra:sps reality intentionally (modus intelligendi) , which is itself repI1esentative of it:he various categories and kinds of reailiity (modus essendi) .11 u See Thurot 153-55, 170. 11 The treatise is divided into seven smaller ones: enunciation, universals, predicamentals, syllogism, topics, fallacies, and properties of terms. 16 Cf. Grabmann, 1: 115-46. The M odistae tra.ctates diminished with the rise of nominalism, which could not abide their realism of universals. 11 See Boethius of Dacia, Opera,: Modi 8ignifica1114i si-ve quaestionetJ Bupe1' PriBoianum Ma.iorem (written ca. 1270), ed. J. Pinborg, H. Roos, S.S. Jensen, RES SIGNIFICATA AND MODUS SIGNIFICANDI 1.79 The modus Signifir;andi gmdua.hly be1came ]identified with a 8 which oonsignifir;atio,1 couM mean two things: the syintactic meaning of a dir;tio, i.e., how a word needs to be il'e1atedto others in a statement in o'l.1derto signify syntactica.Hy; or the secondary, connotative meaning in addition to the primary, denofative one (e.g., the v;erb consignifies tense, one of its1 aiccidentrul modes) .19 The MS, then, which is a r;onsignifiootio and which establishes the paoc:ts of speech, can be different even when the reality (res) referred to l'emains the same because the modus intelligendi on which the MS is based is also different. The usual example is rbhat of pain: dolor and doleo signify the same res, some sort of pain, but the former does so per modum permanentis and the latter per modum fiuxus vel fieri.20 Jan Pinborg offers a concise summary of the grammatical ana1lysiisof the M odistae: 1 According to modistic analysis words consist of a phonological element (vox) and two levels of semantic components, one concerned with specific or lexical meanings (significata specialia), the other with more general meanings, called modi significandi, on which in turn the syntactical component depends .... By a first imposition the expression is connected with a referent, insofar as a name is instituted to refer to a definite object or attribute of an object. How this happens is almost never discussed in any detail. The relation holding between the expression and the object referred to is called the ratio significandi. It is often described as the 'form ' which turns a mere sound into a lexeme ( dictio) .... In a secondary imposition the lexeme receives a number of modi significandi which determine the grammatical categories of the word .... A given lexeme can be associated with different modi, so that the same lexeme may be realised as different parts of speech and as vol. 4/1-2 of Corpus Philosophorum Danicorum Medii Aevi (Hauniae: Gad, 1969) 4.15ff, 7.42ff, 27.36, 64.77ff, 81.25, 83.51, 262.83. Michael de Marhais (late 13th century) writes: "Unde ratio intelligendi sumitur ab ipsa re; quam rationem intelligendi presupponit ratio significandi existens in dictione" (Thurot 156). 1s For the details of this process, see Pinborg, Die Entwioklung 30-45. 19 Bursill-Hall 54-55; Thurot 155-56. 20 O'Mahoney, "A Medieval Semantic " 466-86; idem, "The Medieval Treatise " 124·28. 180 GREGORY ROCCA, O.P. different grammatical forms.... Obviously then, the modi are a kind of semantical modifiers, further determining the lexical meaning of the dictio, thus preparing it for various syntactical functions.21 Aquinais certainly recognizes the traiditional triad of modus essendi, modus intelligendi, and modus signifioondi (Berm. 1.8.90) , and he also knows how to empfoy the purely grammatical distinctions of the Modistae and other medieval logicians and grammarians, especially in his Trinitarian thoology. 22 Nevertheless, he probably did not know ,any of the M odistae texts properly 1speaking, for he does not use the modal definition for the parts of speech, and the first real texts of the M odistae genre only appear about four years before his death, in 1270, with Martin and Boethius of Dacia. 23 Still, some of the ideas and concepts of the grammafica speculativa were probably known and discussed some time before they began to be formally published in 1270. Three points conclude this section. Fil"st, the res/modus distinction has its historical roots in the discipline of grammar, from Beter Helias to the M odistae. Aquinas, however, incorand porates the distinction into his theological 21" Speculative Grammar" 257-58. For the plethora of mocU significandi used by the Modistae in order fully to define each part of speech, see O'Mahoney, "The Medieval Treatise" 128-38; Bursill-Hall 345-91. James Egan shows how Thomas uses the 22 ST 1.39.3, for one example. grammatical distinction between the concrete and abstract modes of naming in his teaching on the Trinity (" Naming in St. Thomas' Theology of the Trinity," in From an Abundant Spring, ed. by Thomist staff [NY: P. J. Kenedy, 1952] 152-71). For a commentary on ST 1.39 from a semantic perspective, see Michael-Thomas Liske, "Die sprachliche Richtigkeit bei Thomas von Aquin," Freiburger Zeitschrift fur Philosophie und Theologie 32 (1985) 373-90. Cf. Fernando Inciarte, " La importancia de la uni6n predicado-sujeto en la doctrina trinitaria de Tomas de Aquino," Scrip ta Theologica 12 ( 1980) 871-84; idem, "Zur Rolle der Pradikation in der Theologie des Thomas von Aquin: Am Beispiel der Trinitatslehre," in Miscellanea Mediaevalia 13/1, Sprache und Erkenntnis im Mittelalter (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1981) 256-69. 2a Pinborg agrees with Manthey and O'Mahoney on this point (Die Elntwicklung 69, n. 19). For some background to the "modes of discourse" in Aquinas, see Mark Jordan, "Modes of Discourse in Aquinas' Metaphysics, New Scholcwtici1m 54 (1980) 401-16. RES SIGNIFICATA AND MODUS SlGNIFICANDI 1$1 justifies it, as we shall see, by recourse to theological truth. 24 Second, while some of the modi are essential. to the various parts of speech, they are accidental to the specific, lexical meanings of individual words. 25 This opens up the possibility, then, of e:xdsing the modi in oroer to penetrate to the pure lexiool meaning of divine names. But Thomas will not allow this in his understanding of the modi, for the ratio nominis of .any divine name is always a creaturely meaning such that we can never cut away a creaturely mode in order to come up with a ratio nominis that applies purely ·and properly to God. 26 Thmd, the grammatical employment of the res/ modus distinction has a propensity to Slllpport univocity to the degree that it refers to an inner-worldly reality that remains the same in itself even though the ways of understanding and signifying it may vary (e.g., pain is the same in itself even though the ways of understanding and signifying it as a noun or verb are different). Aquinas's use of modus intelligendi and modus significandi is more mysterious and diffioolt to grasp: the res of the tmnscendent God and the finite creature is not the same, and yet in true theologicwl judgments the same creaturely ratio nominis, with its attendant creatureily modi of !Understanding and signification, somehow rewches: past the creature to 24 Pinborg sees Thomas's use of the MS as grounded in real existential differences, whereas the Modistae relied more on Avicenna's "existence-indifferent conception of being" (Die Entwiaklung 38-39, 44-45, and n. 68). Keith Buersmeyer shows how Thomas knows that the polysemy of the word est depends on first knowing the truth about reality and how he is more flexible than the Modistae of his time and later in not attempting to make grammar adjudicate for metaphysics ("The Verb and Existence," New Soholastioism 60 [1986] 145-62). D. Salman writes that the theory of the modi signifioand.1:, "classic in grammar since Peter Heliae, had undergone at the hands of St. Thomas a daring epistemol-Ogical transposition, based on a very deliberate psychology of knowledge and on a new conception of the metaphysical structure of the object" (Bulletin thomiste 5 [1937] 184) . :25 We note in passing that Thomas holds, contrary to those known as the Nominales and to some of the Modistae, that the verb's consignification of time is not accidental but essential to its very meaning (DV 1.5; Quod. 4.9.2) ; cf. Chenu, " Grammaire et theologie " 9-22. 211 On this point, see Rocca 540-54. 182 GREGORY ROCCA, O.P. posit ,a, res in the infinite God. This wilJl 'become dearer in the next section. II. Res Significata and Modus Significandi 'in Aquinas Every proper and positive divine name can be llect naturally understands being (esse) in the way rit is found in the things from which the inteHect receives its knowl!edge, and being is in these things not as suhs1isting simply but as inhering concreteJy in some substance. 1 1 Reason discovers, however,. that there is some subsistent being; and so, although the word being signifies in a concrete fashion, 45 when the intellect attributes being to God it transcends its own mode of signifying, attributing to God that which is signified but not the mode of signifying. Thomas is trying to prove herie that God's being and essence are identical, that God is subsistent being (esse). The objection Thomas responds to claims we should not attribute being to God since God is simple i3.J1d subsis1tent whereas being is always attributed to something as if it were a concrete, inhering aiccidrent.. But if we ha,ve discov,ered a subsistent being, Thomas reasons, then the truth that " God is subsistent being " must be upheld, even though the mind rerulizes in the assertion itself that its concepts and way of understanding cannot do jusrrace to the truth it affirms of God. Tvuth outstrips the very 42 SS l.22.l.2ad2; cf. ET l.13.3.ad3. (cf. DDN l.3.77), where Thomas constructs an elaborate schema to show how we come to affirm things of God and harmonizes it with other schemas he has found in the Liber De causis and Pseudo-Dionysius's On the Divine Names. All three schemas begin at the most basic level of sensation. 44 Cf. DP 7.4.adl. 45 Per modum conoreationis must be a typographical mistake for per modum 43 See SDO 6.170-71 ooncretionis. RES SIGNIFICATA AND MODUS SIGNIFICANDI 187 manner in which we understand as humans. Indeed, unless: we a:lready knew that God is ,subsistent being, we wouM never he able to assert that our way of understanding this very truth itself falls short of God, since we only know it falls short of God hecruuse, whereas it connotes God's being as something concrete and composed, we know that God's being is reaUy simple and subsistent. We may generalize, then, and state that the modus intelligendi ,oan be denied of God only beeause some already known divine truth contradicts: what the modus intelligendi, left to woruld connote or imply about God. Thomas's exampJes of denying the modus intelligendi always follow this pattern. sea 2.12 demonstrates that God cannot be reaUy related to creation, since this would imply that God :is dependent on something created; and sea 2.13.919-20 proceeds to argue that, since sU!ch relations are not rerully in God and yet are still predicated of him, they must be attributed to him on oocount of our way of unders1tanding, " for when our intellect understands one thing as referred to a second it also understands at the same time (cointelligere) 1a !'elation of the second to the first e¥en though the second is sometimes not really related to the first.'' 46 If suich relations are predicated of God and yet we know that they cannot acturully be in God, then by a process of elimination we know that their predication and signilication are the result of our naturail way of understanding. Again, ailthough creation is not really a process of change, it seems to be so aJCcording to our mode of understanding since we imagine and understand the same thing 1a,s existing both before and after its creation; and since the MS foMows the modus intelligendi, we also signify creation as if it were a change. 41 46 The mind cannot escape its way of understanding and yet also knows that it cannot escape and so judges its predications about God accordingly. Temporal relations are predicated of God insofar as they result from our way of understanding, not that the intellect discovers any real relation of God to the world, "but more from a certain necessity that is consequent upon the mode of understanding" (DP 7.11). 47 SCG 2.18.953; S'l' l.45.2ad2. SCG 2.10.903 states that power is attrib- 188 GREGORY ROCCA, O.P. For Aquinas, composition is the mos:t salient feature of the human way of understanding that must always be denied in divine predication. Our intellect knows the simpae in the mode of the .composite, apprehending the simple form as a subject and .attributing something to it (ST 1.13.U.ad2), for the in:teJJ.ect forms areo11ding to the mode of composite thlngs, from which it natumhly takes its knowledge (SS 1.4.2.1). Nevierthe1ess, the intellect rises above its natura1 way of knowmg and does not rattrihute the 'composition to God, UII!derstandmg that whwt corresponds to ail·l its different concepts is one and simple: " For the intehlect does not attribute to the things it understands the mode by which it understands .them, as it does not attribute immateriality to the stone though it knows the &one immrutecirully" (SCG 1.36.302). The mind is not false when it understands the simple God :in a composite fashion, for there is ·a double meaning to the proposition " the intellect is false thrut understands ra thing otherwise than it is": 1 The adverb otherwise can determine the verb understand in relation to the thing understood or to the one understanding. If the former, then the proposition is true, and the meaning is: any intellect is false that understands a thing to be otherwise than it actually is; but this is not the case here, for when our intellect forms a proposition about God it does not say that he is composite but that he is simple. If the latter, then the proposition is false. For the intellect's mode of understanding is different from the thing's mode of being, and it is clear that our intellect understands in an immaterial fashion those material things that exist on a level below itself, not that it understands them to be immaterial but that it possesses an immaterial mode of understanding. Similarly, when it understands simple things above itself,. it understands them according to its own mode, i.e., in a composite fashion, but not that it understands them to be composite (ST 1.18.12.ad8). C. The Ruman Mode of Signification Based on rllaith in God as the transcendent and free creator, on the truth that God is the pure positivity of lpsum esse subuated to God with respect to immanent actions only according to the modus iinteUigendi and "not according to the truth of the matter." RES SIGNIFICATA AND MODUS SIGNIFICANDI 1.89 sistens, on qualitative negative theology's rejection of all mode, finitude, imperfection, and composition in God, on modal negative theology's rejection of anything imperfoot in God's possession of perfections, and on Qlllr characteristic modus intelligendi, Thomas's rejection of the modus significandi of any divine predication primarily intoods to bolster and uphold God's simplicity and substi.stence and thus to separate from God the inevitable connotations of composition, abstraction, and concretion that arise whenever our mind forms and signifies ·any predication, as well as the related eonnotation that would imply anything aiccidental in God. Because he already knows thait nothing composite, concrete, abstract, or accidental rea1ly exists in God, he can reject what the MS would seem indirectly to posit in God, and he can impute such connotations to the characteristic fashion in which our mind understands and signifies what it knows rather than to any reality in God. He explains the different modus essendi or modus subsistendi of various substances by ref erenee to their level of simplicity or complexity. Materiail substances have a different mode of esse from that of separate substances, and separate substances from that of God, for God is the divine esse and nature, separate S1Ubstances are not their own nature, and material S1Ubstancesal'e neither their own esse nor their own nature but only S1Ubsist as individruals."'8 But even though we know these di:ffierent modes of being exist, the mode of signification of " God is good " and " that woman is good " is the same in both 4'BDA 17.adlO. DA 17 argues that the essence of the separated soul belongs to the genus of separate intellectual substances and has the same modus subsistendi, since both kinds of entity are subsistent forms. Material things, however, do not belong to the same genus as separate quiddities and have a different modus essendi (DA 16). Cf. DP 7.7 on the different modus ea:istendi of the house in material reality and in the builder's mind. Thomas can also refer to the ten Aristotelian predicaments or categories as diverse grades of material entity that give rise to diverse modes of being (DV 1.1.114-61). Ens is divided into the ten categories according to a different modus essendi, and since the modes of being are proportional to the modes of predication, the ten highest genera are called the ten predicaments. (Phy£:. 3.5.322; cf. SS 1.8.4.3; l.22.l.3ad2). 190 GREGORY ROCCA, O.P. cases; in fact, rit is only because he realizes God's mode of existence :is not the same as the mode implied 1and connoted when we say " God is good " that Thoma1s teHs us we mrust deny the MS when we predicrute goodness of God. 49 A ,similar situation obtains m the oase of concrete and a.bstmrct names. In all the reality that exists below the first cause, certain things are found that are complete and exist perfectly, while others are imperfect and incomplete (diminutus). The perfect things are those that are per se subsistent in nature, which we signify through concrete names (human, wise, etc.); the imperfect things are those that are not per se subsistent, like forms, which we signify by abstract names (humanity, wisdom, etc.) .... Every name we use either signifies a sharing in something complete,. as concrete names do, or signifies something as an incomplete formal part, as abstract names do. Hence no name we use is worthy of the divine excellence.50 The MS is directly dependent on the l'eai composition of s111bsis1tent, concrete things with nonsuhsistent, ahsitraiet qualities and forms; it !'enders every name unworthy of God since we know that God is neither ,concrete in a composite fashion nor abstract in an incomplete or imperfect fashion. SCG 1.30.277 teJ.ls us more exaotly why the MS renderis eve:ry name we use unworthy of God's transcendent e:imeNence. 49 It is not universally true, then, to say that for Thomas " a difference of modus essendi of a referent corresponds to a difference of modus signifioandi of a predicate" (James Ross, Portraying Analogy [Cambridge Cambridge University, 1981] 165), though it is true in the case of the ten Aristotelian categories, which are the ultimate modi praedioandi corresponding to the ten most fundamental modi essendi among material realities (Phys. 3.5.322). It is precisely because the creaturely and material objective mode connoted by a predicate's mode of signification does not correspond to God's objective mode as the predicate's referent that Thomas feels constrained to deny our human mode of signification in all divine predication. 50 sna 22.378; 383. While humanity and human both refer to the whole human e,ssence, the former does so per modum partis and the latter per modum totius (SB l.23.l.l) ; homo signifies the human as a concrete whole and humanitas signifies that formal element by which a human is a human (Meta. 7.5.1379-80). Since Deus signifies divinity in the concrete while Deitas does so in the abstract, the latter, on account of its modus signifioandi, cannot be used in place of one of the personal names of the Trinity whereas the former can (John 1.l.44). RES SIGNIFICATA AND MODUS SIGNIFICANDI 1.91 With a name we express reality in the way that our intellect conceives it. Having the origin of its knowledge in the senses, our intellect does not transcend the mode found in sensible things, in which, on account of the composition of form and matter, the form and that which possesses the form are different. A simple form is indeed found in sensible things, but it is imperfect since it does not subsist; a subsistent thing that possesses the form is also found, but it is composite ( concretio) rather than simple. Whatever our intellect signifies as subsistent,. therefore, it signifies as a composite being, and whatever it signifies as simple it signifies not as toot which is but as that by which something is. And so,. as regards the mode of signifying, every name we predicate has imperfection, which does not belong to God, though the reality signified is suitable to God in some eminent way. This is clearly the case in the names goodness and good: they signify something, respectively, as nonsubsistent and as concrete; in this respect no name is appropriately applied to God but only with respect to the reality that the name is used to signify. Theologicail truth tells us that our names cannot do justice to God, whose is perfeetly subsistent rather than imperfectly abstract, and whose subsistence is totaHy simple rather than concretely composite. 51 Every name fails to signify the divine being since no name signifies at the same time something perfect and simple, for abstract names do not signify a being subsisting through itself and concrete names signify a composite being; ... rejecting whatever is imperfect, we use both kinds of name in divine predication, abstract names on account of their simplicity and concrete names because of their perfection. 52 An inidividuaJ. suhstanioe existing with categorical accidents 51 Cf. SOG 1.26.248. In SS l.4.2.lad2, Thomas justifies the Dionysian modal negation "God is not wise" by saying that God is not wise as other things are wise in such a. way that in God wisdom should differ from the one who is wise. s2 SS l.4.1.2; same idea in ST 1.3.3.adl; cf. SS l.8.l.1.ad3; DP 8.2.ad7; ST l.13.Lad2. Chenu explains how in certain early medieval thinkers the theology of God's absolute simplicity prevents Priscian's definition of the noun ("that which signifies substance with quality") from enjoying a universal extension, since we name with nouns the God in whom there is no composition of substance and quality (La tMologie 100-107). 192 GREGORY ROCCA, O.P. always entails ,a certain degree of composition, at least of the substance or subject and its accidents. 53 For this reason alone we woU!1d have to deny 1any 1aocidentsin God, but we also must do so because an accident implies dependence (SS 1.8.4.3) and because, since God is his own being and nature and therefore identified with .simple and pure actuality, no further perfection can -accrue to him by way of run accident. 54 Because of the theological negation of accidents in God, Thomas holds that, although we predicate of God certain perfection terms (like wisdom) which signify .areidents in creatures, we must not suppose they signify ruccidents in God (ST 1.3.6.rudl) and must therefo!"e deny their modus significandi.55 Once again, his reason for rejecting the MS is its connotation of something in God that he rulready knows to be untrue. Since no divine name can be taken as implying run accident in God, a name that among crea;tu:veswouM have as its highest genus one of :the nine categorical accidents (such as quality) is said to be predicated according to its proper specific meaning but not according to its generic meaning (e.g., wisdom denotes the perfection of knowledge in God but nothing 'accidental), since that generic meaning a;lway.s l"efers to a categorical wooident.56 In coDJclusion,Aquinas acknowledges the traditional triad of modus essendi (objective mode), modus intelligendi, and modus significandi (subjective modes), with eruch member grounding the one (s) after it. 57 As ·such, the denial of the MS is a short1 1 53 Meta. 7.11.1533-36 and SS 1.8.4.3; cf. Meta. 7.5.1379-80. 54DP 7.4 and SOG-1.23. 55 SS 1.9.1.2, and ad4. 56SS 1.8.4.3 and DP 7.4.ad2; cf. SS 1.4.1.1; l.22.l.3.ad2; l.35.l.l.ad2; l.35.l.4.ad7. Strictly speaking, a predicate falling under the category of relation could even be said of God according to its generic meaning, for relation denotes only esse ad and not esse in (SS 1.8.4.3). Only the generic categories of substance (De Deo uno) and relation (De Deo trino) are applicable to God (SS 1.8.4.3; cf. SS 1.8.4.2.adl; l.22.l.3.ad2). 51 See W. Norris Clarke, ".Analogy and the Meaningfulness of Language about God: A Reply to Kai Nielsen," Th-Omist 40 (1976) 75-80; Giinther Poltner, "Die Reprasentation als Grundlage analogen Sprechens von Gott im Denken des Thomas von Aquin," Salzburger Jahrbuoh ffir Philosophie 21-22 (1976-77) 26-37. RES SIGNIFICATA AND MODUS SIGNIFICANDI 193 hand way of pointing out how every proper predication placing a res significata in God inevitably faHs short of God. The denial of the MS pmifies our assertions about God by separating from God all composition, abstra:ction, concreteness, and accidents. 58 A few texts e¥en seem to use the MS stratagem in order to deny of God the finite and determinate mode of creaturely perfections. The rejection of the MS only makes sense in the context of previously known theofog]cai1 truths, for only such truths justify and make possible the denia1 of the imperf ecrtions implied and connoted by our human ways of understanding and expression. The MS stmtagem is negative theology in brief compass, purifying the expressions of positive theofogy by recourse to theological truth. III. The Res/Modus Distinction and the Analogical Nature of. Divine Predication Does use of the res/ modus distinction secretly rea:dmit univocity into divine predication after he has seemingly hrunished it? Does his use of it veil a hidden univocity so that he and Duns Scotus are saying the same thing after aill? Three reasons suggest an 1ans:wer in the negative. 59 First, Aquinas's 1ana1ysis disco¥ers three essential elements to 1aH divine the res significata, the modus significandi, and the ratio nominis. The denial of the MS does not leave us with a pure oolllcept exaetly fitted to God's transcendent perfection, for our concept of any perfection (the ratio nominis) is always and ineluctably hound to and primarily 58 See Ralph Mcinerny, The Logic of Analogy: An Interpretation of St. Thomas (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1961) 59-60, 157-61. 59 David Burrell distinguishes Scotus's use of the distinction, which leads to univocity, from Thomas's (Analogy and Philosophical Language [New Haven: Yale, 1973] 117, 178-80). Thomas uses it but does not rely on it, since of itself it tends to direct meaning to univocity; indeed, his practice "contradicts" the distinction (ibid. 136-39). John Wippel absolves Aquinas of any "veiled univocity" in his use of the distinction (Metaphysical Themes m Thomas Aquinas, Studies in Philosophy and the History of Philosophy 10 [Washington, D.C.: CUA, 1984] 238). 194 GREGORY ROCCA, O.P. predicated of creatures. The mind uses the ratio nominis :to signify the RS in God, .alil the while denying the MS of the ratio nominis, but it never sees or conceives anything more in the concept thc:tn the creature's perfection which the concept nat.iuraJly signirfies. There is no univocal core to the concept th.rut has been !albs"Wacled from its finite and: infinite modes; rather, anallogy comes to pa:ss when the mind :predicates the ratw nominis of God in an oot of judgment that clwims a truth about the holy darkness of God ·which transcends anything the concept can quidditaitively gvasp on its own, hound as it is to creatures. 0 ° Confusion ensues ii we do not preserve the ratio nominis as part of Aquin:ais's analysis. :Bor him, the ratio nomiriis, qua concept, is always referred to the creature as the prime analogue; it does not become analogiml by being reconceived in ra deeper fashion with reference now to a purer divine meaning hut rather by being used in a true judgment th.alt posits some reality in God. The truth of the judgment makes us realize that the concept, as '/.l,Sed hut not as conceived, has been extended beyond the creaturely reailm. We never rea:lly know in a clear con:ceptual fashion what a divine name might mean for God, and whatever we do know about such a name is a;lways a consequence of the judgments we have already made about God. The source of unity, moreover, for every analogical extension within divine predication is always the oreaturely conceptuail meaning of the ratio nomims.61 60 See Edward Schillebeeckx, Revelation and 7'heology, trans. N. D. Smith, 2 vols. (NY: Sheed and Ward, 1968) 2:170-78, 204; "The act of 8ign-ifymg goes further than the ratio nominis ... " (ibid. 171). 61 The ratio nominis is the source of unity in divine predication. Both Kvanvig and Morreau (see our opening paragraph above and nn. 6-7) seem to identify the ratio nominis with the RS, which lands them in trouble: the former thinks Thomas identifies the RS in God and creatures, when actually Thomas speaks of the ratio nominis as being analogically-which does not mean conceptually-one in God and creatures; in the latter's opinion, since for Thomas the RS is what the name really means and since we never actually know what that meaning is, there is ultimately no meaning at all in divine predication-but while Thomas does admit that we have no concept of the RB in God we do have a conceptual knowledge of the ratio mnmnit as it RES SIGNIFICATA AND MODUS SIGNIFICANDI 195 Second, the Tes/modus distinction is really a microcosm or encapsuiwtion of the whole combined expanse of Thomas's positive and l1!egative theology. Faith (supported by reason) in the free and transcendent Creator-God as ipsum esse subsistens grounds the whole of his positive theology. This view of God is the basis for the most fundamental proposition of his qualitative negative theology, the truth that expresses God's infinite modelessness and consequent incomprehensibility and thus allows the supereminent modelessness o.f God to remain -indeed demands that it remain-in impenetrable and transcendent darkness. Positive and qualitative negative theology exercise their influence upon modaJ negative theology, which denies anything imperfect even in the perfections of God.62 The res/modus distinction first posits a reality (RS) in God (positive theology) and then, on the basis of a qualitative negative theology that denies any modus in God at the same time as it refiuses any conceptual knowledge of God's res or modus, rejects the connotations of divine predication (the deniwl of the MS) that would place anything composite, abstract, concrete, or a:ccidentaJ in God (moda:l negative theofogy) . Because of the judgments of and qualitative negative theology, Thomas can deny the MS in divine predication even though he never pretends to know God's res, ratio, or modus; indeed, we must have recourse to negative names or names of ,supereminence in order to express the divine mode, whose quiddity escapes us (SCG 1.80.278). In other words, Thoma.s's theologircwl epistemology teaches us that while the RS can be sa.id of God in true affirmations and the MS of those same affirmations can be simu!l.taneoruslydenied, we still neve,r know, para.doxically, what that res or its infinite mode amounts to in God and this means that one can never use the res/modus applies to creatures, which is then a source of unity for the meanings of divine predication. 62 Burrell reinterprets the res/modus distinction as an integral part of Thomas's negative theology, which continually denies that any concept can represent God (Analogy 162-64). 196 GREGORY ROCCA, O.P. distinction to distill a univocrul core of meaning out of a compound solution of finite and infinite modes.63 It is ,true that the distinction is used by Thomas in regions remote from its original appHcation in grammar, where it cou1d easily cohabit with .a univocal view of reality, and it is true that a too wooden or mwterial interpretation of it quickly 1eaids baick to univooity. 0' It is also true that of itself it adds nothing new to his theological epistemology. Nevertheless, 'I\homas does employ the distinction as a kind of partial compendium of that epistemology, 1and thus its proper interpretation should evoke the compJexus of judgments that comprise his positive and negative theology. FinaNy, ·since the analogical nature of divine predication and the use of the res/modus distinction are, in Aquinas, matters of judgment insterud of concept, 65 the danger of the " common core of univocity " is avoided. His transcendental analogy depends not on a more profound concepturulizfog hut on recognizing the truth about God. One author has written that Thomas uses the distinction to remind us we have to consider ibwo things' any time we employ a peclection-expression for God: " the immediate in which it applies, and the intention or scope latent within the term." 66 This " intention " within the term, however, is not a new level of concept but riather the fact that the term can be used to express true judgments about God. When Thomas speaks of a statement's intentio signifioare, the phrase first of ruR refers to the statement's objective design or tendency to the truth. 67 In Aquinas's 6s Cf. Bernard Montagnes, La doctrine de i'anawgie de dlapres saiint Thomas a'Aquin, Philosophes Medievaux 6 (Louvain/Paris: Publications Universitaires/Beatrice-Nauwelaerts, 1963) 99-103; William Hill, Knowing the Unknown God (NY: Philosophical Library, 1971) 141-42. For Burrell, the res/modus distinction "does not yield any privileged access to the res •.. " (Aquinas: God and Action [Notre Dame: UND Press, 1979] 10). 64 Cf. Burrell, Aquinas 10; Henri de Lubac, The Disco'IJery of God, trans. A. Dru from 3rd French ed. (Chicago: Regnery, 1967) 200-201. 65 On this point, see Rocca 288-315, 339-63. 66 Burrell, Aquinas 10. 61 .Andre Hayen describes how Thomas uses intentio/intendere at the level of intelligence to mean intensity, voluntary intention, voluntary attention, or RES SIGNIFICATA AND MODUS SIGNIFICANDI 197 theological epistemofogy and onomatology, the res/modus distinction serves to underline the cenrtra.il position he gives to the truth sta.tus of our theological judgments about God. the mind's knowledge of the thing-an mtentio intellecta (L'intentionnd sefon saint Thomas, 2nd ed., Preface by J. Marechal, Museum Lessianum (section philosophique) 25 [Brussels/Paris: Desclee, 1954] 47-51, 161-201). See also H. D. Simonin, "La notion d'intentio dans !'oeuvre de S. Thomas d'Aquin," Revue des sciences philosophiques et theologiques 19 ( 1930) 445-63. Intentio signifioare, therefore, could refer to voluntary intention (what the proposition "means " or " wants " to say) or to the know ledge itself (" God is good " intends of itself to posit goodness in God), but the former is reduced to the latter since what the proposition "wants " to say is always at least partially and sometimes totally a function of what it does say. In DDN 4.9.412, for example, the intentio significare is the intelligible meaning or sense of a word or set of words as opposed to the mere physical sound or sight of syllables, words or sentences; in John 1.1.25, the one using the name lapis is said to intend to signify the actual stone. AQUINAS ON RESOLUTION IN METAPHYSICS MICHAEL TAVUZZI, O.P. Angeliaum University Rome F OR AQUINAS a sequence of thoughts, even if interconnected in some manner, does not DJutomatically constitute a scientific discipline. To justify a daim to scientific status such a sequence will have ito he characterized by those properties which raise mere thinking to the level of reasoning: it wiH have to proceed rationabiliter,. in all senses of the term. The sequence wiM havie to he concerned with a 1corresponding obiectum speculabile, with a universal concept or ratio.1 It wi11 have to be endowed with a direct object of in1" Et ideo oportet scientias speculativas dividi per differentias speculabilium, in quantum speculabilia sunt." In Boethii de Trin., q. 5, a. l; " ... scientia est de aliquo dupliciter. Uno modo et principaliter, et sic scientia est de rationibus universalibus ... " In Boethii de Trin., q. 5, a. 2, ad 4um. The term ratio in Aquinas has a remarkable multiplicity of senses. L. Schutz, ThomM-Lexikon (reprinted N.Y., 1957), pp. 679-690, enumerates eighteen principal significations. Without going into detail, I would like to point out that I am employing the term ratio in the sense of a universal concept (Schlitz's 'i '). This is not the universal concept taken as a particular psychological fact or mental event, with the ontological status of an accident inhering in the rational soul as in its subject, but rather the universal concept in the sense of its notional content, taken as a particular psychological fact. The term ratio, therefore, denotes the notional content which: ( l) represents the intellect's understanding of the nature or essence which is instantiated in a multiplicity of particulars (the nature or essence is itself denoted by the term ratio according to another of its senses, Schlitz's sense 'k '); (2) is endowed with the intentio universalitatis whereby the multiplicity of particulars in which the corresponding nature or essence is instantiated falls under the concept as its genus or species; ( 3) is verbally expressed by a definition. This sense of the term ratio is, of course, not to be confused with that wholly different sense (also of great importance for an understanding of metaphysical resolution) whereby it denotes tbe intellect's 199 MICHAEL TAVUZZI, O.P. vestigation, with ·a proportionate subiectum scientiae, which is at foast formally distinct from that of any other scientific discipline. Aquinais affirms thrut this is indeed the case with the sequence of interconnected reasonings which consititutes the science of metaphysics. In the Prooemium to the oommentary on the Metaphysics of he states that metaphysics is concerned, in the first place, with being as sUJCh-with being as being and the properties which are immediately consequent upon it. 2 The diroot subject matter of metaphysics, its obiectum spooulabile as such, is the ratio which is the content of the concept of being in general (ens commune) and which is instantiated in everything which falls under this quasigeneric concept. But just how does the mind have access to this obiectum speculabile? How does the intellect form the concept of being in geneml and sei:z;e its content? After aH, the 1content of this concept which the " nature " of being as such, the ratio entis, is neither readily nor immediately gmsped by ,the intellect. If it were, there wouM indeed be no need for the discipline of metaphysics. Just how then does the intellect attain it? This question represents the crucial probfom of the very possibility of the science of metaphysics as envisaged by Aquinas. Aquinas is ce:vtainly aware of this and in the same Prooemium does not neglect to answer it. The content of the concept of being in general, the obiectum speculabile of metaphysics, is attained by means of a process of resolut:io.8 In this paper I shall examine this process of metaphysical resolution. I shall first trace Aquina;s's gradual clarification of the nature of resolutive reasoning by commencing with its most primitivi1anationand this is be[ng itseH. In apprehending the processes of cognition, one can begin to recognize the means by which the search for ·this reality is universally conducted: Thoroughly understand what it is to understand, and not only will you understand the broad lines of all that there is to be understood, but you will possess a fixed base, an invariant pattern, opening upon all further developments of understanding. 4 a Lonergan, Met hod, p. 25. 4 Bernard Lonergan, Insight (New York, 1957), p. XVIII. Lonergan's cognitional theory draws from the work of Thomas and Kant but moves creatively beyond them in his emphasis upon the dynamism of the human mind and the nature of the reality it perceives and comes to know. For Kant, to whom Lonergan's work is often compared, the mind imposes a conceptual framework and an intelligible order upon that which it seeks to understand METHOD AND CONTENT IN THEOLOGY Lonergan's use of introspective psychology reveals four levds in human consciousness, the empir1ca1, the intellectual, the rationa1l, and the moml. The empirical concentrates upon experience itself and involves the hasic questioning and intel"est in one's surroundings which all subsequent self-transcende1J1ce presupposes. It is " experiencing one's experiencing, understanding, judging and deciding." 5 Intellectual consciousness considers the elements passed on to it as " unknown " by the empirica1l consciousness, it is the level at which fresh tmderstanding of such matters is reached. Prob1ems posed by experience receive an initial, tentative so1ution through the colllceptua1l insights of intelJectua1l consciousness. In mtiona:l cons1ciousness, which leads knower to the point of judgment, the hypotheses of the intellectual consciousness a:re tested, reflected upon, revised if necessary, and ult.h'Ilately assessed to he essentia.Irly a1ccurabe or inaocurate. This is: a crucial step, for at this juncture self-transcendence enabJes the subject to make a truth rcla.im, a claim to describe reality as it ructua1ly is. The judgment represents the "mind's: assurance that the conditions for asserting existence have been met." 6 in the very process of understanding. As a result, what is known lacks any actual reality outside of the "reality" imposed by the knower himself. Whatever order or objectivity appears to exist only does so because the mind has given to the data an intelligible structure. Apart from the order provided by the processes of the human mind, things as they are in themselves cannot be known. For Lonergan, as we shall see, both what the knower experiences and the intelligible pattern within which it is known to exist are aspects of a real, objective world order. This order of things confronts the knower but would still objectively exist in such a pattern even if the knower never sought to understand it. Lonergan moves beyond Kant at another level as well. Where Kant had posited a static, organizational structure within the human mind, Lonergan finds a dynamic movement toward broader understanding and more expansive horizons. Built into the mind is a kind of nagging dissatisfaction with the present understanding, which drives the knower always beyond himself. 5 Lonergan, Method, p. 14, 15. s Denise Carmody, "Lonergan's Religious Person," Religior• m Life 44 ( 1975) : 225. This expTession is used by Carmody but is an accurate representation of Lonergan's perspective on the matter of judgment. fl48 TERRENCE REYNOLDS Finally, the moral ·oonseiousness makes a demand upon the subject that he act in accol'd. wi:th his own assessment of the >truth. This entails a call to responsibility and moral courage in the confrontation with the reality he has come to understand. The agent thereby ads out of love, driV'en to uphold the good, the :real, and the honorable, with a commitment to the preservation and expansion of what he thinks ought to be. Thus Lone:rgan's person is one who mov;es: towards a devotion to reality in love, the highest level of self-transcendence. From these four 1levels of cons1cious intentionrulity proceed, l'espectiV'ely, the acts of experiencing, understanding, judging, and decision-making; by these acts the subject dmws nearer to a full comprehension and appDeciation of reality and to authentic self-trans1cendenee: ... intelligence takes us beyond experiencing to ask what and why and how and what for. Reasonableness takes us beyond the answers of intelligence to ask whether the answers are true and whether what they mean really is so. Responsibility goes beyond fact and desire and possibility to discern between what truly is good and what only apparently is good. 7 This anaJlysis of the phenomenon of human knowing reveals that a:ll knowing is based on the a priori transcendental notions of being, truth, goodness, and vailue; these create for the subject a perpetual tension which driv;es him to seek beyond his present limitations of consciousness. Man is urged from within towa11ds fuUer knowledge of his universe and towards an affirmation of vrulues. As the agent comes to know the world around him, he attends first to the data at hand, proceeds to formulate theories concerning the stmctul"e of the data, and then arrivies at judgments regarding the correctness of the theories. Thereafter, one ordinarily aiets in accord with what one has judged to he the case, for to act otherwise would be inconsistent. In short, the subject spontaneously makes judgments and decisions in the course of living and 7 Lonergan, JJllethod, p. 11. METHOD AND CONTENT IN THEOLOGY 249 knowing and thereby supports Lonergan's claim that being, truth, goodness, and value are a priori notions which give shape to the horizon of the knower. They are the notions which dynamica1ly form the way we seek out knowledge and ultimately appropriate it. As William Reiser expresses it: ... a study of the structure of knowing reveals its intrinsic orientation towards being; the structure of judgment, an intrinsic orientation towards objectivity; the structure of choosing an intrinsic orientation towards goodness and value. 8 Arising from these a priori determinants are the transcendental he reasonable, and be precepts " Be attentiv;e, be l1esponsible," Lonergan insists are fundamental to intellectual growth and integrity. It should be aJdded that al-1 men do not proeeed unerringly to the fullness of self-transcendence. These a priori factors do not propel all subjects inexorably into authenticity. Personal experiences, the influence of egoism, mistaken judgments, and the like contribute to the infinite variety of individual consciousness. But al-1 men do possess a basic dynamism towards fulier comprehension of life: " ... we all share some capacity, some desire and intimation, for mature human consciousness. If our progress is dialectica:l, forward and bruck, yet it continues, so fong as we try to grow, to become more 11ealistic and more wise." 9 There are four decisive steps which should he taken for one to achieV1e a maitul'e and :vuthentic consciousness; Lonergan ca1ls them "conversions." In eaich conversion, a major change occurs in the subject's horizon, 10 so that he carries out the pros William E. Reiser, "Lonergan's Notion of the Religious A Priori," The Thornist 35 (1971) : 247. 9 Carmody, p. 226. 10 When Lonergan uses the term "horizon," he refers to the total scope of one's vision from a particular viewpoint. T'nis inclucles both the "relative" horizon, which describes one's range of vision relative to one's development in psychological, cultural, and sociological terms, and the "basic " horizon, which describes the subject relative to the four transcendental conversions, intellectual, moral, religious, and Christian. For an extended analysis of fl50 TERRENCE REYNOLDS cedures of knowing with a radically revised perception of reality. Intellectual conversion consists of the subject's .appropriation of a raitional view of experience ov;er and against his previous common sense perception. It is from this: inteHectual stance that one learns to equate the real with the ¥erified and acquiesces to the demand from within to require cogent evidence before ,arriving at conclusions. Having undergone this conversion, one would ,ruooept as real only that which conformed rto the critiical demands of reason. The morail conv;ersion is noted by its art.traction to what is right or good and consists in .sustaining a congruence between one's judgments and one's actions. It is a 1oommitment to .the real in wovd and deed, based upon a love for the truth. For Lonergan, the dynamism of the knowing process and the logic of the transcendental notions lead to the question of God and the affirmation of his: existence, the religious conversion. 1t is .a fact of rull knowing that it seeks out explanations in order to apprehend the rewl. This is certailli.y the ease in all scientific inquiry, ,as newer theories revise an:d replace the oM, ·ailid knowledge progresses ever nearer to an ruccurate understanding of being. The on-going differentiation in scientific knowledge demonstrates that man hopes to draw closer somehow to ultimate truth at the end of his quest. If being or reality itself were not the objective of human knowing, ·the search wouM cease or become meaningless. Implicit in aill inquiry is the underlying as.sumption that the universe is intelligible and that aill phenomena do, indeed, possess explanations. If being is intelligilie, says Lonergan, and if facts hav;e explanations, then existence its:elf must have an explanation, an unrestricted act of understanding, which we call God. The gnawing desire to know in foll, therefor·e, is dynamically directed towards the ultima;te ground and sou11ce of ali1. that exists. So for the knowing subject, the grasp of a limited reality and even the love for a finite truth leave a persistent sense of dis1 the concept of horizon, see David Tracy, The Achie'IJement of Bernard Lonergan (pp. 1-21) and Karl Rahner's use of the term in HeM'ers of the Word. METHOD AND CONTENT IN THEOLOGY 251 satisfaction. From the depths of consciousness comes a call for completeness, a crull for the f,tlli:fil.lmentof the person in the Jove of the unlimited, of that which ts found at the end of the chain of ca;usality. A religious conversion oocurs, then, when one comes to grips with the urging from within and opts to fo.V1e unconditionally, making love for all. of reality the absoJute ground out of which one consciously proceeds. This decision to love unconditionally in a finite wor1d is a l'le!ligious one, for it mows man beyond the constricted reality of his experieillce into the mystery of God, who presides over alt The uncl'leated reality outside the eJq>erience of man becomes the center of his being and man's exis:tenee ,becomes filly authentic in his conversion to •a;hsoiutelove. Unrestricted love becomes the principle of his aJctions and re-creates his consciousness.11 This .conv;ersionto :reil.igionmay remain implicit, a touch of the divine imbedided in the very core of the subject out of which proceeds his ability to transcend critical rationaJrity and to arrirvie at a stance of love and compassion. But interiority veaches its fu!Lfillmentin this and the dynamism of human cons:ciousness drives the subject to :ruchieve fuH personhood. Man at his best is man who e:l!Jl>eriences,understands, judges, and decides in the light of the mystery of being which permeates his consciousness: Conversion, as lived, affects all of a man's conscious intentional operations. It directs his gaze, pervades his imagination, releases the symbols that penetrate to the depths of his psyche. It enriches his understanding, guides his judgments, reenforces his decisions.12 On the specific conversion to Christianity, Lonergan does not hav;e a gl'eat deal further to add. 18 He states that it repre11 This reflects the notion of the "fundamental option", a tradition which goes back to Blondel and is given fuller expression by Karl Rahner in his discussions of man's decision to love unrestrictedly in a limited world. 12 Lonergan, Method, p. 131. is Lonergan has said more on the subject elsewhere, however. Writing in the New Oatholio Erwyolopedia, he claims that conversion is not "a change TERRENCE REYNOLDS sents the attachment to a particular historicwl tradition expressing the reHgious consciousness, and that one undergoing a Christian conversion joins his implicit religiosity with an outward community and thereby makes his stance explicit. The conv;ersion "conjoins the inner gift of God's love with its outer manifostation in Christ Jesus and in those who fol!low him." 14 The explicit word of the Gospel has three distinct purposes: The message announces what Christians are to believe, what they are to become, what they are to do. Its meaning, then, is at once cognitive, constitutive, affective. It is cognitive inasmuch as the message tells what is to be believed. It is constitutive inasmuch as it crystallizes the hidden inner gift of love into overt Christian fellowship. It is affective inasmuch as it directs Christian service to human society to bring about the kingdom of God.15 Having outlined his cognitional theory Lonergan attempts to establish ,a means of understanding and appmpriating theological materials which corresponds to rthe manner in which alil. knowledge is apprehended. Thus in Method he devotes the first half of the work to .a review of the dynamism of conscious intentionality and then shows how the four levels of conscious operations (experiencing, understanding, judging, and deiciJding) can be seen to be present and contributing to the on-going inquiry of theology. The recognition and integrrutionof the four leve!lsof oonsciorusnessinto the methodological structures of theology serve to bring it into congruence with :the pattern of inquiry inherent in all enterprises of knowledge. Thus, theology is to be carried out at a variety of levels. '.Uhere is a dynamic continuum of understanding in theology, and work may be conducted ,at any point 1at which one wishes to makes his contribution to the field. or even a development, rather it is a radical transformation which follows on all levels of living, an interlocked series of changes and developments." Yet, as Charles Curran has pointed out in questioning Lonergan on the issue, he has later spoken of conversion as integration, development, and enlargement. This possible ambiguity in the matter of conversion will be discussed later. 14 Lonergan, JJlethod, p. 360. 15 Lonergan, Method, p. 362. METHOD AND CONTENT IN THEOLOGY Q53 Lonergan first draws a distinction between two phases of theology which he calls mediating and mediated. In the first phase, the documents and materials of a religion are studied and understood as thoroughly as possible, while in the second phase the knowledge gained is mediated to others. 16 In a sense, the second phase takes the inquiry beyond the level 0£ history of religions into a theology of affirmation. 17 Comprising these two phases al'e eight functional specialties which reflect the movcement foom the compiling of data to the making of decisions concerning the data. These functional speciailties are: 1) research, 2) interpretation, 3) history, 4) dialectic, 5) foundations, 6) doctrines, 7) systematics, and 8) communications. The first four comprise mediating theology, and the final four are the work of mediated theology, yet aH are integrally related as components in the dynam:iics of human inquiry. Sin:ce the Christian mes1sagie comes to us through •rhe documents of believing communities, the first task facing Christian inquiry is to, discern the actu:aJ content of the materials passed on. The second step is to determine what the authors aJCtually intended to convey in writing as they did, while the thfod step is to place the authors and their writings into a contextual framework out of wh1ch they lived and wrote. In short, this progressive penetr:ation into the materials of Christianity is nothing other than the first three functional specialties of researich, interpretation, and history. Further, these three specialties para:Hel the first three operations of cognition namely, experiencing, understanding, and judging. Dialectics is the final speicia1ltyin the phase of mediating theology; here the knower questions the extent to which the authors were right or wrong in their histor:Ucailly-conditioned assessments. By engaging in dialectics, the knower takes positions vis-a-vis the materials at hand; this paraUels decision-making, the fourth operation of human knowing. 16 For our purposes, the example of Christianity will be used from here on. Winquist, Review of Method, Anglican Theofogical Review 56 ( 1974): 101. 11 Charles 254 TERRENCE REYNOLDS In the mov;ement to mediated theology, the order of the levels of consdousness is l'eversed. Now the dynamism is from decision-making towards the mediating of one's knowledge, or from the adoption of positions to the making of the data accessible to the experience of others. The fifth specialty, foundations, delineates conversion in the intehlecitual, rationa,l, and moral spheres and 'attempts to determine which of these conversions were evident in the writers of the documents. The next specialty, doctrines', sets out the facts and values which are regarded as most essential in the tradition studied. Foundations engages in decision-making, whilie dorctrines is essentially a function of judgment. The finaJ two specialties, systematics the cycle rbad{: to the second m1d communications, and first 1e¥els of consciousness. Systematic:s attempts to form a pattern of how doctrines of a given traidition are coherent1ly interl'elated, thereby exercising bhe skiHs of interpretation; communications seeks to bring the systematized body of truth to hear upon the experienee others. Lonergan's point is that initial progression towards decision-ma.king in the mediated phase leads one onwa11d to commun:iicate the knowledge to the experienJce others, thereby bringing to full circle the unity of knowing and its conveyance to others in the perpetual devefopment of human knowledge. By tying theolog1oail method into the structure of the operations of aM human knowing, Lonergan also wants to make theology 1as subject to historicail development as any form of human knowing and just ,as with ou:r modern sense of distance from the pa.st, which constitutes the he:rmeneutical prob1em. In so doing, he reiterates his rejection of "olass1cist notions: '' of culture, rconcretize periods of history as supposedly uniquely expressive of the truth, and affirms: his approval of "empiriicist notions " of culture, which acknowledge the progressive flow of knowl'edge, evoJ,vin_g through cultures and time. As Lonergan describes his transcendental method, he maintains that it is "the concrete and unfolding of METHOD AND CONTENT IN THEOLOGY 255 human attentiveness, inte1ligen1oe,reasonableness and respon1sibility,"18 and is therefore as appropriate to theology as to a;1l other fields of inquiry. The method offers the "key to 1a unified sicienoe," and outside of its field of application " there is nothing at all." 19 Man progresses towards authentic selftr:ansoendence; his end is a life of faith, hope, and love, the means by which he will ultimatdy fulfill the transeendental precepts to fo 11e intelligently, reasonrubily, and responsibly. In defining the grasp of truth as the fruit of authentic subjectivity and in positing this subjectivity as a universal end which all seek and are capa1citated to :attiain, Lonergan leaves open the question of the specific value of the Christian faith and the particular impact that it may have upon his proposed method. Critics have argued that Lonergan's programmatic division of the labor of theology from that of method is unsatisfactory. 20 A very DuUes in a review of Method in Theology provides a concise summary of this perceived difficulty in Lonergan's approa,ch: A third unfortunate separation pervading Lonergan's book is that of method from theology. He repeatedly avers that he writes not as a theologian but as a methodologist. On this ground he abstains from discussing the nature of revelation, the authority of Scripture, the Fathers, doctors, popes,. councils, bishops, etc. While he evidently accepts conciliar pronouncements and staunchly adheres to the teaching of Vatican I, he provides no theory of the nature and limits of authority in theology. Granted that one's view of authority will necessarily depend upon one's theory of revelation, Christology, and Church, I am convinced that method in theology cannot be adequately treated without some attention to these questions. In theology as in other sciences, method and content are dialectically interdependent. 21 is Lonergan, JJ! et hod, p. 24. 19 Lonergan, Method, p. 23, 24. 20 Other issues raised by Lonergan's critics which cannot be given proper attention in this essay include his division of theology into his proposed eight functional specialties and his confidence in the scope and capacity of human reason. 21 Avery Dulles, Review of Met hod, Theological Studies 33 ( 1972) : 555. 256 TERRENCE REYNOLDS From this critique arise further questions riegariclingLonergan's notion of love, his understanding of the l'elationship of Christianity to other religions, and his anthropology. Beforie analyzing the charges directed at Lonergan's Method, a few clarifying remarks are in order. As Dulles correctly avers, the majority of critics ,do not 1rucicuse Lonergan of harboring non-Christian or, more specificaUy, non-Catholic premises; the charges tend to focus on his al,leged failure to make explicit the manner in which his Christian understanding influences the construction of his method. 22 Others have suggested that Lonergan's approa:ch domesticates the Gospel, removing its "No" to man's religiosity. Some argue that Method deprives theology of its uniqueness by advocating that it be studied as scientifically as any other discipline. Thomas TorranJoe, for example, has referred to Lonergan as the " Catholic Sdtleiermacher " and has claimed that Method makes man the source for theology, thereby unde11cutting the free, revelatory act of God. It will not he the purpose of this essay to answer these cha;rges. Suffice it to say that there are models in which the relationship of nature and graoe is so delineated as to permit a fruitful degree of theofog1cia1l insight based upon a descriptive analysis of the human person. This essay will look at the question of whether or not Lonergan has successfully incorporated such a model of nature and grace into his wo:rk, and whether it enables him to answer the conoerns of the majority of his critics. Anthony Kelly has pursued the concerns mised by Dulles and '\!Viles23 and has fooused specifical.J.y upon Lone.rgan's treatment of ·three interrelaited matters: man's seilf-transcendenoe in the direction of the divine, :religiosity and Christianity, 22 Lonergan's reputation, based upon previous exegetical and doctrinal studies, is virtually unblemished. His critics have been unsettled by the lack of clarity in his recent undertaking. 23 This is not to suggest that Kelly's concerns are completely representative of what Dulles and Wiles "might " have said, had they expanded their critiques. My point is only that Kelly's objections do arise from the concern expressed by both reviewers over Lonergan's division of content and method. METHOD AND CONTENT IN THEOLOGY 257 and the uniqueness and value of Christ for authentic subjectivity. Lonergan asserts that the grasp of truth is a product of wuthenticity and that one achieves such authenticity as a :resul,t of a progression to the fovel of self-transcending love. This love is to be discovered in a variety of trnditions, promoted in a variety of oultures, and represents a human possibility not bound to a particular society or creed. Faith, hope, 1and love, as trans-cultural phenomena, are 'the means by which men everywhere are able to fulfiH the demands of the transcendentail precepts (to live intelligently, reasonably, and responsibly). With this schema, Lonergan provides a basis for understanding and collaboration in cognition which Kelly applauds: "By taking his stand on what is fundamental to an cultures, the self-transcending drive towards authentic values, he o:ffers the promise of a theoretical and practical coherence for the totaJ human enterprise." 24 Yet EeHy remains uncomfortable with Method bemuse he 11egards Lonergan's treatment of the person and work of Jesus Christ as fundamentally ambiguous: " ... and here precisely is my question: how does this theological method take faith in Christ into its inner vitality? How is Lonergan's Method a1ive to the unique, the original, the absolute element in Christian faith?" 25 Pressing the point, he qru:estions the significance of faith for the ,theological enterprise 1as Lonergan sees it. Does one's commitment to Christ and the Church impinge upon one's approach to the methodological task? EelJy argues that Lonergan is disconcertingly unclear on such matters, and he focuses his line of inquiry even more sharply as he continues: ... there is the possibility of forestalling this whole question by the rather devastating' Why should Christ make any difference to theological method? ' This type of question is quite illuminating. It suggests presuppositions about what is absolute and original in 24 Anthony Kelly, " Is Lonergan's Met hod Adequate to Christian Mystery," The Thomist 39 (1975) : 439. 25 Kelly, p. 440. 258 TERRENCE REYNOLDS Christian experience, and more basically, an implicit approach to theological knowing. The extremes are clear. Either make theological method into a function of faith,. or see faith as any faith, a mere range of data that theology will dispassionately survey in the light of a method designed to ensure such detachment and disinterestedness. At this juncture, because of the irrationality of allowing theology to become either the ideology of a sect or a stance of concerned religious skepticism, all we can demand of a method is that it not be so generalized as to suppress some data for fear of disconcerting its anticipations. 25 The danger of generaliza,tion is thought to exist because Lonergan proposes a re,ligiously neutra,l methodological model and recommends it to Roman Catholic theologians 21 yet demurs .from providing an explicit Christology. For Kelly this is ineXiCUsabJe, since Christian faith demands that !a Christology be included within any methodological study. In its: plwce, Method speaks of the " data " of the human mind. 1and of the universailily discemibfo drivie for self-transcenden!ce. KeiUy asks whether theo<1ogyor the theologian can be correctly understood in terms of such or whetiher alJ theology mus t begin with the " data " of God's gift of Himself, which discloses to man his human possibilities and the nature of his genuine authenticity: 1 1 1 The divine self-transcendence precedes and provokes the human. Is not the self-gift of God the foundation of theology rather than man's self-transcendence in the direction of the divine? Which is more fundamental to theological thinking? Here we have a question that I regard .as basic for a critical reading of Method. 28 Lonergan's aecount of self-transcendence, :in which he treats 1the questions just rnised, is unsatisfactory, as far as Kelly is ieonce:rned. The highest form of self-transcendence in Lonergan' s s1chema is attained through religious conviersion, the dynamic stiarbe of being in love with God. 29 (This is said to attune the theologian especially for his task.) 30 The root cause 2s Kelly, p. 441, 442. Method, p. XU. 2s Kelly, p. 442. 21 Lonergan, 29 Lonergan, Method, p. 104 ff. Method, p. 271. so Lonergan, METHOD AND CONTENT IN THEOLOGY of this conversion is said to be a form of sanctifying grace, attributed to the working of the Holy Spirit. But this rais,es a further problem for Kelly: This would indicate the methodological presupposition that the Holy Spirit is flooding the hearts of all authentically human beings with his love. I have some hesitation at this point. Is this general reality of religious love ... to be immediately interpreted as the Christian reality of love communicated to us by the Spirit of Christ? 31 To support his position on the significance of love, Lonergan extensivcly cites the love texits of the New Tesrbament both in Method 'and, in response to inquiries, in Philosophy of God and Theology. Yet he exo1udes any mention of the person of Christ from his discussion a:n:d allows the impression to be given that the r!Jexts refer to a kind of transcendental piety rather than a specilicrully Christian experience and expression. The res1.Ult,Kel1ly believes, is tihe .suggestion that rthe Holy Spirit s1 Kelly, p. 445. Lonergan's position on the nature of such love is spelled out in Phil<>Bophy of G-od and Theofogy; ·see especially p. 9 and following. He also responds tellingly to a series of questions on pages 17-20. In effect, he relies heavily upon I Timothy 2: 4 which says it is the will of God that all men be saved. From this he discusses the great varieties of human religious experience and the transforming effect of such experiences upon the lives of people everwhere. A particularly interesting exchange follows: Question: "But Paul says in other places that unless the gospel is preached and unless the gospel is believed, all men will not be saved. So God is not providing the salvation of all men in any other way than to send his Son to whom the salvation of the world is owed." Lonergan: "Well, that's another view isn't it? But what Paul has to say about charity, that there isn't salvation without it-and there's lots of evidence of people leading extremely good lives without being Christians." Question (cont.). "But Paul never says charity is enough for salvation; for Paul it is faith in Jesus. Charity is the most important virtue, the most important response." Lonergan: "Well, perhaps according to 'Paul.' It's an exegetical question. I was suggesting a line of thought. I am not doing detailed exegesis ... " This exchange (and what ·precedes it) demonstrates that Lonergan is confronting the issue of religious pluralism which engaged Rahner as well. Their responses do not appear dissimilar. 260 TERRENCE REYNOLDS is the basis of aJH self-trianscendence, an!d that the love which the Christian observes phenomenologica.Myin others is essentially identical to his own Christian religious Both appear to be dynamic states orf being in loV'e with God. Despite ,the fact that Lonergan uses the expression " being in love " to serve different purposes in his hook, the fi11st (in the "Background ") to denote data submitted for interpretation •and the second (in the " Foreground ") to indicaite rthe theofogian's own conversion or principle of interpretation, Kelly cites a lingering ambiguity: ... a confusion begins and persists when both are named " being in love" in this religious sense. . . . What might have been intended as a flexible methodological description seems to be already implicitly Christian, so that the specifically Christian is read into the general phenomenon. It could be that the general phenomenon embraces the specifically Christian, which not only raises a theoretical issue hut makes one ask what the New Testament texts are doing here. I doubt that either is completely the case, but since Lonergan is at pains to build up a framework of creative collaboration, this kind of latent confusion needs to be clarified.... We invite confusion, if not regression, by identifying the general impulse towards self-transcendence with the activity of the Spirit of Christ, especially when this is a basic, though admittedly implicit, methodological position. 32 Lonergan's description of the distinctiveness of Christian conversion ailm fails to satisfy Kelly: Further, religious conversion, if it is Christian, is not just a state of mind and heart. Essential to it is an intersubjective, interpersonal component. Besides the gift of the Spirit within, there is the outward encounter with the Christian witness. That witness testifies that of old in many ways God has spoken to us through the prophets but in the latest age through his Son.33 Ke1ly continues ·to probe for a recognition of the uniqueness of Christian conversion in Lonergan hut fails to find it. Lonergan speaks of the " prior wol1d " of gmce, which enables man to transcend to a state of loving God, and of the " outward word " a2 Kelly, p. 447. sa Lonergan, Method, p. 327. METHOD AND CONTENT IN THEOLOGY 9261 of religious expression, which is historicaHy conditioned but which nevertheless complements the prior or inner wo11d. He asserts that the Gospel serves as a particular objeotification of the implicit reiigiosity of those converted to a love of God. Kelly questions this complementary function of the Gospel: What is the relationship of the Incarnate Word of revelation with the outward word of religious expression? Is it like any other " outward word," the declaration of an inner state? Does the incarnate event of God's love and self-giving not enter more deeply into the understanding of religious love? At this point, at least, Lonergan seems to make no demand that it should, for "the religious leader, the prophet, the Christ, the apostle, the priest, the preacher announces in signs and symbols what is congruent with the gift of love that God works within us." 34 It thus appears that Chris1t, like the prophet and the priest, merely explicitates that which is already experienced inwardly 'by the convert to religion. The impl'essfon is given, says Kelly, that there are two "zones of religiousness," the one prior, inwa.11d, and commonly experienced cross-culturally, and the other outward, historica,l1ly-bound, and serving to express through specific signs and symbols the wctivity already occurring within. But Lonergan nullifies such an interpretation when he speaks rather dramatically of the additional value to be attached to the outwa11d, historierul wo11d of God as it comes to his peopfo: 1 Then not only the inner word that is God's gift of his love but also the outer word of religious trandition comes from God. God's gift of his love is matched by his command to love unrestrictedly . . . . The narrative of religious origins is the narrative of God's encounter with his people .... Finally, the word of religious expression is not just the objectification of the gift of God's love; in a privileged area, it is also a specific meaning, the word of God himself. 35 Here, then, theological inquiry appears to confront unique information. A dis1tinJCt encounter with God himself has taken 34 Kelly, p. 449. 35 Lonergan, Method, p. 119. TERRENCE REYNOLDS expects that Lonergan will adjust his method p1are, and to a1low for the impact of SIUlch data, perhaps the receipt of a form of reV'elation. But Kelly is disappointed once more, for Lonergan at this point reiterates his methodolog]cial pai:ameters, " ... here we come to questions th:at are not methodologiicrulbut questions concerning revielation ,and inspiration, scripture and tradition. . . . To rthe theologians we must leave them." 86 Ke1ly no attempt to veil his distaste for this distinction: Indeed. The methodologist does not feel constrained to leave to the theologians the rather momentous questions concerning the nature of grace, the universality of its occurrence, the significance of world religions; yet he hands back to theologians the specifics of Christian experience as outside the concerns of method .... I think theologians could be pardoned for indulging a little disappointment when they have such " methodological" matters handed hack to them. I think we could have hoped for an understanding of method in theology more responsive to the "subject matter." But the fact remains we have an obscurity where we are most in need of clarification. 87 Ke1ly' s remarks are useful on a variety of leV'els, for they offer several lines of possible inquiry into Lonergan's Method. But the Barthian element in Kelly's critique wiM be left unconsidered, and rthis for two reasons: first, Kelly's article and the co111cerns expressed by DuHes and Wiles are not principally addressed to that 1aspect of Lonergan's Method on that basis, and the normative question of how theological inquiry ought to be conducted is not central to the purpose of this essiay. What is at issue here is the question of how weU Lonergan fulfills his own objectives . .The :f.undamenrbaldilemma in Lonergan is that he seeks to establish a method of investigation in theofogy which is tematicaMy divm1ced from the content of theology. He constmcts his Method so tha,t it might serve what David Tracy has cruled the " revisionist model " for contemporary theologi36 Lonergan, Method, p. 119. sr Kelly, p. 451. METHOD AND CONTENT IN THEOLOGY 263 phifosophical reflection upon cal inquiry. This modei the signmcance of human experience and the meanings present m the Christian fact. 38 Lonergan's merthodological schema seems designed to satisfy the first four of the five theses which Tracy includes as ·components of the model. The first four theses are essentially methodological in chM"acter while the filth describes: the H1eo1ogical task itself: The first thesis defends the proposition that there are two sources for theology, common human experience and language, and Christian texts. The second thesis argues for the necessity of correlating the results of the investigations of these two sources. The third and fourth theses attempt to specify the most helpful methods of investigation employed for studying these two sources. The fifth and final thesis further specifies the final mode of critical correlation of these investigations as an explicitly metaphysical or transcendental one. Upon reaching the final thesis, one should be able to provide a summary of the meaning and truth value of the present model proposed for theology, viz., the philosophical reflection upon common human experience and language, and upon Christian texts. 89 Lonergan appropriately takes great ewe to fulfill the first four of these requirements, while leaving the :bask implied in the fifth thesis to the theologians:. As can be seen in Lonergan's own works on Christian texts and later in his extraordinary efforts towwds a philosophical psychology in Insight, Lonergan appears committed to the satisfaction of Tl'rucy's initial thesis. Neither the texts of the faith nor common human experience can be understood apart from one another, and both must be studied with scientific neutmlirty and rigor. His phenomenological inquiry and criticwl appraisal 0£ the doouments 0£ the Church demonstrate a faithful a.dherenrceto Tracy's theses two through four as well. At this point, one can £nd Jrittle quarrel with Lonergan's methodology, but he ohooses to press onwal'd, launching his investigation into the muddier waters of the telos of human in88 David 89 Tracy, Tracy, Blessed Rage for Order (New York, 1979), p. 43. p. 43. 264 TERRENCE REYNOLDS tentionality. At the ultimate horizon of consciousness, he posits a religious dimension, echoing Tracy, Langdon Gilkey, and others who haV'e similarly directed their attention ito the consideration of such " limit " questions and their answers:. Here he raises the legitimate :religious quesitions which appear at the outer edge of human capacities and understanding. God is phiis a prime :requfoement for success. We 'are aware of the Marxist/Leninist insistency on toeing the line on dogma, for conformity to doctrine. But can the Christian ,aiccept the uniformity of interpretation which effective acbion seems to require? If the Christian liberation theofogian argues that aU Christians cannot be required to aiocept some one program of wction, he or she is limited by the division that plurality brings. On the other LIBERATION THEOLOGY AND POLITICAL VIOL]j]NCE '277 hand, the Christian revotutionary activist should not be told that his program is " unchristian " as judged by some singular, authoritative standard. Of course, the chief complication in saying this lies with a hieI"archical church which includes authorities to formulate doctrine. The Christian who wants to act differently from what the srbructure of such a chureh allows will either: (1) have to find a way to act independently and still stay within that community; or (2) convince the hierarchy of the rightness of the position, mwhich case the church's officiail position becomes his own; or (3) leave the churoh for another less doctrinaJJy rigid Christian community. Does Liberation Necessitate the Use of Violence? Up until this: point we have just :assumed that any effective To liberation of human beings requires the use of deal with this 1assumption, we must first distinguish the inner and the outer human natUl'e. As is known, Christianity often makes this distinction 1and often clrui:ms to offer a new inner freedom. lt talks of being "born again" in the sense of one's inner nature, not the physical human being. Of course, external change is sometimes offered rtoo, but usually it is to be at a later time, not now. It is clear from Jesus' statements, that, no matter what later ohureh interpretations may conc1ude, Jesus' foNowers were enjoined to help the poor, heal the sick, and relieve suffering. No specific instructions are given ,as to how this i:s to be done (which is the basis for ,a Marxist complaint about the lack of action-program) , but still the intent is clear. I argue that any implementation program is the 11esponsibilityof the individual and that no spooifics are enjoined; Christian doctrine says only that some action should be undertaken. This provokes the Christian indiviidua.il crisis: I must do something for human relief, but the burden is mine as to how I choose to do this; no group plan has been laid out. Furthermore, two problems plague Christianity with regard to Marxism/Leninism: (1) The Marxist doctrine of "mate- 278 FREDERICK SONTAG rialism" and (2) the stress on the use of revolutionary violence. The Christian appraisal does not deny that there are material causes of unhappiness and ·enslavement, but still it tends to stress (as Hegel does in opposition to Marx) the spiritual or internal causes; these must he addressed first, and they may not necessarily have been materially determined (they may he of some other). How, then, one attacks the material/economic/political situation is not specified. It may be to work as Mother Teresa works, simply caring for the suffering individually. But it might also involve a political/material program. But whatever may be proposed it should not be required of all hy reason of their Christian belief. The universalism and uniformity of doctrine generally demanded by Marxism/Leninism as a condition for success should not be demanded in Christian terms. Some church groups have attempted to impose uniformity of doctrine, but while this may he demanded of the members of a particular group, no interpretation can be required of all Christians. Uniformity of action on a" Christian" basis is e:xduded from the beginning. All this does not bode well for a " Christian " revolution and certainly it makes the use of violence to aichieve liberation a matter of great debate. Cornell West With some of these issues and proposals in Inind, let us look at some recent proponents of Liberation Theology in a Christian setting and use these as a testing ground for our thesis. We begin with a recent (and Inild) statement, Cornell West's, Prophesy Deliverance: An Afro-American Revolutionary Christianity. 2 West profeS1Ses to " an abiding allegiance to progressive Marxist social analysis ·and political praxis." 3 But it is hard to understand how his Christianity meshes with Marxism, since .the latter involves an allegiance to material/economic 1 2 Cornell West, Prophesy Deliverance: an A.fro-American Revolutionary Christianity (Philadelphia: The Westminster Press, 1982). a Ibid., p. 10. LIBERATION THEOLOGY .AND POLITIC.AL VIOLENCE 279 determinism and a commitment to political revolution, using violence as necessary. Marx stresses inevitable class strife and the necessity to use force to break these bonds. West describes "the Christian people" as "the self-realization of individuality within the community." 4 That this involves in principle a" this-worldly" liberation as well as otherwor1dly salvation is hard to deny. But the issue is: what does " this-wor1dly " liberation mean and what sort of force is to be used to achieve it? Are the f orees that bind us such that only violence and political revolution can break them? West notes that Marxism and Christianity " share a similar moral impulse." 5 This is quite true, and it often pits them against each other as rivals . But the issue is the analysis of which " binding structures " must be attacked and which means must be used. Otherwise platitudes unite us all. West then goes on to say that the two basic challenges confronting Afro-Americans are "self-image and self-determination." 6 Again, it is hard to argue with this, but what if violence and revolution are necessary to achieve self-determination? He urges a" dialogical encounter" between Afro-American Christian thought and progressive Marxist social analysis. 1 Again, dialogue is harmless enough, but what if the good Marxist argues for the necessity of violence, revolution, and the extermination of opponents who block the revolution? West proceeds to an histo:vcial aiccount of the Afro-American experience, but this still skirts the issue of " what is to be done " and how. Even if as West says "the alliance of prophetic Christianity and progressive Marxism provides a fast human hope for mankind," 8 the issue at stake still remains: the role of violence in its reaJiziation, a question he does not address. Fiurthermore, rther:e surely is no one agreed definition of " prophetic Christianity" which aJl Christians can support. It is hard to see 4lbid., p. 16. 5 Ibid. 1 Ibid., e Ibid., p. 80. 8 Ibid., p. 83. p. 95. 280 FREDERICK SONTAG how 1a "lasit human hope" can rest on such a divided and splintered foundation; Marxist knows this to be a formul a for political-social inaction. We get involved in arguing about whait program a Christian ought to foHow rather than uniting What is the evidence that " all. ito ruchieve transformation. Christians " have or ever can be unit ed on one One of West's principles that seems 1ocucial to his theology is: "God sides 'wth the oppressed and 1aots on their behalt" 9 Christian Hterature iClertainly is fuH of concern for the " oppressed," but we must he careful to determine what an author means by " oppressed" and what he says the cimses of the oppression are. It cannot be argued that alil. Christians use (or ought to use) "oppressed" as a Marxist would. But more importantly, among both Jews 1and Christians God has been said to "act." Tl'ue, brut do the actions God has en:dorsed include revolution and violence? That would be hard to establish, particufa11ly since God's incarnation in Jesus lef1t the Roman pire untouched: Jesus was crucified, and the Jews were left ,subjugated. West asknowledges that " one is hard put fo find a sketch of what liberation would aotualJy mean in the everydray lives of Mack people." :i.o But even if there are any concerns that can he shared with Marxism, even these wilil fade insignificance unless a poHticalfsocfal 1action program can he agreed upon an:d particulady unless the use of or the rejection of viio1ence mn be 1agreed upon. West suggests that " human liberation occurs only when people participate substantively in the decision-making proeess in the major institutions which libemte their lives." 11 But this still leaves untouched the major and decisive issue of how this is ;to be achieved and whether any Christian program can become :identical with a Mar:xiistfo:rmu1a. West claims that Marxism l'eoognizes "the posiitive liberating aspects of popular (luiliture and religion." i 2 But there is a 1 1a 1 1 9 Ibid., 10 Ibid., p. 106. p. 11 l. 11 Ibid., 12 Ibid., p. 112. p. ll 7. LIBERATION THEOLOGY AND POLITICAL VIOLENCE 281 difference between Christianity and Marxism here that is ci311. The Marxist sees most religion ·as haviing a subjugating e:ffoot, and his notion of what is needed to overeome human alienation inv:olV'es more force. Given this difference, little can be held in common when it comes to practical implementagy of the act of faith seems closer to the actuality of lived human experienoe than rationalist approa.ches. :Bor Rousseilot. neither .the concept nor the impressed 'Species couM oocount for the objectivity of knowledge. Rather, the mind'!s connatum[ love for God, its attitude of connatural sympathy for :the Fi:Iist Truth, is required for the mind to make obj ootive judgments. For Rousselot the inte1leot was the facu\Lty of the real because it was the £aou1ty of the divine. For Marechal it was the dynamism of the mind rather than the representative content of the concepts which grounds the concepts in reality. In every jrudgment the mind aidways signifies more than :ist can represent in its ioolllOepts. God is known 1through the mteHigibility of objects affirmed in judgments, but significant intelligibility can oniy he represented in analogous form through inadequate con-0epts. For MarOOhalthe key Jt.o the analogy of being was metaphysica[ affirmation, and saw that no objoot could be .affirmed if the Infinite Being, the term of the mind's dynamism, is denied. The wrudition epitomiZled by Rousselot and Marechal was carried on by their Jesuit cohleagues. The relativization of roncep'buail knowledge, suspicion of an Aristotelian science of history, ,emphasis on the ract of insight ,and upon Marechal's anail1 GERALD MC COOL AND THOMISM 313 ysis of the judgment ito ground the truths of theology and metaphysics-alil these made Transcendental Thomism a truly new approach toward history and p1urrulism in both theology and philosophy. While this was happening, Jacques Maritain under the inspimtion of Thomas's commentators Cajeta.n and John of St. 'llhomas was working out his hril.Jiant synthesis and applying St. 'llhomas's principles to science, al't, morals, oulture, and politics. But because Maritain's Thomism was based on an Aristotelian philosophy and theology, and Rousselot had rejected the possibility of an Aristotelian s1cience mediating the Chmoh's historiical revelation, 'lliiansicendental Thomism and Marifain's Thomism wel"e incompatible. In McCool's judgment Mairitain's writings represent neoThomism's most successful a.ttempt to achieve the goal of Aeterni Patris and to integrate contempomry culture through the wisdom of 'I\homas. Grounding his metaphysics on an eiidetiic intilltion of being, Maritain thought that the transcendell!ta.I method was arbitrary and doomed to error. In his philosophy of person Maribain's opposition to Cartesianism is very pronounced. This philosophy of person was fed by his own inner expecience and sympathetic knowledge of contemporary .art, literature, and euLture; in turn it became the foundation on which his aesthetics and political philosophy rest. (McCool thinks that Maritain's most lasting contribution is in his phiilosophizing about a,rt.) Marit ain's Integral Humanism is clear evidence that traditional Thomism could respond to contemporary culture. McCool's chief criticism of Maritain concerns the tension between experience 1and the framework he. took ovell.· from Caj:eitan. For Maritain the valid1ty of metaphysics and the possibility of a metaphysicai interpretation of ihuman knowledge rests uJtimateJy on the concept. For an his openness :to ou1ture and his deep sensitivity ,to cultural diversity and historiic1a1ldeviefopment, Maritain opted for a very different approach from Roussefort and Marechal. 1 314 ROBERT E. LAUDER Gi1son came to see that medieva.l philosophy was contained in medieval theology. It was the kuitful contact between Greek metaphysics and Christian revelation in the theology of the medieva1 Doctors which reaUy pmduced the uniqueness, originality, and powm" of philosophy. For Gilson, Christian philosophy is !a speciail way of doing philosophy. McCooJ. underlines the significance of this: This means,. of course, that Gilson's interpcretation of St. Thomas' Christian philosophy was in open opposition to the Thomistic philosophy which had come into being in the seventeenth-century Catholic schools and whose influence could still be felt in contemporary Thomism. The seventeenth-century Thomists had extracted their 'theses ' from both St. Thomas' theological works and his commentaries on Aristotle, Gilson maintained, because they had, for all practical purposes, equated the philosophy of St. Thomas with the philosophy of Aristotle. Then they compounded their error when they arranged these Aristotelian-Thomistic ' theses' in the ascending philosophical order which St. Thomas himself had never used. By doing that, Gilson complained, they had treated the Christian philosophy of St. Thomas as though it were simply one more ' separated ' philosophy on the model of the modern rationalist systems. Such an unwarranted transposition of St. Thomas' philosophy to the order of a ' pure' philosophywhich was content simply to avoid contradicting the theology it systematically ignored-did violence to the essential nature of the Angelic Doctor's thought. (pp. 169-170) Gilson sihowed rthat there was no rcommon 1sys1tem of Scholastic thought in the MiddJe Ages; there was rather a radical phHosophical pluralism. Augustine, Duns Scotus, Bonaventure, and Thomas had different philosophies. Though Augustine lea;rneid more from rthe " I am Who am " of Exodus than he did from Plotinus, the gl'ewt Churrch Father was sWl sufficiently influenced by Plotinus not to think of being in tieorms of existence. Thooe were seveml deficiencies in Augustine's Plotinian philosophy whieh were not present in Thomas's metaphysics: it diid not preserve the essential unity of rthe human composite, it did not gmn:t the human body proper dignity, !it deprived GERALD MC COOL AND THOMISM 315 finite a.gents of the independence they deserve as true secondary causes, and its theory of illumination seems an invitation :to skepticism. Thomas took the same divine statement from Exodus hut went fmther than Augustine. Echoing Gilson, McCool writes that having read the passage from Exodus, Thomas learned the ' sublime truth ' it contains. The name of God who made the world is 'I am Who am'. Aquinas, however, did not conclude that to be meant to be an essence. On the contrary, Thomas concluded that if God's name is ' I am Who am,' God must be the pure act of existence. That the highest form of being is pure act he already knew from Aristotle, for the pure act of self-thinking thought, the prime mover, is Aristotle's supreme divinity. But that the pure act of being must be a pure unlimited act of existence was his own discovery. After Thomas had made it under the inspiration of Exodus, to be no longer meant to be an essence or a form. To be meant to exist. (p. 182) B-eoause of his insight into the act of existence, Thoma.s's metaphysics was radically different from Augusitine's metaphysics and even more raidicaUy di:ffeTent from Aris:totle's, with its emphasis on substance. Gilson stressed that Aristotle's selfthinking thought could not be concehned as an wet which, instead of making a thing to be wha.t it is, rnafues a thing to exist. As McCool insists, Thomism is neither Platonic essen,tialism nor Aristotelian substantia1ism and cannot he reduced to any other metaphysics. When the human knower affirms " it is " of any being given in sense experience, he grasps an intelligibility thait is not the same as the intenigibility of :form or essence. Gilson' s stu1dy reveaJed thrut cailling iattention to the inte1lligibiility of existence is Thomas's unique contribution to the history of philosophy. G:Hson's research revealed :bhat Thomistic commentators, such as Cajetan, did not really understand. Thomrus's aet of existence. Furthermol'e, neither the Thomas of Roussefot nor of Marechal nor of Maritain was the aJuthentic Thomas, acco:vding to Gi,lson. Rousselot and Marechal were making the 1 316 ROBERT E. LAUDER Cartesian mistake of going from thought to being, and Maritain, relying on Cajetan and John of SL Thomas, did not present Thomas's metaphy,sics authentiic1alJy, even in his master work, The Degrees of Knowing. McCool demonstrates what Gilson had done, even if unwittingly, to Aeterni Patris: In reality, therefore, Gilson could not accept the validity of the program for Neo-Scholasticism's development set forth in Aeterni Patris. He always referred to the encyclical in tones of agreement and high praise. Yet, according to his own criteria, none of the forms of Thomism which the encyclical inspired, whether they took their inspiration from Suarez or the great Dominican commentators, can be called authentic Thomism. Gilson was able to agree with Aeterni Patris because he understood the encyclical to be saying what in fact it never says: that to be a Thomist is to adhere with absolute fidelity to the way of philosophizing St. Thomas employed in his theological works. (p. 196) In the world of theology in the 1940s a p1urailism was developing, and works by two French theofogians also contributed ito the undermining of neo-Thomism. Henri Bouillard and Henri De Lubac mad e clear that St. Thomas had no doctrine of man existing in a state of pure nature. Bouillard showed that manuails gav;e the impression that theology was changeless, eolllcerned with timeless problems, whereas the troth is that theology lives iin history; tiheologica1l meaning changes with the passage of time. In explaining Bouilla11d and De Luhaic's contribution to the dismantling of neo-'I1homism's mosaic, McCool summarizes a number of important points they made. The affirmations of faith can never be separ1ruted from the cont:ingent and time-condit:ioned notions needed to e:k"Press them, hut this does not mean that truth is affirmations of the faith are :relative. The ruhsolute in spite of the relativity of the notions in which they are exp11essed. The two F11ench theologians made it clear that the scholastic theology of gmcie 1aind natme whiJCh Aeterni Patris defends is not the theology of either the Fathers or the medieval Doctol's. In effect ti.hey underout some of the strong1 GERALD MC COOL AND THOMISM 317 est arguments that the Neo-Scholastics ha