A THOMISTIC ANALYSIS OF THE GAIA HYPOTHESIS: HOW NEW IS THIS NEW LOOK AT LIFE ON EARTH? LAURA LANDEN, W: 0.P. Providence College Providence, Rhode Island HA T IS THE Gaia hypothesis? A recent article in Time magazine mentions the first major scientific conerence on Gaia, sponsored by the American Geophysical Union in 1988.1 The scientists ended their meeting by giving James Lovelock an exuberant standing ovation. Lovelock' s book Gaia: A New Look at Life on Earth, first published in 1979, is now in its second edition. 2 James E. Lovelock, British atmospheric chemist, introduced the Gaia hypothesis in 1975. This hypothesis emerged from his comparison of the chemical composition of Earth's atmosphere with the atmospheres of Venus and Mars. He found the contrast striking: Earth's atmosphere, hospitable to life, is markedly unlike the atmospheres of her two closest neighbors, Venus and Mars, both considered lifeless. Unsatisfied with mere chance as an explanation of this difference, Lovelock attributed a kind of active influence on the atmosphere by the whole of living organisms (called the biosphere) to effect conditions favorable for life. The following is taken from Lovelock's initial article on Gaia in 1975 : 1 Eugene Linden, "How the Earth Maintains Life," Time, November 13, 1989, p. 114. 2 See James E. Lovelock, Gaia: A New Look at Life on Earth (New York: Oxford University Press, 1987). Lovelock has published more recent work on Gaia. See James E. Lovelock, The Ages of Gaia: A Biography of Our Living Earth (New York: Bantam Books, 1990). 1 2 LAURA LANDEN, O.P. It appeared to us that the Earth's biosphere is able to control at least the temperature of the Earth's surface and the composition of the atmosphere. Prima facie, the atmosphere looked like a contrivance put together co-operatively by the totality of living systems to carry out certain necessary control functions. This led to the formulation of the proposition that living matter, the air, the oceans, the land surface were parts of a giant system which was able to control temperature, the composition of the air and sea, the pH of the soil and so on as to be optimum for survival of the biosphere. The system seemed to exhibit the behaviour of a single organism, even a living creature. One having such formidable powers deserved a name to match it; William Golding, the novelist, suggested Gaia-the name given by the ancient Greeks to their Earth goddess.• In this paper I present some of the factual evidence for the Gaia hypothesis and identify the underlying concepts of this position. Next, I note some reasons the hypothesis has encountered objections within the scientific community. Finally, I look to Aristotle and to Thomas Aquinas, as commentator, for insight as to how these apparent contrasts might find resolution. The factual evidence for Lovelock's claim lies in known measurements about the atmospheres of Venus, Earth, and Mars. In addition, he was able to construct a mathematical model of an abiological Earth. The following comparisons are of interest : GASES. PLANETS Venus Lifeless Earth Mars Actual Earth Carbon Dioxide 96.5% 98% 95% 0.03% Nitrogen 3.5% 1.9% 2.7% 79% Oxygen trace 0.0% 0.13% 21% Surface Temp °C 459 240to 340 -53 13 a James E. Lovelock and Sidney Epton, "The Quest for Gaia," New Scientist 65 (1975) : 304. 'Table taken from Lovelock, Ages, p. 9. GAIA HYPOTHESIS: A THOMIST ANALYSIS 3 Carbon dioxide, one of the " greenhouse " gases, is related to surface temperature. Nitrogen and oxygen, both highly reactive gases, are essential to life as we know it. When he first proposed the Gaia hypothesis, Lovelock himself may not have been aware of the ancient roots of the concept of earth, even the universe, as a living organism. J. Donald Hughes has traced this ancient view among the Greeks and Romans, noting the following progression : First, the Earth is the oldest goddess, supporter and nurturer of her children, human and non-human, and therefore entitled to respect and worship .... Second, the Earth is a living being of whom humans are only part. Right relationship with the Earth means that the total organism is in good health .... Third, Earth is seen as responsive to human care or the lack of it, giving rich returns to those who treat her well and punishing those who are lazy or who weary her by trying to wrest from her what she is not ready to give.... 5 This concept of a living Earth would understandably meet some resistance among scientists-and among others, as well. One major obstacle to the acceptance of Gaia by scientists is the holistic nature of the hypothesis, 6 and even Lovelock has backed away from this extreme. The Gaia hypothesis implies that both the composition of all the reactive gases as well as the temperature of the lower atmosphere have remained relatively constant over aeons in spite of many external perturbations. 7 Such constancy suggests a controlling mechanism of some sort, which the Gaia hypothesis in its early stages failed to describe. A feedback mechanism explaining a]. Donald Hughes, "Gaia: An Ancient View of our Planet," Ecologist 13 (1983) : 60. • " It is rather the holistic nature of the Gaia hypothesis, with the idea that the planet is greater than the sum of its parts, that sticks in the throats of mainstream scientists " (Omar Sattaur, " Cuckoo in the Nest," New Scientist, December 1987, p. 17). 1 See Dorion Sagan and Lynn Margulis, " The Gaian Perspective of Ecolou," Ecologist 13 (1983) :160. 4 LAURA LANDEN, O.P. the interactions between the biosphere and the environment was needed. Further study and some creative modeling filled in this gap. Atmospheric composition is now better understood, and Lovelock himself devised a mathematical model, called Daisy World, to show how planetary surface temperature might be modulated. Lynn Margulis, a microbiologist at the University of Massachusetts, Amherst, and a major proponent of Gaia, writes: Atmospheric regulation can be attributed to the combined metabolic and growth activities of organisms, especially microorganisms with their capabilities of transforming the nitrogen, sulphur and carboncontaining gases of the atmosphere. Prior to Lovelock's daisy model it was suggested that whatever controlled atmospheric methane concentration would provide a mechanism by which the stability of atmospheric temperature could be maintained. In addition ... [other researchers] showed in a quantative [sic] model that evapotranspiration from forests determined the concentration of water vapour in the atmosphere and thus certain corelated [sic] climatic features. 8 Lovelock proposed his Daisy World model as a cybernetic model, a system that can control itself and maintain specified variables constant in spite of perturbing influences. The model consists of two colors of daisies, dark and light, together with some herbivores. Life is possible within a range of 5 to 40°C, with the optimum being 20°C. The dark daisies absorb solar radiation, thus having a cooling effect on the atmosphere close to the planet's surface, whereas the light daisies reflect radiation, having a warming effect. Variations in temperature and in solar energy output were shown to affect the relative abundance of the various species of daisies. The net effect was a stabilizing of Earth's surface temperature. As Margulis writes: Daisy World is only a model. But even with its oversimplification the Daisy World model shows quite clearly that thermal [stability] of the biosphere is not something too mysterious to have a mechanism. . . . The radical insight delivered by Daisy World is that global [stability] is in principle possible without the introduction of any but well known tenets of biology. The gaian system does not have to plan in advance or be foresighted in any way in order to show [ stabilizs Sagan and Margulis, " Gaian Perspective," p. 161. GAIA HYPOTHESIS: A THOMIST ANALYSIS 5 ing] tendencies. A biological system acting cybernetically gives the impression of teleology; if only the results and not the feedback processes were stated it would look as if the organisms had conspired to insure their own survival.9 This statement reflects indirectly some of the opposition to Gaia raised by some scientists. How can organisms act harmoniously to achieve a common end? How can the biosphere be an organism itself if it has no organic structure of its own and if it does not reproduce? In the preface to the second edition of his book, Lovelock notes his surprise at the reactions Gaia initially faced.10 Apart from maintaining that Earth is alive, the Gaia hypothesis contrasts in other ways with some cherished scientific convictions. Let us examine these further. Darwinian evolution maintains that conditions of even a fairly stable environment affect a living organism. Pressure is on the organism from the environment : adapt or die. Natural selection as the mechanism of evolution rests on the assumption that species, even individuals, compete for limited resources; those individuals with the most suitable adaptations will be successful in transmitting their genes to the next generation. Purposeful action, or teleolo_gy, is thought to be unnecessary. 11 Sagan and Margulis, "Gaian Perspective," p. 164. have taken a strange turn in recent years ; almost the full circle from Galileo's famous struggle with the theological establishment. It is the scientific establishment that now forbids heresy. I had a faint hope that Gaia might be denounced from the pulpit; instead I was asked to deliver a sermon on Gaia at the Cathedral of St. John the Divine in New York. By contrast Gaia was condemned as teleological by my peers and the journals, Nature and Science, would not publish papers on the subject. No satisfactory reasons for rejection were given; it was as if the establishment, like the theological establishment of Galileo's time, could no longer tolerate radical or eccentric notions. It would have made much more sense if Gaia had been rejected on the grounds that there was no novelty in it; that it had all been said before" (Lovelock, Gaia, pp. vii-viii). For more recent sympathetic criticism of Lovelock's work within the scientific community, see Lawrence E. Joseph, Gaia: The Growth of an Idea (New York : St. Martin's Press, 1990) . 11 Consider the following: " Adaptation, as measured by evolutionary success, consists of a greater ecological-physiological efficiency of an individual 9 1 0 " Things 6 LAURA LANDEN, O.P. The Gaia hypothesis appears to contradict this viewpoint in several ways. Gaia presents the biosphere as active and altruistic: species act harmoniously to effect environmental conditions favorable for life. Lovelock claims Daisy World answers some of the objections: I made a model of a planet with a simple ecosystem of white and black daisies and herbivores to graze them. This theoretical world kept a constant comfortable climate over a wide range of heat fluxes from the star that warmed it. No foresight or planning was needed, only the unconscious growth and competition of the species leading to their natural selection as Darwin described it.12 Lovelock presents natural selection as a mechanism that yields the kind of apparently altruistic stability that Gaia speaks of. Does this suffice to address some of the more profound conceptual discrepancies between the Gaia hypothesis and Darwinian evolution? The answer will be clear later. Ecologists and environmentalists might seem the most likely group to be favorably disposed to the Gaia hypothesis. Yet a certain loss of interest soon follows upon realizing some of the implications. Consider the following comments by Charles J. Hughes: Dr. Lovelock proposes that life on Earth is not only a response to and controlled by physical conditions but also modifies and controls its own environment! . . . Dr. Lovelock in collaboration with Dr. Lynn Margulis defines Gaia as follows: " We have since defined Gaia as a complex entity involving the Earth's biosphere, atmosphere, oceans, and soil; the totality constituting a feedback or cybernetic system which seeks an optimal physical and chemical environment for life on this planet." than is achieved by most other members of the population or at least by the average. . . . There is a struggle for existence not only among individuals of the same species, but sometimes also among individuals of different species. If such competition leads to the extinction of one of the species, this process is referred to as species selection" (Ernst Mayr, Toward a New Philosophy of Biology: Observations of an Evolutionist [Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1981], p. 146). Mayr is acknowledged as one of the foremost experts on Darwinian evolution today. 11 Lovelock, Gaia, p. ix. GAIA HYPOTHESIS: A THOMIST ANALYSIS 7 This notion I find hard to swallow. It is the expression of sentient feedback as a mechanism that gives me difficulty. Can the great system really be dissected to reveal a causative or controlling agent? Who is to presume to judge, given the known complexities of the many equilibria involved? Is cybernetic the right term-communication between the biosphere and other spheres, yes, but control? Is Dr. Lovelock making too extravagant a claim that can in turn lead all too readily, as we shall see, to unwarranted complacency? 13 Hughes identifies three corollaries of the Gaia hypothesis, reacting as a scientist to each, and summarizes his own reaction to the Gaia hypothesis as follows : My conclusion is simply this. Given that Homo sapiens has somehow, very suddenly, arrived at such a position of dominance in numbers, intellect, consciousness, purposiveness, and technology on planet Earth and has been granted some insight into Gaia (call Gaia God's handiwork if you will), should we not do our utmost to preserve Gaia as we are privileged to see Her and form a living and breathing part of Her today? 14 To summarize, the Gaia hypothesis raises some questions : Is Earth alive? Can the biosphere act as a whole? Might organisms act harmoniously? The name ' Gaia ' has ancient roots. Some insight into these questions, as well as the possibility of a self-regulating natural mechanism, may be found in other ancient sources. I draw upon the Aristotelian tradition for help in answering three questions about Gaia: ( 1) Need we hold that Earth is alive? (2) What sort of whole might the biosphere be, and what constitutes its unity? ( 3) Can nature, especially among the non-living, be a source of motion or activity? In other words, is a self-regulating mechanism involving the nonliving a reasonable concept? In defining nature, Aristotle keeps two distinctions in mind. First, natural things are distinct from artifacts, just as natural motion is distinct from artificial, or violent, motion. Second, nature must be defined so as to include the nonliving as well as the u Charles J. Hughes, "Gaia: A Natural Scientist's Ethic for the Future," Ecologist 15 (1985) :93. u Charles Hughes, " Gaia," p. 94. 8 LAURA LANDEN, O.P. living. Too broad a definition destroys the first distinction; too narrow a definition destroys the second. Artificial things and natural things differ in that the latter have within themselves a principle of their own motion and rest, whereas the former do not. Aristotle contrasts a bed as an artificial thing with the wood from which it is made as a natural thing. The bed, if planted, will not generate another bed; a seed, however, will generate a tree. As an artifact the bed is changed from without by the carpenter who made it and thus lacks an intrinsic principle of change. An acorn, on the other hand, generates a sprout from within. Despite this care to draw clear distinctions, other influences have entered the Aristotelian tradition through commentators. One such influence is the N eoplatonic concept of nature as an absolute intrinsic force (vis insita rebus). This concept of nature as a fixed power or force implanted in things (vis insita rebus), is an' interpretation' neither justified nor necessary.15 The downward motion of a falling stone is natural, as natural, in fact, as the growth of a plant or the sense perception of an animal. The falling of a stone, however, is not the motion of a living thing. In contrast with a nonliving thing, a living thing has a soul, characterized by Aristotle as the source or origin of self-movement. Even though the stone is nonliving, its downward motion is different from the motion it would have if thrown i 5 The concept of nature as an absolute intrinsic force (vis insita rebus) is a Neoplatonic one. One commentator who so interprets Aristotle's definition of nature is John Philoponus. " Natura est quaedam vita sive vis quae per corpora diffunditur, eorum formatrix et gubernatrix, principium motus et quietis in eo cui inest per se primo et non secundum accidens" (John Philoponus, in Aristoteles: Physicorum libri quatuor, cum Ioannis Grammatici cognomento Philoponi commentarius [Venice: Hieronymus Scotus, 1558], p. 67, col. b. The first translation of Philoponus's commentary into Latin was not published until 1539. However, Avicenna's commentary on the Physics mentions an unnamed predecessor who emends Aristotle's definition of motion as a power diffused through bodies. This predecessor could be Philoponus. For this information concerning Philoponus the author is indebted to William A. Wallace, Prelude to Galileo: Essays on Medieval and Sixteenth-Century Sources of Galileo's Thought, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, no. 6Z (Boston: D. Reidel Publishing Co., 1981). GAIA HYPOTHESIS: A THOMIST ANALYSIS 9 upward. The di:fference lies in this : the stone, if free to fall, will move downward by itself but must be thrown upward by some extrinsic agent. The natural downward motion of the stone, therefore, proceeds from an intrinsic principle, even though the stone is clearly not alive. Taking account of these distinctions, Aristotle defines nature as follows: Nature is a principle or cause of being moved or being at rest in that to which it belongs primarily, per se, and not per accidens.16 In his commentary, Thomas Aquinas observes that nature is called a ' principle ' to emphasize that it is something relative in the thing and not some absolute or fixed factor. He illustrates his point by noting that ' nature ' derives from the word for " being born"; something which is born was first attached to its generator, such as a plant or animal. Nature is thus relative to each species. What is natural behavior for a bear, for instance, is not natural for a human being, and vice versa. Because of this relational characteristic, nature is not correctly thought to be some absolute, intrinsic force or power within the natural thing. As Aquinas notes : Thus, they are to be laughed at who, wishing to correct Aristotle's definition, tried to define nature by something absolute, saying that nature is a force implanted in things [vis insita re-bus], or something of the sort.17 Aquinas remarks that although the existence of nature is selfevident, since natural things are evident to sense, the nature of any given thing is not nearly so apparent. Yet, because nature is an intrinsic principle of natural things, it must correspond to the intrinsic principles of matter and form. Matter can, indeed, be 1 s " hOs ouses tes phuseos arkhes tinos kai aitias tou kineisthai kai eremein en hOi huparkhei protos kath' hayto kai me kata sumbebekos" (Aristotle, Physics, in Opera, vol. 1, ed. Immanuel Bekker [Berlin: George Reimer, 1831], 2. 1. 192b21-23). 17 Thomas Aquinas, In octos libros Physicorum Aristotelis expositio, ed. P. M. Maggiolo (Rome: Marietti, 1965), 2. 1. 148, henceforth referred to as On the Physics. All translations are my own. 10 LAURA LANDEN, O.P. considered part of the nature of a thing insofar as it enters into the constitution of the substance of each natural thing. The nature (ratio) of a thing is captured in its definition. Nature ( natura) can thus refer to this defining aspect of the thing, its form, as Aquinas observes: In another way nature is called the form or species, which is [said] according to the defining notion, that is, from which the notion [ratio] of the thing is constituted.18 A single substance, in the Aristotelian sense, can have a nature and properly so. A natural substance is a composite of matter and substantial form. But can a composite whole, such as the biosphere, have a nature? To answer this requires some consideration of the sense in which the biosphere is a whole. Thomas contrasts a natural whole, such as an animal, with an accidental whole, ·such as a house. The form of a house, unlike the soul, does not give being and species to both the whole and its parts. Nor is it one simply, but only by aggregation. 19 This comparison of an animal with a house is instructive. An animal is a natural whole, whereas a house is a composite whole. An animal has but one intrinsic substantial form. In contrast, a house has many forms, some of which are extrinsic, such as the exemplar in the mind of the builder. The animal has unity per se, the house only per accidens. The animal whole and its parts receive their being and species from the one substantial form of the soul. The whole of the house is found only in the whole; the form of each part of the house, such as the foundation and walls, is found only in that part. Therefore, in an artificial whole, the whole and its parts do not receive their being and species from one substantial form. Upon the death of an animal, the bodily parts are such only equivocally. The eye, for example, is truly an eye only in the living body. Should a house be razed, leaving the foundation, that part of the house may be called a foundation in 1s Thomas Aquinas, On the Physics, 2. 2. 151. Emphasis in the original. Thomas Aquinas, Quaestio disputata de anima, in Quaestiones disputatae, vol. 2, ed. P. M. Calacaterra, et al. (Rome: Marietti, 1965), 1. 10. 19 See ad 16. GAIA HYPOTHESIS: A THOMIST ANALYSIS 11 the same manner as when the house was standing. We understand that a new house could easJly be built upon the old foundation. The eye of a dead animal, however, cannot become a functional part of another animal's body. Thomas provides an interesting breakdown of relationships of whole to parts in his commentary on Aristotle's Metaphysics. He first distinguishes two ways in which one thing may go to make up another : as a part or as an essence, such as a whole, composite, or species. (This is taken directly from Aristotle's text. 20 ) When something is a substance, the corresponding form is the species of the thing. This holds true of a simple whole, such as an animal, which has a substantial form and can be alive. When several things join to form one, a unity may be formed in one of three ways: by order, by contact, or by mixture. When the parts are joined by order only-as people in an army or houses in a city-the form is the corresponding whole, to which the name ' army ' or 'city ' is applied. (We might add that in nature a forest is just such a whole.21 ) Sometimes there exists not only order but also contact and joining of the parts, as with a house. Then the composite serves as the form. In the case of mixture an alteration of the components also obtains. The mixture itself, which is in some way a composition of species, has a substantial form of its own. Unity in an integral whole comes from one principle: the form, as in a mixed body; the composition, as in a house; or the order, as with speech (ordered syllables) or an army. In sum, Aquinas considers a natural substance to be one simply. The unity of such a substance comes from its substantial form. A whole composed of several substances, such as the biosphere, has unity from the order which constitutes it as a whole, as with an army or a city (or perhaps a forest). Here unity :20 See Thomas Aquinas, In duodecim libros Metaphysicorum Aristotelis expositio, ed. M.-R. Cathala (Rome: Marietti, 1964), 5. 3. 779. For Aristotle, see Metaphysics in Opera, vol. 2, 5. 3. 1013b21-23. 2 1 A forest is formed by the closing of the tree canopy. This affects the growth patterns of the individual trees, the amount of light reaching the ground, and hence the type of lower vegetation which can thrive. 12 LAURA LANDEN, O.P. derives from order among the parts. Its form is the form of the corresponding whole. What name for the biosphere as such a whole? Perhaps-Gaia. The Gaia hypothesis claims more than that the biosphere may be considered as a whole. It claims that this biosphere acts as a whole to effect conditions in the environment favorable to life. In what sense might Aristotle and Aquinas view a natural but nonliving thing as exercising efficient causality? Thomas accepts Aristotle's four-fold division of causes: matter, form, agent, and end. He also agrees with Aristotle that an efficient cause in the proper sense must be distinct from its effect. Aristotle proves that the principle, " whatever is moved is moved by something," is true in general. 22 Even though his discussion is of local motion, he establishes principles applicable to all changes. Mover and moved are found in pairs, hence a division of one corresponds to a division of the other. Aristotle notes three pairs of means by which things are moved : ( 1) per accidens or per se, (2) by themselves or by another, and (3) naturally or not naturally. Thomas observes that things moved per accidens " are not so much moved as said to be moved when other things are moved." 23 Self-movement and natural movement are examples of things being moved per se. These two types are not mutually exclusive, for anything moved naturally must have within itself the source of its motion. (Anything moved unnaturally must have an external source of its motion.) We may not conclude from this that things moved naturally correspond to the living. Aristotle is careful to use ' source ' (ark he), not ' cause ' ( aitia), in describing things moved naturally. The living and the nonliving, however, may be identified as things moved by themselves and things moved by another. Aristotle then proves within each case that everything moved is in fact moved by another. He easily disposes of things moved unnaturally, or by compulsion, since they are clearly moved by another. 22 See Aristotle, Physics, 7. 2s Thomas Aquinas, On the Physics 8. 4. 1024. GAIA HYPOTHESIS: A THOMIST ANALYSIS 13 The living move themselves. Yet Aristotle claims in the Physics that they also are unquestionably moved by another. This is accomplished by an organic body in which one part, remaining unmoved, may move the whole. The most serious difficulty arises in discovering the source of motion in the nonliving, such as heavy bodies. Heavy bodies do not move themselves, Aristotle claims, because they are nonliving and they are homogeneous in composition. I maintain that the biosphere, though a whole, is not living. The biosphere derives its unity from order, but it is not a substance, that is, it does not have a substantial form, and hence it has no soul. Does such a conclusion entail that this unique sort of whole is incapable of a kind of self-regulatory motion? Further consideration of the way in which Aristotle approaches natural motion in the nonliving will be helpfttl in answering this question. Aristotle turns his attention to movers, that is, to the efficient causes of motion. He attempts to ascertain the cause of the natural motion of the elements. He notes that fire and earth are moved naturally when their proper potentialities are actualized.u Aquinas enlarges Aristotle's remark as follows : Therefore, since something in potency is naturally moved by another in act, and nothing is in potency and in act in the same respect, it follows that neither fire nor earth nor anything else is moved by itself, but by another. Fire and earth are moved ... naturally when they are moved to their proper acts, to which they are in potency according to their proper nature. 25 From this we conclude that natural motion in the elements proceeds from their proper natures. Aristotle continues his search for the cause of natural motion in the elements by saying that 'potency' may have many senses. This multiplicity, he tells us, is the reason why the source of the natural motion of the elements is not apparent. He proceeds to give several examples of kinds of potency and to distinguish bePhysics 8. 4. 25Sa28-30. Thomas Aquinas, On the Physics 8. 8. 1029. 24 See Aristotle, 14 LAURA LANDEN, O.P. tween first and second potency, each of which relate to both first and second act. In one example Aristotle asks his reader to consider both someone who does not know a particular science and one who knows it but is not exercising the knowledge. The one who is ignorant of the science must be taught, and in the change from being ignorant to knowing teacher and pupil must be in contact. But one who knows the science but is not exercising it can come to exercise it without a teacher. Still once brought from ignorance to knowledge, the learner does not necessarily continue to exercise the knowledge acquired. Although one sort of potency has been actualized, another may still remain. Thomas applies the names ' first potency ' and ' second potency' to the two states of the learner: being ignorant, and knowing but not exercising the knowledge. He writes : Something is reduced from first potency to second when an active principle is in contact with its passive principle; then, by the presence of the active principle, the passive is brought into some kind of act which is still in potency in a way. In just this way the learner, by the action of the teacher, is brought from potency into act, an act to which another potency is adjoined. 26 Aristotle observes that the knower will immediately engage knowledge unless something prevents him from doing so. In his commentary, Thomas expands this observation and makes an important statement about the requirement for an efficient cause in the actualization of this ' second potency ' : But when he has acquired the habit of science, it is not necessary that he be moved to second act by some agent ; rather, he will himself immediately exercise his knowledge unless something prevents him, such as other occupations or sickness or his will. On the other hand, if unimpeded he is not able to exercise his knowledge, then he does not have the habit of science but its contrary-that is, ignorance.27 In sum, the move from first potency to first act requires an ac28 Thomas Aquinas, On the Physics 8. 8. 1031. Aquinas, On the Physics 8. 8. 1031. 2 1 Thomas GAIA HYPOTHESIS: A THOMIST ANALYSIS 15 tually existent external agent : the teacher in the case of the student, the generator in the case of the elements. The move from second potency to operation, on the other hand, occurs immediately and without further need of an extrinsic agent, unless some additional factor impedes this natural action. The actualization of a natural operation is spontaneous. Aristotle next applies the principles of this example to the motion of the elements. He says that what is heavy is potentially light. For example, air is generated from water. The newly generated air will immediately rise, unless prevented from doing so.28 Thomas phrases this slightly differently, but without misinterpretation : At first this water is potentially light, but afterwards becomes actually light. It then immediately has its own operation, unless something prevents it.29 Aristotle defines heaviness as a relationship to a certain place, that is, to ' being down '. The complete actualization of a heavy thing consists in its ' being down '. He is now prepared to give his explanation of the cause of the motion of heavy bodies : The question is: What causes the motion of the heavy and the light to their proper places? The only answer is that they have a tendency to those places. In this consists the essence of lightness and heaviness, the former being an upward tendency and the latter a downward.30 He explains this as follows. A thing may be potentially light in more than one sense. Water is potentially light. After it becomes air, however, it may still be potentially light in the sense that it is prevented from rising. Should the hindrance be removed, its actuality may be realized and it will rise. We recognize this difference as that between the potency to first act and 28 " touto gar dunamei proton, kai ede kouphon, kai energesei g' eythus, an me ti koluei ... " (Aristotle, Physics 8. 4. 255b9-11). 2e " Haec ergo, scilicet aqua, primo est in potentia levis, et postmodum fit levis in actu ; et tune statim habet operationem suam, nisi aliquid prohibeat " (Thomas Aquinas, On the Physics 8. 8. 1033). ao Aristotle, Physics 8. 4. 255b13-17. 16 LAURA LANDEN, O.P. the potency to second act. Water is in potency to air substantially, that is, at the level of first act. Once the water has become air, it is potentially 'up' with regard to operation, or second act. This potentiality to ' being up ' is precisely what is meant by lightness. According to this doctrine, then, air will spontaneously exercise its operation to move up by reason of lightness, unless something prohibits this motion. Thomas formulates the argument more strongly: For although the act of a light thing is to be up, some still ask why the heavy and the light are moved to their proper places. The reason is that they have a natural aptitude to such places. For this is what it is to be light: to have an aptitude to be up. It is the nature of heaviness to have an aptitude to be down. Hence, to ask why the heavy thing is moved down is nothing other than to ask why it is heavy. And so the same thing that makes it heavy also makes it move down.31 We may conclude that the generator of the heavy thing is also its mover because the generator is precisely the agent that makes it heavy by giving it its form, or nature. Aristotle concludes his discussion of the cause of the natural motion of the heavy and the light by saying that they do not move themselves, but do contain within themselves the source, or arkhe, of their motion. He writes : And so, in all these instances, the thing does not move itself. However, it does have within it a[n active] principle of its motion-not an active [potency], but a passive one.32 Aristotle and Aquinas provide some valuable analyses which are of help in assessing the Gaia hypothesis. The sum of living organisms may well act as a whole; Gaia seems to be a valid concept. This need not imply that earth is alive. Lovelock may have BJ. Thomas Aquinas, On the Physics 8. 8. 1034. hoti men toinum ouden touton ayto kinei heayto, delon, alla kineseos arkhen ekhei, ou tou kinein oude tou poiein, alla tou paskhein " (Aristotle, Physics 8. 4. 255b29-31). Aristotle uses 'principle' (arkhe) here rather than ' potency ', but the paraphrase provided is more faithful to the meaning of the text. i12 " GAIA HYPOTHESIS: A THOMIST ANALYSIS 17 maintained this in his earlier work, but he has backed away from this position after introducing Daisy World. Gaia as a self-regulating cybernetic machine is admittedly much more complex than the simple world of black and white daisies, yet the Aristotelian tradition is helpful even here. The fall of heavy bodies can be seen as a natural motion of the nonliving, that is, as motion proceeding from an intrinsic principle. In light of this, it is entirely reasonable to maintain that the natural order has many nonliving, but moving, systems (cybernetic machines?) in which motion proceeds naturally, from an intrinsic principle. Acceptance of Gaia by scientists is taken by some as an indication of a mature science. Consider the following : [David] Abram suggested that the Gaia hypothesis "may well signal the emergence of just such a mature science. A science that seeks not to control the world but to participate with the world, not to operate upon nature, but to cooperate with nature." Gaia, he says, " will never fit very neatly within the discourse of mechanism." 33 The seasons come and the seasons go, and there is nothing new under the sun-but perhaps we now have a clearer understanding of how things under the sun operate. The scientific community recently accorded the Gaia hypothesis a warm reception. Perhaps philosophers and theologians might find rich insight here as well: insight which is old, yet newly grasped; insight which is radical, yet compatible with solid philosophical traditions. sa Sattaur, " Cuckoo," p. 18. Abram has investigated the implications of the Gaia hypothesis as a way of looking at the natural order. See David Abram, "The Perceptual Implications of Gaia," Ecologist 15 (1985) : 96-103. AQUINAS AND THE PRESENCE OF THE HUMAN RATIONAL SOUL IN THE EARLY EMBRYO STEPHEN J. HEANEY University of Saint Thomas Saint Paul, Minnesota F IRST IN RELATION to evolution and more recently in relation to abortion, there has been a recurrence of Thomas Aquinas's arguments for the thesis that the human rational soul is not present in the human body immediately upon conception. Since soul and body must be proportioned to each other, it is argued, a rational soul cannot be present until the human body is formed enough to support it, i.e., until there are organs in place through which the rational soul can begin to exercise its proper powers. The question of this paper is : Given modern embryological knowledge, would Aquinas be likely to come to the same conclusion? In regards to such a question Rudolph Gerber has made the following observation: Some scholastic philosophers and theologians insist that it is simply impossible to determine exactly when rational animation occurs. This belief, however, has deterred few prophets in either camp from stating their positions with dogmatic certainty.1 The authors whose interpretations we will be encountering in this paper have generally been less than dogmatic, but they have been insistent on the rectitude of their respective positions. I will attempt to do likewise : I am in no position to be dogmatic (after all, how will we test the thesis?), but I believe I have good grounds for the conclusion I have reached. 1Rudolph Gerber, "When Is the Human Soul Infused?" Laval theologique et philosophique 22 (1966) : 235. 19 20 STEPHEN J. HEANEY We begin with certain positions which both sides in the debate agree upon : the human intellectual soul is produced immediately by God and not through another agency since, as immaterial, it cannot come from a change in matter; 2 further, the human soul is infused, that is, produced directly in a body as the body's natural perfection. 8 As we shall see in the texts, Aquinas argues that this latter position requires that, while the embryo is alive, it is alive first through the power of a vegetative soul, then a sensitive soul, and finally, when the body is organized enough to be able to perform the functions demanded of it, by a rational soul, this ultimate form replacing the previous one. This theory of delayed animation--or, more to the point of this paper, the view that Aquinas would today still hold such a theory-has several contemporary proponents. The most prominent spokesman is Joseph Donceel, S.J. He has presented his arguments in a pair of articles' which we will now review. In the earlier article, Donceel blames a latent Cartesianism for the proliferation of supporters of immediate hominization. If you hold, with Descartes, that the soul and body are two separate substances, that the soul is not the form of the body, then there is " no longer any reason for rejecting the presence of a real human soul in a virtual human body," 5 i.e., in matter that has the potential to be a human body (with human shape) but is not one yet. Thus, the soul could act as the efficient cause of the body, molding the matter into the organs proper to human beings. This, however, is not Aquinas's view, Donceel argues; "he did not admit that an actual human sould could be coupled with a virtual human body," 6 because "a substantial form can exist only in and with a human body." 7 If we accept the Cartesian 2 S. Th. I, 90, 3, corp. s S. Th. I, 90, 4, corp. 'Joseph Donceel, S.J ., "Abortion: Mediate v. Immediate Animation," Continuum 5 (1967): 167-71; "Immediate Animation and Delayed Hominization," Theological Studies 31 (1970) : 76-105. B Donceel, "Abortion," p. 169. e Ibid., p. 168. T Ibid. THE HUMAN SOUL IN THE EARLY EMBRYO 21 explanation, we would be equating the soul with the architect or builders of a building. These, however, are not the building's form; that exists only in the finished building. Rather, Donceel says that the soul is related to the body as sphericity to a ball. An embryo is like a deflated ball; it cannot contain the form of ball until it is actually spherical. 8 For these reasons, Donceel approves of the arguments of Henri de Dorlodot, who says the following: One would have to be extremely ignorant of embryology not to know that . . . a fertilised ovum, a morula, a fetus which has reached the stage resembling a gastrula, and even an embryo in the first period of its existence, do not possess the organisation of a specifically human body. And the seat of the imagination and the vis cogitativa does not exist so long as the brain itself does not exist, and indeed as long as there are not present the first rudiments of the structure of a human brain. We might perhaps add that it is very probable that the organization necessary in order that the brain may be said to be human is completed only during the third month after conception, and in fact nearer the end of the month than the beginning.9 It is in the later article that Donceel lines up some texts from Aquinas and Aristotle in support of this position. We will consider all the relevant texts a little bit later. For now, let us quote from Donceel this summary of his position. To my mind, these statements of St. Thomas contain a mixture of erroneous biological information and sound philosophy. If this philosophy were derived from the biology, we would have to drop it. Likewise, if Thomas had reached his conclusions only by subsuming his scientific mistakes under his sound philosophical principles, we would have to question them. But it is my contention that these conclusions have been reached, or could have been reached, on the basis of sound philosophical principles and of the common-sense-knowledge which was available to Thomas and his contemporaries. The main philosophical principles are as follows. The soul is the substantial form of man. A substantial form can exist only in mat11 Ibid., p. 169. 11 Canon Henri de Dorlodot, "A Vindication of the Mediate Animation Theory," in E. C. Messenger, ed., Theology and Evolution (London: Sands and Co., Ltd., 1949), p. 260. Cf. Donceel, "Abortion," pp. 169-70. 22 STEPHEN J. HEANEY ter capable of receiving it. In the case of man's soul this means: the human soul can exist only in a highly organized body. Now these philosophical principles owe nothing to primitive medieval biology. They represent Thomas' hylomorphic conception of man. This conception continues to make sense even today, at least for him who understands it. Without it we are steadily in danger of slipping into some kind of Platonic or Cartesian dualism.10 In Donceel's understanding of the situation, Aquinas's conclusion of delayed animation is as sound today as it was in medieval times, because a) the philosophical principle is sound, and b) both medieval and modern embryology agree on " the following undeniable fact, of which Aquinas was fully aware: at the start of pregnancy there is not yet a fully organized human body." 11 What we have instead is "potentially, virtually, a human body." 12 For ensoulment, for the presence of a human rational soul, we must have the organs necessary for the activities proper to human beings, i.e., we need a brain and sense organs. 18 If form and matter are strictly complementary, as hylomorphism holds, there can be an actual human soul only in a body endowed with the organs required for the spiritual activities of man. We know that the brain, and especially the cortex, are the main organs of those highest sense activities without which no spiritual activity is possible.14 Quoting authors who suggest that the soul, in its role as form of the body, shapes and organizes the body, Donceel argues that such an understanding is erroneous. Such a formative principle could not be a substantial form, for, as Aquinas says: " Every substantial generation precedes and does not follow the substantial form." u 10 Donceel, " Immediate Animation," p. 79. 11 Ibid., p. 80. 12 Ibid. 1s Ibid. H Ibid., p. 83. u S. C. G. II, 89, in Donceel, "Immediate Animation," p. 94. THE HUMAN SOUL IN THE EARLY EMBRYO 23 Difficulties in Donceel's Interpretation Donceel makes a number of very good points here, but there are also some difficulties in interpretation that need to be dealt with. Obviously, the big questions will be whether Donceel is correct in his assertion that the human body must have such a high degree of organization before the soul can be present and to what extent Aquinas's conclusion was rooted in biology. But there are a few lesser, but instructive, points to be raised first. For one thing, it is begging the question to assert that the " body at the moment of conception is obviously virtual." 16 To say that immediate animation requires a rational soul to be joined to a virtual or potential human body misses the fact that, when a rational soul is joined to matter, you no longer have a potential human body but rather an actual human body with potential, potential to develop in certain ways. Thus, Donceel's use of Aquinas's statement, "Every substantial generation precedes and does not follow the substantial form," is misplaced. Donceel seems to think that, by joining a rational soul as form to a body as yet unorganized (i.e., not having organs), we would have generation (the corning-to-be of a substance) after the form is in place. Obviously, however, when the substantial form is in place, substantial generation is complete, and all further changes would be developments of the substance. We can only say that the embryo body is a potential human body once we have established that there is no rational soul present. This remains to be seen. A second point of interest is Donceel' s analogy of a building to the human body. He suggests that the form of the building is only present in the finished building and that the human soul is similarly present in an organized human body. But this analogy is somewhat off base. As Aquinas notes in De Anima, the "form " of a house is artificial; a building does not have a sub16 Thomas (1967) : 417. Wassmer, S.J., "Questions About Questions," Commonweal 86 24 STEPHEN J. HEANEY stantial unity as a human body does.17 The body is one because it is perfected by one form. 18 The building is an aggregate or composite; it is, if you will, only analogically one. Donceel's comparisons of the soul to the form of a ball or of a statue are somewhat more apt. There is a sense in which the form of ball is not present until it attains a spherical shape; a statue needs to be molded in clay or chipped from the stone before it is a statue. There is, on the other hand, still a basic artificiality to these forms. Does the ball, for instance, have to be perfectly spherical to be a ball? Can it not be a fair or poor ball rather than only a potential ball? How many chips in the stone does it take to make a statue? The uniqueness of the forms of living things as compared to man-made objects is an interesting topic in itself but takes us away from our main point. The question remains to be answered: Is it possible that there is a human intellectual soul in the embryo from conception, or must there be time enough for the development of the body before God infuses such a soul? The only way to answer such a question is to go directly to the texts of Aquinas in which he lays out his theory of human generation and of the proper proportionality of soul to body. The Thomistic Texts Donceel relies heavily for his interpretation of Aquinas on the following definition of the soul, which is taken from Aristotle: " The soul is the act of a physical organic body which has life potentially." 19 Since " organic " in this context means " having organs," Donceel interprets this statement as saying that all the organs necessary for the proper operations of the human soul must be in place for a human rational soul to be infused in the body. There are other texts throughout Aquinas's works to support this understanding. In the De Anima, for instance, Aquinas says that De Anima X, ad 16. is De Anima X, corp. 1 9 S. Th. I, 76, 4, ad 1; cf. Aristotle, De Anima II, 1. 11 THE HUMAN SOUL IN THE EARLY EMBRYO 25 form gives an act of existing and species to matter according as matter is disposed for the operations of the form, and because the body, which is capable of being perfected by the soul, requires diversity in its parts in order that it may be disposed for the different operations of the soul.20 Similarly, in the Summa Contra Gentiles, Aquinas says the following: [S]ince the intellective soul is the most perfect of souls and its power the highest, its proper perfectible [subject] is a body having great diversity in its organs through which the multiplicity of its operations can be carried out.... 21 Clearly, however, the embryo is alive, even from conception. But if the embryo is not informed by a human rational soul, what sort of form does it have? Today's thinkers in favor of mediate animation turn again to Aquinas's texts, where the answer is available. Agreeing with Aristotle that the embryo is an animal before it is a man, 22 Aquinas says: "The embryo has first of all a soul which is merely sensitive, and when this is removed, it is supplanted by a more perfect soul, which is both sensitive and intellectual." 23 In order to stay with his understanding of the higher soul as containing within it the operations of the lower forms, 24 he explains further: And therefore it is said that since the generation of one thing is the corruption of another, it is necessary to say that, both in man and in other animals, when the more perfect form comes, the prior is corrupted, in such a way that the subsequent form has whatever the first hand, and even more. And so through many generations and corruptions it arrives at the ultimate substantial form, both in man and in other animals. And this is apparent to the senses in animals generated from putrefaction. Thus it is said that the intellectual soul, which is simultaneously both sensitive and nutritive, is created by God at the end of human generation, the preexisting forms being corrupted. 25 20 De Anima X, ad 2. 21 S. C. G. II, 86, 4. Aristotle, De Gen. Anim. II, 3. zs S. Th. I, 76, 3, ad 3; cf. S. C. G. II, 89, 9; De Spir. Crea. III, ad 13. 24 S. Th. I, 76, 3, corp.; 4, corp. 25 S. Th. I, 118, 2, ad 2. '22 26 STEPHEN J. HEANEY Clearly, then, Aquinas believes that there is a succession of souls, nutritive and sensitive, before the body is finally in a position to be informed by its ultimate form, the human rational soul. How can this change take place? Given that what comes into being is brought into being by something already existing (reduction from potentiality to act by what is already in act), we need to find the part or being that does the moving or changing in this situation. There is a suggestion in the Summa Contra Gentiles that it is the soul which is responsible for the change. That which is configured to something is constituted from the action of that to which it is configured: the wax which is configured by the seal receives this configuration from the impression of the seal. Now one sees the bodies of men and other animals to be configured to the proper soul: for the disposition of the organs is such that it suits the operations of the soul exercised through them. The body therefore is formed by the action of the soul ; and that is why Aristotle says (De Anima II) that the soul is the efficient cause of the body.26 Aquinas concurs in this, 21 insofar as it makes sense to say that a soul is responsible for the formation of the human body. Could it be that each successive soul, in some way, manages to transcend itself-that is, to produce by its own power a body capable of receiving a higher form? In this scenario, the original vegetative soul produces a body with the organs necessary for the sensitive soul, which in turn produces a body capable of receiving an intellectual soul. No; such a production is impossible and is not what is indicated by the argument of wax and seal. There is a lack of due proportion of producer to what is produced; a cause cannot be the cause of what is greater than itself. Thus a lower soul, which itself is incapable of higher operations, could not be responsible for the production of organs of higher operations. Nor could it be the case that a lower soul upon further perfection becomes the higher soul, for this would mean : a) that a substantial form is susceptible of degrees, and b) that a rational 26 S. C. G. II, 88, 11. 2r S. C. G. II, 89, 21. THE HUMAN SOUL IN THE EARLY EMBRYO 27 soul is corruptible, since it would thus be founded in a vegetative and sentient substance. 28 It would seem, then, that a rational soul must be responsible. Granting for the sake of argument that a rational soul is the informing principle of the embryo, Aquinas goes through its powers one by one. The power to organize the body cannot come from the embryo's generative powers, for these are operative only in adults and for the purpose of generating others. It cannot be the embryo soul's nutritive power at work here, for in this process nouishment is not assimilated but nutritive material in the mother is brought together to form organs. The power of growth is not responsible, Aquinas claims, because its function is to produce change in quantity, not form. Obviously, the sensitive and intellective powers are inappropriate to such a formation. 29 What is Aquinas left with? It remains therefore that the formation of the body, especially concerning its primary and principal parts, is not from the soul of the thing generated, nor from a formative power acting by virtue of the generated thing, but from [a formative power] acting by virtue of the generative soul of the father, the work of which is to make something like the generating thing according to its species.30 It is thus apparent that, for Aquinas, it is the soul of a parent that is responsible for the development of the embryo body until it is capable of supporting a rational soul. In Aristotelian physics, whenever we speak of change or movement, there is that which acts and that which is acted upon, i.e., something passive. The same holds true for Aristotelian biology, which Aquinas accepted completely as authoritative. In the abstract, it would serve perfectly well if the active part were donated by the mother, and the passive part by the father. This is not the case, however, according to this early theory of generation. Each parent donates a particular element: the female provides the menstrual blood, the father the semen. From a prac2s De Spir. Crea. III, ad 13; S. C. G. II, 89, 6 and 7. 29 S. C. G. II, 89, 8. 10 S. C. G. II, 89, 8; cf. 89, 21. 28 STEPHEN J. HEANEY tical perspective, it makes some sense that the fetal matter be provided by the female, simply in terms of mass. This is precisely what Aquinas says is the case : the female provides the passive element. 31 If this is so, however, then the father provides the active element. This means it is the father's soul which is responsible for the development of a human body in the embryo. Yet this seems to put us in the awkward position of saying either a) the soul is transmitted in the semen, or b) the action of the father's soul must take place at a distance. Aquinas devotes a chapter in Summa Contra Gentiles to laying out arguments favoring the transmission of the soul in, or the forming of the soul from, the semen; he spends the next chapter showing how this is impossible. 32 We have already seen how the soul cannot develop through its stages on its own account. It is equally impossible that the soul be transmitted in the semen, for thus we would have the form before the generation. 33 It is possible, however, for the father's soul to act at a distance, not directly, but through a medium. The generative power of the soul is at work in the instrument of the semen,34 rather as the power of the hunter would be in the arrow which strikes an animal at a distance. 85 "This active force, which is in the semen, and which is derived from the soul of the generator, is, as it were, a certain movement of the generator's soul itself.... " 36 The semen contains a " formative power " which is based " on the vital spirit which the semen contains as a kind of froth." 37 The semen contains an active " spirit," rather like an active gas or heat or electrical charge, which explains the frothy whiteness of the semen. When this comes in contact with the matter being carried in the female, the menstrual blood, the semen goes to work transmuting this blood, organizing it into a body. For the animal, this transmutation by the semen takes place until the body is disposed to activation by the sensitive soul. a1 S. Th. I, 118, 1, ad 4. s2 S. C. G. II, 88 and 89. sa S. C. G. II, 89, 4 and 5. 34 S. Th. I, 118, 1, ad 4. De An. II, ad 2. ss S. Th. I, 118, 1, ad 3; cf. S. C. G. II, 89, 8. ar S. C. G. II, 89, 8. 35 THE HUMAN SOUL IN THE EARLY EMBRYO 29 Afterwards, however, through the power of the active principle which was in the semen, the sensitive soul was produced in the thing generated in respect to some principal part, then already the very sensitive soul of the offspring begins to work to the completion of its own body through nutrition and augmentation.88 Only then does the semen, as the instrumental agent, dissipate. This is an important point. Since the species of the subject formed changes, passing from semen to pure blood and on further until it receives the ultimate form of a rational soul, it is necessary that the formative power remain the same throughout the process, from the beginning of the body's formation until the end (when it can support a rational soul). Thus one power is at work through many generations and corruptions. 89 Arguments against Mediate Animation Donceel believes that, even in the context of contemporary embryology, Aquinas would still today hold for some theory of delayed hominization; the body would be seen to develop step by step, through vegetative and sensitive stages, until it is developed enough to have organs, or at least the beginnings of organs, capable of performing the tasks demanded of the body by an intellectual soul. Donceel's claim is that Aquinas's conceptualization of a succession of souls is valid regardless of the facts of generation. But this claim rests completely on an understanding of the relationship between soul and body which prohibits the soul's presence unless the body has reached a sufficient degree of organization. We must take issue with Donceel's claim. Aquinas's acceptance of Aristotle's theory of a succession of souls is, in fact, totally dependent on his acceptance of the corresponding theory of generation. But what if generation does not take place in the manner described? In order to explain the succession of souls, which are not themselves responsible for the formation of the body, there must be an active power, the semen, at work on the passive matter, organizing the body throughout the succession of u S. Th. I, 118, 1, ad 4. ao S. C. G. II, 89, 9. 30 STEPHEN J. HEANEY souls. Without this organizing power, there is no way to explain the formation of the body. Clearly, the semen-or, in modern terms, the sperm-does not perform such a task. It appears that the development of the organs is an activity internal to the embryo, not one being performed by an extrinsic power. At the very least, we can definitely say that the semen does not have an active power or spirit in the sense that Aquinas understood the term. Such spirits, as I said earlier, were "like hot, energetic gases (or even like our idea of electricity)." 40 Thus the seminal spirit contained the quality of heat necessary for the refinement of the menstrual blood and the consequent proper disposition of a living body as something with both natural heat and natural moisture. 41 Obviously, neither the semen nor the sperm have such properties as this, nor do they continue to exist in themselves after conception. The sperm that do not penetrate the ovum die shortly thereafter. The semen that is not used as nutrient by the sperm is absorbed or otherwise dissolved in the maternal body. One might suggest that the genetic material carried by the sperm (and, for that matter, by the ovum) performs this formative function, thus organizing a human being by the power of the soul of the begetter rather than of the begotten. This seems implausible, however, given the apparent character of the embryo. Genetic material from the sperm does not work independently, any more than does that from the mother; it is only when they come together that there is any development in the direction of the maturity of the individual. Conversely, whenever they come together, such a tendency toward a mature individual is the result. Genetic material, being essentially chemical, operates by the 40 Benedict Ashley, " A Critique of the Theory of Delayed Hominization " in D. G. McCarthy and A. S. Moraczewski, ed., An Ethical Evaluation of Fetal Experimentation: An Interdisciplinary Study (St. Louis: Pope John XXIII Medical-Moral Research and Education Center, 1976), Appendix I, p. 119; cf. Generation of Animals, ed. A. L. Peck (Cambridge, Mass.: Loeb Library, 1953) Appendix B, pp. 576-93, for a discussion of the semen and pneuma. u De An. IX, ad 16. THE HUMAN SOUL IN THE EARLY EMBRYO 31 same basic properties as any chemical compound: the parts may have one set of characteristics, but, with their joining, they each cease their former existence, and a new set of characteristics becomes manifest. (In Thomistic terms, a new form manifests itself.) Sodium and chlorine, for instance, are both poisonous to human beings, but as the chemical compound sodium chloride (NaCl) they become common table salt. Such, analogously, is the case with human genetic material. The ovum carries twentythree chromosomes, bearing the generative power of the mother; the sperm's twenty-three chromosomes bring the generative power of the father. When they meet at fertilization, however, the combination takes on a new set of characteristics specific to this embryo. We are thus without a way for the soul of the parents to provide the power, either immediately or mediately, to organize the body of the embryo. Without the power of the soul of the begetter, Aquinas clearly would have nowhere else to turn but to the soul of the begotten to explain this development. This seems to put us between a rock and a hard place. We are forced to say that the power must be in the soul of the embryo, since the soul of the parent has been ruled out. Aquinas, however, has already said how it is not a power in the embryo. How do we get around this difficulty? First of all, I think it would be fair to say that Aquinas worked through his theory with such consistency, coming to the conclusions he did, because he was never faced with the possibility that generation might take place in a way he had never even considered. Aquinas was a philosopher interested in metaphysical principles not so much in themselves but rather as proper explanations of the facts of the world. The " known facts " of his day included this primitive theory of generation and embryology. Faced with the facts as we know them, however, he probably would have worked out a different theory to explain human development. Naturally, we do not want to abandon any metaphysical principles or ideas needlessly. Perhaps there is a way out of this difficulty, based on principles drawn from within this philosophy. 32 STEPHEN J. HEANEY Arguments for Immediate Animation by the Rational Soul The first thing that needs to be explained is how the soul of the embryo can be responsible for the development of a human body capable of exercising the operations proper to the intellectual soul. We have ruled out the possibility of the vegetative or sensitive souls of themselves being responsible for such development. Donceel offers a modified version of this idea. Borrowing from Rabner and Teilhard de Chardin, he suggests that "God [as primary cause] enables the secondary causes to transcend their own virtualities, inserting, as it were, His divine causality within their own causality, without becoming a constitutive element of their being." ' 2 Such a theory, while interesting and arguable, is not Aquinas. Since we are trying to sort out how Aquinas would answer the question, it is best to leave this theory aside. Given that neither a vegetative nor a sensitive soul is capable of producing a human body, we are left with something of Aquinas's answer but with an important difference: a human rational soul must be responsible, not the soul of the begetter, however, but the soul of the begotten, of the embryo. Of course, we have yet to explain how it is possible to say that the matter of the embryo is sufficiently disposed to receive such a form. Let us return for a moment to the analogy of soul to body as impress of seal to wax. Aquinas seems to have some feeling for this analogy and for its implications, for he says the following in another work: " a soul is said to be in a body through a definite shape, not in the sense that the shape is the cause of its being in the body, but rather the shape of the body results from the soul. ... " ' 8 Thus, he is following closely Aristotle's explanation of the soul as cause. The soul is the cause or source of the living body. The terms cause and source have many senses. But the soul is the cause of its body alike in all three senses which we explicitly recognize. It is a) the Donceel, " Immediate Animation," p. 85. 'a De Spir. Crea. IV, ad 9 (my emphasis). ,42 THE HUMAN SOUL IN THE EARLY EMBRYO 33 source or origin of movement, it is b) the end, and it is c) the essence of the whole living body.44 We have already recognized the soul as the essence or ground of a living thing's being, as the substantial form. For now, the point of interest is the soul as end or final cause. Nature does what it does, notes Aristotle, for the sake of something. All natural bodies are organs of the soul and exist for the sake of the soul. 45 In other words, we need a soul even simply to have the organs we do, and we need a rational soul. As we have seen, it cannot be the rational soul of anyone but the embryo. Lest it be said that I have been unfair to the text of Aquinas, let us continue for a moment with a passage quoted above. In a line which once again appears to support mediate animation, he says the following: " ... and hence where there is no shape suited to ' this soul ', ' this soul ' cannot actually be." 46 Now if this is taken to mean that, the human soul cannot be if the complete human organism is not present, with all the organs necessary for the operations of the soul, then we must contest this statement. For one thing, this conclusion not only does not follow from the premises; it is, in fact, contrary to the premises. It also appears to be empirically falsifiable. If I am missing my arms or my eyes or if I have an artificial heart, am I less a person simply because I do not have the right shape? The real point here is that we have a natural tendency toward certain limits of shape. It seems to me that these natural tendencies are precisely how it is that we define a thing and decide what sort of form it has. Natural potentialities are due to the form, in this case, the soul. Francis Wade talks about them in this way: Between natural potentialities and their action there is nothing needed except usable matter and this latter is from the side of the patient, not the agent. The agent's constitution is ready and prepared to act when conditions permit. This will, of itself, supposing usable matter, develop all that is needed to become what it will be.... However «De Anima II, 4 ( 415b 9-10). 4.5 De Anima II, 4(415b15-20). u De Spir. Crea. IV, ad 9. 34 STEPHEN J. HEANEY one accounts for this process, no one would say that the plants and animals in fact do not do their own self-developing from resources in their constitution .... [To summarize.] The potentiality of the fetus to become an adult is not a passive potency [like the ability to get a good suntan], which is neutral to the future; nor a specifiable active potentiality [such as the potential to learn geometry], which is a very " iffy " promise; but is an active natural potentiality or tendency, which is a guarantee of the future as far as the agent is concerned.47 Rudolph Gerber argues that the whole point of the term " organic " or the phrase " having organs " is to indicate " specifically human structure." The genotype is sufficient to give us this structure; 48 through the DNA, the entity is determined to develop in a specifically human way, toward becoming an adult human, with all the organs necessary to perform the operations of a rational soul. Wade concurs : Now, I would like to suggest ... that the natural tendency to think and to choose is basic to the being of the fetus, and the biological tendencies (the ones most clearly active in the genotype) are only specifications of the radical tendency to become a thinking being.49 Some suggest, however, that while it may be true that the rational soul might be present, it is necessary for it to have an organ by which it might perform the formation of the rest of the organs necessary for its functions. Without a first primary organ, one might argue, the whole will never even get started. Benedict Ashley takes this objection particularly seriously and looks for something that could be considered such a primary organ in the one-celled conceptus. His answer is the nucleus of the cell. The nucleus contains the specifying genetic material. Following this, the nuclei of the daughter cells can be considered the primary organs, until the appearance of the " primary organizer " and the beginning of cell differentiation. Soon, there appears the primitive streak, the primordial central nervous system, which from its 47 Francis Wade, S.J., "Potentiality in the Abortion Discussion," Review of Metaphysics 29 (1975): 239-55. 48 Gerber, p. 245-6. 4 5 Wade, "Potentiality," p. 254. THE HUMAN SOUL IN THE EARLY EMBRYO 35 beginning exhibits a polarity indicating at which end the brain will be formed. From this point on, we have the beginnings of the primary organ in the human being. 50 Ashley argues that the nucleus in the one-celled conceptus " is epigenetically and substantially identical with the primordial central nervous system manifested in the primitive streak." 51 He goes on to say that this means that an existential and dynamic continuity can be traced from the nucleus of the zygote to the cortex of the human infant. There is at all times a central organ maintaining life and producing development and differentiation, and this constitutes epigenetic identity.52 It could be argued, however, that a nucleus is not an organ in the sense that Aquinas meant the term, and thus we are left without the properly disposed matter to move the rest of the matter of the zygote into the proper human shape. There is an answer to this objection available in Aquinas. In describing the whole process of generation in question 118 of the First Part of the Summa Theologiae, Aquinas makes these two statements. [T]his active power in the semen, which is derived from the generating soul, is as it were a certain movement of the generating soul itself.... Therefore it is not necessary that this active power havesome organ in act. ... 53 [T]he fetal matter is provided by the female. In this matter there is already from the beginning a vegetative soul, not according to second act, but according to first act, like the sensitive soul in one who is sleeping. When, however, it begins to take in nourishment, then it already operates in act.54 The significance of these lines must not be lost. The first is saying that the formative power does not need an organ to be operative. If this is true of a power of a soul working at a distance, how much more must it be true of a soul immediately present. 50 Ashley, pp. 123-4. n Ibid., p. 125. u S. Th. I, 118, 1, ad 3 (my emphasis). 12 Ibid. HS. Th. I, 118, 1, ad 4. 36 STEPHEN J. HEANEY The second is saying that it is possible for a soul to be present even though there are no actual organs present. When the organs develop, then the soul begins to operate. Aquinas is saying this of the nutritive soul, but a rational soul, which also contains the powers of nutrition and sensation, is equally capable of informing such matter. Gerber makes this point forcefully. In the first place, one might question the validity of the mediate animists' attempt to interpret the Aristotelian-Thomistic definition of the soul as the rigid requirement for the time of the soul's infusion. With the exception of the words actus primus, that definition is an operative account of the soul. The soul itself is the first or vivifying, substantial act; its operations are second acts, and it was from the diversity of these operations that Thomas concluded that the subject of the soul needed a diversity of organs .... But the soul itself is first act independently of its operations, which are second acts. In order to account for the required perfections of matter, it does not seem necessary to posit additional substantial forms as preparatives of the matter of the soul. Rather, it would suffice to consider the soul as a causally complex form which itself prepares matter for those operations. Since the human soul as substantial form contains the vegetative and sentient faculties within its own influence, it could by these functions progressively inform the embryo to the operative intellectual stage. 55 Aquinas himself seems to be making this same point in the following passage. Aristotle does not say that the soul is merely the act of a body, but the act of a physical organic body having life potentially ; and that this potentiality does not reject the- soul. Thus it is manifest that in this the soul is called the act such that the soul itself is included, in the same way of speaking that we say that heat is the act of what is hot, and light of what is lit; not that separately there be a lit thing without light, but because it is a lit thing through the light. And similarly we say that the soul is the ad of a body, etc., through which soul it is both a body, and organic, and has potential life [i.e., is capable of performing living operations]. But the first act is said to be in potency in respect to the second act, which is operation; for such potency is not rejecting-that is, not excluding-the souP 6 55 Gerber, " Soul Infused," p. 244. &6 S. Th. I 76, 4, ad 1; cf. Aristotle, De Anima II, 1 ( 412b 25ff.). THE HUMAN SOUL IN THE EARLY EMBRYO 37 It is important not to rely too heavily on the phrase " organic " or " having organs " in discussing the relationship of soul to body and what constitutes a properly disposed body. The human body must have a diversity of organs to be properly disposed for the operations of the soul, that is, for second act. A one-celled conceptus with the specific human genotype, on the other hand, is matter well enough disposed to be the proper subject of the human intellectual soul in regard to first act, to be the matter for which such a soul is the substantial form. In summation, I hope to have shown several things: a) that Aquinas's theory of the succession of souls is dependent on his theory of generation, based in an outmoded biology; b) as a result, there is no power other than the embryo's own soul which can perform the formation of the organs necessary for the operations of the soul ; c) that soul must be a human intellectual soul from the beginning of the embryo's being; and d) from the time of fertilization the conceptus is matter properly disposed to be the subject of such a form as the rational soul. Thus, it is reasonable to say that infusion of this soul by God takes place at conception and that we are from conception human persons. Postscript: More Recent Opinions Views similar to Donceel's are expressed in an article by William A. Wallace, 0.P., entitled "Nature and Human Nature as the Norm in Medical Ethics." 57 This article contains some very interesting attempts to cast substantial form and prime matter in the light of contemporary physics, chemistry, and biology, but with regard to our problem here Wallace presents the following arguments: Is the transient form that is becoming a chimpanzee really a chimpanzee from the first moment of formation of the zygote? Alternatively, is the radioactive neptunium that is breaking down into lead really lead from the first moment of its radioactive decay? Invok&7 William A. Wallace, O.P., "Nature and Human Nature as the Norm in Medical Ethics,'' in Catholic Perspectives on .Medical Morals, ed. Edmund D. Pelligrino (Dordrecht, Netherlands: Kluwer, 1989), pp. 23-52. 38 STEPHEN J. HEANEY ing the agere sequitur esse axiom, one would think that, just as an element with the properties of neptunium should be regarded as neptunium and not as lead, even though it will eventually become lead, so a transient nature that exhibits only vegetative activities should be regarded as a plant and not as an animal, even though the term of its growth is a stable animal nature. 58 The case is similar for humans. Wallace concludes that a Thomistic natural philosophy, updated to incorporate the findings of modern science, can influence the decision between the two alternatives, and would probably favor delayed over immediate hominization on the basis that the former is more consonant with nature's other operations.59 For Wallace, the theory of immediate hominization "misconstrues how nature itself operates as a cause in the eduction of forms, and would bring God into a natural process at a stage where his action is not required." 60 Wallace's analysis in this area misses the mark on several key points. 1) " Nature " is not something above and beyond the substantial forms that make it up. Each individual nature is what it is because of its substantial form, i.e., the substantial form gives the thing its nature. (In the material world, it must be coupled with matter to be a complete nature.) 2) An effect cannot be greater than the cause. Demanding, however, that lower forms be responsible for the shaping of the material, such that a higher form is educed, in effect demands that a lower form produce what is greater than itself. The analogy between the movement from neptunium to lead and that from "transient-" or "plant-chimpanzee" to" animal-chimpanzee" is not valid. A shift in form on the same level might be possible due to the power inherent in the first forms. A " downgrading" of form-say, from sensitive to vegetative-might also be possible, due to the fact that a higher form contains within itself the powers of the lower forms. An " upgrade," however, violates the principle of the effect not being greater than the cause. 3) Aquinas escapes this 58 Ibid., p. 47. 59 Ibid., p. 48. eo Ibid., p. 50. THE HUMAN SOUL IN THE EARLY EMBRYO 39 dilemma by saying that the soul (the substantial form) of the parent has produced a body ready for infusion of a new soul by God. As we have seen, this is not the case. Thus, we are left with only one conclusion: there must be a human soul from fertilization to account for human development. The argument Wallace notes regarding historical and functional identity 61 is not a account of biology which demands infusion at fertilization but rather an explanation of how such infusion-already demanded by causal concerns-is possible. Norman M. Ford, S.D.B., (of the Catholic Theological College in Melbourne, Australia) has put together one of the most thorough treatments of this topic in When Did I Begin'!. 62 This book is impressive not only because it presents a depth of scientific research and explanation but also because it takes so seriously the argument for immediate animation and the Aristotelian-Thomistic principles involved, before deciding in favor of delayed animation. Indeed, once one reads the section on immediate animation, one is hard-pressed to figure how anyone could find fault with such a position-and yet Ford does. Unfortunately, it seems to this writer that he comes to his conclusion by misappropriating the very principles he seemed to understand so clearly earlier on. For Ford, it is true that the fertilized ovum has a "biological human nature", 63 but this does not mean that a human person, with a human soul as form of the body, is present. Rather, he argues that a genetic human being is present but not an ontological human being. The latter does not seem to be present until the primitive streak stage. 64 A person is "a distinct on-going ontological individual with a biological human nature." 65 Ford argues that the possibility of twinning and recombination indicates that such an on-going individual is not present. If, for instance, one cell divides into two, neither is said to be the original cell-neither of the two new individuals is the first in61 Ibid., p. 49. 62 Norman M. Ford, S.D.B., When Did I Begin? (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1988). t1a Ibid., p. 128. &4 Ibid., pp. 168-77. 66 Ibid., p. 128. 40 STEPHEN J. HEANEY dividual. Similarly, recombining cells would destroy the identity of the recombined cells, with a new entity-the combinationbeing a new individual. Ford is also concerned with the fact that both the embryo and placenta come from the same cell mass at differentiation, even though one is the individual and the other is not. Since there is no guarantee prior to cell differentiation that twinning or recombination will not occur nor that any particular cell will differentiate into embryonic vs. non-embryonic cells, Ford is unwilling to say that there is an ontological human individual (a person) prior to the appearance of the primitive streak. Like Donceel, Ford waits until an actual organ (of sorts) appears before conceding that a human soul is present in this matter. There are several problems with Ford's analysis, despite the care he takes. 1) In Thomistic terms, what would it mean to say that something has a " biological human nature " without thereby having a human form? Ford claims to be fighting against dualism, 66 but this is a very dualistic notion. 2) Just because it is not this human individual person does not mean that it is not a human individual person. Ford has not adequately dispelled the argument that at least one individual could continue through twinning or recombination-a position which he is careful to spell out. 67 Even if it were true, however, that the coming to be of two individuals from one, or of one from two, entails the death of the prior individual ( s), it does not entail that there was no ontological individual at all. In fact, Ford's own definition" a human person begins as a living individual with the inherent active potential to develop towards adulthood without ceasing to be the same ontological individual " 68-applies equally to the onecelled zygote as to the blastocyst. The conceptus has this inherent active potential; the fact that some might not realize this potential does not argue against their being ontological individuals. The problem here seems to be a confusion of material with formal causality. To say that one individual may give rise to two sa Ibid., p. 130. 61 Ibid., pp. 112-16. es Ibid., p. 85. THE HUMAN SOUL IN THE EARLY EMBRYO 41 is true but only materially. The form either ceases to be in this matter or continues in one of the material bodies. It seems to me that Ford ultimately makes the same mistake that Donceel and many philosophers make in this area: he is searching for material conditions rather than looking to see what operations are being performed that require the presenice of the human soul. Two other articles which appeared recently seem to put the same metaphysical cart before the horse. 69 The first article appeared in Theological Studies in December of 1990. Entitled "Reflections on the Moral Status of the Pre-Embryo," it was authored by Thomas Shannon and Allan B. Wolter, O.F.M. The second piece, " Who or What is the Preembryo? " by Richard McCormick, S.J., led off the inaugural issue of the Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal in March, 1991. Essentially, McCormick asks the question: What is necessary for personhood? His answer is developmental individuality. Even genetic individuality is not enough. In taking on the arguments of the Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith expressed in Donum vitae, McCormick says this document seems unaware that in the preembryo's earliest stages the constituent cells are only "loosely associated." 10 Thus: For the CDF, if the preembryo is genetically individualized, it is individualized in the most radical sense. Thus it asks: " How could a human individual not be a human person? " A possible, and in my judgment sufficient, response to this question is: " by not yet being a human individual (developmentally single)." 71 Ultimately, however, the question is rather: What is necessary for development toward a physically discernable individual at the primitive streak stage? I suggest Aquinas's answer (and mine) would be that it is the presence of a human rational soul. McCormick's own observation seems to indicate this. 69 This may be due to the fact that they rely so heavily on some of these same authors. 1o Richard McCormick, S.J ., "Who or What is the Preembryo? " Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, March 1991, pp. 7-8. 'Tl Ibid., p. 8. 42 STEPHEN J. HEANEY Under favorable circumstances, the fertilized ovum will move through developmental individuality then progressively through functional, behavioral, psychic, and social individuality. In viewing the first stage, one cannot afford to blot out subsequent stages.12 How is such development possible at all without the presence of a human rational soul? Shannon and Wolter's errors are similar. Concentrating on the question of human individuality, they assert that "a determinate and irreversible individuality is a necessary, if not a sufficient, condition for it to be a human person." 73 Further, this individuality, i.e., being properly speaking a "human individual," cannot eventuate until after the process of restriction and determination. 74 Until that time, the possibility of twinning and the totipotentiality of cells in the zygote indicates that " the organism is not necessarily single." 75 In other words, the zygote is more correctly a loosely bound aggregation of individuals. Again, though, the issue arises: while immediate animation can explain the facts of twinning and totipotency, how can the mediate animation theory explain the fact that most zygotes do not divide-or, for that matter, that any do not divide? that the totipotent cells are loosely bound in this particular way, and not in a variety of ways? that they all develop according to the same process? For Aquinas, if effect is not to be greater than cause, a human soul must be responsible. Since for us the soul of one of the parents cannot be the cause, the cause must be the human rational soul of the zygote, right from the moment genetic uniqueness is established. Furthermore, one is struck by the somewhat dualistic characterization of the relationship between soul and body in this account of the human person. Dualism could be seen in Norman Ford's explanation, but it is much more evident here. For in12 Ibid., p. 12. 73 Thomas Shannon and Allan B. Wolter, 0.F.M., "Reflections on the Moral Status of the Pre-embryo," Theological Studies 51 (1990) : 613. 74 Ibid., p. 614. 1s Ibid., p. 613. THE HUMAN SOUL IN THE EARLY EMBRYO 43 stance, Shannon and Wolter opt for the terms " immaterial individuality" and "immaterial selfhood" instead of "soul." 16 This sounds more Platonic that Aristotelian/Thomistic. For Aquinas, there is no human immaterial individual or self apart from the composite of body and soul. While the soul may survive death, it is incomplete in its nature, not fully a self or particular individual. 17 A second instance of this dualism occurs where they examine the definition of personhood used in Catholic moral theory: an individual substance of a rational nature. When is such a rational nature present? they ask: at the primitive streak stage, or the completion of simple neural circuits, or at the appearance of an integrated nervous system? 18 Of course, the Thomistic answer to the question is : there is a rational nature when the material being is informed by a rational soul. The soul is the form of the body and so makes it to be, to be a body, and to be this kind of body (living and rational). " Nature" is not limited to material things. Angels and God are considered persons because they are complete individual substances of a rational nature, yet they are non-bodily. In the third instance of dualism, and using an argument much like William Wallace's, Shannon and Wolter reach back to Walter's own 1960 article, "Chemical Substance." 19 Philosophically speaking, we have every reason to believe that the dynamic properties of the organic matter-the elements of the fully formed zygote-owe their existence to their organizational form or the system. Important to note is that " where there are only material powers-that is, the ability to form material systems-, there is only a material nature or substance." Thus the material system or form of the developing body can explain its own activity. We conclude that there is no cogent reason, either from a philosophical or still less from a theological viewpoint, why we should assert, for inIbid., p. 615. See S. Th. I, 75 art. 2 and 4. 18 Shannon and Wolter, p. 620. 79 Allan B. Wolter, "Chemical Substance," in Philosophy of Science (Jamaica, N.Y.: St. John's University, 1960), originally titled "The Problem of Substance." 16 11 44 STEPHEN J. HEANEY stance, that the human soul is either necessary or directly responsible for the architectonic chemical behavior of nucleo-proteins in the human body.80 The mistake here, it seems to me, is precisely the same as Wallace's: the argument fails to respect the utterly foundational axiom that an effect cannot be greater than its cause. Yes, form can be educed from the potency of matter, but only if there is a sufficient cause, equal to or greater than the form educed, which is responsible for bringing the matter to that potentiality. Aquinas would hold that the human soul is directly responsible for the behavior of proteins in the human body. Otherwise, we must say there is more than one form, more than one soul, in the human being, and this in turn would mean we are not one being, but several-which Aquinas emphatically denies. 81 Finally, although the passage and footnote are fairly brief, Shannon and Wolter seem particularly concerned about the problem of embryonic wastage. The fact that about SS% of fertilizations come to a quick end in miscarriage " intuitively argues against the creation of a principle of immaterial individuality at conception." 82 This is, indeed, a jarring statistic, and perhaps one day we will have a full explanation of why this might be the case. Still, our job as philosophers is to explain how all the facts are possible. This the theory of immediate animation does; the theory of mediate animation cannot. We should not be deterred from accepting the explanation simply because the corollaries make us uncomfortable. 83 There is one small item in Shannon and Walter's article which Shannon and Wolter, pp. 620-621. Theologiae I, Q. 76, art. 1, 3, and 4. s2 Shannon and Wolter, p. 619. 83 I find it far more disturbing that the authors are willing to suggest that the claim of immediate animation is " not only irrational but blasphemous" (p. 618). In footnote 60 (p. 618), they say, "To ascribe such bungling of the conceptual process to an all-wise creator would seem almost sacriligeous." It seems to this writer that our job is to discover and explain what is happening and not to set about blaming God for his apparent inefficiency. The blasphemy occurs when we try to hold God to our far from wise standards. 80 81 See Summa THE HUMAN SOUL IN THE EARLY EMBRYO 45 sent me searching for more information. In discussing the physiological status and development of the preembryo, they quoted an article by Carlos A. Bedate and Robert C. Cefalo, entitled " The Zygote: To Be or Not to Be a Person." 84 What was most significant there was the claim that, for the zygote to become an embryo, " further essential and supplementary genetic information to what can be found in the zygote itself is required." 83 In other words, the zygote appears not to be self-sufficient for further development. Could it be that Aristotle was right-that, at least in the earliest stages, the body is still being formed by the power of the parent? If so, it would not be necessary to posit the existence of a human rational soul from the time of the combination of genetic material. In their very short article, Bedate and Cefalo come at the personhood of the zygote from a completely different (and particularly challenging) angle. As their introductory paragraph states : Many of the philosophical and moral-theological arguments against very early abortion or manipulation of the pre-embryo presuppose that the zygote contains all the information necessary to produce the specific biological character of the future adult. . . . In such arguments the zygote is accorded a special status because of the claim that the biological uniqueness of the future adult is determined at the moment of conception. Such philosophical and theological positions that depend on this empirical presupposition must be radically revised if that presupposition can be shown to be false.86 Bedate and Celafo's argument runs essentially as follows: 1) The fact of differentiation cannot be explained simply by reference to genetic information already in the zygote ; for 2) a hydaditiform mole can be produced from a healthy zygote; therefore 3) not all genetic information necessary for becoming an embryo is present in the zygote, so 4) it must come from interaction with the mother. 8' Carlos A. Bedate and Robert C. Cefalo, "The Zygote: To Be or Not to Be a Person," Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 14 (1966): 641-645. H Shannon and Wolter, p. 608. 88 Bedate and Cefalo, p. 641. 46 STEPHEN J. HEANEY If the authors are correct about 2), this would indicate that the personal soul is not present at this stage but would not prove it. It would be still possible that this zygote was subject to a genetic defect or other malady which killed it as a person. The fact is, however, that Bedate and Cefalo's information has simply been superseded. An article by Donald DeMarco in the January 1991 issue of Ethics an'finitum. That perfection in creatures is by them according to their modality of being, which limits all that is received from God according to the limits of what God has thought not of himself and thus made creatures so much of what they are and no more. But this is not to say that, therefore, creatures are outside of God in any other meaning than that they are less perfect than God. There simply is no metaphysical abyss between God and his creatures. Separation here bespeaks only relative imperfection, measured to each creature along with its perfections according to the infinite wisdom of God. The second theological postscript concerns the Incarnation. The Incarnation is accomplished in the assumption of a human nature by a divine Person. Thomists have traditionally held that, because the human nature is terminated by the Person of the Word, Jes us has only the divine existence and not a human existence. Cajetan teaches that in Christ the human nature exists by an "ecstacy of existence." Capreolus, too, and John of St. Thomas can be called as witnesses to this tradition. 16 What has been said here is not opposed to that traditional Thomism. Indeed, it has been intended to be no more than a repetition of that teaching. The objection may be raised, however, that according to what has been said it is impossible to distinguish any creature from the incarnate Word. Thomists say the human nature of the Word exists not by a human existence but by its termination at the divine existence. That does not seem different from what has been said here of being. If all being terminates at the divine existence, everything would seem to exist as the Thomists say Jesus' human nature 1s See Cajetan, In De Ente et Essentia, c. 5, q. 9; In Summa Theol., 1, q. 3, a. 3; 3, q. 4, a. 2; Capreolus, In I Sent., d. 4, q. 2, a. 1; In III Sent., d. 5, q 3, a 3; d. 6, q. 1, a. 3; John of St. Thomas, Cursus Phil., I, Ars Logica, II, q. 14, a. 1; q. 17, a. 2; q. 19, a. 1. See also Banez, In Summa Theo/., I., q. 45, a. 3. Cf. T. U. Mullaney, " Created Personality: The Unity of the Thomistic Tradition,'' The New Scholasticism 29 (1955): 398ff. 68 ROBERT C. BEISSEL exists. The objection is forceful, since it turns the traditional view against itself. At least a note on this is required. As Cajetan teaches, personality is the ultimate termination of a rational nature, i.e., it is the last ratio entis to precede the existence at which such an essence terminates. That termination of essence which precedes existence is nothing other than the modality of created being mentioned above, which differentiates it from its cause and which really opposes and, therefore, relates being to Being. The Word, the divine person, takes the place of such a termination and modality and relation in Christ. That person is not the modality of being or a transcendental relation. That person terminates the human nature of Christ with the infinity of Being itself, so that it might exist by the unreceived existence of the Godhead. That person is a divine and subsistent relation to the Father, which relation is identical with the divine essence and the divine existence. That person is the light which shines in the darkness to make it be. That Person is Being, in which being exists. The existence that actualizes the human nature of Jesus is the very same existence that actualizes every other essence and nature. Jesus' human nature is being, after all. But, since its modality is the active and unmeasured measure proper to Being, its existence is unmeasured; it is the infinite existence which is Being. It is as though the moon were made an illuminative light not by reflecting the sun's light but by being taken up to be the sun itself. Indeed, this is just what the Church declares and its members know only by faith: that God (the sun of justice, ipsum esse, Being) became man. It is also why the Word made flesh (except at the Transfiguration) was seen and known to be not different from other men. Every man, indeed every thing, exists by the divine existence. This man, Jesus, too, exists by the divine existence. In him that existence is not reflected, participated, or caused ; therefore, in him it is unmeasured and unmeasurable. As St. Thomas says, " the Son of God assumed a human nature that THE MODALITY OF BEING 69 he [the Son] might be visible to men in it." 17 It is literally true that those who saw the man Jesus looked upon the only begotten (1John1 :1). In brief, it is not because the divine existence makes Jesus' human nature to be that Jesus is God; it is because Jesus is God that his human nature exists. Further, as we have seen, every perfection in being is from God in such wise that it does not cease to be God. Essence and existence in being are God's own perf ection shared by being through God's knowledge, which knowledge is God. All the creature is of itself (which it has also from God) is that it is not God and is totally dependent upon God, its necessary modality and relation to God. Neither the essence nor the existence of the creature is its own; they are God's. The creature has them only in that creative knowledge which is God. The words of St. John also are literally true, " the true light . . . came into his own" (John 1 :9,10). By creation God makes creatures to be. They cannot be God. They are necessarily less than God. Such is the modality that distinguishes them from God. It does not distinguish God from them but them from God. Creatures are known by God as less than God and, therefore, must always be less than God. The only begotten Son alone is known to be God and, therefore, is not made. That Word took unto itself a human nature by terminating it with the measure rather than the mode of being. This Word, made man, proclaimed the good news that God had crossed the divide of imperfection separating his creation from himself (though it never separates him from his creation) so that men might by grace become God in the kingdom of heaven, where they shall know even as they are known (1 Cor, 13 :12). Mysterium tr emend um. 11 Summa Theol., 3, q. 4, a. 4. RAHNER AND HIS CRITICS: LINDBECK AND METZ J. A. COLOMBO University of San Diego San Diego, California HE "TRANSCENDENTAL MOMENT" has been he hallmark of Rahner' s theology as well as the focus of ontroversy and criticism. This essay treats the criticisms of Rahner's theology by George Lindbeck and Johann Metz. Though Lindbeck and Metz represent very different theological positions, their critiques share a common focus : the transcendental moment in Rahner's theology. For Lindbeck, this aspect of Rahner's theology is symptomatic of a theological reductionism: the specificity of Christian faith is reduced to a cultural expression of some universal, prethematic experience. For Metz, the transcendental moment immunizes the contents of Christian faith against the challenges, dangers, and threats of history and society. This essay is divided into two parts. The first part is an exposition of Rahner's understanding of the relation between nature and grace.1 Through this focus both the theological context of the notion of transcendental revelation and Rahner's under'standing of the essence of Christianity as " the religion of imme1. References to Theological Investigations, 21 vols., various translators (New York: The Seabury Press, 1%1-88) are abbreviated by Tl, followed by the volume number. The major extended discussions of nature and grace can be found in "Concerning the Relationship between Nature and Grace," Tl, I, pp. 297-317; "Some Implications of the Scholastic Concept of Uncreated Grace," TI, I, pp. 319-346; "Reflections on the Experience of Grace," TI, III, pp. 8690; "Nature and Grace,'' TI, IV, pp. 165-188; "Questions of Controversial Theology of Justification," TI, IV, pp. 189-218; Nature and Grace. trans. Diane Wharton (New York: Herder and Herder, 1961); and Foundations of Christian Faith, trans. William Dych (New York: Seabury Press, 1978), pp. 116- 137. 71 72 J. A. COLOMBO diacy to God in his self-communication." 2 may be seen most clearly. In the second part the criticisms of George Lindbeck and Johann Metz are examined. After summarizing their criticisms, I seek to argue two points : Lindbeck has ignored the specifically Christian theological context of the transcendental turn in Rahner's theology, and Metz has misdirected his criticism, for his basic dispute with Rahner lies not with the transcendental turn in theology per se but in their differing notions of the essence of Christianity. -ICharacteristic of Rahner's theology is the close correlation he posits between Christology and anthropology. This correlation has often evoked the criticism that Rabner simply accommodates Christology to the demands of an anthropology which has a foundation independent of Christian revelation. 3 Yet from his earliest essays on Christology, Rabner has insisted upon the mutual conditioning and qualifying of each theme by the other. 4 In the hermeneutical structure of " retrieval," which for Rabner constitutes the essence of historical knowledge, 5 the nontheological preunderstanding (i.e., anthropology) which guides one's inquiry as an anticipation of meaning is corrected in the process of confronting and bringing to speech the theological subject matter (i.e., Chris2 Foundations, p. 125. As indicated at the close of the essay, I use the category " essence of Christianity" solely in Ernst Troeltsch's sense of the term: as a way of naming the necessary synthetic moment by which the systematic theologian heuristically construes the point or center of the Christian tradition:. While Rahner himself never used the language of the " essence of Christianity," his reflections on the necessity of a contemporary Kurzformel in an age characterized by " gnoseological concupiscence " in fact converge with Troeltsch's understanding of the function of the "essence of Christianity." See, "The Need for a 'Short Formula' of Christian Faith," TI, XI, pp. 230-46, and the "anthropological creed" in Foundations, pp. 456-7. a See, e.g., Walter Kaspar, Jesus The Christ, trans. V. Green (New York: Paulist Press, 1976), pp. 60£. 4" Current Problems in Christology," TI, I, pp. 158f. 5 Ibid., p. 150. The best description of the nature of "retrieval" as distinct from pure historical inquiry can be found in Spirit in the World, trans. William Dych (New York: Herder and Herder, 1968), pp. xlix-lv. RABNER AND HIS CRITICS 73 tology}. Preunderstanding and subject matter condition one another and must be thought together. This hermeneutical circle is captured and specified in the formulation ". . . Christo logy may be studied as self-transcending anthropology and anthropology as deficient Christology." 6 Anthropology conditions Christology. If the Word became flesh, then Christology must be reflected upon within the wider context of the ontological relation between Creator and his creation. Unless one wishes to affirm that the Christ is a hybrid somewhere between the human and the divine or the divine disguised in human form, one must think through-as distinct from simply repeating-some crucial christological concepts. The hypostatic union, for example, may be seen as the unique perfection of a relation between God and creature, but the relation has an analogue in the experience of all men and women. Christology conditions anthropology. Such an assertion can only be denied on the basis of an a priori claim to have achieved a self-contained, definitive understanding of human nature. Yet precisely in a situation characterized by " gnoseological concupiscence" such claims are suspect. 7 Human existence is a s " Current Problems," p. 164. 7 The description of "gnoseological concupiscence" and the way it (1) conditions the situation of contemporary theology, (2) " limits " the scope of the magisterium in intervening in the work of theologians, ( 3) renders improbable any further infallible declarations of dogma, and ( 4) has led to the decisive shift from philosophy to the empirical sciences as the major dialogue partners of theology, can be found in various essays in the later volumes of Tl. See especially "The Historicity of Theology," Tl, IX, pp. 64-82; " Pluralism in Theology and the Unity of the Creed in the Church" and "The Future of Theology," TI, XI, pp. 3-23, 137-48; "The Teaching Office of the Church in the Present-Day Crisis of Authority," TI, XII, pp. 3-30; " Possible Courses for the Theology of the Future," " The Current Relationship of between Theology and Philosophy," "Theology as Engaged in an Interdisciplinary Dialogue with the Sciences," and " On the Relationship between Theology and the Contemporary Sciences," TI, XIII, pp. 32-60, 61-79, 80-93, 94-104; and the "Dispute Concerning the Church's Teaching Office," TI, XIV, pp. 86-97. Given the nature of Lindbeck's criticisms of Rahner, it is particularly important to note that the acknowledgement of gnoseological concupiscence in Rahner's work is tantamount to the repudiation of " foundationalism " as a strategy for the grounding of theology. 74 J. A. COLOMBO muddy affair whose roots extend far below the limits of self-conscious experience and reflection and whose mediocrity often belies the self-transcendence common in day-to-day experience. By taking Christology as a clue to anthropology, Rahner seeks to unveil a dimension of human being as mystery-human being as that creature whose self-transcending dynamism is not limited to the world merely but whose ultimate term is a supernatural one : the ineffable God as the abiding mystery. As the " clue " to the meaning of all human existence and history, Christology conditions anthropology by disclosing that that which happened in the Incarnation of the Logos in human history is also that which God intends for all men and women : a sharing in his own selfcommunication. Thus a circle is completed: " Christology is the end and beginning of anthropology. And this anthropology, when most thoroughly realized in Christology, is eternally theology." 8 Again, . . . anthropology and Christology mutually determine each other within Christian dogmatics if they are both correctly understood. Christian anthropology is only able to fulfill its whole purpose if it understands man as the potentia obedientialis for the "Hypostatic Union." And Christology can only be undertaken from the point of view of this kind of transcendental anthropology.9 If this "placing" of Rahner's anthropological reflections is in fact correct, the results, I believe, are considerable. Far from being the case that Christology is accommodated to an a priori (i.e., secular) anthropology, the latter is brought within the sphere of the former as an essentially theological statement. Rahner's anthropology is a Christian anthropology. It arises from within and is conditioned by the Christian confession of faith and hence is characterized by those formal characteristics which Rahner explicates in conjunction with his discussion of the nature of doctrinal/theological assertions. 10 Specifically, even the assertions of his Christian anthropology are statements ex fide "On the Theology of the Incarnation," Tl, IV, p. 117. Tl, IX, p. 28. 10" What is a Dogmatic Statement," TI, V, pp. 42-66. 8 9" Theology and Anthropology," RAHNER AND HIS CRITICS 75 ad fidem, which ultimately must be resolved in a reductio ad mysterium. This is not to deny that such assertions may be acknowledged as credible outside the specifically Christian circle of believers and hence play an apologetic role in the theological enterprise, but it is to assert that such assertions have their origin from within the Christian community of faith and from within a Christian systematic theology and are directly and primarily addressed to that same community. As is suggested below, fundamental theology as transcendental anthropology is an abstract moment in confessional or systematic theology, as reflection on the categorical revelation of Christianity. Given Rahner's emphasis on the hermeneutical structure of historical-theological understanding, his position on nature and grace and on the nature of grace is itself contextualized by other contemporaneous positions. Specifically, he sought to steer a middle course between the positions of neo-scholasticism and the nouvelle theologie. 11 For the former, the relation between nature and grace is an extrinsic one : nature and grace appear " as two layers so carefully placed that they penetrate each other as little as possible." 12 As Diekamp expressed it: "A nature which is complete in itself and has everything necessary for itself receives the supernatural as something added on to it." 13 Such an affirmation is rooted in the neo-scholastic position that the concrete, experienced quiddity of a human being is to be identified with "pure nature." Thus the supernatural, known only through verbal revelation, must lie beyond the present range of experience of a human being, and apart from such revelation " what by himself 11 Rahner's characterization of the manualist theology can be found in "The Prospects for Dogmatic Theology," TI, I, pp. 1-19. The specific description of the neoscholastic position on grace can be found in "Nature and Grace," pp. 165f. A more " sociological " critique of that position can be found in Leonardo Eoff, Liberating Grace, trans. John Drury (New York: Orbis Press, 1979), pp. 18-25. For a characterization of the position of the nouvelle theologie, see " Relation between Nature and Grace,'' pp. 302f. 12 "Nature and Grace,'' p. 167. 1s F. Diekamp, Katholische Dogmatik, 2 :47, quoted in Eoff Liberating Grace, p.41. 76 J. A. COLOMBO he experiences of himself here and now he could have on this view also experienced in an order of pure nature." 14 Apart from the witness of Christian revelation, God's binding ordination of men and women to a supernatural end consists only in a juridical or moral decree which is external to human experience. Similarly, from the side of nature, there is no indication of an intrinsic ordination of men and women to grace, for nature as a potentia obedientialis is defined in a purely negative manner: as having a mere " non-repugnance " to supernautral grace. In Rahner's estimation, the position of the nouvelle theologie, censured in the encyclical H umani generis, fails to affirm the utter gratuity, the sheer giftedness of grace as God's self-communication in love. In this view, there is posited for concrete human nature an intrinsic and unconditional reference to grace and the beatific vision, "a natural desire for God." Grace may still be spoken of as gratuitous, yet such gratuitousness does not seem to differ qualitatively from the gratuitousness of creation itself. The problem is [t]his reference to the beatific vision was regarded in this recent view as on the one hand an intrinsic, inadmissable constituent of man's nature, and on the other hand so conceived that the withholding of the end of this directedness was expounded as being incompatible with God's wisdom and goodness and in this sense unconditional (provided of course that the creature does not fall short of the end by its own fault). We hold that with these presuppositions grace and beatific vision can no longer be said to be unexacted.15 This being the case, it is not clear whether there is any significant difference left between nature and grace at all. I will now summarize Rahner's position, and, for the sake of both brevity and clarity, I will restrict myself to a quasi-thesis format. First, the distinction between nature and grace is a distinction within the concrete created order of reality. Creation in and for itself may be spoken of as " grace" only in an improper sense, i.e., u " Relation between Nature and Grace," p. 300. 15 Ibid., p. 304. RABNER AND HIS CRITICS 77 as witnessing the freedom of God to bring forth an " other than itself" by efficient causality. 16 Thus the distinction between nature and grace applies to both prelapsarian and infralapsarian existence. Second, the ultimate basis of this distinction lies in the acknowledgement that (pure) nature, in principle, is intelligible in itself: it could conceivably " stand forth on its own." Grace as the self-communication of God to men and women in love is not constitutive of and hence not demanded by (pure) human nature for the fulfillment of its own proper exigencies and ends. Grace remains the freely given, gratuitous gift of God. Third, (pure) nature may be spoken of as possessing a potentia obedientialis for the supernatural order and this not merely in the negative sense of a " freedom from contradiction " or " nonrepugnance" of nature for grace. As potentia obedientialis, (pure) nature may be spoken of as having a radical expandability or openness for grace. Yet such openness does not include a natural desire for God in the sense of unconditional ordination toward the supernatural and thus negate th.e quality of grace as gratuitous. Fourth, in fact human beings (concrete nature) always and everywhere exist within the order of grace. Concrete human nature is always already qualified by a supernatural finality and by God's offer of himself, which is freely given to all as disclosed in His universal salvific will through Christ. The supernatural is not the unnatural, and to designate God's grace in its temporal modality as universal does not denigrate its essence as a supernatural, gratuitous self-communication of God. Fifth, the concept of " pure nature " is an abstraction and not a concrete existing entity. Pure nature does not actually occur in a pure state in the world and history. It is a hypothetical entity, what is " left over " when the supernatural is " subtracted " from concrete human existence. It thus functions as a Restbegriff, a is To anticipate, ultimately the difference in principle between "creation" and "grace" is one between efficient and (quasi-) formal causality. 78 J. A. COLOMBO " remainder concept," intelligible in itself, which points to the graced graciousness of concrete human existence. Sixth, for Rahner then, the mistake of the neo-scholastics was to confuse and exchange an abstraction (pure nature) for what concretely exists (concrete human nature as always already graced) and what was concrete (the supernatural as a de facto existential of human existence) for what is abstract (the supernatural as tangential to concrete human existence). The mistake of the nouvelle thiologie was to eliminate the concept of pure nature by simply identifying it with concrete human existence and endowing this latter with a natural and unconditional orientation to grace and glory. Seventh, analogous to the relations between concrete nature, grace, and pure nature and on the basis of the a posteriori experience of Christian salvation history, creation in and for itself must also be seen as an abstraction. In the single divine decree of God, while creation must be seen as the conditfon of the possibility of " covenant " (the self-communication of God to spirit and history), it must also be said that the actuality of creation inl fact rests on God's decree for his self-communication to spirit and history. 17 Thus the Incarnation as the unique and absolute, unsurpassable self-communication of God to humanity and the man Jesus' unique and absolute self-transcending acceptance of God, which all men and women participate in to various degrees through grace and glory, may be spoken of as the apex, the goal of creation and that in view of which it is called into being.18 11 "We shall say, therefore, that what we mean by the creation is that the divine being freely ' exteriorises ' his own activity so as to produce non-divine being, but does this solely in order to produce the necessary prior conditions for his own divine self-bestowal in that free and unmerited love that is identical with himself; that he does this in order to raise up beings who can stand in a personal relationship to himself and so receive his message, and on whom he can bestow not only finite and created being distinct from himself, but himself as well." "Intellectual Honesty and Christian Faith," TI, VII, p. 62. 18 See "Christology within an Evolutionary View of the World," Tl, V, pp. 157-93; "The Unity of Spirit and Matter in the Christian Understanding of Faith," TI, VI, pp. 153-77; and "Christology in the Setting of Modem Man's RAHNER AND HIS CRITICS 79 This relation between creation and covenant is ultimately given its quintessential formulation in the Christian doctrine of the Trinity. 19 Eighth, in sum, the relations between "pure nature," "concrete nature," "the ordination, call and offer of a supernatural finality," and the " fulfillment of such an ordination by an absolute self-communication of God in the Incarnation and glory " appear as follows. Pure nature is " open " to a supernatural finality and hence also to the consummation of the self-communication of God in glory. As spirit, concrete nature is always qualified by a supernatural finality which always assumes some " having" of its object, even in the mode of an offer and anticipation. In principle, this offer does not demand for its integrity an actual absolute self-communication of God or its consummation in the immediate vision of God, while in fact such actualization is historical (Incarnatfon) and also universal (glory), given man's acceptance of God's offer. Rahner posits such a distinction given the integrity and intelligibility of a conception of man in freedom before and towards God where his goal is only asymptotically realized. 20 Understanding Himself and of His World," TI, XI pp. 215-29. For a critique of contemporary forms of Scotist Christocentrism, see Eugene Teselle, Christ in Context (Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1975). 19 The doctrine of the Trinity plays a peculiar role in Rahner's theology. On the one hand, in the ordo cognoscendi it is the last of all Christian doctrines and the conclusion of theology ; on the other hand, in the ordo essendi it is the presupposition of Christian faith and, indeed, world, spirit, and history. The " operators " of such a movement are the a posteriori experience of Christian salvation history and an analysis of the concept of a self-revelation of God. The result is Rahner's axiom of the identity between the economic and immanent Trinity. Yet it is precisely at this point that a danger arises, for it appears that the speaker has taken up a position ab aeterno and abandoned the historicity of his own starting point as well. Especially at this point it is important to sort out the relation between fundamental and systematic theology as well as the relation between propositions regarding the ordo essendi and the ordo cognoscendi. For Rahner's position, see The Trinity, trans. Joseph Donceel (New York: Seabury Press, 1974), and "The Mystery of the Trinity," TI, XVI pp. 255-9. 20" Nature and Grace," p. 186. 80 J. A. COLOMBO To be ordained to grace, and to be so constituted that there is an exigency for grace which would render the whole ordination to grace futile if grace were not actually imparted, are by no means the same thing. Spirit, that is openness for God, freedom and self-conscious possession, is essentially impossible without a transcendence whose absolute fulfillment is grace. Still a fulfillment of this sort is not owed to it, if we suppose that this self-conscious possession in freedom before God is meaningful in itself, and not just as a pure means and a mere stage on the way to the beatific vision. Again, Rahner refers to this same distinction within the one de facto movement of grace by asserting " in grace the spirit moves within its goal (because of God's self-communication) toward its goal (the beatific vision)." 21 This distinction between, yet linking together of, the offer and the consummation of God's self-communication becomes especially important in the question of "uncreated grace." Ninth, concrete human nature is a composite of pure nature and grace. No precise delimitation may be made between the two in human experience; we cannot assign some parts of experience to the realm of pure nature and others to the realm of grace. 22 Further, grace ought best be conceived not as a static quality but as a dynamic orientation given in human existence (an existential). It follows from the above that the self-transcending dynamism of man and its fulfillment is always already qualified by grace and falls within a human being's consciousness and experience, though in any given individual it may not be self-consciously adverted to or adequately expressed. 23 Tenth, this relation, whereby the human being is conditionally yet constitutively oriented toward God and whereby a new formal object forming man's horizon is given him, is what Rahner p. 130. to the relation between nature and grace is that between philosophy and theology. See "Philosophy and Theology," TI, VI, pp. 72f. 23" Nature and Grace," p. 183. See also, "Reflections on the Experience of Grace," TI, III, pp. 86-90; "Reflections on the Unity of the Love of Neighbor and the Love of God," TI, VI, pp. 231-249; and "Religious Enthusiasm and the Experience of Grace," TI, XVI, pp. 35-51. 21 Foundatfons, 2 2 Analogous RAHNER AND HIS CRITICS 81 terms the "transcendental relation between God and man." 24 As formal object, God as the ultimate mystery is no mere object of knowledge or ontic object to be decided for or against in freedom but rather something implicit and prethematic. God is that horizon or background within which (and indeed on account of which) all objects of cognition or acts of human freedom come to pass and are acted upon. 25 This universal relation between God and men and women defines the original relation between spirit and God by which the experience of the self and the experience of God are inextricably intertwined. 26 While, therefore, experience of God and experience of self are not simply identical, still both of them exist within a unity of such a kind that apart from this unity it is quite impossible for there to be any such experiences at all.... This unity consists far more in the fact that the original and ultimate experience of God constitutes the enabling condition of, and an intrinsic element in, the experience of self in such a way that without this experience of God no experience of self is possible. . . . Of course the point could equally be formulated the other way around. The experience of the self is the condition which makes it possible to experience God. The reason is that an orientation to being in the absolute, and so to God, can be present only when the subject (precisely in the act of reaching out towards being in the absolute) is made present to himself as something distinct from his own act and as the subject of that act. 27 This original, prethematic, yet real relation between God and the self is truly transcendental, that is, the condition of the possibility for the intelligibility for all explicit religious assertions. In a unique way, "the final a priori precondition for the subject's theological knowledge, i.e., grace (ultimately the self-communicat24 Foundations, pp. 1-160; esp. pp. 153f. pp. 135-46. "The Experience of God Today," Tl, XI, pp. 149-65; "Experience of Self and Experience of God," TI, XIII, pp. 122-31; "Theology and Anthropology," TI, IX, pp. 28-45 and "Reflections on Methodology in Theology," Tl, XI, pp. 84-101. A fine exposition of Rahner's use of the transcendental method can be found in Anne Carr, The Theological Method of Karl Rahner (Missoula, Mont.: Scholars Press, 1977). 27 " Experience of Self," p. 125. 25 Spirit, 26 See 82 J. A. COLOMBO ing God, acting freely in history) is the real content, or rather, the objective foundation of what is known and experienced a posteriori in history." 28 As such, Rahner can call the explicit, thematic, or categorical/predicamental history of religions the history of the transcendental relationship between God and men. 29 From this position drawn within a Christian dogmatics, Rahner posits the reality of an " anonymous Christian," based upon the reality of a " universal salvific will of God " but distilled from the confession of Jesus as the Christ (as the absolute self-communication of God to humanity), the identity of the immanent and economic Trinity, and hence the Christocentricity of creation. 30 Theology and Anthropology," p. 30. Foundations, pp. 140-2. 30 The theorem of the " anonymous Christian " and " implicit theism " are among the most controversial in Rahner's theology. The central texts may be found in: " Membership of the Church According to the Teaching of Pius XII's Encyclical 'Mystici Corporis Christi'," TI II, pp. 1-88; "History of the World and Salvation History," "Christianity and the Non-Christian Religions," and "Christianity and the 'New Man'," Tl, V, pp. 97-114, 115-34, 135-43; "Anonymous Christians," Tl, VI, pp. 390-8; "Atheism and Implicit Christianity," Tl, IX, pp. 145-64; "Church, Churches and Religions," Tl, X, pp. 30-49; "Theological Considerations on Secularization and Atheism," Tl, XI, pp. 166-84; "Anonymous Christianity and the Missionary Task of the Church," Tl, XII, pp. 161-78; "Observations on the Problem of the 'Anonymous Christian'," Tl, XIV, pp. 280-94; and "The One Christ and the Universality of Salvation," Tl, XVI, pp. 199-224. A common criticism of this theorem is the charge of theological imperalism: a particular categorical event (the Christ) is described not only as manifesting in an eschatological and definitive sense the self-communication of God to the world but also as constituting that self-communication as an existential of human existence. It would appear that it is precisely the gnoseological concupiscence about which Rahner speaks that renders any such identification illicit. The scope of this essay prohibits any lengthy treatment of the theme, and hence only three brief comments will be made. First, the anonymous Christian is a theorem derived from a Christian systematic theology. Second, if, given the situation of gnoseological concupiscence, the identification of Jesus as the eschatological manifestation of God is a proleptic statement, then the assertion of the existence of " anonymous christians " is also a proleptic one. Third, the theological basis of the possibility of an anonymous Christian is to be found in the doctrine of the Trinity and not some pretheological transcendental anthropology. "Prior to any subjective attitude, man is really different from what he would be as a mere creature and mere sinner, because 2s " 29 RAHNER AND HIS CRITICS 83 Such a horizon or call of God to man may be either explicitly or implicitly accepted or rejected by human freedom, though never with definitiveness (apart from the privileged moment of " death ") and never with an adequate self-certainty. 31 Yet even if rejected, the concrete nature of human being remains such that it is installed " in a supernatural order which man can never leave, even as a sinnner and unbeliever." 82 Thus, the impossible possibility of an " absolute contradiction " remains open to men and women. 33 Eleventh, in contradistinction to the scholastic theory wherein God's self-bestowal of himself upon men and women (uncreated grace) is made in virtue of and as a consequence of an absoredemption has taken place in Christ" ["Controversial Theology," p. 200J.. This "is", is the supernatural existential: " ... prior to any subjective appropriation of salvation, man is inwardly determined by a supernatural existential, which consists in the fact that Christ in his death ' justified ' sinful man before the all-holy God" [ibid.]. While such an affirmation might conceivably cover all those contemporaneous to the Christ or those living after him, there is still the problem of the justified " before Christ " and the status of the affirmation that in the infralapsarian order all men and women concretely exist under the supernatural existential. Given the identity of the economic and immanent Trinity, one is permitted to say that creation as wrought by God's efficient causality in this concrete order is founded upon the single eternal decree of God to communicate his very self to human beings in grace and glory in the manner of a (quasi-) formal causality. Therefore all infralapsarian grace would be given to men and women " in view of the Incarnation," which is the historical consummation and eschatological manifestation of the one single decree of God to communicate himself absolutely and be received irrevocably by human beings. Yet precisely insofar as the theorem of the anonymous Christian has its foundation in the doctrine of the Trinity, the remarks noted above (n. 19) apply here also. s1 See "Guilt-Responsibility-Punishment within the View of Catholic Theology" and" Justified and Sinner at the Same Time," TI, VI, pp. 197-217, 218-30. On the priority of death, by which men and women dispose of the entirety of their existence as a "whole," see "Theological Considerations on the Moment of Death," TI, XI, pp. 309-21 and "Ideas for a Theology of Death," TI, XIII, pp. 169-86. On the Christological parallel of the finality and decisiveness of the death of Jesus as a faithful exercise of his freedom, see Karl Rahner and Wilhelm Thiising, A New Christology, trans. D. Smith and V. Green (New York: Seabury Press, 1980), pp. 32-41. s2" Nature and Grace," p. 180. ss Foundations, pp. 97-106. 84 J. A. COLOMBO lute entitative modification and determination of human being (created grace), Rahner reverses the relationship and asserts that in a real sense uncreated grace must accompany and even precede created grace. Twelfth, the major principle operative in this affirmation is the continuity that is posited between grace and glory. As Cardinal Newman states it, grace is glory in exile and glory is grace arrived at in its homeland. Grace and glory constitute the two continuous stages of the single divinization of men and women. Thus the nature of God's communication to men and women in grace may be seen more clearly when the ontology of the visio beatifica is applied to the question of grace. Thirteenth, in the ontology of the beatific vision, there is an isomorphism between the knower and the known by means of the species in the created mind: knower and known are really the " same thing " entitatively. Such a species cannot be a created one, given the disparity between the nature of the species as created and the being of God. Therefore, " the reality of the mind in the beatific vision, so far as such a reality in itself is due to a species as the means of knowledge, is the very being of God. " 34 Hence, the nature of such a communication is not properly designated as one of efficient causality or production of another out of a cause; rather, it must be noted as a mode of formal causality, "a taking up into the ground," where the cause becomes a real, intrinsic principle of the effect. In grace, the giver himself is the gift. It is precisely this communication of grace which ultimately empowers the self-transcendence of spirit in knowledge and freedom and leads to that restlessness with all but the holy mystery. 35 Rahner denotes the causality of God's self-communication as one of quasi-formal causality so as to emphasize the analogical nature of the concept used. It must be maintained, first, that such a self-communication does not divide God from himself or subject him to the difference posited therein : " the intrinsic constitutive 34" Uncreated Grace," p. 332. a;;" Nature and Grace," p. 184. RAH NER AND HIS CRITICS 85 cause retains in itself its own essence absolutely intact and in absolute freedom." 36 Second, it must be maintained that in such a communication (and even when consummated in glory), God remains the permanent and absolute mystery as such. " Grace is the grace of the nearness of the abiding mystery : it makes God accessible in the form of the holy mystery and presents him thus as the incomprehensible." 37 Such a mystery is not merely the term of an " unknowing " as " ignorance " but is an abiding with the fullness of being itself where knowledge is surpassed, preserved, and transformed and passes over to the other in the immediacy of love.38 Lastly, because in uncreated grace there is a true self-communication of God and because such a God is confessed in Christian salvation history to be essentially triune (the identity of the economic and essential Trinity), it must be maintained that the relations of men and women to each person of the Trinity are not merely appropriated relations. Each of the divine persons is present and operative in men and women according to its notional properties: the Father as absolute mystery, 39 the Son as knowledge and truth, and the Spirit as love and union. Rahner's reflections on nature and grace open up a Christian vision of spirit in the world and its history wherein the world in fact exists by, for, and within a graced graciousness. Men and women truly do live in a divine milieu, for human existence occurs always and everywhere within a world suffused and permeated by grace. " God has always given himself, as himself with his glory, to the world as power, origin and good in the mode of an offer to the freedom of that world." 40 As an offer accepted in freedom, it is God himself as Triune which is communicated 36 Foundations, p. 121. The Concept of Mystery in Catholic Theology," TI, IV, p. 56. s See " Concept of Mystery in Catholic Theology "; " Reflections on Methodology," TI XI, pp. 101-14; "The Hiddenness of God" and "An Investigation of the Incomprehensibility of God in St. Thomas Aquinas," TI, XVI, pp. 227-43, 244-54. 3 9 " Theos in the New Testament," TI, I pp. 79-148. • 0 A New Christology, p. 25. 37 " 3 86 J. A. COLOMBO to incarnate spirit. Indeed, one may say that in the dialogue of grace between God and creature, God becomes anthropomorphic, while men and women become theomorphic. 41 -IIIn The Nature of Doctrine: Religion and Theology in a Postliberal Age/ 2 George Lindbeck argues for two positions: a " cultural-linguistic " model of religion against an " experiential-expressive" model; a " regulative theory of doctrine " against both " propositionalist " and " symbolist " theories. While showing some elective affinity for one another, Lindbeck's two positions are nevertheless both distinct and separate from one another. Since Lindbeck's cursory comments on Rahner largely concern the first issue, I will not address the question of doctrine here. Important questions regarding the precise explication of the two models of religion and whether these models are mutually exclusive, as Lindbeck intimates, are also beyond the scope of this essay. My interest here lies solely in Lindbeck's identification of Rabner as a proponent of the " experiential-expressive " model. Lindbeck identifies four affirmations which constitute the core of the experiential-expressive understanding of religion: ( 1) Different religions are diverse expressions or objectifications of a common core experience. It is this experience which identifies them as religions. (2) The experience, while conscious, may be unknown on the level of self-conscious reflection. ( 3) It is present in all human beings. ( 4) In most religions, the experience is the source and norm of objectifications: it is by reference to the experience that their adequacy or lack of adequacy is to be judged. 43 Religion is modeled more on the understanding of art than science. It is seen simply as the "expressive and evocative objectification (i.e., nondiscursive symbols) of internal experience." u 41" Theology of the Incarnation," pp. 107-10. Lindbeck, The N atitre of Doctrine: Religion and Theology in a Postliberal Age (Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1984). o Ibid., p. 31. u Ibid., p. 21. 42 George 87 RAHNER AND HIS CRITICS Lindbeck suggests that this " suspicious secular-looking model of religion " 45 dominates in theological circles because it represents an accommodation to the sensibilities of modernity. This model mirrors the modern understanding of the self as an abstract universal. It sees only an extrinsic connection between public religious traditions and private religious experience. It relativizes public religious traditions in relation to a specific form of private experience and sees this as a universal characteristic of human religious experience. The experiential-expressive model represents, by consequence if not by intent, a leveling of the specific content of particular religious traditions in an implicit reductionism : individual religious traditions are nothing but an accidental cultural determination-expression of some identical, prethematic, core Sache which is accessible to a more basic phenomenological or ontological analysis. Against this position, Lindbeck advances a " cultural-linguistic " model of religion in which a particular system of religion is regarded as grounding a particular " form of life " : " a religion can be viewed as a kind of cultural and/or linguistic framework or medium that shapes the entirety of life and thought." 46 In this model, the relation between internal experience and objectified religious tradition is reversed-the latter is productive of and the norm of the former. Particular religious traditions thus operate like a Kantian a priori : . . . while there are of course nonreflective experiences, there are no uninterpreted or unschematized ones. On this view, the means of communication or expression are a precondition, a kind of quasitranscendental (i.e., culturally formed) a priori for the possibility of experience. We cannot identify, describe or recognize experience qua experience without the use of signs or symbols.47 Here, " becoming religious " is less a matter of voluntary association by which the believer expresses an internal, private experience complete in itself through a particular system of religion; it is more like becoming competent in a language, the acquisition of 's Ibid., p. 22. •s Ibid., p. 33. 4 1 Ibid., p. 36. 88 J. A. COLOMBO a set of skills by which one interprets the world and has any experience at all. Within the " cultural-linguistic " model, a postliberal theology is one that is antifoundational and narrative. It is antifoundational in that it repudiates the quest to ground particular systems of religion in some " neutral, framework-independent language " 48 regarding human subjectivity and its private yet universally prethematic experience. It is narrative in that it sees the primary task of theology as an explication of the intratextual meaning of that religion's fundamental narratives: "intratextual theology redescribes reality within the scriptural framework rather than translating Scripture into extrascriptural categories." 49 Lindbeck suggests-in an all too oblique manner-that Rahner's work, especially his use of the transcendental method (the positing of a Vorgriff auf esse and a real, prethematic knowledge of God) and the notion of implicit faith, falls clearly into the experiential-expressive model. To be sure, much of Rahner's language resonates with this model. Yet, is Lindbeck correct in this identification of Rahner's work? I think not. As the exposition of the position on nature and grace suggests, the relation between transcendental and categorical revelation cannot be simply understood under the rubric, " the latter is nothing but the explicit expression of the former." Rahner himself asserts so much in Foundations of Christian Faith: . . . Christianity assumes that these presuppositions which it makes are inescapably and necessarily present in the ultimate depths of human existence, even when this existence is interpreted differently in its reflexive self-interpretation, and that at the same time the Christian message itself creates these presuppositions by its call.... The presuppositions which are to be considered here refer to man's essential being. They refer to his essential being as something which is always historically constituted, and thus as existing in confrontation with Christianity as grace and historical message.50 In positing a real, prethematic knowledge of God, Rahner's transcendental anthropology is a theological anthropology, always .a Ibid., p. 130. •11 Ibid., p. 118. 110 Foundations,pp. 24-5. RAH NER AND HIS CRITICS 89 already marked by the witness of categorical revelation, i.e., that grace as the supernatural existential is given to human beings in view of the Incarnation. Like the concept of pure nature, a " pure " transcendental anthropology is a Restbegriff, an abstraction which does not actually occur in a pure state in the world. Further, like the distinction between grace and nature, there can be no final delimitation between a natural transcendental anthropology and a theological one. The former concept remains a limit-axiom. The notions of a " supernatural existential," " implicit faith," and " anonymous Christian " are thus not theorems derived from the more " basic " propositions of a secular transcendental anthropology and hence a "foundational" theology in Lindbeck's sense of the term. They are derived from the sphere of a Christian systematic theology as reflection on categorical revelation. In this sense, Rahner's use of the transcendental method and his understanding of transcendental revelation and implicit faith differ qualitatively from that of Schubert Ogden whose position more closely approximates the " implicit-explicit " rubric of the experiential-expressive model. As Ogden asserts: Although such revelation [categorical] cannot be necessary for the constitution of human existence, it can very well be necessary to the objectification of existence, in the sense of its full and adequate understanding at the level of explicit thought and speech.51 Rahner differs from Ogden in affirming that not only is categorical revelation the full, adequate, and decisive objectification of the constitution of human existence, but also that concrete human existence as graced is constituted by the categorical event of the Christ, which is fully, adequately, and explicitly acknowledged in the Christian religion. This leads to a peculiar interrelationship between fundamental and systematic theology. Fundamental theology as transcendental 51 Schubert Ogden, "On Revelation," Our Common History as Christians: Essays in Honor of Albert C. Outler, eds. J. Deschner, L. T. Howe, and K. Penzel (New York: Oxford University Press, 1975), p. 284. 90 J. A. COLOMBO anthropology is reflection on the condition of the possibility of human being as a " hearer of the word." While propositions on this matter are first in the ordo essendi, they are second in the ordo cogn;oscendi. Systematic theology as reflection on the categorical specificity of the Christian tradition is the reverse: first in the ordo cognoscendi, but second in the ordo essendi. In Rahner's execution of the theological enterprise, as is visible in his position on nature and grace, fundamental theology remains an abstract moment of systematic theology, essentially bound in its claims regarding the ordo essendi by its stance as always already acknowledging the claim of categorical revelation in the ordo cognoscendi. In this manner, the historicity of the standpoint of the theologian and the reality of gnoseological concupiscence are preserved in the theological enterprise and condition the status of propositions deriving from fundamental theology. Propositions regarding the ordo essendi in Rahner's fundamental theology are proleptic insofar as the content of such propositions is founded in the doxological confession that " Jesus is the Christ." Thus, Lindbeck's categorization of Rahner strikes me as simply wrong and a diversion from what I suspect is the real locus of disagreement: the description of the task and procedure of systematic theology as intra textual. Yet it is here that the constructive aspect of Lindbeck's work breaks down. More precisely, intratextuality has both a formal and material significance in Lindbeck's text. Formally, it specifies the methodological exigency of systematic theology : to redescribe " reality within the scriptural framework rather than translating Scripture into extrascriptural categories." Materially, it refers to Lindbeck's own instantiation of this methodological exigency in the form of a " Barthian realism." 52 Even if the formal exigency is acceptedand what this means remains elusive in the text-what has not been proven is that the latter is the only or most appropriate 62 For a description and defense of "Barthian realism," see David F. Kelsey, The Use of Scripture in Recent Theology (Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1975), pp. 39-50, and Hans Frei, The Eclipse of Biblical Narrative (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1974). RAHNER AND HIS CRITICS 91 formulation of the former. Lacking this, however, the weight of Lindbeck' s criticism defaults to his characterization of Rahner as an " experiential-expressivist." This is simply misguided. Much like Lindbeck's, Metz's criticism of Rahner focuses on the transcendental moment of Rahner's theology. Indeed, Metz contrasts Rahner's "transcendental-idealistic" understanding of theology with his own understanding of theology as " narrativepractical." Using the fairy-tale of "the hedgehog and the hare," 53 Metz charges that Rahner's theology secures the historical identity of Christian faith ahistorically, through a "transcendental omnipresence." As is most clearly seen in the theorem of the " anonymous Christian " and the isomorphism posited there between transcendental and categorical revelation, the content of Christian faith is so construed as to be in principle immunized against the dangers and threats of the concrete events of history and society. Further, the exigency for a socialhistorical mediation of Christian faith in the specific praxis of solidarity with the suffering is attenuated. Grace (the self-communication of God) and hence the substance of Christianity itself (the religion of immediacy to God in his self-communication) is like the hedgehog: it is always already vindicated in the world in the subjectivity of the subject, without having to "run the race" and seek its vindication in the worldliness of the world, in history and society. The thrust of Metz's objection to Rahner is clearer: Rahner's transcendental theology represents an anthropological reduction of history and society, the occlusion of the historical suffering of 53 " One Sunday morning, the hedgehog is going for a walk in a ploughed field and a hare teases him about his bandy legs. He challenges the hare to a race in the furrows of the field. First, however, he goes home to breakfast because, as he tells the hare, he cannot run on an empty stomach. He then returns with his wife, who is exactly the same in appearance as her husband, and gets her to stand at the far end of the furrow. He himself stands at the other end beside the hare in another furrow. The hare falls for this trick. He runs and runs in his furrow, but the hedgehog is (in both positions) 'always already ' there. In the end, the hare falls dead from exhaustion on the field." Johann Metz, Faith in History and Society, trans. David Smith (New York: Seabury Press, 1980), p. 161. 92 J. A. COLOMBO men and women, a symptom of the privatization of Christianity and an immunization of its truth claims vis-a-vis secular history. 54 But the precise locus of his disagreement is not clear. Is Metz's objection to the transcendental turn to the subject as such or to a specific execution of this turn? If the latter, then what in particular is being objected to in Rahner's theology? Clearly Metz desires to distance himself from transcendental theology, if by the term one means the theology of Rahner, but that Metz repudiates the transcendental turn in general is questionable. (The term can mean a reflection on the condition of the possibility of the intelligibility of (Christian) categorical revelation through a turn to the subject.) I believe that what Metz objects to in Rahner's theology is the turn to the subject as the subject of knowledge, the subsequent positing of a Vorgriff auf esse as the condition of the possibility of knowledge and the intelligibility of religion, and the further theological identification of this transcendental anticipation as graced nature with the substance of categorical (Christian) revelation. Metz counters that the subject as the subject of knowledge is an abstraction, for that subject is always already mediated by history and society. Thus, in his starting point, Rahner's transcendental reflection circumvents the issue of whether " the conditions governing knowledge in a changing world also change themselves, in other words, that they cannot simply be determined in a purely reflective way (as factors that are given or present.)" 55 Metz's practical fundamental theology does not negate the turn to the subject; rather, it extends this turn by considering the subject not in its historicity, an abstract existential, but in its history, that is, as it is constituted by its specific placement in a particular social totality. 56 H Faith in History and Society, pp. 62-65. 55 Ibid., p. 81. 56 This aspect of Metz's polemic against Rahner resembles in both its form and content an earlier philosophical one: Theodor Adorno's against Martin Heidegger. See Theodor Adorno, The Jargon of Authenticity, trans. Knut Tarnowski and Frederic Will (Evanston: Northwestern University Press 1973), and Negative Dialectics, trans. E. B. Ashton (New York: Seabury Press, 1973), pp. 97-133. RABNER AND HIS CRITICS 93 Related to this, Metz disagrees with how Rahner construes "anticipation," the condition of the possibility of human subjectivity in freedom. In positing a Vorgriff auf esse, "the transcendental pre-apprehension ( Vorgriff) of Being as a whole is concerned with what exists (Bestehendes) and not with what develops (Entstehendes) ." 57 By his construal of the anticipatory character of subjectivity in terms of a metaphysics of esse, history, particularly the openness and indeterminateness of the future, is occluded in Rahner's theology. Metz is not denying the anticipatory character of human subjectivity or claiming that this is a matter of irrelevance to religion. Quite to the contrary, he affirms that although we theologians do not like to speak about the claim to universality [of religion], there is apparently no ' discourse about God ' which is not, at least tendentially and implicitly, an (anticipatory) discourse about the whole of reality.58 His dispute is with how this anticipation is characterized. For Metz, in positing a V orgriff auf esse Rahner miscontrues both the manner in which this anticipation is mediated, as historical and practical, and its Sache, as a vision of the process of becoming and history Further, Metz affirms that religion has a peculiar relation to this anticipation : its subversive power to interrupt hegemonous social totalities arises from its subject matter as an anticipatory discourse about God and hence the whole of reality. In a real sense, the elaboration of a practical fundamental theology is itself an exercise in transcendental reflection : the description of how the interest in freedom of the subject is itself historically, socially, and practically mediated by " dangerous memories " in narrative form. 59 57 Johann Metz, "Die Rede von 'Ende der M etaphysik' und die Theologies" (unpublished manuscript, 1966), p. 17 cited in Roger Dick Johns, Man in the World: The Theology of Johannes Baptist Metz, American Academy of Religion Dissertation Series, no. 16 (Missoula, Mont.: Scholars Press, 1976), p. 96. 58 Metz, "Zu einer interdizipliniir orientierten Theologie auf bikonf essioneller Basis: Erste Orientierung anhand eines konkreten Projekts," in Die Theologie in der interdizipliniir Forschung, eds. J. Metz and T. Rendtorff (Diisseldorf: Bertelsmann Universitatsverlag, 1971), p. 21. Translation mine. ou Faith i·n History and Society, pp. 184-237. 94 J. A. COLOMBO The material theological disagreement becomes clear in Metz's estimate of the essence of Christianity and his assertion of a caesura between the interest in freedom of the subject and the specificity of Christianity's dangerous memory as memoria passionis et resurrectionis J esu. Christianity " intends the anticipation of a particular future of man as a future for the suffering, the hopeless, the oppressed, the injured and the useless of the earth." 60 Again, Christian faith is a hope in solidarity in the God of Jes us as a God of the living and the dead who calls all men to be subjects in his presence. Christians justify themselves in this essentially apocalyptic praxis (of imitation) in their historical struggle for their fellow men.61 The point of Christianity is here construed not as the religion of the nearness of the Abiding Mystery but as the religion which announces a promise to the world and calls men and women to solidarity with those who suffer in the world. Despite his often global and unguarded remarks about transcendental theology, Metz's fundamental disagreement with Rahner does not concern the transcendental turn in theology as such. His objection is against a specific interpretation where the " essence of Christianity " as categorical revelation is posited as isomorphic with transcendental revelation. Rahner's position includes two steps. First, the interpretive determination of the essence of Christianity and, second, the identification of Christian revelation so construed with human beings' transcendental orientation as graced nature. This second step is clearly dependent upon the first: the interpretation of Christianity as "the religion of immediacy to God in his self-communication." Metz's disagreement with Rahner is fundamentally a difference in describing what is central in the Christian message, what the focus is through which both the Christian tradition and the world are to be interpreted. For Rahner, this focus is the Incarnation and the hypostatic union, and it is through his understanding of these so Ibid., p. 117. Sl Ibid., p. 73. RABNER AND HIS CRITICS 95 mysteries that transcendental and categorical revelation are identified as isomorphic. For Metz, this focus is the memoria passionis et resurrectionis J esu, and it is through his understanding of this that a caesura is preserved between the transcendental orientation of subjectivity, its interest in freedom, and Christianity. It is the collapsing of this caesura which Metz objects to through the fairy-tale of the hedgehog and the hare. To reduce the root of their disagreement to their differing estimates of the transcendental method is, in my judgement, misguided; it overlooks the fact that just as there is a hermeneutic circle between Rahner's anthropology and Christology so also there is one operative in Metz's. In short, their disagreement is essentially a theological one. Who is "correct?" My hunch is that Lindbeck would side with Metz against Rahner, claiming that the latter has strayed too far from the exigency of intratextuality and the scriptural categories to a derivative dogmatic tradition. Is Metz then more faithful to the specificity of categorical revelation than Rahner or vice versa? The " answer " to this question is itself dependent upon the answer to a prior question: How should one construe the point of categorical revelation and thus interpret the " essence of Christianity? " In his essay "What Does ' Essence of Christianity' Mean?" Ernst Troeltsch attempted to explicate the category " essence of Christianity " as the mediating link between fundamental and dogmatic theology and as naming the locus of the basic synthetic activity of the theologian as he or she continues the traditio of the Christian tradition in the present. 62 The positing of the essence of Christianity is not the abstraction of a " least common denominator " from the past tradition. It is the determination, comprised of a complex of critical judgments about the past tradition and the present intellectual, social, and pastoral situation of men and women, of an interpretive center for dogmatic theu Ernst Troeltsch, " What Does ' Essence of Christianity ' Mean? " in Ernst Troelstch: Writings on Theology and Religion, trans. and eds. Robert Morgan and Michael Pye (Atlanta: John Knox Press, 1977), pp. 124-81. 96 J. A. COLOMBO ology which functions simultaneously as a critical, developmental, and ideal principle. As Troeltsch wrote After a long and careful consideration of the past, present and future, after extending one's view over as much detail as possible, after taking into account all available cases which might further understanding through comparison; there remains one final act, in which the purely historical which belongs to the past and the normative which belongs to the future are combined in the judgment of the present. . . . To define the essence is to shape it afresh.63 As such, the category " essence of Christianity " denotes the broad preunderstanding of the point of the Christian tradition as a whole; it is a necessary condition for the more detailed explication of any of Christianity's dogmatic parts. The disagreement between Metz and Rabner (and, perhaps, Lindbeck and Rabner) lies not so much in the foreground disputes about transcendental method as in the background of their respective judgments concerning the "essence of Christianity." That this category was discredited as the epitome of theological liberalism with the Barthian revolution was perhaps inevitable. That this category came to be seen as a symptom of relativistic historicism in Troeltsch's own work is perhaps appropriate. That it needs to be retrieved to name accurately the locus of theological disagreement and the source of theological pluralism and that it can be retrieved without the implications of relativistic historicism is something to be pondered. 64 This remains, however, a task to be done. es Ibid., p. 161-2. 64 To pursue this topic further would be to write another essay. That such a suggestion, however, is not a blind one can be adumbrated in two recent works: David Tracy, Plurality and Ambiguity (San Francisco: Harper and Row, 1987), and Richard Bernstein, Beyond Objectivism and Relativism (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1983). Particularly in its final chapter, Tracy's book highlights the complexity and unavoidability of "interpretation" in the work of constructive (systematic) theology. Bernstein's book articulates a hermeneutical understanding of rationality whereby both the positions of objectivism and relativism, positions which haunted Troeltsch in his later work, may be overcome. LONERGAN'S "CRITICAL REALISM" AND RELIGIOUS PLURALISM TIMOTHY R. STINNETT University of Detroit Mercy Detroit, Michigan T HE PHENOMENON of religious pluralism is raising ome basic questions for philosophical thought that must e faced not only by philosophies not linked to any particular religious tradition but also by the theologies or philosophies of specific religious traditions. Christian theologians seem first to have discovered the range of questions raised by religious pluralism in the face of apparently conflicting truth claims. No less important, however, are certain moral questions: how the advocates of the various religious traditions should bear witness to their respective traditions, and how they should go about identifying and correcting the ideological biases that seem inevitably to occur as the result of the historical and cultural conditions in which their respective witnesses emerge and develop. Thus, a philosophical treatment of religious pluralism will need to make explicit the relevant conditions of truth by which religious claims must be assessed. It will also need to clarify how apparently conflicting truth claims may be examined to see whether they are genuinely conflicting and then how genuinely conflicting truth claims may be adjudicated. Bernard Lonergan's philosophy of critical realism may be considered a valuable resource for addressing such questions insofar as he undertakes to answer such fundamental questions as " What am I doing when I am knowing? Why is doing that knowing? What do I know when I do it? " 1 Attention to these questions 1 Bernard Lonergan, Method vn Theology (New York: The Seabury Press, 1979), p. 25. See also Bernard Lonergan, A Third Collection: Papers by Bernard I. F. Lonergan, S.J., edited by Frederick E. Crowe, S.J. (New York: Paulist Press, 1985), p. 210. 97 98 TIMOTHY R. STINNETT promises clarification about how religious truth claims may be shown to be true (and thus to count as " knowledge ") and how genuinely conflicting truth claims may be adjudicated. It also promises to clarify how one may recognize ideological bias and correct for it in a fully reflective understanding of a particular religious witness. For Lonergan, answers to the three questions cited above provide respectively a cognitional theory, an epistemology, and a metaphysics, all three of which together constitute his philosophy of critical realism. 2 In this essay I will explore the relevance of his critical realism for philosophical treatment of questions raised by religious pluralism. After an analysis of the salient features of Lonergan's philosophy, I will consider the disadvantages and advantages it affords a philosophy of religious pluralism. By attending to the disadvantages I will register an immanent criticism of Lonergan's critical realism, and I will atexplain how it must be revised in order to become a useful resource for treating philosophical questions raised by religious pluralism. Lonergan's "Critical Realism" The human capacity to know is for Lonergan what constitutes human being as spirit. " Let us say," he writes, that intelligibility that is not intelligent is material, and that intelligibility that is intelligent is spiritual. . . . But inasmuch as we are spiritual, we are orientated towards the universe of being, know ourselves as parts within that universe, and guide our living by that knowledge.8 Knowing, then, is a process with distinguishable moments, and it is completed in action consistent with what is known. Moreover, what can be known by a human subject determines the parameters of "proportionate being." The coordination of all of the departments of human knowledge is the object of metaphysics, 2 Method in Theology, pp. 25, 83, 261, 316. See also Bernard Lonergan, Insight: A Study of Human Understanding, revised ed. (New York: Harper & Row, 1978), pp. 322ff., p. 350. a Insight, p. 516. LONERGAN ON RELIGIOUS PLURALISM 99 which Lonergan defines as " the integral heuristic structure of proportionate being." 4 Proportionate being is not, however, a comprehensive term for everything that exists ; there is also "transcendent being." Transcendent being is revealed as mystery, and knowledge of it is obtained through the operation of grace in religious conversion. 5 But I will postpone discussion of this knowledge of transcendent being for the moment. The orientation of the human spirit toward " the universe of being" manifests itself in "the primordial drive" to know. "It is prior to any insights, any concepts, any words, for insights, concepts, words have to do with answers; and before we look for answers, we want them; such wanting is the pure question." 6 The human spirit transcends itself and its immediate experience by a process of accumulating knowledge in accord with the drive of "the pure question." To the description of this process I now turn. Four different moments may be identified in the process of knowing : experience, intelligence, reflection, and deliberation. Lonergan identifies these distinctive moments in the process of knowing by means of a "generalized empirical method," 7 which concretely analyses the process of knowing first in the acquisition of mathematical knowledge, then of natural scientific knowledge, then of common sense knowledge, and finally of the knowledge of oneself as a knowing subject. It is impossible to do justice in a 4 Ibid., p. 391. 5 Ibid., pp. 635-686. See also Method in Theology, pp. 242-43. Lonergan adheres to Aquinas's view that some revealed truths are attainable by natural reason, but for the knowledge of God (objective genitive) that brings a solution to the human problem of sin an " absolutely supernatural solution " is necessary. "Then faith includes objects beyond the natural reach of any finite understanding" (Insight, p. 725). On this view, "the act of faith will be an assent of intellect to an object and because of a motive. As a belief within a new and higher collaboration, the object of faith will be the truths transmitted by the collaboration. Because it is a belief within a collaboration of man with God as initiator and principal agent, the motive of faith will be the omniscience, goodness, and omnipotence of God originating and preserving the collaboration " (Ibid., p. 720). a Insight, p. 9. See also pp. 74, 331, 348, 521-22, 638. 1 Ibid., pp. 70 ff. A Third Collection, pp. 140, 150, 177, 202. 100 TIMOTHY R. STINNETT brief essay to the lengthy discussions by which Lonergan attempts to warrant his account of the distinctive moments of knowledge. But an analysis that abstracts his account of the distinctive moments from their larger context will serve my purposes. First, then, experience provides the data for consciousness upon which knowledge is based. The undifferentiated awareness of experience is named "empirical consciousness." It registers the sensations of "outer experience," and it registers as "inner experience " a preconceptual awareness of oneself as sensing, perceiving, and imagining. 8 It does not, however, distinguish between inner and outer experience.9 Further, empirical consciousness is not yet knowledge, but it is the first condition of the emergence of knowledge. Although it is undifferentiated, because it has not yet applied names to the data presented as the given, it is not to be confused with "the unconscious." The latter intentionally represses awareness of the given, while empirical consciousness includes such awareness as a given. 10 Experience is not knowledge, then, but it supplies the materials for the posing of questions at higher, differentiated levels of consciousness. When experience provides data for human consciousness " questions for intelligence" result. Questions such as Why? How? and What for? are put to the data of empirical consciousness. By such questions the data are named, and the laws of their relations either with one another or with the human subject him/herself are described hypothetically. 11 Common sense judgments concern the latter kinds of relations; theoretical scientific judgments, the former. 12 Through questions for intelligence the .process of human knowing " moves to accumulations of related insights which are expressed or formulated in concepts, suppositions, definifions, postulates, hypotheses, theories .... " 13 Consciousness differentiated by the questions and answers for intelligence is "intelligent consciousness." It is characterized by s Insight, pp. 322; see also p. 274 and A Third Collection, p. 57. Method in Theology, p. 84. 12 Insight, p. 281. 10 Insight, p. 321; see also pp. 192-203. ls Ibid., p. 252. 11 Ibid., pp. 252, 272-278. 9 LONERGAN ON RELIGIOUS PLURALISM 101 its accumulated insights " not as a schoolboy repeating by rote a definition, but as one that defines because he grasps why that definition hits things." 14 The drive of " the pure question " is not satisfied by questions for intelligence, however. Human knowing presses to a higher level or moment in which " questions for reflection " are asked about the answers given to questions for intelligence. The former ask What is it?; the latter ask Whether it is? The former have the peculiarity of never being answerable by Yes or No ; the latter always "can be answered appropriately simply by saying either Yes or No." Intelligence understands; reflection judges. " Generally,'' Lonergan explains, "the enunciation of every law can be followed by the question for reflection that asks whether the law is verified, and the definition of every term can be followed by the question for reflection whether the defined exists." 15 To answer a question for reflection, then, is to exercise judgment about the data of experience that are differentiated and understood by intelligent consciousness.16 But precisely by what procedure are questions for reflection to be answered? A judgment is reached when the conditions of the answers of intelligence are known and these conditions are fulfilled. A judgment, then, is a grasping of what Lonergan calls the " virtually unconditioned." He explains, The function of reflective understanding is to meet the question for reflection by transforming the prospective judgment from the status of a conditioned to the status of a virtually unconditioned; and reflective understanding effects this transformation by grasping the conditions of the conditioned and their fulfillment.17 The conditions that must be met by judgment are determined by the data themselves, as differentiated in intelligent consciousness. The relevant conditions to be met in judgment are dependent upon the data to be judged, and so for data of logically distinct types different conditions must be specified. Irrespective of the logicalu Ibid., p. 322. 1s Ibid., pp. 271-316. 10 Ibid., p. 83. 11 Ibid., p. 280. 102 TIMOTHY R. STINNETT ly distinct type of data, however, judgment always occurs by linking the known conditions with their fulfillment. In other words, while the conditions of judgment are " field-dependent " upon the logically distinct type or " field " to which the data under consideration belong, the procedure for linking the conditions with their fulfillment is " field-invariant." 18 In every exercise of judgment the " virtually unconditioned " is attained by linking the known conditions of the data with their fulfillment. Only by such a procedure can judgment produce " knowledge" of what is manifestly judged in the answer Yes or No. It is a major characteristic of modern science that judgments of empirical fact never attain the " virtually unconditioned " but only approximate it to a greater or lesser degree. Lonergan remarks that the probability of a judgment, like the certainty of a judgment, is a property of its content. If that content coincides with what is grasped as virtually unconditioned, then it is a certainty. But what is grasped as virtually unconditioned may be that a given content heads towards the virtually unconditioned, and then the content is a probability.19 Thus, modern scientists do not claim absolute knowledge of the data they study but only probable knowledge. 20 Moreover, some 1 8 I have borrowed this terminology from Stephen Toulmin, The Uses of Argument (New York and Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1958). 19 Insight, p. 550. 20 Accordingly, scientific theory is always subject to revision. This point lies at the heart of Lonergan's central criticism of Aristotle's view of natural science as expressed in the Posterior Analytics. Aristotle conceived genera and species descriptively, and the particular natural sciences were to be inferred from the more general science of metaphysics. Consequently, natural science was unable to secure methodological independence from metaphysics. This blocked the emergence of modern natural sciences as autonomous disciplines. Lonergan, in contrast, develops an explanatory conception of genera and species in a way, he holds, consistent with the canons of modern scientific inquiry (Insight, pp. 166-67, 482-83; see also A Third Collection, pp. 41-47). Similarly, metaphysics is explanatory rather than descriptive. "Metaphysics has been conceived as the integral heuristic structure of proportionate being. Proportionate being is what is to be known by experience, intelligent grasp, and reasonable affirmation. Integral heuristic structure is the anticipatory outline of what would be known by affirming a complete explanation of experience" (Insight, p. 483). LONERGAN ON RELIGIOUS PLURALISM 103 judgments do not even approximate the virtually unconditioned according to the classical laws of science. In other words the classical laws are restricted in their relevance to only a partial range of the data of experience. Another whole range of data is known to diverge from the classical laws non-systematically. This range of data, which Lonergan calls "the empirical residue," can be understood and known only through the development and application of the science of statistics. Thus, Lonergan argues, There does not exist a single ordered sequence that embraces the totality of particular cases through which abstract system might be applied to the concrete universe. In other words, though all events are linked to one another by law, still the laws reveal only the abstract component in concrete relations ; the further concrete component, though mastered by insight into particular cases, is involved in the empirical residue from which systematizing intelligence abstracts ; it does not admit general treatment along classical lines; it is a residue, left over after classical method has been applied, and it calls for the implementation of statistical method.21 Statistical science investigates what classical scientific laws cannot account for. But the field-invariant rules of judgment also apply in statistical judgments. In this case the conditions of fulfillment are the limits of the data's non-systematic divergence from classical laws, the random frequencies of the occurrence of the data. 22 When knowledge is attained by the exercise of sound judgment, the human spirit presses on to yet another kind of question, "the question for deliberation." This question shapes the choice to be exercised volitionally in the light of the judgment about what is known. Questions for deliberation, then, emerge in " moral consciousness." Know ledge is attained by experience, understanding, and judgment; it is fulfilled in praxis. 23 Questions for deliberation arise, therefore, as the demand for " self-consistency in knowing and doing." 24 87. Ibid., pp. 46-69. 21 See A Third Collection, pp. 169-250; Insight, pp. 595-633. 24 Insight, p. 599. 21 [nsight, p. 22 104 TIMOTHY R. STINNETT Lonergan's theory entails a rejection of any sort of unqualified determinism. " For the concrete includes a non-systematic component, and so the concrete cannot be deduced in its full determinacy from any set of systematic premises." 25 Precisely what can be known is not predetermined. The question remains open and is only determined by the increasing accumulation of human knowledge in all its distinctive departments. Furthermore, his theory requires the differentiation of various fields of inquiry; each bears the burden of identifying the relevant conditions of the data they study that must be fulfilled by sound judgment. Thus, Lonergan rejects "naive realism," which views knowledge as the result of " taking a look " at the world of experience to see what is already there, for knowledge is the result of experience, understanding, and judgment. He rejects that kind of "empiricism" that denies cognitive meaning to statements that are not verifiable in some way by sense perception, for sensible perceptions are only a preliminary stage in the acquisition of knowledge of matters of empirical fact. He rejects " idealism" that holds human "knowledge " to be of the ideal rather than the real, for knowledge is based upon experience, and experience is always of what is real, whether transcendent or proportionate being. Instead, Lonergan's theory of knowledge is a "critical realism ... that human knowledge consists not in experiencing alone but in the three2 5 Insight, p. 99. But, given his view of the systematic and non-systematic aspects of the data of experience, Lonergan conceives divine omniscience in a surprising way. He claims that " God lmows exactly what every free will would choose in each successive set of circumstances contained in each possible world order" (ibid., p. 662). And again, "from the viewpoint of unrestricted understanding the non-systematic vanishes to yield place to a fully determinate and absolutely efficacious plan and intention" (ibid., p. 665). But it is difficult to see how these claims about omniscience can be anything other than merely verbal, for if divine lmowledge is perfect surely its perfection would entail lmowledge of the non-systematic as non-systematic. But if that is the case, then a knowing from which " the non-systematic vanishes" would be imperfect. The inconsistency of his argument suggests that Lonergan has imposed upon his critical realism metaphysical categories not derivable from it. For an argument to this point see Schubert M. Ogden, "Lonergan and the Subjectivist Principle," The Journal of Religion 51 (July 1971): 155-172. LONERGAN ON RELIGIOUS PLURALISM 105 fold compound that embraces experiencing, understanding and judging." 26 Strangely enough, the one department of "knowledge" that is exceptional to Lonergan' s theory is the religious. It is exceptional because the conditions of fulfillment for the object of religious knowledge, transcendent being, are not known before being linked with the known conditions. Indeed, they cannot he known because, in contrast to every other kind of knowledge, the " unconditioned " of religious knowledge is formal, not virtual.2 7 In judgments about select data of proportionate being, the data are conditioned, and from them the conditions to be fulfilled in judgment may be derived and linked with them. But in the case of transcendent being the datum is formally unconditioned; it yields no conditions that may be linked with the unconditioned for affirmative judgment. Accordingly, arguments for the existence of God, where God is conceived as transcendent being, arrive only at the virtually unconditioned with regard to the truth of the premises from which the existence of God may be inferred. Now, Lonergan holds that "The immanent source of transcendence in man is his detached" disinterested, unrestricted desire to know." 28 But it is not possible for a human being to know in unrestricted fashion; human abilities do not match human desires. This mismatch renders proportionate being not completely intelligible in itself. Therefore, the desire for unrestricted knowledge becomes the premise for an inference to the existence of transcendent being, and this inference completes the intelligibility of proportionate being. The general form of the argument is as follows : " If the real is completely intelligible, God exists. But the real is completely intelligible. Therefore, God exists." 29 In this argument and in other theistic arguments he employs, Lonergan holds that " what is grasped is not the unrestricted act but the extrapolation that proceeds from the prop26A Third Collection, p. 240; Method in Theology, p. 76. 21 Insight, p. 672. 2s Ibid., p. 636. 29 Ibid., p. 672. 106 TIMOTHY R. STINNETT erties of a restricted act to the properties of the unrestricted act." 80 Thus, Lonergan maintains that "The most fundamental of all questions . . . asks about existence yet neither empirical science nor a methodically restricted philosophy can have an adequate answer." 31 Religious knowledge or, more precisely, what is most important in the field of religious knowledge is not obtainable by the ordinary process of human knowing. Accordingly, Lonergan typically speaks of the knowledge of God ( objective genitive) as the exception to the adage nihil amatum nisi praecognitum.32 He also typically speaks of the basic form of Christian religious experience as having God's love "poured into our hearts through the Holy Spirit " (Romans 5 :5). 88 The knowledge of God, then, is obtained by conversion, brought about by divine initiative. Even so, it is anticipated by human knowledge in the orientation of the human spirit to mystery, to the transcendent being which always confronts human being as " a ' known unknown '." 3' The Disadvantages and Advantages of " Critical Realism" I must begin an evaluation of Lonergan's theory of knowledge by calling attention to its central difficulty. It appears most clear3o Ibid., p. 670. a1 Ibid., p. 653. 32 A Third Collection, pp. 31, 77. 33 Method in Theology, pp. 122. 34. Insight, p. 546. Lonergan's discussions of conversion typically interchange " religious experience " and " being in love with God," just as he invariably interchanges " God and "transcendent being." He is persuaded by Friedrich Heiler's argument for seven common features of the world religions, all seven of which may be summarized by " being in love with God " (Met hod in Theology, pp. 109 ff.; A Third Collection, pp. 217 ff.). But Heiler's argument is difficult to defend, and I suspect it has little credibility except to those who know little about the history of religions. For if it is dubious to suppose that the world religions share a common concept of love, it is far more dubious to suppose that they share a common concept of God. But both suppositions must hold in order for Heiler's argument to succeed. One may note, furthermore, that the abandonment of substantive definitions of religion by most historians of religion is, in part, the consequence of the unsupportability of the secondmentioned supposition. LONERGAN ON RELIGIOUS PLURALISM 107 ly in the question about how to adjudicate conflicting truth claims between the religions. And unless this difficulty is resolved, one may well wonder what use any of Lonergan's theory may be for solving philosophical problems raised by religious pluralism. If the " absolutely supernatural solution " to the human condition is beyond the grasp of the human mind, then there appears no way to adjudicate putative conflicts between religious claims to truth. Further, it appears impossible even to judge affirmatively that a religious claim is true. If religious conversion is the condition of the possibility of discriminating true from false versions of the solution to the human condition (or, in Lonergan's language, " positions " from " counter-positions "), 85 then the question arises about the criterion for discerning who is religiously converted. Lonergan's answer is unsatisfying. He argues that "each theologian will judge the authenticity of the authors of views, and he will do so by the touchstone of his own authenticity." 88 But the only sure sign of one's own authenticity is adherence to the permanent meaning of dogma, and "The permanence of dogmas . . . results from the fact that they express revealed mysteries." 37 Further, adherence to the permanent meaning of dogma is the result of the transformation of the limits of one's knowledge, i.e., of one's "horizon," by religious conversion.38 Thus, Lonergan holds that religious conversion is the condition of the possibility of discerning true from false solutions to the human condition, but the criterion for discerning who is religiously converted is an adherence to the true solution. Unless the circularity of Lonergan's argument can be broken, there is little hope for use of his critical realism for the solution of philosophical questions raised by religious pluralism. For example, non-Christians will be unable to enter into dialogue with a& Insight, pp. 387-90. sa Method in Theology, p. 331. See also pp. 270-71. a1 Ibid., p. 326. ss A "person's horizon is the boundary of what he !mows and values" (A Third Collection, p. 234). 108 TIMOTHY R. STINNETT Christians, even if their own religious traditions do not argue religious conversion to be a condition of the possibility of discerning the true solution to the human condition. They will not have attained the " Christian horizon," and they will be unable to evaluate Christian formulations of the solution to the human condition. But it is also conceivable that members of any nonChristian religion could hold their own tradition to be the bearer of the true solution and to view Christians as advocates of a counter-position because of the absence of genuine religious conversion. The difficulty under consideration calls into question Lonergan's remark that in the light of the priority of divine love " not only is the ancient problem of the salvation of non-Christians greatly reduced, but also the true nature of Christian apologetic is clarified." 39 It seems that the result of Lonergan's theory of religious conversion is rather to exacerbate the problem of the salvation of non-Christians, for if adherence to " the true solution " as visible in the Christian witness is a sign of authentic conversion, then in no straightforward sense may non-Christians be said to be authentically converted. Further, Lonergan's theory appears to render a " Christian apologetic " that can appeal to non-Christians all but impossible, insofar as conversion is the prerequisite for obtaining the " absolutely supernatural " point of view from which religious claims may be judged. There is another difficulty with Lonergan's theory of religious conversion, but to understand it we must be clear about the principal warrant of his argument for the necessity of religious conversion. The warrant is that transcendent being is thoroughly transcendent. If it is real, it must be intelligible. But it exceeds the apprehension of a finite mind by definition. Hence, knowledge of transcendent being must be revealed, and such revelation is obtained only by religious conversion, in which God floods our hearts with love and brings about the transformation of our horizon by the operation of grace (gratia operans). Thus transcendent being is not immanent in human experience at all, for, if it 39 Method Theology, p. 123. LONERGAN ON RELIGIOUS PLURALISM 109 were, human reason could attain knowledge of it solely by the resources of experience, understanding, and judgment. 40 What is immanent in human experience is only the incomplete intelligibility of proportionate being; given the data of experience, understanding and judgment may proceed from the known to the unknown. Transcendent being is always, however, "the 'known unknown'." Even when it has revealed itself, Lonergan argues, the most human reason can accomplish is an analogous and imperfect understanding of the revealed " mysteries." 41 This view of the relation of proportionate to transcendent being is vulnerable to the critique of what Antony Flew calls " Stratonician atheism." The point of the critique is that "all qualities observed in things are qualities belonging by natural right to those things themselves; and hence that whatever characteristics we think ourselves able to discern in the universe as a whole are the underivative characteristics of the universe itself." 42 Thus, if the data of experience do not support an understanding and affirmative judgment about transcendent being, or if they do so only by "deficient analogy," 43 then the only proper conclusion is that the existence of transcendent being cannot reasonably be affirmed. Further, if the data of experience lead by understanding and judgment to the conclusion that proportionate being is only incompletely intelligible in itself, then the proper conclusion is only that we inhabit a universe that is not completely intelligible in itself. Accordingly, the rule of judgment offered by the Stratonician atheist is " the presumption that the universe is everything there is : and hence that everything which can be explained must be explained by reference to what is in and of the universe." 44 The Stratonician atheist, I contend, has provided the would-be 4'o The force of my argument is restricted to " the mystery " of transcendent being. See Insight, pp. 672 ff. 41 Ibid., pp. 322-23. 42 Antony Flew, God: A Critical Enquiry, 2nd edition of God and Philosophy (LaSalle, Illinois : Open Court, 1984), p. 63. 43 A Third Collection, p. 26. H Flew, God, p. 187. 110 TIMOTHY R. STINNETT theist with the only rule of judgment which offers escape from the circularity of Lonergan' s position (that religious conversion is the condition of the possibility of saving knowledge about transcendent being). It is necessary, then, to rethink the order of nature to grace, for either what faith claims is what may be reasonably affirmed on the basis of the conditions of existence or the content of faith (fides quae) fails to count as knowledge. The consequence is an unreasonable faith. Further, as Bultmann puts it, if faith were belief in an incomprehensible X, then faith would be an action dependent on a specific resolve; it would be a purely arbitrary accidental occurrence. And it would be ... the beginning of justification by works.45 Moreover, the very " work" upon which one's justification would be based would be the act of choosing to be unreasonable rather than reasonable about what is most important in life. But a view that implies that human beings achieve authentic existence in faith only by overcoming a proclivity to reasonableness is, at best, a suspicious view of authentic existence. 46 I also suggest that the " mystery" revealed in the New Testament is not the incomprehensibility of the concept of God but, rather, the incompenensibility of God's boundless and unqualified love for all his creatures, especially the constant and free off er of the forgiveness of sin and of the possibility of new and authentic life "in Christ." What is needed to meet Flew's criticism is a thorough-going empiricism that juxtaposes the orders of nature and grace, so that transcendent being is not beyond the universe of proportionate being but perfectly immanent in it. In my view transcendence should be conceived as perfect immanence. An imperfect immanence is what one expects of individuals whose experience is limited rather than inclusive of the entire range of proportionate 45 Rudolf Bultmann, Faith and Understanding, translated by Louise Pettibone Smith (Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1987), p. 123. 46 To be fair, Lonergan does argue that "If God is a being, he is to be known by intelligent grasp and reasonable affirmation" (Insight, p. 657). But I am trying to show why I think his argument unsuccessful. LONERGAN ON RELIGIOUS PLURALISM 111 being. But a transcendent being would be transcendent precisely insofar as no aspect of proportionate being is excluded from the range of its experience. This view differs from pantheism, however, if the transcendent being is itself a self-transcending subject, as Lonergan suggests. 47 Then, to illustrate my point in Christian theological terms, transcendent being may be said to transcend itself by a perfect love of the world which is expressed in God's self-communication to all his creatures. Further, because God is transcendent he experiences every event that occurs in proportionate being as an occasion for creative synthesis into the ever increasing novelty of divine experience itself. Now Karl Rahner's theological anthropology suggests itself as a viable alternative to Lonergan's thought, even if Rahner's account of the nature of divine love does not successfully resolve the very problems of the scholastic heritage common to himself and Lonergan. 48 But as soon as one appeals to Rahner for help in revising Lonergan' s view of the order of nature and grace yet another difficulty appears, and this one most serious of all. For Rahner' s distinction between the " thematic " and " unthematic " knowledge of God (objective genitive) does not correspond to Lonergan's distinction between differentiated and undifferentiated consciousness. Rahner argues that "the knowing subject possesses itself in knowledge about itself and its knowledge."'° Every concrete act of knowledge presupposes, then, a "transcendental experience" of the subject, knowing itself "unthematically" as a knowing subject and always returning to itself to possess itself in its subjectivity. Unthematic knowledge for Rahner is given, therefore, with and in the experience of being a subject that transcends itself in acts of knowledge-and in every act of freedom. 50 The unthematic knowledge of God, it follows, is given to the human subject in its constitutive experience of 47 Method in Theology, p. 116. s See Mark Lloyd Taylor, God Is Love: A Study in the Theology of Karl Rahner (Atlanta, Georgia: Scholars Press, 1986). 4 9 Karl Rahner, Foundations of Christian Faith (New York: Seabury Press, 1978), pp. 17-18. 00 Ibid., p. 20. 4 112 TIMOTHY R. STINNETT possessing itself in self-transcendence. To be more specific, Rahner argues that God is the " Whither " or goal of self-transcendence and is characterized as " holy mystery." 51 The knowledge of God (objective genitive) becomes " thematic" when the unthematic knowledge given in every experience of the selftranscending subject (hence, "transcendental experience") is made explicit. Then the unthematic knowledge of God becomes the thematic knowledge of God as God. Of course, for Rahner grace is the precondition even of unthematic knowledge of God, as indicated by his concept of the "supernatural existential." We cannot pursue Rahner's thought further here, but what I have said should make Lonergan's thought somewhat clearer. For Lonergan, undifferentiated consciousness is the fully conscious awareness of " inner " and " outer " experience. Thus, the only experience he admits as data for understanding and reflection is conscious experience. Even " the unconscious " is derived from conscious experience, for what is repressed must first be presented to empirical consciousness clearly and distinctly, even if only preconceptually. As Lonergan puts it, " not wanting an insight has the opposite effect of repressing from consciousness a scheme that would suggest insight." 52 Moreover, in Lonergan's view not only are the cognitive operations of which one is aware in " inner experience" conscious, but it is not even possible to have an experience of objects as objects unless they are already the data of conscious awareness and are intended by cognitive operations. Thus, Lonergan explains, " Just as operations by their intentionality make objects present to the subject, so also by consciousness they make the operating subject present to himself." 53 For Rahner, by contrast, the subject is present to himself in cognitive operations because the transcendental experience of subjectivity is always manifested in them. Rahner's analysis of selftranscendence focuses upon transcendental experience as the cons1 Ibid., pp. 65-6. 52 [nsight, p. 192. See also, pp. 199-206, 477. Method in Theology, p. 8. For a more fully developed argument for this point see Ogden, "Lonergan and the Subjectivist Principle," pp. 164-66. 5s LONERGAN ON RELIGIOUS PLURALISM 113 dition of the possibility of cognitive operation. Lonergan's analysis focuses upon concrete cognitive operations, thereby failing to give a full account of the experience of the subject himself. While Rahner holds that consciousness presupposes experience, Lonergan seems to hold that experience presupposes consciousness. But if Lonergan fails to give a full account of the experience of self-transcendence, then the integral heuristic structure he proposes for metaphysics will also fail fully to anticipate all that can be explained about experience. 54 It follows that Lonergan's undifferentiated or " empirical consciousness " attains neither the transcendental comprehensiveness of Rahner's "transcendental experience," which is presupposed by every concrete experience, nor a full analysis of the self-transcendence of the knowing subject, upon which he claims to base his critical realism. If my contrast between Rahner and Lonergan is not mistaken, then the question should be, What precisely does Lonergan's incomplete metaphysical anticipation obscure? I believe it obscures that range of experience that is not presented in the clear and distinct impressions of the senses or of cognitive operations. Rather, empirical consciousness abstracts from a larger domain of experience, and only when that larger range of experience is recovered can we give an account of our experience of God within proportionate being in a way that satisfies the rule of the Stratonician atheist. It may be, as A. N. Whitehead writes, that " The definition of the environment is exactly what is omitted from special abstraction." 55 And until we have a complete account of " the environment " we shall not be able to demonstrate that God or any other formulation of ultimate reality must be included in a full explanatory account of it. Finally, what advantages does Lonergan's critical realism offer? I believe the most significant contribution it makes is to focus attention upon the logically distinct candidate each individual religion proposes as ultimate reality and to indicate that Cf. Insight, pp. 541-42. North Whitehead, Modes of Thought Press, 1966), p. 55. H 55 Alfred q) ." Ibid., p. 59. But, surely, this is too narrow a view of Aquinas's concept of what is required for a conditional proposition to be true. 20 Ibid., pp. 77-78. 21 See ibid., p. 72. GOD,S KNOWLEDGE: FUTURE CONTINGENT SINGULARS 125 At least in one of his readings of Aquinas, Craig indicates that he is actually cognizant of the latter's position on God's knowledge of things other than Himself, viz., that He knows them as possible or actual reflections of Himself in His intellect. 22 Consequently, I find it puzzling that he should entertain the objection that temporal things could be the cause of God's knowledge. (Perhaps Craig would say, " not of His knowledge of approbation but of His knowledge of vision," but more on this subject later.) Thus, by way of commenting on Saint Thomas's position here, he observes, " Hence by knowing His own essence He knows the essence [ s] of all things and in knowing them He knows all possible propositions that could be truly enunciated of them." 23 Craig makes other statements relating to God's knowledge, to which, again, exception must be taken. He seems to think that, at least where it is a question of God's knowledge of vision (although his argument also seems to apply to God's knowledge of approbation), the truth in the divine intellect concerning creatures depends upon a conformity of that intellect to things outside it rather than the other way around (viz., that their essential ontological truth comes from their necessary conformity to their proper mental types in the divine mind). Thus he says, " Just as the artist created the painting on the pattern of his exemplar idea and yet knows the truth of the proposition, ' This painting portrays an idyllic English countryside' (because this is in fact what the painting portrays) so God creates the actual world after His archetypal ideas and yet knows the truth of the proposition ' The universe contains n hydrogen atoms ' precisely because it does contain that quantity of hydrogen atoms." 24 This argument is made within the context of his discussion of God's knowledge of approbation and I will return to criticize it later in this discussion. Other observations of a similar vein but expressly relating to God's knowledge of vision are the following: (A) " Indeed, on 22 See ibid., p. 68, p. 74. 28 Ibid., p. 74. 2• Ibid., p. 75. 126 THEODORE J. KONDOLEON Aquinas's analysis there seem to be three moments in God's knowledge: ( 1) scientia simplicis intelligentiae of all possibles, (2) scientia approbationis of which possibles shall obtain, and (3) scientia visionis or God's knowledge of the actual world based (my italics) upon what obtains; " and also ( B) " Knowledge of vision is, it seems, conditioned by what actually exists. In this sense God knows what will happen because it will in fact happen." 25 (Yes, but does this latter statement indicate a logical or a causal dependency? Earlier, however, Craig had said the same about God's causal knowledge when he answered his question, " Is it not enough that He merely know Himself insofar as He is the cause of all particulars which do obtain ? ", with this reply, " The answer would seem to be ' yes'; but He knows Himself as the cause of particulars that do obtain precisely because they do obtain. If they did not actually obtain, God could not know Himself as their cause." 26 (As I shall argue later, when I return to consider his analogy of the human artist, Craig's last observation implies God's causal dependency upon things for His knowledge of their actual existence.) These last three passages seem to indicate that to Craig's mind God's knowledge of vision must causally depend upon things and that it is not merely a question of a logical dependency, i.e., that God's knowing something will happen is logically entailed by its actually happening. Indeed, Craig is fully aware of Aquinas's answer to Origen's observation that "A thing will happen not because God knows it as future; but because it is future it is on that account known by God," and deems it important enough to quote it in what appears to be his English translation: His saying that God foreknows certain things because they are going to happen, is to be understood of the causality of logical consequence, not of the causality which produces existence. For it follows logically that if certain things are going to happen, God foreknows them; but the things themselves are not the cause of God's knowledge.27 21 Ibid. 2a Ibid., p. 70. 21 Ibid., p. 72. The passage which Craig quotes is from Summa Theologia1, I, q. 14, a. 8, ad 1. GOD'S KNOWLEDGE: FUTURE CONTINGENT SINGULARS 127 Yet Craig apparently sides with Origen and opposes Aquinas's benign reading of the latter when he says, " God knows what will happen because it will in fact happen, and not vice versa." 28 Craig may be led to this view because he affords a separate status to God's knowledge of vision apart from His causal or archetypal knowledge. He apparently finds that warranted by certain statements which Saint Thomas himself makes about God's knowledge of vision being a knowledge of things as they are in themselves. Thus, Craig appears to think that if God knows future contingents according to the being which they have in themselves, He knows them, not in Himself as actual reflections of Himself-in which case His knowledge of vision would not depend upon the things which God sees in this knowledge-but directly according to the being they have in themselves, in much the manner that we know when we actually see them (hence the expression " knowledge of vision "). 29 In developing this point Craig quotes a number of passages from Saint Thomas's writings. One is from the Summa Theologiae, from a text where Saint Thomas maintains that God's knowledge of vision extends to a knowledge of future contingents, not only as they are in their proximate causes but also as each one exists in itself.30 Aquinas says here that God's eternal knowledge is not merely of the intelligible natures of things present within Him but one which has for its object all things (past, present, and future) as they are in their very presentness. Craig also quotes a passage from the Compendium Theologiae, which 2s Craig, p. 76. See Summa Theologiae, I, q. 14, a. 9, c. Concerning the knowledge of vision Aquinas observes here, " This is so called because the things we see around us have distinct being outside the seer." 80 See ibid., I, q. 14, a. 13, c. For another perhaps clearer statement of this point one can read the following : " In another way future events are known in themselves. To know the future in this way belongs to God alone .•. for God sees all things in His eternity, which being simple, is present to all time, and embraces all time. And therefore God's one glance is cast over all things which happen in all time as present before Him; and He beholds all things as they are in themselves, as was said before when dealing with God's knowledge." Ibid., I, q. 57, a. 3, c. -119 128 THEODORE J. KONDOLEON reads in part, " Even before they come into being, He sees them as they actually exist, and not merely as they will be in the future and as virtually present in their causes, in the way we are able to know some future thing." 31 In other words, according to Saint Thomas, apparently, God knows future contingents in their real existence and not simply according to the existence which they have in Him. On the strength of these passages, therefore, Craig is able to say, "The point here seems to be that this presence is not internal to God, but a real external presence. Since God knows contingents according to their actual existence, it seems undeniable that for God future contingents actually exist." 32 (Craig immediately goes on to say that this does not mean that such contingents always exist but that the entire temporal series would seem to exist timelessly, on the analogy of a spatial extension, and as such is known by God.) However, later in his discussion Craig seems to withdraw the above reading of Saint Thomas's position on God's knowledge of future contingents by saying, " The picture I have presented thus far of Aquinas's view of God's knowledge of future contingents would, however, be misleading if it were taken to imply that for Thomas God has direct knowledge of the created order. In fact God has no direct knowledge of anything other than Himself ... Hence the only immediate object of God's knowledge is His essence." 33 Moreover further on he observes, "In knowing Himself as First Cause of everything which exists, God knows all His effects. Thus God knows Himself through Himself and all created things through Himself." 34 Yet he seems perplexed by this summary of Aquinas's teaching-and little wonder given what he had previously said about God's knowledge of future contingents-and expresses this perplexity as follows, "Now it is perplexing how this understanding of God's knowledge is related to God's knowledge of future contingents as explained by Aquinas. We have seen that God's knowledge of vision seems to entail the actual existence of the temporal series of events as 31 See Craig, 82 Ibid. p. 65. as Ibid., p. 67. 3 4 Ibid., p. 68. GOD'S KNOWLEDGE : FUTURE CONTINGENT SINGULARS 129 the proper object of God's knowledge. But in the context of the doctrine of God's simplicity and pure actuality, it seems that the eternal divine essence, not the temporal series of events, is the proper object of God's knowledge." 35 Perhaps Craig's perplexity here may be traced to what Aquinas has left unsaid about the divine scientia visionis, viz., that it presupposes God's causal knowledge, if it is not actually logically identical with it. Still this does not excuse what must strike any careful reader as conflicting presentations, on Craig's part, of Saint Thomas's teaching on the divine knowledge. This observation is confirmed by what Craig has to say soon after. In an effort to choose between- what to him appear to be two radically different positions in Saint Thomas's supposed teaching here, Craig decides as follows: " One therefore is led to ask why the presence of all things to God in His eternity might not be construed to mean the presence to God of the divine ideas. In this way Aquinas would not seem committed to the ontological parity of the past, present, and future. The events themselves are not present to God but only their exemplar ideas. In His eternity God sees the ideal archetypal world and so timelessly understands the truths about past, present, and future events in the temporal series, which is in a state of genuine becoming. But while one might wish to reinterpret the Thomistic doctrine in this way, one cannot plausibly claim that this represents Aquinas's own view. In his discussion of God's knowledge of future contingents, he always speaks of the things or events themselves, never of their exemplar ideas. Indeed, this Augustinian doctrine seems to fit ill with Thomas's view of God's immediate and simple knowledge of Himself." 36 Why Craig maintains that this last-mentioned view is a " reinterpretation " of Saint Thomas that cannot plausibly claim to represent Aquinas's own view is something I find perplexing. Earlier he had presented it as representing it when he said, "The picture I have presented thus far of Aquinas's view of God's knowledge of future contingents would, however, be misleading HJbid. ae Ibid., p. 69. 130 THEODORE J. KONDOLEON if it were taken to imply that for Thomas God has direct knowledge of the created order. In fact Aquinas believes that God has no direct knowledge of anything other than Himself." 37 (Incidentally, contrary to the straw man Craig seems to have constructed in the passage above, Aquinas would not maintain that the divine ideas are really anything other than the divine essence itself as that essence is understood by God as imitable by creatures.) And shortly thereafter he also said, " In knowing Himself as First Cause of everything that exists God knows Himself through Himself and all created things through Himself." 38 This last statement (as all Thomists know) implies for Saint Thomas God's exemplary causality. Moreover, it is not true to say, as Craig does, that " In his discussion of God's knowledge of future contingents, he always speaks of the things or events themselves, never of their exemplar ideas. Indeed this Augustinian doctrine seems to fit ill with Thomas's view of God's immediate and simple knowledge of Himself." 39 In the following passage from the Summa contra Gentiles, Book I, in the context of a discussion of God's knowledge of vision, Aquinas observes: Nevertheless whatever being a thing has God knows through His essence. For His essence can be represented by many things that are not, nor will be, nor ever were. His essence is likewise the likeness of the power of every cause, through which effects pre-exist in their causes. And the being which each thing has in itself comes from the divine essence as from its exemplary source.40 It is the last sentence of this passage which shows what Craig has to say, in the quotation above, to be false. But to address what I believe to be Craig's main difficulty with Aquinas's teaching here, it should be noted that inasmuch as God has created each creature's existence, He sees His creatures in Himself according to the existence which they have in themselves (for their existence is modelled after His). Thus God Ibid., p. 67. ss Ibid., p. 68. s9 Ibid., p. 69. &7 f existing as unum, verum and bonum. (pp. 234-235) BOOK REVIEWS 153 Woznicki argues convincingly that order is an attribute of being and can be found in the very structure of esse. The ultimate foundation of the order of being is essence and existence. The unity and plurality of beings, even the diversity and community of beings, are ultimately due to the meaning and structure of esse. The various relations of potency to act according to a mutual and reciprocal proportion of ac· tuality and potentiality are due to the various ways esse is, and the ways that esse is account for order. As I was reading Father Woznicki's brilliant analysis of order in the thought of Saint Thomas, I thought of Sartre's rejection of the intelligibility of being. The atheistic existentialist refused to accept that being makes ultimate sense. For him there is no metaphysical marriage between being and the human mind; though the mind might think in an ordered fashion, there is unfortunately no intelligible order to reality. What Sartre's rejection of the intelligibility of being underlines for me is that while the principle of contradiction is self-evident and undeniable, the principle of sufficient reason is not. An individual in choosing to reject the principle of sufficient reason opts for absurdity. For such an individual, like Sartre, all reflection on order is literally pointless because all reflection on order is tied either to acceptance of the principle of sufficient reason or to what might he called a philosophical act of faith in the principle of sufficient reason. Woznicki's detailed and dazzling exploration of order calls attention not only to the mystery of being but also to the magnificent marriage between being and the human mind that makes metaphysics meaningful. For me, Woznicki's insights into Thomas's metaphysics underline the poverty of Sartre's view and indeed all versions of the absurdist view. Noting that God has established all created beings according to a rational plan, Woznicki points out that this rational plan can be conceived of as an integrated whole or as an arranged plurality. Conceiving the rational plan as an integrated whole depicts the harmonious constitution of each individual being; conceiving the rational plan as an arranged plurality depicts reality as a hierarchical descent from the highest to the lowest beings. In a summary statement that could serve as a model of clarity and succinctness, Woznicki writes: In the universe then, there is a plurality of things which are instituted on different levels of being. At the top of all beings is God, and at the bottom is prime matter. Between God and prime matter there are several degrees of perfection which can he reduced to either intellectual or material beings. In the order of the intellectual beings there is a composition of essence and existence, of substance and accidents, and of act and potency. In the order of material beings there is, moreover, a composition of prime matter and substantial form. In a word, the order of the universe is a unity of diversity, instituted by God in a harmony and hierarchy of all created beings. (p. 35) 154 BOOK REVIEWS Woznicki highlights his own interpretation of St. Thomas's view of being and order by comparing and contrasting it with the views of other thinkers, such as Duns Scotus and Ockham. Woznicki points out that Duns Scotus's insistance on the primacy of essence over exist· ence led to a metaphysics quite different from that of Saint Thomas, in which existence had priority over essence, Woznicki emphasizes that Ockham's denial of the validity of analogy has bequeathed to us an instrumentalistic understanding of being as being; the real unity of being is replaced by a unity that is the product of our minds. What actually happens in Ockham is that metaphysics is subordinated to the demands of logic. Ockham's metaphysics also resembles the Heraclitean philosophy of becoming, and Woznicki points to Nietzsche as evidence that such a philosophy of becoming necessarily leads to nihilism. In his criticism of Ockham as well as in his criticism of Descartes, Kant, and Whitehead, Woznicki not only makes Thomas seem more attrac· tive but also, at least implicitly, reveals the deleterious effect that influential false philosophies can have on the human adventure. Woznicki's explanation of Thomas's doctrine of esse does involve abstract thinking, but the result, the rooting of order in esse, is anything but irrelevant. Metaphysics does bury its undertakers; bad metaphysics creates victims. Father Woznicki has produced a fine work as the author of this first volume in the series Catholic Thought from Lublin. I hope that in his role as editor he will be able to present in the near future other volumes as good as Being and Order. ROBERT E. LAUDER Saint John's University Jamaica, New York An Introduction to Metaphysics of Knowledge. By YVES R. SIMON. Translated by Vukan Kuic and Richard J. Thompson. New York: Fordham University Press, 1990. Pp. xii 180. + Almost sixty years have passed between the first appearance of Jn. troduction a l'ontologie du connaitre and its English translation. But even though we have had to wait so long, we now have this treasure in hand. An Introduction to Metaphysics of Knowledge leaves no doubt that here is a thinker of the first water. Simon's writings never fail to exemplify the medieval fusion of the concepts " teacher " and " master " in the Latin " magister." As I observed when reviewing one of his posthumously published books, Work, Society, and Culture, BOOK REVIEWS 155 Simon had the knack for using concrete words and vivid imagery drawn from everyday life to carry the reader to the very heart of pro· found thoughts. That testifies to more than just a good prose style; the freedom from reliance on jargon and formalized academic language shows that Simon was neither a " scholastic" (in the pejorative sense of the word) nor a pedant or mere academician. His ready access to everyday language is simply one more indication that he was an independent philosophical thinker for whom reflective personal experience, not the text, was the ultimate court of appeal for arriving at the truth. A case in point is the book's structure. Flipping through its pages, one notices the frequent extended discussions in the footnotes and the abundant citation of classical texts, often leaving room for no more than three or four lines of Simon's own prose on a given page. This may well remind the reader of the musty pedantry of so many doctoral dissertations. But although Simon frequently cites the texts of Aristotle, St. Thomas, Cajetan, and John of St. Thomas, the arguments he advances clearly do not depend on any appeal to the authority of these authors. Although a Thomist, he assumes complete responsibility for his critique of knowledge; he is a thinker whose arguments stand on their own merit. All the references to the aforementioned authorities are truly footnotes; they are never an essential part of Simon's own text. (This bears mention for the benefit of the august members of "The Guardianship of the Undefiled Text of St. Thomas Aquinas," who can be counted upon to insist that commentators, such as John of St. Thomas, are unreliable interpreters of the master's texts.) The book sparkles as a splendid example of a philosopher who understands the philosophia perennis. He successfully blends the tradition of Aristotelian-Thomistic realism with his own philosophical integrity. As the title indicates, Simon's aim in the book is to inquire into the metaphysical foundation of knowledge. But to understand what Simon is about, the reader must keep in mind the essentials of Simon's critical realism: we know, what we know are things, and we know that we know. It is a realism because it starts with the certitudes delivered to us by our experiential knowledge, a knowledge that is prephilosophical. Simon asserts more than once that an analysis of knowledge will not be constructive unless it presupposes that our knowledge of things is a fact: " the fact of cognition represents its [epistemology's] experimental starting point" (6). Regarding our knowledge of the sensible world, he writes: " The most subtle psychology of the senses relying on the most elaborate data is still not capable of demonstrating the objective value of sensible knowledge-unless this value has previously been established by a priori reasoning. Furthermore, if one were to put aside all questions concerning the value of knowledge until we have 156 BOOK REVIEWS completed a full-fledged theory of knowledge, would we know what we are talking about when we use words such as ' sense ' and ' intelligence ' ? " (38) . Thus, in answer to his opening question, " What is knowledge ? ," Simon appeals to our personal experience to validate the claim that knowing is a way of being, a becoming the other as other. Since the knower cannot become the known in the latter's physical nature, the rationally defensible alternative is that the known enjoys intentional being within the knower. That knowing is a way of being within the knower cannot be demonstrated because it is logically prior to all demonstration and is known by intuition. Because this " intuitive W esenschau " is the very starting point for a valid metaphysics of knowledge, Simon makes it clear at the outset that he will not waste time jousting with critics of it; instead his primary concern will be to produce a formula for arriving at that intuition (1-10). The intentional being of knowledge is the basis of the entire book. Clearly, we do not know things by some intermediary; we know that we know things because the object of our knowledge is directly accessible to us. Since we do not become the physical tree when we know it, the intentional being of the tree known must be our object of knowledge. The idea sheds light on this. The fact of cognition tells us that to be and to know are quite different from each other. This difference becomes all the clearer the moment we grasp the kind of existence that the thing known enjoys in the soul. The difference between to be and to know is the difference between physical and intentional existence. This, in turn, bespeaks the difference between thing and idea, a difference in the order of nature and not merely in the mind. The possibility of the thing having an intentional existence in the mind, despite the fact that it has its own existence in nature, springs from the idea. It allows the mind to be the object of knowledge. Insofar as it is real, the idea possesses its own being which is united to the soul as an accident related to a substance. In its own natural being, the idea is distinct from the thing it expresses. But its intentional existence allows the idea to fulfill its primary function, which is to become the object of knowledge. "In fact, the idea is the object itself existing intentionally" (16-17). Two particularly illuminating passages in the book are the discussion of sensation and the defense of the immateriality of the concept against idealism. To reduce sensation to a purely physical action would be to deprive it of its realistic moorings as well as to call into question its obj ectivity ( 95) . If sensation were just the physical impression on the sense faculty, there would be no guarantee of objectivity. (Presumably, BOOK REVIEWS 157 Simon is thinking here of situations like the inability of an impression made on wax to be identical to the impressed design.) But how transport the identical form in the sensible object to the sense faculty? Efficient causality must he involved: the sensible ohj ect must act on the senses. Pure passivity in the sense faculty can mean only a physical or material union. Passive reception of a sensible form would amount to no more than a material perception, which could never count as an act of knowledge. Sensation, like cognition, is a form of knowing and this involves an intentional action. But an intentional action cannot occur without a reaction. The only way around this obstacle is to distinguish two aspects of an idea, its physical or subjective aspect and its intentional or objective aspect (107 ff.). The causality exerted by the sensible object on the sense faculty cannot be reduced to ordinary causality. It is more than a physical action; it is also an intentional action because, by its very nature, it is ordered to an intentional union: it results in sensory cognition. The sensible object acts on the sense faculty to produce an image containing the object itself in a dormant state; its object-ness is awakened when the soul bestows its own vital activity on it (108-109). Despite the book's focus on the intentional and thus immaterial being of the object of knowledge, Simon's understanding of realism's dictum, "We know, and what we know are things," saves him from a tumble into the idealist pit: " What we must insist upon . . . is that the intentional transitive action, which is all that goes on in the preparatory phase of sensation, and in which the sense faculty is totally passive, does not cease when the faculty, stirred into initial act, joins with the intentionally present object in the full act of cognition" (112). Otherwise, if the sensible object stops its determining exertions on the sense faculty, an essential requirement for our knowledge of extramental reality-the bridge between thought and thing-would disappear. In the intellect's graps of the universal, the form once impressed on the soul, remains forever. But in sensation the singular sensible thing, residing as it does outside the soul, can he united with it only by exerting efficient causality on it. For this reason, thought is a more genuinely immanent activity than sensation (112). This affirmation of the pure immanence of thought suggests a further challenge to realism, this time from the quarter of idealism. This challenge is the topic of the book's last section. Apparently paraphrasing Aristotle's observation that " the intellect in act is the intelligible in act," Simon acknowledges that "The thing thought is, in a certain sense, the work of thought " ( 132) . Thought is immaterial, as intellect is immaterial; the intellect can have as an object only what is like itself, only what is immaterial. Does this mean that " ... the intellect is 158 BOOK REVIEWS a kind of divine ego open only unto itself? " (132). How can trans· cendental idealism be avoided? Simon credits idealism because it sees the problems generated by admitting the spiritual nature of the object of thought, but he rebukes it for failing to proceed further with its inquiry. It is the grasp of the object of thought as an intentional form that furnishes the correct interpretation. Because existent things lack immateriality, they cannot be embraced in an act of knowledge. For the latter to take place, the thing must be represented to the knower by means of an idea, which expresses the thing in an immaterial state without changing its essence. Against the idealists, Simon thus concludes: "Thought does not produce the content of thought, what it produces is the state (the existential modality) in which what is thought is delivered to it " ( 132-33) . The error of the idealists is to have confused thought with the production of concepts: " Thought is being, not production; it is pure quality not a movement" (134). To suppose that thought is nothing more than the production of a concept is to treat it as a transitive rather than immanent activity. The need for a transitive activity to deliver the datum to be known to the knower is indisputable. But the expression of what is thought cannot be an action really distinct from thought itself. The immateriality of the object of thought in act can occur only with the exercise of thought; thought nevertheless can be in act only with an object raised to that immaterial state. The absurdity of an act of thinking that is not associated with the act of expressing what is thought evinces itself in the realization that this implies the possibility of thought without an object of thought. Thought and the expression of what is thought comprise a single act, and this act, although both immanent and productive [transitive], is primarily immanent, for the goal of the concept's production is thought. In other words, immanence and productivity are distinct only in the sense that they are two modalities of that single act ( 134-35) . The book offers a nice demonstration of Simon's ability to critique other philosophical positions. His response to skepticism is crisp and trenchant. The skeptic claims that it is impossible to tell if there is a thing residing behind the phenomenon, which is the object of knowledge; since all we ever know are phenomena, they encircle us as a blind, and we cannot compare the object of knowledge with the putative thing. Simon points out that the skeptic fails to carry his analysis of the phenomenal object far enough. Had he done so, he would have seen that two objects of thought that are necessarily identical-as in "Socrates is a man "-imply the presence of a transobjective thing. "Socrates" and "man," although necessarily identical in the judg- BOOK REVIEWS 159 ment, cannot he identical within the realm of phenomena, otherwise the two objects of thought would be one, which they clearly are not. The only other possibility is the transohj ectivity of the thing: the ohj ect (of knowledge) and the thing are one (146-48). This example of the critical component of Simon's realism must be understood as no more than a dialectical gambit. It shows, by rational analysis, skepticism's fallacious separation of the object (of knowledge) and the thing (known). But for the realist, critique presupposes reality; the real must enjoy primacy over the critical. Simon would never have supposed that the inference from the object of knowledge (phenomenon) to the transobjective thing justifies, in turn, the inference that extramental things exist. It is impossible to proceed from thought to thing; the proper direction is from thing to thought. And the thing is known, directly and certainly, by a prephilosophical intuition embedded in our experiential knowledge. The genre in which Simon writes is notable for its scant attention to empiricist epistemology, hut that is quite understandable. The period in which An Introduction to Metaphysics of Knowledge was written has much to do with it. The early decades of this century witnessed an intense controversy among Thomistic philosophers in France over the use of critique in epistemology. Its proponents, Noel and the Louvain School of epistemology, not to mention Marechal, argued that the Kantian critique had undermined the credibility of the objective knowledge of things and that henceforth epistemological realism must defend itself by taking the knowing subject and the object of knowledge as its starting point. Its opponents, notably Gilson, argued that the concept of critique was incompatible with realism and that to endorse it was to fall into the trap of idealism. What explains Simon's neglect of empiricist epistemology more than anything else, however, is the clear distinction between cognitive and noncognitive beings that he argues for in the opening pages of the hook. He bases his claims for the uniquely privileged nature of cognitive beings on an appeal to our own experiential knowledge of what it means to know. Given this orientation, it is quite understandable that Simon would not find much merit in an inquiry into the materialized concept of mind defended by empiricism. All in all, this is a must-have hook for any student of epistemology and the foundations of knowledge. Vukan Kuic and Richard J. Thompson deserve our thanks for their painstaking e:fforts in bringing this philosophical treasure to the English-reading public. RAYMOND DENNEHY Universityof San Francisco San Francisco,Califomia 160 BOOK REVIEWS Theology and the Dialectics of History. By ROBERT M. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1990. Pp. xvi Can. $95.00 (hardcover) ; Can. $45.00 (paper). DORAN. + 732. This work aims to explain, extend, complement, and employ the philosophical and theological writings of Bernard Lonergan. The University of Toronto Press has recently begun publishing Lonergan's Collected Works, a series projected to 22 volumes; Doran's book is the first in a related series of monographs planned by the same publisher. The book consists of an introduction plus 21 chapters, with the chapters grouped into five main sections: (1) Basic Terms and Relations; (2) Personal Values and the Dialectic of the Subject; (3) Social Values and the Dialectic of Community; (4) Cultural Values and the Dialectic of Culture; and (5) Hermeneutics and the Ontology of Meaning. Doran's fundamental argument is that careful phenomenological analysis brings to light a series of utterly basic and pre-voluntary structural tensions in the concrete life processes of human individuals in community. These tensions may be characterized generically as the resultants of two contrasting human tendencies, the tendency toward limitation and the tendency toward transcendence. At the level of the individual person as such, at the level of the culture, and at the level of the society, these structural tensions constitute occasions of lifeshaping decision for human agents, occasions of unavoidable choice among what in fact are alternative basic personal, cultural, and social values. For at each level there is the " dialectical option" of living in such a way as to do justice to both poles of the tension, or of reinforcing only the tendency toward limitation, or of reinforcing only the tendency toward transcendence. Drawing upon Lonergan's studies of personal conversion in the intellectual, moral, and religious realms, and complementing them with his own extensive study of personal conversion in the psychic realm, Doran goes on to argue that the constructive option at every level is that of reinforcing both the tendency toward limitation and the tendency toward transcendence. To favor either tendency alone is ultimately at odds with individual, cultural, and/or social well-being. This conclusion, in turn, provides the basis from which Doran proceeds in elaborating anticipatory or " heuristic " categories for a normative theory of history-general categories for discriminating between progress and decline in the reciprocal relations among individual lives, cultural ideals, and social structures. Because at its most fundamental level it expressly addresses the issue of religious conversion, this heuristic theory of history is a heuristic theology of history. More- BOOK REVIEWS 161 over, because academic inquiry is one of the human activities it anticipates, this heuristic theology of history stands as the potential framework of fully integrated interdisciplinary studies, a foundational framework clearly distinguishing and relating theological studies, human scientific and scholarly studies, and the natural sciences. I see four main reasons why this hook is noteworthy. First, the significance of thoroughly and accurately explaining someone else's work is proportionate to the significance of that other person's work in the first place. But Lonergan's studies of human knowing, deciding, and loving, of bias and conversion, and of social progress, decline, and healing are coming to be widely recognized as the work of a seminal thinker. Doran's account of this work is lucid, detailed, and nuanced. Second, Doran extends Lonergan's work itself, making explicit certain important points that Lonergan merely implies and completing certain fundamental analyses that Lonergan does not bring fully to term. Especially significant in this regard are Doran's treatments of such themes as " the situation" as a theological source; the notion of dialectic; the apprehension of value; the fivefold scale of values; understanding religious doctrines in terms of understanding historical process; and the notion of cosmopolis. Third, the hook goes beyond Lonergan's own studies in many important respects, complementing Lonergan's findings with brilliant, profound, and far-reaching conclusions by Doran himself. Among the most notable of these original conclusions are those regarding the relationship of feelings, symbols, and values (a topic on which Doran's previous writings have already earned him an extensive following) ; psychic conversion; a:ffectivity, meaning, and praxis; the dialectic of culture; and the Church as servant of God in the world. Fourth, Doran does not elaborate the stances of Lonergan and himself at a level of utter generality and in isolation from the work of others. On the contrary, a further important and original feature of his hook is the way that it elucidates those stances by relating them to certain particular issues and in dialogue with the work of certain other thinkers. In the most extensive of these instructive clarifications by contrast, Doran engages Jung on depth psychology; Marx on social, economic, and political theory; and Segundo on liberation theology. In its style, as in its other features, this book is easily the best of Doran's writings to date. It is measured and deliberate in tone, smooth and sometimes even elegant in phrasing; and it exhibits the mastery and confidence that are the fruit of Doran's many years of reading, thinking, and writing about the matters he treats here. I recommend it warmly. MICHAEL VERTIN Saint Michael's College University of Toronto 162 BOOK REVIEWS L'un et l'autre sacerdoce: Essai sur la structure sacramentelle de l'Eglise. By DANIEL BOURGEOIS. Desclee, 1991. Pp. 243. 89F (Paper). This essay in sacramental theology forms part of the prestigious Desclee collection Essai, which includes works by such celebrated authors as Jean Danielou and Hans Urs von Balthasar. The present author belongs to a recently-formed monastic community, the Fra· ternite des Moines apostoliques, which claims among its principal ministerial priorities the proper celebration of the Church's foll liturgy. The Fraternity staffs the parish church of Saint Jean de Malte, which enjoys a well-earned reputation in the French region as a center of liturgical and ecclesial renewal. The present book actually contains two essays. The first essai comprises the book's principal divisions where the author presents his main proposal. Developed during a series of conferences that the author delivered to a group of French bishops, these seven chapters unfold Bourgeois's fundamental thesis concerning the sacramentality of the Church. Unlike a great deal of contemporary ecclesiology, which tends to focus on structural analyses of the institutional Church, the author retrieves a significant theme of the Second Vatican Council's Lumen gentium on the sacramental nature of the Church. In particular, his thesis holds that the sacramentality of the ministerial priesthood forms a living center of the Church's visible presence in the world. While the transcendence of Christ's saving action guarantees the validity of the Church's commission to sanctify, to teach, and to govern, this three· fold mission operates efficaciously only to the extent that the whole Church, priests and Christian faithful together, sacramentally form a catholic Body throughout the world. At the same time, the author strongly insists that one cannot reduce the sacramental dimension of the Church to a number of £unctions which either priests or the Christian faithful discharge. Instead, Bourgeois envisions a complementarity of charisms which, by reason of their common derivation from divine grace, manifest an unambiguous manifestation of the true Church of Christ, in which excessive clericalism finds no quarter. But there is another essay in this book, and it is found in the "Notes" attached to each of the seven chapters and to the appendix significantly entitled, " On a certain ambiguity in post-conciliar ecclesiology." These eight sections of "notes," it is true, contain the ordinary references and bibliographical information which serve to document and support the author's main argument, but there is much more to be found in these 46 pages of fine print text. Here the author 163 BOOK REVIEWS sets forth in a trenchant style his incisive analysis of a wide range of theological issues, from the influence of Heidegger on modern university-centered theology to certain interventions made by a Swiss bishop during the synodal debates over the Apostolic Exhortation Christifideles laici. In reading these notes, one is reminded a hit of the genius of Nietzsche, for instance, in Beyond Good and Evil, who brilliantly exposes the core of critical questions in epigrammatic style and still leaves the reader with something to think about. In fact, the substantial notes are so well constructed that they can he read with profit, even independently of the main text. The author is to he congratulated for sharing his theological culture with us and for contributing such a fine essay on this important contemporary question, the distinctive character of the ministerial priesthood. ROMANUS CESSARIO, Dominican House of Studies Washington, D.C. O.P.