"INTRINSICALLY EVIL ACTS" AND THE MORAL VIEWPOINT: CLARIFYING A CENTRAL TEACHING OF VER/TATIS MARTIN SPLENDOR 1 RHONHEIMER Roman Athenaeum of the Holy Cross Rome, Italy 1. Introduction: Distinguishing choices and their objects from further intention:s and consequences M ANY CATHOLIC moral theologians have asserted during the last few years that to know what a person really does each time he or she is acting and, consequently, to qualify morally this concrete doing, one must take into account all the further goals for the sake of which this person chooses what he concretely does. Equally, so these theologians contend, a balance of all foreseen consequences should be established to make out whether a determinate behavior is the right or the wrong thing to choose. Therefore, according to this view it will always be impossible to qualify as morally evil according to its speciesits "object "-the deliberate choice of certain kinds of behavior or specific ads, apart from a consideration of the intention for which the choice is made or the totality of the foreseeable consequences of that act for all persons concerned (VS 79). The encyclical Veritatis Splendor rejects this view of so-called " teleological " ethical theories 2 as incompatible with the exist1 I thank Prof. John M. Haas of Philadelphia for having carefully reviewed my English version of this paper, originally written in German (and not yet published). 2 The term "teleological " as a characterization of ethical theories became successful through C. D. Broad's essay, " Some of the Main Problems of Ethics," Philosophy XXI (1946), reprinted in C. D. Broad, Broad's Critical 1 2 MARTIN RHONHEIMER ence of describable concrete actions which are " intrinsically evil," that is, which are evil " always and per se, in other words, on account of their very object, and quite apart from the ulterior intentions of the one acting and the circumstances " (VS 80). Consequently, this view finally is judged as incompatible with the Essays in Moral Philosophy, ed. D. R. Cheney (London: Allen & Unwin; New York: Humanities Press, 1971), pp. 223-246. Broad simply identified any "teleological" argumentation with a consequentialist one. So he says (p. 230 of the reprinted essays) : " One characteristic which tends to make an act right is that it will produce at least as good consequences as an alternative open to the agent in the circumstances ( ... ) We can sum this up by saying that the property of being optimific is a very important right-tending characteristic. I call it teleological because it refers to the goodness of the ends or consequences which the act brings about." Broad, then, goes on to say that a " nonteleological " characteristic of an action would be, for example, the obligation, independent from considering consequences, to perform what one has promised. But already in 1930 Broad had distinguished "teleological" from "deontological" ethical theories; see C. D. Broad, Five Types of Ethical Theory (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1930), pp. 206 ff. Many, today, call non-teleological ethics (in Broad's sense) "deontological "; cf. William K. Frankena, Ethics (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall, 1963). The term "teleological ethics" was thus " imported " by German moral theologians, mainly by Bruno Schuller; see his Die Begrundung sittlicher Urteile. Typen ethischer Argumentation in der Moraltheologie, 2nd ed. (Diisseldorf: Patmos, 1980), pp. 282-298 (first published in 1973). According to Schuller, a normative ethic would be "teleological " if it affirms that " the moral character of all the actions and the omissions of man is exclusively determined by its consequences" (282). So he uses "teleological ethics" as synonymous with "consequentialism" (a term in fact created by G. E. M. Anscombe) and even with " utilitarianism." Its counterpart would be " deontological ethics," which holds that there are some actions the moral rightness of which should not be judged exclusively on the basis of their consequences; see also Bruno Schiiller, "Various Types of Grounding for Ethical Norms," in Readings in Moral Theology No. 1: Moral Norms and Catholic Tradition, ed. Charles E. Curran and Richard A. McCormick, S.J. (New York: Paulist Press, 1979), pp. 184-198. However, as it seems to me, these distinctions are not very clarifying; they rather seem to confuse judgments of prudence ("such and such is the right thing to do") with judgments of conscience ("I must do what I know to be the right thing, whatever the consequences "). Everyone must be a " deontologist" on this (second) level, if he does not want to deny that one must follow one's conscience (see for this some of my publications to which I refer further on). For supplementary terminological clarifications, see J. M. Finnis, Fundamentals of Ethics (Washington: Georgetown University Press; Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983), pp. 81-86. THE MORAL VIEWPOINT OF VERITATIS SPLENDOR 3 existence of absolutely-without exception-binding prohibitive (or : negative) moral norms, that is : with so-called " moral absolutes." The encyclical clearly distinguishes the object of a concrete choice, and the corresponding action, from ulterior intentions with which a choice is made. It seems to me that one of the central problems implied in thus distinguishing choices and their objects from further intentions may be formulated as follows: What precisely is qualified when an action or freely chosen behavior is qualified as " morally evil " by virtue of its very " object" ? This point, I think, must be carefully elucidated if we want to talk reasonably about concrete actions, or choices of determinate behaviors, being morally evil by virtue of their very object, i.e., independent of further intentions. If we could not sustain the distinction between the "object" and "ulterior intentions " of a concrete choice, adherents of " consequentialism " or " proportionalism " could successfully deny being implicated in the encyclical's criticism of these positions. In order to answer the above question, however, another very important assertion of the encyclical must not be overlooked. After having affirmed, in number 78, that " the morality of the human act depends primarily and fundamentally on the 'object' rationally chosen by the deliberate will," the text of the encyclical adds the following remark : In order to be able to grasp the object of an act which specifies that act morally, it is therefore necessary to place oneself in the perspective of tho acting person. And this is so, the encyclical continues, for the following reason (the emphasis is mine) : The object of the act is in fact a freely chosen kind of behavior. ( ... ) By the object of a given moral act, then, one cannot mean a process or an event of the merely physical order, to be assessed on the basis of its ability to bring about a given state of affairs in the outside world. Rather, that object is the proximate end of a deliberate decision which determines the act of willing on the part of the acting person ( VS 78) . 4 MARTIN RHONHEIMER The above quoted rejection (VS 79) which follows m the encyclical in fact is formulated in quite a sophisticated way (e.g., it refers both "object" and the predicate "morally evil" to " choice of behavior " and not simply to " behavior "). 3 This sentence, repeated in number 82, remains the doctrinal core of the whole encyclical and one of the cornerstones of its argument. And it seems to me that no " teleological " ethical theory-be it " consequentialist" or "proportionalist "-can reasonably deny being affected, indeed, hit in the heart, by this rejection. For it is characteristic for all " teleological " ethical theories that they consider senseless any distinction between "objects" and "further intentions," as well as that they reject the possibility both of judging "wrong" a chosen action independently from all the foreseen consequences, and of speaking on this level as such about " moral evil." During the following exposition I will, without referring much to the text of the encyclical, simply expose how-according to my views which owe so much to the work of many others-the encyclical's teaching should be understood. I not only intend to follow Aquinas's ethical theory but also to render explicit some implicit presuppositions in the field of action theory that are necessary to render fully intelligible both Aquinas's account of "moral objects" as such and its pertinence for our present problem. 4 8 Compare this also with No. 1761 of the Catechism of the Catholic Church, quoted in VS 78: " . . . there are certain specific kinds of behavior that are always wrong to choose, because choosing them involves a disorder of the will, that is, a moral evil." 4 See a more detailed account in my following books and articles : N atur als Grund/age der Moral (Innsbruck-Wien: Tyrolia Verlag, 1987); La prospettiva della morale. Fondamenti dell'etica filosofica (forthcoming: Rome: Armando Editore, 1994) ; "Menschliches Handeln und seine Moralitat. Zur Begriindung sittlicher Normen," in Martin Rhonheimer, Andreas Laun, Tatjana Goritschewa, Walter Mixa, Ethos und Menschenbild (St. Ottilien: EOSVerlag, 1989), pp. 45-114; "Zur Begriindung sittlicher Normen aus der Natur," and "Ethik-Handeln-Sittlichkeit," Der Mensch als Mitte und Massstab der Medizin, ed. Johannes Bonelli (Wien-New York: SpringerVerlag, 1992), pp. 49-94 and 137-174; finally, my investigations into Aquinas's THE MORAL VIEWPOINT OF VERITATIS SPLENDOR 5 I shall first clarify the term " object " as used in practical reasoning (section 2). I then clarify the basic perspective in which we have to consider our problem, the perspective of intentionality, showing how problematic it is when an ethical theory distinguishes " moral " from " non-moral " goods (section 3). This opens the way to speak properly about the " object " of a human act, which of course is fundamental for knowing what precisely is qualified when an action is qualified as " evil by virtue of its object " (section 4). In the longest section ( 5), I will challenge the distinction between " right making properties " and " good making properties " of an action ; I argue for a virtue-orientated rather than norm- or rule-based ethics, showing why only the former is able really to explain why there are in fact some "intrinsically evil acts." In section 6, I shall show how intentionality explains the rational structure of what we call the "object" of a human act. Finally, in section 7, I will add some remarks about how to integrate my analysis into the general frame of a natural law theory. 2. Objects of actions as objects of practical reason According to Aquinas, every action intended by the will is a " bonum apprehensum et ordinatum per rationem," a " good understood and ordered by reason." 5 Clearly human acts are specified by different objects; every potency has its own specific object which is its proper end. However, the human act is morally specified only by an "object in so far as it is related to the principle of human acts, that is reason." 6 One must, therefore, guard against identifying the object which provides the moral specificainterpretation and completion of Aristotle's action theory are expected to be published under the title Praktische Vernunft und Verniinftigkeit der Praxis (Ber !in : Akademie Verlag, 1994) . 5 ST I-II, q.20, a.I ad 1. In ST I-II, q.18, a.IO, Aquinas affirms that the object which specifies an action morally is a "forma a ratione concepta." 6 " ••• ab obiecto relato ad principium actuum humanorum, quod est ratio" (ST I-II, q.18, a.8). The "bonum virtutis" consists "ex quadam commensuratione actus ad circumstantias et finem, q1wm ratio facit" (In II Sent., d.39, q.2, a.l). 6 MARTIN RHONHEIMER tion of an act with " things " or the natural ends of single potencies. As Germain Grisez has put it, " ... human acts have their structure from intelligence. Just insofar as an action is considered according to its naturally given structure, it is to that extent not considered as a human act-i.e., as a moral act-but rather as a physiological process or as instinctive behavior. Action with a given structure and acts structured by intelligence differ as totally as nature differs from morality. Nature has an order which reason can consider but cannot make and cannot alter. Morality has an order which reason institutes by guiding the acts of the will." 1 The object which provides the moral specification is always the object of a human act just insofar as it is an act of a human being. Without the act of practical reason which relates to any object in a specifically moral way, there is neither a human act nor a personal meaning of such acts. To speak of the "object of an action " is to speak of the content of an intentional action. That is to say, the morally relevant object of an action is the content of an act insofar as it is the object of an intentio voluntatis (whether this is on the level of the choice of concrete, particular actions, or on the level of intending further ends for the sake of which a concrete action is chosen as a means). With this we see that every object is equally the object of the practical reason which orders and regulates, the fundamental rule or measure of which is the natural law. Only in this way do both the various natural ends of human potencies and the usus rerum exteriorum become integrated into the personal suppositum in a cognitive-practical way. They thus become objectified in their intelligibility which renders possible the recognition of their morally objective meaning. 3. The perspective of intentionality and the so-called " non-moral " goods The bona propria, i.e., the proper goods toward which the individual potencies are ordered as ends-considered in their ontic 1 Germain Grisez, "A New Formulation of a Natural-Law against Contraception," The Thomist 30 :4 (1966) : 343. Argument THE MORAL VIEWPOINT OF VERITATIS SPLENDOR 7 structure, independently from their being potencies of a human person, that is, considered on the level of their "genus naturae " -are not yet moral goods which are as such morally significant (they are no bona debita for the acting person as such). 8 But calling them " non-moral" goods seems to be equally erroneous. One simply cannot make moral judgments on the level of "genus naturae." However, to call these proper goods of potencies "nonmoral goods " is actually a moral qualification since it is possible only from an ethical perspective. To be ethical, a perspective must take account of the acting subject's intentional relation to acts and ends. To affirm that the ends of natural inclinations are nonmoral goods or non-moral values is to assert that they do not possess an inherent " proportio ad rationem." This would mean that they were exactly as inclinations "indifferentes ex specie," in St. Thomas's language, or that these inclinations, acts, and ends are morally indifferent not only if we consider them " abstractly" in their "genus naturae,'' but also if we conceive them as forming part of the human suppositum. Again, this would mean that only further circumstances or intentions of the acting subject by which he acts on these inclinations and performs the acts proper to them would have a moral qualification, while the inclinations themselves would not. To look at natural inclinations and their ends in an abstractontic way is, however, neither ethically nor anthropologically an adequate way of considering them. It simply can never lead to a morally qualifying judgment, and this is precisely what the assertion means which states that they are " indifferent " (" adiaphora ") or non-moral goods. 9 It is not the ends of these inclina8 The distinction between (" actus" or "finis") proprium on the one side, and debitum on the other, goes back to ST I-II, q.91, a. 2. See for this my N atur als Grundlage der Moral, pp. 72 ff. 9 Cf. ST I-II, q.18, a.8: Aquinas arrives at identifying an act as indifferent "in specie " by the assertion that the act as such has no proportion to the " ordo rationis" ; considered in itself the choice of such an act is not yet meaningful for practical reason, " sicut levare festucam de terra, ire ad campum et huiusmodi." It is something quite different to consider an act, which by itself does possess such a " proportio ad rationem," independently from this relation 8 MARTIN RHONHEIMER tions which are non-moral, but rather the abstract way of considering them which is non-moral. The problem springs from looking at natural inclinations simply as natural inclinations, inclinations of the "genus naturae " abstracted from the actual human person. 10 This means that inclinations, their proper acts, and ends are falsely looked at as " data," "facts," and " state of affairs," from the perspective of an outside observer, rather than as inclinations of a intellectually and thus willingly striving person. As such, every human being experiences his inclinations as his inclinations, as something that he willingly and intentionally pursues. This, precisely, is not recognizable from the viewpoint of an outside observer. From the viewpoint of the external observer we also say that birds build nests because the outcome of a bird's gathering different materials and executing determinate bodily movement is in fact a nest. But do birds really build nests? That is, do they perform the action of "building a nest" ? For this they should intend, in gathering materiais, the goal of building a nest; they should gather materials, move, and work for the sake of building a nest. Moreover, they even should also intend the " why " of building the nest, e.g., " to protect their offspring." With good to reason, that is, on its merely natural level (e.g., an act of eating or nutrition, an act of sexual copulation). In this case, this will be a biological, physiological or psychological viewpoint which in no way allows a moral judgment. The qualification of an act as "indifferent," however, is precisely such a moral judgment. 1 0 Aquinas also sometimes uses the expression " consideratio absoluta," that is, a consideration of acts detaching them from the wider context in which a moral qualification would be possible. Cf. In IV Sent., d.16, q.3, a.1, qla.2 ad 2: "aliqui actus ex suo genere sunt mali vet boni ( ... ) . Hoc autem ex quo actus reperitur in tali genere, quamvis sit de substantia eius inquantum est ex genere moris, tamen est extra substantiam ipsius secundum quod consideratur ipsa substantia actus absolute: unde aliqui actus sunt idem in specie naturae qui differunt in specie moris ; sicut fornicatio et actus matrimonialis." Both fornication and a matrimonial act are, as sexual acts considered in their "genus naturae" and in their corresponding physiological, biological, and in a sense also in their affective aspects, strictly identical acts. Nevertheless the human sexual act is not an "actus indifferens" if considered in its "genus moris." THE MORAL VIEWPOtNT OF VERITATIS SPLEN1>0R 9 reason we assume that they indeed are not doing this. 11 A human person, however, who strives for self-preservation or for the care of his off spring, and who performs corresponding actions, does not only "arrive at" preserving his life, etc.; rather, he also intends it i'.n his actions. He does something for the sake of preserving himself and caring for his offspring, and this "for the sake of " is a content of his will. Self-preservation and care for offspring are, in this case, objects of an intending will, guided by reason. And as such, the corresponding goods ( self-preservation, care for off spring) are much more than the resulting states of affairs of " self-preservation" or " protection of offspring." It rather is a practical principle which guided a freely chosen act and its intentional content, a content which determines as an intelligible good the agent's will. 12 These contents of intentionality (self-preservation, care for others, and similar things) are already on the level of natural inclination a " good " of a striving human person and, therefore, " good for man " in the context of the person as a whole. It is precisely this which we call a "moral good." " Moral goods " are the contents of acts of the will. And the contents of acts of the will are precisely that which we call, from a moral viewpoint, their objects. We can conclude that to call the ends pursued by natural inclinations " non-moral " goods signifies, in the final analysis, a moral qualification (or " dis-qualification ") based on the "genus naturae" of these inclinations and their corresponding acts. This, however, is an illicit transgressio in aliud genus and, therefore, results in a conclusion easily recognizable as a sort of "naturalistic fallacy." The naturalistic fallacy is based on a failure to see that the "genus naturae" and the "genus moris" are not 11 This is not an argument against teleology in nature; just the opposite is the case : this teleology exists because we affirm both ( 1) that birds do not intend the goal of building a nest and (2) that they indeed do what they do for the sake of building a nest; so the " intention " is inherent in nature. 12 Compare again VS 78 (the emphasis is mine): "The object of the act of willing is in fact a freely chosen kind of behaviour. To the extent that it is in conformity with the order of reason, it is the cause of the goodness of the will; it perfects us morally. . .• " 10 MARTIN RHONHEIMER derivable one from the other. 13 The fallacy occurs when one adopts a morally qualifying predicate on the level of " genus naturae." But " moral indifference" actually is such a predicate. Equally, "morally right " is a morally qualifying predicate. It is a predicate which proportionalists adopt for actions on the basis of the resulting balance of non-moral goods which can be foreseen. In this context the Stoic doctrine of the adiaphora is sometimes invoked: 14 Life, health, beauty, property, social status, honor, etc. are not, one says, goods which determine a person's being a good person. This depends exclusively on the goodness of the will. I would argue in the following way against this attempt to defend consequentialism by invoking this Stoic teaching : The Stoic doctrine only intends to differentiate the sphere of being from the sphere of acting. Indeed, whether somebody is a good or a wicked person does not depend on the state in which he happens to find himself or the state in which he happens to arrive independently from his willing as an acting subject. "Good" and "evil" as objects of practical reason and intentional striving, however, are not at all states of affairs, in which the acting subject happens to find himself. As soon as the agent relates practically to goods/ bads as life, health, physical integrity, truth, property, it is no longer possible to call those goods or bads adiaphora, indifferent things or " extra-moral " goods; for the practical relation itself involves, with regard to them, one willingly taking a position on the basis of a judgment of practical reason; and it is precisely this which determines the quality of the will as a good or an evil will. So precisely insofar as a good is a practical good (or object of a free will orientated to action) it cannot be a non-moral good because it is impossible that the will relates to "good" in a nonmoral way (not even to a piece of bread practically judged and i3 This reproach, which I have invoked against adherents of so-called "teleological ethics," is not, it seems to me, sufficiently refuted by W. Wolbert in his critique of my position; cf. Werner Wolbert, "Naturalismus in der Ethik. Zurn Vorwurf des naturalistischen Fehlschlusses," Theologie und Glaube 79 (1989) : 234-267, especially pp. 259 ff. 1 4 Bruno Schuller, Die Begrundung sittlicher Urteile; Werner Wolbert, Ethische Argumentation und Pariinese in 1 Kor 7 (Diisseldorf: Patmos, 1981). THE MORAL VIEWPOINT OF VERITATIS SPLENDOR 11 chos·en as " to be eaten here and now "). The Stoics only wanted to emphasize that moral goodness consists in an attitude of indifference with regard to any good other than virtue itself. So, they intended to render praxis itself indifferent as far as it relates to these goods called adiaphora. The important thing, the Stoics affirmed, is to be virtuous, which means to live in apathia with regard to indifferent goods. Consequentialists and proportionalists, however, are not Stoics. For they assert that precisely in the sphere of these " indifferent goods " man has to take responsibility for optimizing these goods (and minimizing the bads), and that this is the basic criterion of the " rightness " of an action. That means that they also consider the practical relation to single adiaphora as "morally indifferent " (while Stoics want to render insignificant this practical relation) and that only the action, which optimizes them, is morally right. This, however, is a thesis in the field of action theory which is profoundly problematic. 4. "Object" in the perspective of human actions This problematic consists in confusing the viewpoint of the "first person" (the agent's perspective) with the viewpoint of the third person (the observer's viewpoint). To a large extent, these two perspectives correspond to two quite different concepts of human action : the intentional and the causal-eventistic concept.15 The latter looks at actions " from outside " and sees them as events which cause determinate effects. Events which cause effects, however, are not yet actions (it could, for example, be an earthquake). From such a perspective, " acting" can only be reconstructed, as it were, by interpreting the foreseen connection between act-event and its effect as being the reason for which a rational subject has performed this particular act. An action would be explained precisely when it was possible to indicate u About the importance of the perspective of the "first person" see J. M. Finnis, Fundamentals of Ethics, pp. 114 ff.; Giuseppe Abba, Felicita, vita buona e virtu (Rome: LAS, 1989) ; Angel Rodriguez Lufio, Etica (Florence: Le Monnier, 1992) and finally my own La prospettiva della morale. 12 MARTIN RHONHEIMER those reasons which the agent might have had for performing the action. The same applies to its moral qualification: The action itself and its effects are simply events or states of affairs (that is, non-moral realities). Only those reasons which an agent might have for causing through the action-event x the effect y (the state of affairs) are morally qualifiable; this, however, only as " morally right " or " morally wrong." This, I should add, is more a qualification of effects (of y) and their desirability than a qualification of the actions (of x) by which these effects are brought about. For example, the action-event x brought about by A could consist in causing (in what way does not matter) the death of P. The caused state of affairs will be "death of P." Only the reasons for the desirability of P's death (in the context of a balance of other goods and bads) would determine whether "to do x " is right or wrong. Such a reason may be, e.g., the foreseeable consequences of A's doing x for all concerned (i.e., also the effects of doing x with regard to the life of Q, R, S, ... , T as a consequence of A's doing x; e.g., in a case of hostage-taking and blackmail). What here, however, is entirely put aside is precisely the acting person as a subject which intends something in doing x; the acting subject, therefore, which performs x for the sake of causing P's death (with the purpose of killing him). That is: What is put aside is the choice of "killing-P " as a setting of A's will against the life of P. This also means: What is put aside is A's taking a position with regard to a specific person to which he owes, as to his fellow-man, this and that. This act of choice can adequately be seen only by looking at human actions in the perspective of the first person: From such a viewpoint there are not only two states of affairs (an action-event and its resulting effect), but also the act of intending P's death. This intentionality (which here is a choice, the choice of an action) cannot be reduced to "causing the state of affairs of P's death." Otherwise there would be no difference between what an earthquake " does " and what an acting person does: the object and intentional content of "causing P's death" means to set one's will against the THE MORAL VIEWPOINT OF VERITATIS SPLENDOR 13 life of P ( = against P in the dimension of what fundamentally is "good-for-him") and this positioning of one's will constitutes a specific relation between the acting person and P. The content of this "taking a position" shapes the agent's will and is, as such, the content of a free will, and is " good " or " evil " wholly independently of other (foreseeable) resulting states of affairs which might be brought about as a consequence of A's abstaining from killing P (as, for example, saving the lives of Q, R, S, ... , T). From an observer's viewpoint there is, therefore, no difference between "causing P's death" and "killing P," that is, "doing something for the sake of causing P's death." From the observer's viewpoint we may say in the same way" John killed ten persons " and " the earthquake killed ten persons " (as we affirm " The bird built a nest "). What we cannot say in either case from this particular perspective is: Besides the ten killed persons, there is also a murderer. In the case of the earthquake this would be simply nonsense; in the case of John, however, it could well be the case that he is, in fact, a murderer. But it will never be possible to justify such a differentiation from the observer's viewpoint (otherwise we should equally admit that an earthquake at least could be something like a murderer). In reality, however, "to kill P" is not simply "to cause P's being dead," but rather it is to choose, to intend, to want P's death (for the sake of whatever further end). Those practical goods which are objects of our actions (and here P's death is, for the agent, a "practical good," the content of his action) are never such objects simply in their natural, antic value-quality as states of affairs, but rather as objects of an act of the will guided by reason. That is why objects of actions-precisely because of their being objects of a human action-are goods in a moral sense. As said before : bonum apprehensum et ordinatum per rationem. Therefore, practical reason, which is embedded in appetite, and the corresponding moral reflection never relate to the " bona propria "-the particular goods of single natural inclinations-as mere state of affairs on the level of their " genus naturae " ; as such they cannot be objects or contents of the natural inclination 14 MARTIN RHONHEIMER of a humaw person who relates to them appetitively, by will informed by reason. For whom is "self-preservation" ever simply something given, a good only to be " taken into account " or a mere state of affairs, no matter how desirable? For whom is it ever a " non-moral " good, that is, a good which does not concern him as a person striving for the fulfilment of his being? As it was said, the ontic-natural aspect of these goods or ends is a posterior abstraction which abstracts them from the context of practical self-experience; so, this purely natural aspect is a reduction of the proper intelligibility of these goods. The goods of natural inclinations are never simply a set of given facts, and man is not simply the sum of various inclinations. They rather constitute the proper practical self-experience of persons as a certain kind of being. They form a whole, grasped by intelligence as " my" being. So, the practical self-experience of man as naturally striving for goods is precisely what constitutes the identity of a person as a human person : every inclination and its proper good are experienced as correlated to my own striving and not as something alien to me, as, e.g., nature which surrounds me, the world in which I am placed, my environment.16 This "good-for-me" as object of a reason-guided 1 6 This, it seems to me, is an often overlooked differentiation. An example is provided by Louis J anssens, " Ontic Evil and Moral Evil," Louvain Studies 4 (1972) : 121 (note 34) and 135 f. The bodily dimension of man is here conceived simply as "material part of the material world"; it is named "human" only insofar as this " material part of the material world " participates at the same time in the subjectivity of single human individuals. Therefore, Janssens considers the body, in a consequent way, as a " means to action," as an instrument of man's subjectivity for his being able to act in the sphere of the external world. With this, the properly "human" is restricted to a spiritually understood subjectivity (without taking into account that also the body originally forms part of man's subjectivity). This, however, is not a personalist view of man, but a view which we could call a " personalistic spiritualism." The consequences of this view are, in the case of J anssens, absolutely clear, e.g. when he says that the exterior act (" actus exterior") is an "exterior event" (120) which, in itself, does not possess a moral meaning because it does not yet participate in the subjectivity of man, i.e., before it is assumed by the spiritual " ego " as a "means to action." So, bodily acts are, according to this view, a sort of "raw material," determined in their moral meaning exclusively by the spirit. This is obviously true as far as bodily acts need to THE MORAL VIEWPOINT OF VERITATIS SPLENDOR 15 will, as intelligible human good, is the content of true self-love which, through the golden rule (a rule of reason and as such a rule of the structural principle of justice based on acknowledgment of others as equal to me), leads to the command " Love your neighbor as you love yourself." This kind of self-experience reflects the original ontological or anthropological integration of different natural parts of the human suppositum. On the basis of a metaphysic of the suppositum, such an experience is open for a deeper explanation. So it becomes obvious that each natural inclination by its very nature possesses, in the context of the person as a whole and precisely as an inclination belonging to a human person, a meaningfulness which from the beginning transcends the mere "genus naturae." This transcendence is destroyed or at least obscured by an abstract view which detaches these inclinations from their original context as inclinations of a human person. In a moral objectivation, the "natural meaning" of each natural inclination is precisely a personal meaning which must not be identified with its "genus naturae." The proper work of natural reason-the acts of which are always acts of a person--consists in grasping the transcendence of particular goods, exactly on the basis of the fact that they are integrated into the whole of the human suppositum : as intelligible goods. As such an experienced intelligible whole of goods they form the "Self." In its natural act, which corresponds to a natural inclination to virtue, i.e., to a life guided by reason, reason comprehends these particular goods as human goods and, therefore, as fundamental practical goods of the person. These goods constitute our identity, the consciousness of who we are (I and be "operationally" integrated into the whole of the person. It is not true, however, as an anthropological thesis which reduces " moral meaning" to what proceeds from the spiritual part of the soul or even as a thesis which reduces "human person" to "spirit." Cf. also Martin Rhonheimer, "Contraception, Sexual Behavior, and Natural Law," The Linacre Quarterly 56 :2 (1989) : 2057. Also published in "Humanae Vitae": 20 anni dopa. Atti del II Congresso lnternazionale di Teologia Morale, Roma 9-12 novembre 1988 (Milano: Edizioni Ares, 1989), pp. 73-113. 16 MARTIN RHONHEIMER the others) and fundamentally shape the will in respect of " the good for man." 5. The fallacious distinction between "right making properties" and "good making properties" of an action Moral philosophers who defend-however divergent be their approaches-a consequentialist position (a " teleological ethic ") usually are much concerned with emphasizing a fundamental difference between the " moral rightness" (or the " right-makingproperties ") and the " moral goodness" (the " good-makingproperties ") of an action. 11 The first, they say, concerns the question about the properties which render an action " right " or " wrong " ; the second is related to those properties of an action insofar as it springs from a free will. By way of balancing goods and bads, only the question about the " rightness of types of actions " is meant to be resolved. And this, it is asserted, is the question which properly belongs to so-called "normative ethics." The question, however, about what makes the will of the acting subject a "good" will does not, according to their view, depend on whether an action is " right " or " wrong" but rather, e.g., on whether one acts out of benevolence toward other persons, out of love of justice, with a will to fairness or to respecting the other's conscience, with a "Christian intentionality,'' etc. Of course in a sense this is rather obvious. It is true in the sense that an involuntary, and thus not imputable, error about what one has to do-in this sense a wrong action-may not hinder the will of somebody who acts in this way from being a good will, even as it does the wrong thing, e.g., a will which, in fact, intends justice even if it does not do the just thing. The corresponding action, then, would be at the same time " morally 1 7 The distinction between the "goodness" and the "rightness" of an action was introduced by W. D. Ross, The Right and the Good (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1930). The terms "right-making" and "good-making characteristics" ("wrong-making" and "bad-making characteristics") of an action was first used in 1946 by C. D. Broad, in his famous, above quoted, essay " Some of the Main Problems of Ethics." THE MORAL VIEWPOINT OF VERITATIS SPLENDOR 17 good " and " wrong." The widespread acceptance of this distinction seems to be caused, to a large extent, by the possibility of this state of affairs. It is, however, a case in which the agent in reality does not choose and thus willingly perform the action which he thinks he is choosing and performing. It is, therefore, an exceptional case which, for analytical purposes, must be set aside until after having determined what basically causes the goodness and the rightness of actions; precisely, because of this, it cannot serve as a paradigm. To be able to justify a distinction between " right " and " good " we must start from the normal condition in which actions are chosen and performed, that is, from the condition that the agent chooses and thus willingly performs exactly the action which he believes he is choosing and performing. Now, the predicates "right" and "wrong" are morally qualifying only insofar as we consider them as predicates for human acts. Certainly, a physician may perform an operation " rightly " (correctly, well, efficiently, competently, etc.) ; despite this, his way of acting may be qualified as " wrong " (e.g., if it is-in the first sense-a " well done " abortion). The first type of qualification concerns the technical aspect of the physician's acting, the second concerns the moral rightness of the choice of this action. In both cases we may, instead of " right " or "wrong," also call the action, respectively, " good" or " evil." The designation derives from the perspective in which we consider the action: Either we consider it from the technical perspective (the aspect of surgical techniques) or we consider it from a moral perspective (the aspect of its being the voluntary and deliberate action of a human person; this is the properly moral perspective). The second perspective includes the first (one cannot act in a morally right way without caring about one's technical competence). The distinction, however, between " morally right " and " morally good " seems to be off the point here. The only relevant distinction is the distinction between " non-morally (e.g., technically) right/wrong " and "morally right/wrong"; the second, however, is equal to (morally) "good" and (morally) "evil." 18 MARTIN RHONHEIMER The position I am criticizing overlooks the fundamental difference between praxis and poiesis, taking its orientation from a " poietical " model of action. 18 It is indeed characteristic of technical actions that its (technical) " rightness " is distinguished from the goodness of the will of the person who performs a technical act. Aristotle, however, taught us that the goodness of a praxis (which is eupraxia) and the goodness of a moral agent (and this means his wilful striving: ore.xis) is a specific kind of "rightness " ( orthotes) : the rightness of prohairesis, of the choice of an action. Indeed, we can say that there exist fundamental structures of the " rightness " of desire which reveal themselves precisely through the " le.r naturalis." These structures determine-despite the legitimacy of a limited and well defined balancing of goods-that certain actions are always wrong, precisely because the desire or will involved in these kind of actions cannot be "right." Yet a will which is not "right" is an evil will. In this sense it is " wrong " to choose to kill a human person (that is : to set one's will against another man's life), whatever be the further intention or end for the sake of which this is chosen. To affirm that such a choice is "not right" (or " wrong ") means precisely to affirm that this is a disorientated choice of the will, that this is a type of action which as such (" in itself ") is evil. " As such " or " in itself " here signifies : independently from further intentions or foreseen consequences. 19 Such an action springing from a corresponding choice is evil, because it shapes the will, rendering it an evil will, a will directed against "the good for man" (here from the perspective of jus1 8 See for this also Rudiger Bubner, Handlung, Sprache und Vernu·nft, 2nd ed. (Frankfurt/M: Suhrkamp, 1982), pp. 74-90. 19 Of course it may be considered as " good " (desirable) that P finally dies (and we may even pray for it) ; in this sense we also say: "It was precisely the 'right' thing for him (and probably also for his relatives) that he finally died." With this, however, we do not qualify an action or the choice of an action, but a state of affairs and its desirability. The goodness, rightness or desirability of such a state of affairs, however, cannot serve as a criterion for qualifying a possible action of mercy-killing. Because in such an action a will set against P's life is involved, with the further intention of bringing about a desirable state of affairs. THE MORAL VIEWPOINT OF VERITATIS SPLENDOR 19 tice). This precisely is what we designate " not right " or " wrong " in a moral sense. 20 Hence, the distinction between " right-making-properties" and " good-making-properties " is in principle questionable. We always have to describe actions and behaviors as objects of choices and, therefore, as intentional actions. From such a perspective, however, the goodness of the will is regarded as depending on the goodness of freely chosen, wanted actions which also includes the agent's willingly referring to the specific goal which constitutes the objective intentionality of this action (I will come back to this below). That is why acts of choice are always describable as forms of rightness, that is, of the rightness of desire or of the will. This enables us to indicate specific kinds of actions which are never to be chosen because they are not consistent with a good will, e.g., the choice of killing a person, whatever be the further intention. On the other hand, it is indeed possible to choose what 2 0 This affirmation, as is obvious, presupposes that killing as the execution of capital punishment (pronounced by the competent judicial authority) and taking into account the fact that the punished is really guilty according to the standards of penal law, cannot be described as a choice of the death of a person. Intentionally this action is (as any type of punishment is) "restoration of the order of justice," violated by the criminal and in danger of being disrupted without imposition of punishment. However it is precisely not the choice of the death of a person as resulting from weighing the good of a person's life against other goods which by this person's death would be brought about (whether capital punishment can be considered as an adequate, proportionate, and in this sense just kind of punishment at all is another question which still may be answered negatively; but in an objective-intentional sense it is "punishment" and therefore an act intentionally and objectively belonging to the virtue of justice, and not the choice that a person not be, whether as a means or as an end). Cf. the excellent treatment of this question in John Finnis, Fundamentals of Ethics, 127 ff.; and my own remarks in Natur als Grundlage der Moral, 371-374 and in La prospettiva della morale V, 3, d. Secondly, the above affirmation also implies the concept of non-intentional sideeffects, e.g., in the case of self-defense which (physically) causes the aggressor's death. This means quite precisely that the aggressor's death was not chosen for the sake of defending one's life; cf. ST 11-11, q.64, a.7: "illicitum est quod homo intendat occidere hominem ut seipsum defendat." Here, "intendere" means the elective will referring to the concrete action (" occidere hominem "), while the defense of one's life is the further intention with which the concrete action is chosen. 20 MARTIN RHONHEIMER is morally right with an evil intention; or to choose to do the morally wrong thing with a good will. Moral philosophers and theologians have always known this in the past, and it has traditionally been considered in ethics. 21 Certainly many decisions, probably even the great majority of them, are legitimately worked out on the basis of weighing goods and consequences. This is particularly true for decisions taken in a wider social context (e.g. social, economical, scientific and research policy). But corresponding possibilities of action are, on the grounds of moral reasons, restricted. They are restricted by the condition that they be consistent with the fundamental " rightness of the will " on the level of concrete choices of actions. Here we encounter the kind of responsibilities which we are accustomed to expressing in so-called absolute prohibitions. On this level, the " right " and the " good " (or : the " wrong " and the " evil ") basically are identical. Here, balancing goods and calculating possible consequences is excluded. 22 It is one of the most important assertions of classical virtue ethics that there exist conditions for the fundamental rightness of actions which depend on basic structures of the " rightness of desire" and that it is therefore possible to describe particular types of actions, the choice of which always involves wrong desire. However, an ethic which understands itself-on the level of "normative ethics "-as providing a rational discourse for the purpose of justifying moral norms (or rules) will never be able to acknowledge this. "Norm-ethics" are "objectivistic" in the sense that they may not, on the level of the concrete performance of actions, include in their reflection the acting subject and his willingly " taking a position " with regard to " good " and 2 1 Compare Peter Geach, "Good and Evil," Analysis 17 (1956) : 33-42; republished in Theories of Ethics, ed. Philippa Foot (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1967), 64-73; see especially p. 72. 22 This is why VS 77 rejects in a very specific and restricted way the method of balancing goods and evils : " The weighing of the goods and evils foreseeable as the consequence of an action is not an adequate method for determining whether the choice of that concrete kind of behaviour is 'according to its species,' or ' in itself,' morally good or bad, licit or illicit." THE MORAL VIEWPOINT OF VERITATIS SPLENDOR 21 " evil " in choosing this or that particular action. Similarly they cannot pose the question about the " rightness of desire," or about the "truth of subjectivity," on the level of concrete choices of particular actions (independently from taking into account further intentions regarding the state of affairs or the weighing of consequences which foreseeably will be brought about by these actions or by refraining from them). I concede it to be true, as has been argued, 23 that the traditional doctrine about the " f ontes moralitatis" as such does not resolve problems of normative ethics; it rather presupposes these problems to be already resolved. For with respect to this approach, everything depends each time on what one considers to be the "object" of an action. Consequentialists will assert that to determine the object of a concrete action, one has to take into account its foreseeably resulting consequences for all concerned. In this sense, consequentialism does not deny the doctrine about the "fontes moralitatis," it merely puts forward a specific solution about how to work out what the "object" of a particular action lS. Nevertheless this classical doctrine about " sources of morality" contains an undeniable assertion which, however, is implicitly denied by consequentialism. It is the assertion that, with regard to human action, it is possible each time to distinguish between ( 1) an " object" by which this action (and the agent's will) is already morally specified as " good," " evil," or " indifferent" independently from further intentions and (2) these further intentions. So the classical viewpoint holds that there are actions which are evil despite the best of intentions or despite the foreseen and intended outcomes precisely because the choice of this particular kind of action through which these laudable intentions are meant to be fulfilled must already be considered as morally evil. It will, however, never be possible to render intelligible this moral methodology on the grounds of an ethic which from the 28 Cf. Bruno Schuller, " Die Quellen der Moralitat. Zur systematischen Ortung eines alten Lehrstiickes der Moraltheologie," Theologie und Philosophie 59 (1984) : 535-59. 22 MARTIN RHONHEIMER beginning is concerned with justifying "moral norms." This is so because in such an approach the distinction between "object" and further intentions necessarily drops out of view. The only thing which a norm ethic can produce in the way of an action theory are the particular " occurrences " (" actions "), on the one hand, and the consequences, brought about by them, on the other. If an agent intends the best consequences, then it is these which come to be designated the "object" of his "act." But this does not correspond to our ordinary experience as acting subjects and to the way we arrive at moral decisions; it rather has about it the air of casuistry. From the viewpoint of the acting subject we always encounter at least two intentionalities to be distinguished. If I break the promise of repaying somebody a determinate amount of money, causing by this his economic ruin because I, simultaneously, intend to prevent by this action the ruin of many others, I have chosen to break the promise given to my creditor for the sake of realizing an intention which is very laudable in itself. But here the object of choice ("breaking the promise") is not less intentionally " taking a position " than the further intention (" benefitting others "). The same applies to killing or lying with good further intentions. Moral virtue is not only, as it is sometimes asserted, the will or the free determination to do " the right thing" each time. Were it like this, there would exist only one single moral virtue. Instead moral virtue is the habitual rightness of appetite (of sensual affections, passions, and of the will, the rational appetite) related to the various spheres of human praxis. An act which is according to virtue is an act which is suited to cause this habitual rightness of appetite which produces "the good person." To keep one's promise is indeed such an act according to moral virtue. Certainly, we can describe the action " to promise " from the very beginning in an "eventistic" way, say, as a kind of uttering words (a " speech act ") by which A causes in B the mental state of being certain that A will do x. One may for various reasons consider it very beneficial that in a society there exists a practice of this sort. So one will formulate a rule (or norm) ac- THE MORAL VIEWPOINT OF VERITATIS SPLENDOR 23 cording to which one is bound to abstain from any performance which could deprive others from being certain that, whenever A performs the speech act of "promising x," x will be brought about by A. The norm " never break promises " means precisely " always abstain from weakening the practice of promise-keeping." Even if one holds that the rightness of an action has to be determined exclusively on the basis of its foreseeable consequences, one must equally consider that the weakening of the practice of " promise-keeping " will be one of the consequencesprobably the most weighty one-to be included in the balance. So, on the basis of such a rule-utilitarianism, one should insist that one is always obliged to keep promises. Or more precisely: one will not insist that promises have to be kept but rather that the rule or norm "keep your promises " has to be observed. This is an important difference (which will become clear immediately). The rule does not express the intrinsic morality of a type of action but rather constitutes the reasonableness of a certain behavior on the grounds of the utility of the rule under which this behavior is subsumed and which is to be maintained by this behavior (for the benefit of society, of course). It is obvious that there remains the possibility of conflict with other such rules ("conflicts of obligations ") ; consequently the rule cannot be valid " absolutely." As a result we have to work out which rule has to be followed in such a case: Either on the basis of a "hyperrule," or by arguing in an act-utilitarian way. Utilititarian ethics thus tends to become a complicated attempt to resolve the problems of " normutilitarianism." Actually it becomes much more concerned with resolving the problems of utilitarian ethical theory than with resolving ethical problems. It is quite clear that in all these cases an agent may very well do the " right " thing with an evil will, and sometimes the " wrong" thing with a good will (calculating or subsuming incorrectly or applying the wrong rule, though intending the overall benefit of society or of all concerned). Here, the discourse concerned with grounding norms and resolving cases of conflict of rules and obligations must be sharply distinguished from another discourse, the one concerned with the conditions of good- 24 MARTIN RHONHEIMER ness and wickedness of appetite and will. This distinguishing does not, however, reflect the requirements and the structure of moral action but merely the requirements which arise from the particular characteristics of a " norm-ethic." As said before, with such arguments one does not resolve ethical problems, but at most, if at all, the intrinsic problems of a particular ethical theory. In reality, as acting subjects, we neither observe nor follow norms or rules, nor do we work out our decisions each time exclusively on the basis of foreseeable consequences for all those affected by our actions. Instead, human action realizes itself in the context of definite "moral relationships," the relationships between concrete persons (fellow-men, friends, married persons, parents and children, superiors and subordinates, employer and employee, creditor and debitor, physician and patient, partners in a contract, persons who live in a particular community, etc.). 24 Here, it is always concerned with what we owe to others, with the question of right and of good will toward particular fellowmen, with the question of responsibilities toward concrete persons. Let us consider again the example of promise-keeping. Above we have defined " to promise " (" eventistically ") as an utterance by which A causes in B the mental state of being certain that A will do x. However, the bringing about of B's mental state of being convinced that A will do x is not necessarily a promise; it could also be a menace, an announcement or a reassurance (what is really meant by a speech act like " You can be sure that tomorrow morning I'll come and see you " ?) . The above eventistic description of promising contains everything except the 24 This category of " moral relationship " and its importance for explaining responsibility in moral decision-making was very well emphasized by Robert Spaemann, "Wer hat wofiir Verantwortung? Zurn Streit um deontologische oder teleologische Ethik," Herder Korrespondenz 36 (1982) : 345-50 & 403-8. The subsequent criticisms by A. Elsasser, F. Furger and P. Miiller-Goldkuhle (ibid. 509 ff.; 603 ff.; 606 ff.) unfortunately do not enter into the fundamental question posed by Spaemann; Spaemann himself remarks upon this in his concluding reply (Herder Korrespondenz 37 [1983]: 79-84). THE MORAL VIEWPOINT OF VERITATIS SPLENDOR 25 element which confers on this speech-act the quality of being a promise. This it will be only if A wants to confer on B a right or a claim on A's doing x. So B's certitude that A will do x is grounded in a relation of justice caused precisely by the promissory act. Exactly this relation between A and B (that is : B's having a claim or a right on A's doing-x, and B's owing to A to do x)-a relation brought about by the speech-act "I promise you "-shows that a norm " keep your promises " is nothing else than a more particular or specific version of the principle of justice to render each one what one owes him. The promissory act indeed creates a relationship between persons in which this general rationale of justice now is valid. It may happen that a situation changes in such a way that the doing of x (for whatever reason) subsequently turns out to be an unjust action; or even that doing x was unjust from the very beginning, that is, that A had promised B to do something unjust. Is it possible that B has a claim (a right) on A's committing an unjust act? Certainly not. The promise becomes in reality vain (or reveals itself as vain or immoral from the beginning). So the promise, in reality, is not " broken " ; by not keeping it no injustice is committed; rather the very promissory act was unjust, and it now would be according to justice that A in a way indemnifies B, who has been deceived. In order to be able to judge whether a promise keeps binding the person who made it, the consequences of doing x must be considered (an action without any consequence is not an action at all). But these will always be the consequences in the sphere of the question whether B continues licitly to claim A's keeping the promise, that is: A's doing x. The question can never arise whether such an eristing claim may be overridden in favor of other more important or more numerous goods benefitting Q, R, S, ... , T (even if there may be cases in which the benefits for Q, R, S, ... , T precisely will determine whether B continues to have a claim on A's doing x). In any case, the relation between A and B established by making the promise, and the consequences relating to Q, R, S, ... , T, are two different things; one cannot say that we are, on principle, responsible for all the foreseen consequences of our 26 MARTIN RHONHEIMER actions or omissions. B's being deceived by a promise which may possibly not be kept certainly cannot be regarded as simply one among many consequences of not keeping the promise. So it may be possible that not-keeping a promise is unjust with regard to B even if the state of affairs resulting from not-keeping it were, as such, more desirable than the one brought about by keeping the promise. In this case, not keeping it would be morally wrong because the choice of an unjust action involves the wrongness of the will. Anyhow, this view remains far too abstract. In reality things are resolved in other ways. In reality an agent who intends justice will try, for example, to achieve a delay in repaying the debt. Or he will find (or at least try to find) a way to prevent by other means the ruin of Q, R, S, ... , T. His refusal to commit an injustice against his creditor by breaking the promise will lead him to discover new lines of action, alternatives, and formerly unseen opportunities. To describe this we would need to tell a story. Virtuous actions are, in this sense, rendered intelligible only in a narrative context. 25 But the right thing to do will always be the action which is consistent with the rightness of appetite, with the rightness of our will's relation to concrete persons with whom we live together in defined relationships. Many details should be added, and there is still much to be specified. But the fundamental difference between virtue- and norm-ethics consists in the fact that for the former the morally right is always determined, as well as rightness of appetite, with regard to the " good-for-man " on the level of concrete actions and in relation to particular persons, persons with whom the agent encounters himself living in morally qualified relationships (be they naturally given or be they relationships established by free acts, such as promises, contracts, etc.). That is why a virtue ethic can speak about actions which are " intrinsically," " always and per se," "on account of their very object" evil (cf. VS 80). A norm-ethic of utilitarian character, however, that in the last 25 This is one of the very valuable insights of Alasdair Mcintyre's After Virtue, 2nd ed. (Notre Dame, Indiana: Notre Dame University Press, 1984). THE MORAL VIEWPOINT OF VERITATIS SPLENDOR 27 analysis is an argumentatively proceeding norm-ethic, cannot do justice to such qualified relationships. Consequently, it is compelled to detach the category of the " rightness of actions " from the category of the "goodness of the will." That is why it simply will not understand that the intentional relation of the will to "justice," i.e., the " just will," is at stake in every concrete choice of a particular action. 26 6. The intentional structure of practical objects as " forms conceived by reason" So called " teleological ethics " owes a large amount of its plausibility-as far as Catholic moral theology is concerned-not least to the fact that it was directed against a naturalistic (or " physicalist ") misunderstanding of the " moralitas ab obiecto." 27 Yet, despite this justified aim, adherents to these "teleological" approaches do not seem to have recognized the real source of this misunderstanding, which consists in overlooking the fact that practical reason is embedded in the intentional process of human acting, being a part of it. That is why, I think, these new approaches remained themselves addicted to a surprising, even extreme, naturalism. Particular actions implicitly are considered by them as analogous to " events " and their outcomes as state of affairs. They implicitly presuppose, on the level of particular actions, a causal-eventistic concept of action (action as causing a state of affairs). I said " implicitly," because adherents of " teleological ethics " do not explicitly defend such a corre26 This, it seems to me, explains why virtue ethics do not require a " personalistic complement." Recent personalism often seems to be an attempt to overcome the one-sided views of modern rule-ethics. Ethics based on the concept of moral virtue are intrinsically " personalistic," but are also probably more open to rational discourse than many forms of actual personalism. 27 See, e.g., Franz Scholz, Wege, Umwege und Auswege der M oraltheologie. Ein Pliidoyer fur begrundete Aitsnahmen (Miinchen: Bonifatius, 1976), 16f.; Joseph Fuchs, " 'Intrinsece malum '. 'Oberlegungen zu einem umstrittenen Begriff," in Sittliche N ormen. Zum Problem ihrer allgemeinen und unwandelbaren Geltung, ed. Walter Kerber (Diisseldorf: Patmos, 1982), 76£.; Peter Knauer, S.]., "The Hermeneutic Function of the Principle of Double Effect," in Readings fo Moral Theology No. 1, pp. 1-39. 28 MARTIN RHONHEIMER sponding action theory (they actually deal very little with questions of action theory). 28 That is why they are compelled to reclaim the aspect of intentionality-the aspect of willingly taking a position with regard to " good " and " evil "-on the level of fundamental options and attitudes, on the level of Gesinnung. So, consequentialists fail to see that, independently from further intentions required to optimize consequences or goods on the level of caused states of affairs, an action may already be qualifiable as morally evil. And this means : That a particular type of action, describable in behavioral terms, may be qualified as causing an evil will simply because it is evil to want (and, therefore, to choose) certain actions as practical objects ( = as the " good to be done "). The problem is bypassed, even veiled, by describing chosen actions from the observer's viewpoint, thus leaving out of consideration precisely the act of choice. Probably the most famous example of such an argumentative reductionism is Caiaphas's advice to the Sanhedrin: " It is better for you that a single man dies for the people, than that the whole people perishes." As a judgment about a simple event or a state of affairs and its desirability this obviously is quite true. But it is well known that Jesus did not simply die but was killed. Precisely because objects of our actions are intentional objects, that is, objects of acts of the will, they can only be " shaped " by reason; for the will is the appetite which follows the judgment of reason. As Aquinas emphasizes: "Species moralium actuum constituuntur ex formis, prout sunt a ratione conceptae." 29 This "form conceived by reason" is nothing other than the object of an action in its "genus moris." This again is closely connected with the fact that every human action is an intentional action. And this is why it is something 28 A more recent attempt to do so by referring to Kant is not very satisfying, and it remains unclear to what extent the author may be called a representative of "teleological ethics." Cf. Gerhard Hover, Sittlich handeln im Medium der Zeit. Ansiitze zur handlungstheoretischen Neuorientierung der Moraltheologie (Wiirzburg: Echter Verlag, 1988). However, this book contains some valuable criticisms of positions defended by adherents of " teleological ethics." 20 ST 1-11, q.18, a.10. THE MORAL VIEWPOINT OF VERITATIS SPLENDOR 29 that does not simply " happen," but something willingly pursued and as such farmed or shaped by reason. A concrete practical matter (" materia circa quam ")-the same applies to the "matter" of natural inclinations-is as such, considered in its pure "materiality,'' always less than the content or object of an action with respect to the natural inclination of a human person. If in greeting somebody or giving a starting signal, I raise my arm, then " raising my arm " (the matter of action) is as such something which can neither be chosen or performed. The real content of an act of choice and of the describable behavior is exclusively the intentional, i.e., human, action "greeting somebody" or "giving a starting signal." In this, however, the practical reason which judges the action as a practical good (something good to do here and now) is already involved. To know what a person is doing by raising his arm, one must know why (in the sense of " what for") he raises his arm. The " why" here is the formal aspect, the "f orma ration is " which only renders understandable the event of the raising of an arm as a human action. This " why " (or " what for ") confers on the action its intentional identity which is able to inform and shape the agent's will.so In his " Philosophical Investigations,'' Ludwig Wittgenstein asks "what is left over if I subtract the fact that my arm goes up from the fact that I raise my arm ? " 31 We might answer: What is left over is precisely the purpose or intention to greet so Cf. for this G. E. M. Anscombe, Intention. Professor Anscombe conceives, in the course of her analysis, the question " Why ? " in a larger sense (any sort of motives, or also unvoluntary causes of actions); it includes the "what for ?," without being reduced to it. But insofar as we are concerned with properly human, voluntary actions, the "why ? " precisely is the "what for? ". It properly concerns " intentions." 31 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, No. 621, translated by G. E. M. Anscombe, ed. G. E. M. Anscombe, R. Rhees (Oxford : Basil Blackwell, 1958), 161e. Wittgenstein thinks that nothing is left over ("Are the kinaesthetic sensations my willing ? "). Wittgenstein refuses (see the next number) to differentiate conceptually, besides the physical fact, an act of willing. Anyhow, Wittgenstein here clearly mixes up the observer's viewpoint ("the fact that my arm goes up") and the acting person's perspective ("I raise my arm"). Nobody ever can really observe "I raise my arm"; only 30 MARTIN RHONHEIMER somebody or to give a starting signal. That means that what remains is "to want to raise the arm under the aspect of a specific description " which is a description of the intentionality involved in the performance. To choose an action "under a description" again involves practical reason which judges "greeting somebody " or " giving a starting signal " as something which is "good" to do here and now. One might object: But you could just simply raise your arm. Well, I would answer, just try to do it! It is true that it might just "happen " (involuntarily, as a reflex, while sleeping); but this is not a human act. If, however, somebody wanted " simply " to raise his arm, he again would do more than simply "raise his arm." If we subtracted from his doing this action the fact that his arm goes up, we would have left over, e.g., "Wanting to show the author of this paper that he is wrong." What would be left over is a " why," the intentional content or the "form" of this act of "raising one's arm." Therefore, "to greet somebody by raising one's arm" is properly the object of an action, which in itself possesses already an intentional structure. In precisely this structure, respectively the " whole " (the " matter " of the action its " why" or " what for ") is a "f orma a ratione concepta." Things like " greeting " or affability or gratefulness or justice, that is, corresponding actions to these, do not " exist " in nature. There do not exist corresponding "natural forms." These acts are intentionalities formed by practical reason. That is why the objective content of human actions can be expressed ·each time only in an intentional description of the corresponding action. " What " we do is always a " why " we do something on1 purpose. It is a " material doing " (" materia circa quam ") chosen under a description, while it is the "description " which actually contains the intentional content of the action. That is why it seems to me correct when Elizabeth Anscombe writes : " We must always remember + " the fact that my arm goes up " is observable. " I raise my arm " can properly be described only as a choice by a willing subject. Everybody has personal interior experience of such choices as something different from " kinaesthetic sensations." THE MORAL VIEWPOINT OF VERITATIS SPLENDOR 31 that an object is not what what is aimed at is; the description under which it is aimed at is that under which it is called the object." 32 It is often overlooked (as, for example, by L. J anssens) that an object of the will necessarily is an action-matter "apprehensum et ordinatum a ratione." For this reason, it possesses by itself a moral specificity; it never can be wanted or chosen as a non-moral good or end. 33 Equally one overlooks that the "end" ("finis") is not only an object of further intentions, but also that the particular choice of an action has its proper " end " : the action as an object. That is why, each time Aquinas speaks about "finis," an author like L. Janssens reads "finis operantis," overlooking thereby that the object of the exterior act of the will is in itself an end, but not this further end for the sake of which the action itself is chosen; instead it is the sort of end which Aquinas sometimes (very few times) calls the " finis operis." 34 This "finis operis," however, is the basic intentional content of a concrete action (without which it would not be a human action at all), and therefore something like the "formal object" of an action. 35 Such basic contents are not events like " the raising of an arm,'' but rather " greeting somebody" or " giving a starting signal." They are neither " things " nor " qualified things " as, for example, a res aliena; but actions " under a description " as " misa2 G. E. M. Anscombe, Intention,§ 35, 66. 33 Here we may find probably the most decisive misjudgment of Janssens; for he assumed that the will is able to relate to " ontic" goods as on tic; so he asserts that it is possible to want " per se " an ontic evil on the level of its being only an ontic state of affairs, and that, as such, it can be the object of a choice which, then, would not be subject to moral qualification as a "good" or an " evil " choice. Only if the ontic evil is the end of the further intention with which a choice is performed, if it, therefore, were the proper reason of bringing such an evil about, could a corresponding will be called an evil will. Such an objectifying of ontic goods by the elective will, however, is simply impossible; it contradicts the very nature of the will which is "appetitus in ratione" or "intellectual appetite"; the will receives its object through reason. Janssens' argument is simply naturalistic. 34 Cf. e.g. In IV Sent., d.16, q.3, a.l, qla.2 ad 3. 8 5 About formal and material objects of actions cf. Anthony Kenny, Action, Emotion and Will, 5th ed. (London: Routledge & Kegan, 1976), pp. 187 ff. 32 MARTIN RHONHEIMER apropriate a res aliena," that is " stealing." The arm itself is not able to greet or to give a starting signal; and an action in which a " res aliena" is involved is not necessarily a theft (it may also be the action of seizing something stolen carried out by the police). Equally the so called " finis operis" is an agent's goal; but it is the goal he pursues independently of the further goals he may pursue by choosing this concrete action. It is the goal which specifies the performed action as a determinate type of intentional action, the one which Aquinas usually calls the " finis proximus" of a human act, i.e., its object. The " species " of an action is precisely the species " ab obiecto relato ad principium actuum humanorum, quod est ratio." 36 The "finis operis" is nothing other than the object of choice (the choice of the action), which by itself is an act of the will informed by reason. The so-called " absolute prohibitions," that is, normative propositions which indicate that certain, describable actions may never be licitly chosen and willingly performed, therefore relate to actions described in;tentionally. It is impossible to do this independently from the content of the acts of choice which relate to such actions. So, for example (although this is not the case with such prohibited actions), a " norm " cannot refer simply to "raising one's arm" but to "greeting somebody by raising one's arm" or "giving a starting signal by a movement of one's arm." Only to actions described in such a way can a moral norm reasonably relate. The norm "never kill" receives, in this way, a clear structure. 37 7. Natural law: the fundamental rule for the goodness of will As Aquinas says in one of his most concise phrasings, "natural law is nothing other than the light of the intellect given us a6 ST I-II, q.18, a.6. does the norm of never lying; see my N atur als Grimdlage der Moral, 346 ff.; 367 ff. About both, killing and lying, see also La prospettiva delta morale, chapter V, section 3 d. About contraception, see my paper Contracept,ion, Sc.ma! Behavior, and Natural Law. 3 7 Equally THE MORAL VIEWPOINT OF VERITATIS SPLENDOR 33 by God by which we recognize what is to be done and what is to be avoided, a light and law which God has bestowed to man in creation." 38 Natural law is not simply an object of human reason, but, like all kinds of law, it consists precisely in judgments of practical reason itself, it is a specific set of "propositiones universales rationis practicae ordinatae ad actiones," a set of " universal propositions of practical reason directed to actions." 39 As I have shown elsewhere, there exists a parallelism between the constitution of objects of actions as moral objects on the one hand, and the constitution of the precepts of natural law on the other. 40 Both objects of human actions and precepts of natural law refer to an " appetibile apprehensum et ordinatum per rationem." Both the praeceptum of the natural law and the object of a concrete action (which is the object of choice, in itself " prescriptive ") are " aliquid a ratione constitutum" 41 and spring from an " ordinatio rationis." 42 By natural law, this objectivethat is, rationally ordered-meaning of natural inclinations is expressed in universali. And, therefore, natural law is properly the law by which particular judgments of practical reason are rectified.43 So in two senses natural law is a " law of reason " : it is a law constituted by reason (on the universal level), and a law referred to and regulating reason (on the level of particular judgments). as Thomas Aquinas, In Duo Praecepta Caritatis et in Decem Praecepta, Prologus: " lex naturae . . . nihil aliud est nisi lumen intellectus insitum no bis a Deo, per quod cognoscimus quid agendum et quid vitandum. Hoc lumen et hanc legem dedit Deus homini in creatione." And further on: ". . . lumen scilicet intellectus, per quad nota sunt nobis agenda." aa ST I-II, q.90, a.l ad 2. 4o See Naturals Grimdlage der Moral, mainly part II. "1 ST I-II, q.94, a.l. 42 ST I-II, q.90, a.4. 4 3 " Lex naturalis est secundum quam ratio recta est" (In II Sent., d.42, q.2, a.5). This would be the appropriate place to speak about the constitution of "prudentia" (practical wisdom or "prudence") by the " fines virtutum," and about the twofold (intentional and elective) aspect of moral virtue; finally one must say something about the relation between " synderesis " and prudence. See for this ST II-II, q.47, a.6. 34 MARTIN RHONHEIMER In this way the precepts of the natural law are recognizable as properly practical principles of the practical intellect determining concrete actions. This intellect possesses its perfection in prudence (practical wisdom). The questions dealt with here were not questions of " normative ethics " ; I did not claim to ground specific moral norms. It concerned a question which first had to be clarified before one could even speak about the grounding of moral norms and normative ethics. I wanted to clarify how, from a properly moral perspective, we have to speak about moral norms and " normative ethics " and what " moral norms " even refer to. Briefly we now can say: " Moral norms " are, in ethics and in the moral life, a quite specific way of speaking about intentional human actions and their practical principles. More precisely, norms are normative propositions (propositions in the mode of " ought," " may," " must not," etc.) about intentional actions based on practical principles. 44 Theories like " teleological ethics " ( consequentialism and proportionalism) sometimes present themselves as natural-law theories. They on principle rightly do so, because every natural law theory consists of a theory about practical reason and the structure of moral judgment performed by human reason. And teleological ethical theories, defending the cognitive " moral autonomy " of man, in fact are theories about what is meant by "to act according to reason ". 45 However, we may now be able to give a critical evaluation of these theories. First, they do not properly have a conception about principles of practical reason. This can also be regarded as a consequence of their lack of action-analysis. " Teleological ethics " essentially and exclusively is a decision-making theory: it tries to explain how we work out 44 About the relation of so-called " moral absolutes " to intentional actions, see also the excellent Marquette Lecture by William E. May, Moral Absolutes. Catholic Tradition, Current Trends, and the Truth, The Pere Marquette Lecture in Theology 1989 (Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1989), especially pp. 40 ff. 4 s See Bruno Schuller, "Eine autonome Moral, was ist das ?,'' Theologische Revue 78 (1982), 103-106. See for this my above quoted article "Zur Begriindung sittlicher Normen aus der Natur," especially pp. 67 ff. THE MORAL VIEWPOINT OF VERITATIS SPLENDOR 35 decisions about what to do here and now. If adherents of this theory speak of principles, they do so only to establish some more general rules for the orientation of decision making. These rules or principles, however, do not have, according to this theory, a proper origin, that is, an origin different from the very logic of a particular decision making process. So consequentialism and proportionalism do not really provide a natural-law theory. They provide a theory about reasonable action which basically fails to acknowledge what is most essential for natural law: The existence of real practical principles which are not derived from determinate forms of decision-making procedures, but are the real moral measure for the decision-making process. Secondly, by measuring the moral " rightness " of single types of action exclusively on the basis of their foreseeable consequences related to non-moral goods and bads, this theory presupposes a concept of action which simply leaves out of consideration a basic aspect of human actions: The fact that the acting subject, that is, its will, takes a position with regard to good and evil already by choosing concrete actions which bring about such consequences. This taking a position relates to the agent's own person and to other persons (including God). So it seems that the theory does not acknowledge what actually follows from a more adequate analysis of human action : That in the will of the agent the properly moral qualities of " good " and "evil " may also appear independen:tly from the whole of foreseeable consequences. Adherents of so-called " teleological ethics " consequently omit in principle an intentional description of those particular types of action which afterwards they qualify, on the basis of their decision-making procedure, as "right" or "wrong." To defend their theory, they are compelled to describe these actions as mere " events." Then at the same time they indicate the difficulties and aporias which logically derive from such a non-intentional concept of action, difficulties and aporias regarding the concept and the respective determination of the "object" of an action, so that, finally, they are able to offer their theory as the only reasonable solution for these problems, problems, however, created by their 36 MARTIN RHONHEIMER very approach rather than by the subject matter of ethics itself. 46 The solution offered by adherents to " teleological ethics " maintains that "action-events" brought about by acting subjects may be qualified as " right " or " wrong" according to whether they bring about the best overall consequences for all the concerned, an optimum of goods or a minimum of bads. I have argued, however, that even if the non-moral consequences of an action are optimal and mostly desirable, the action by which they have been brought about may nevertheless be an evil action. I would insist that everybody knows that this is possible. Whoever brings about " the best of all worlds" (the world with an optimum of non-moral goods or a minimum of non-moral bads) can, at the same time, be a murderer or a villain, and this not simply because he acted, say, to assure his own glory and, therefore, with a fundamentally evil intentionality, but precisely because we would judge as wicked the actions he performed. This obviously shows already that such a world would not be the best of all. The problem with consequentialist ·ethics is not that it does not share this conviction or that its adherents are inclined to plead for amorality, but that consequentialism is not able to explain what all of us know. The "secret" of consequentialism does not consist in denying this truth, just as it does not deny the truth of the proposition that a good intention cannot "sanctify " evil means. Instead the " secret " of these methodologies consists in making the acting subject disappear which, in its concrete choices of particular actions, takes a position with his will with regard to "good" and "evil." As a result, the verdict about the good intentions which cannot " sanctify " evil means is simply rendered irrelevant and pointless. For if the "means" (that is : the concrete actions we choose and willingly perform) 46 This approach, however, is not so different from traditional approaches that can be found in some classical manuals of moral theology. Some of them used to look at actions as physical processes or events, relating them afterwards to the " norma moralitatis," an extrinsic rule determining whether it is licit or illicit to perform such and such an " action." What most classical manuals failed to do was precisely to render intelligible what a human action is and that its moral identity is included in it because it is included in the intentional structure of an action. THE MORAL VIEWPOINT OF VERITATIS SPLENDOR 37 only can be " right" or " wrong," and this depending on their foreseeably resulting consequences in the field of non-moral goods and bads, then by definition there cannot exist such a thing as an "evil means." Instead there can be, at most, "wrong means," that is, means chosen on the basis of an error about which means would be the right one in order to achieve a determinate goal. To justify the concept of " intrinsically evil action," an intentional concept of action is required, and a corresponding concept of the intentional basic contents of concrete types of actions. This " intentional basic content " of an action is what we usually call its "moral object." 47 We all understand a " good person " to be a person whose will is a good one, even if, to be good, such a will must often pay a high price: The price of accepting mostly undesirable consequences of its being a good will. But it is better to suffer injustice than to commit it. 48 This proposition precisely means quite specifically that it is morally better to abstain from an action the performance of which would be unjust, even if, as a consequence of refraining from it, a much greater injustice committed by others would foreseeably result, an injustice that, however, I will suffer. If we set aside the acting subject, the injustice committed by me and the injustice suffered by me (and committed by another person) appear just as two different states of affairs. The point (long ago expressed by Democritus) is that one cannot and may not compare these two consequences, nor may one weigh the action to be avoided against the undesirable consequences of refraining from this action. And this simply for the reason that the action as such, considered in itself, is an unjust action. This is precisely what a consequentialist (" teleological ") ethic is unable to justify. It can be seen that the natural law manifests itself as the totality of principles of practical reasonableness which not only moves us to act and to do the truly good but also compels us to refrain 47 For a full account of the concept of " intentional basic content " and " intentional basic action" see my La prospettiva delta morale. • 8 For the following I am indebted to A. W. Mi.iller, "Radical Subjectivity: Morality versus Utilitarianism," Ratio 19 (1977) : 115-32. 38 MARTIN RHONHEIMER from committing injustice. Natural law is the proper "law" of a good will. It orients human persons, as striving subjects, to the "good-for-man," on the level of himself and of his fellow-men. It equally makes him refrain from evil, from " poisoning his soul." A life that maintains this orientation to the "food-forman " in each and every single act of choice may rightly be called a "successful" life. A person who lives such a life therefore deserves praise and we consider him or her as a person who is on the way to sharing in true happiness, of participating in what the Greek Philosophers called eudaimonia. It will always remain difficult to disprove convincingly so called " teleological " ethical theories ( consequentialism, proportionalism) as long as one tries to do so in the logic proper to norm or rule ethics. The Church's teaching about "law"-" eternal," " natural," or " positive," " divine " or " human," " old" and "new "-was, in the past centuries, profoundly and not very happily influenced by the logic of norm and rule ethics. For different reasons, moral theologians emphasized the " observers' viewpoint." Unlike the classical and medieval tradition of moral theory, the modern tradition was not interested in exposing a comprehensive conception of the good life as part of the intellectual enterprise involved in coming to an understanding of man and of the sense of his existence. From the 16th century onward, moral theology, intensively permeated with casuistry, was rather concerned with judgments about whether particular acts were compatible, or not, with a conception of the good life already established by revealed positive law and the corresponding moral norms. This concern, however, falls short of the genuine way we arrive at a proper understanding of the real requisites of morality. For this, also in a Christian context, a virtue-centered moral theory is needed, be it on the level of philosophical ethics or on that of moral theology. 49 So called " teleological ethics " have not yet 49 See an example of the latter in Romanus Cessario, 0.P., The Moral Virtues and Theological Ethics (Notre Dame/London: University of Notre Dame Press, 1991). THE MORAL VIEWPOINT OF VERITATIS SPLENDOR 39 escaped from the logic of a legalistic approach ; they only now try to "save" freedom from a supposed menace by law. By asserting in number 78 that "to be able to grasp the object of an act which specifies that act morally, it is therefore necessary to place oneself in the perspective of the acting person," the encyclical Veritatis Splendor opens a new way directed to rediscovering the perspective proper to virtue ethics, which is the genuine perspective of morals. DID AQUINAS CHANGE HIS MIND ABOUT THE WILL? DANIEL WESTBERG University of Virginia Charlottesville, Virginia 0 NE OF THE MOST fundamental and challenging problems in the interpretation of St. Thomas is the proper relationship of intellect and will, on which so much of moral theology (and thus of the Summa Theologiae) hinges. As Alasdair Macintyre indicates in both After Virtue and Whose Justice? Which Rationality? the problem involves our understanding of how to appreciate the genius of Aquinas in the monumental task of harmonizing Aristotelian practical reason and the biblical and Augustinian categories of will, sin and the law of God. When this framework is brought to the reading of St. Thomas, it is very difficult to understand certain texts which can seem to be obscure or inconsistent. In some cases he seems to be following Aristotle's explanations of practical reason and choice, and elsewhere he emphasizes the freedom of the will. One method of dealing with this is to argue for a change in Thomas's thinking: that he shifted from an early emphasis on the intellect (his Aristotelian phase) to an appreciation for the dynamic freedom of the will (which he inherited and developed from the Augustinian tradition). This has the virtue of seeming to deal neatly with inconvenient texts by consigning them to a position which he abandoned; but as we shall see the treatments by Aquinas do not fit the chronology required by this schema of development. There is very little evidence, actually, to recommend this thesis though it has been advocated by prominent scholars- 41 42 DANIEL WESTBERG and there are strong reasons why we should reject this theory of change. That this explanation has nevertheless been widely held says more about the tradition of voluntarism in our thinking (and our tendency to see Aquinas in that light) than about the merits of the case brought forward to argue for Thomas's shift from reason to will. Proponents of the Theory of Change Dom Odon Lattin questioned the dating of De Malo 6 to 126368 by Mandonnet (and ca. 1268 by Grabmann) on the basis that the work shows advances in the treatment of liberum arbitrium. He argued that whereas Thomas had placed the primary motive factor on reason in his earlier works 1 the emphasis was shifted to the will in De Malo 6 and ST I-II, q.9, a. 4. Therefore we could conclude that De Malo is posterior to ST I and anterior to ST I-II.2 Lottin was right about the dating, but not about the reasons given for it. He alleged that the structure of the argument in De Malo 6 is entirely different from previous treatments because the distinction between voluntas and liberum arbitrium has disappeared and been replaced by " liberty of specification " and "liberty of exercise." Lattin admitted, however, that the former belongs to reason and the latter to will implying (without realizing it, perhaps) that we might well interpret this as a change of terminology rather than a change of doctrine. Lottin softened his claims the following year in an article where he wrote: " ll ne faudrait pas urger la difference ... qui eziste entre cet expose du De Malo et celui du De Veritate," admitting that the distinction between specification and exercise is also to be found in De Veritate. Therefore we should not speak "d' opposition ni meme de diversite de doctrine." 3 E.g. De Veritate 22.12; Summa contra Gentiles III, 89; ST I, q.82, a.4. La date de la Question Disputee De Malo de Saint Thomas d'Aquin," Revue d'histoire ecclesiastique 24 (1928) : 373-388. 3 0. Lottin, "Le libre arbitre chez saint Thomas d'Aquin," Revue thomiste 12 (1929): 424, n. 1; reprinted in vol. 1 of Psychologie et morale a=- Xlle et Xllle siecles (Gembloux, 1948). 1 2 " DID AQUINAS CHANGE HIS MIND 43 There is still a difference, however, in emphasis, Lottin argued, for two reasons: ( 1) In the De Malo a text from the Eudemian Ethics of Aristotle is quoted to indicate that God is the first mover of the will; this apparently undercuts the priority of the intellect over the will; Lottin noted that this text is cited also in ST I, so that the "change" in Thomas must now be shown to have occurred before this work; and ( 2) the connection of the argument of De Malo 6 with the controversies and condemnations of 1270. Thomas Deman, however, had previously pointed to the influence of the Eudemian Ethics on Thomas's thinking in the Summa Contra Gentiles.4 This meant that whatever "shift" Lottin saw in Thomas's thinking should have taken place earlier in his career. A few years later, in an article on human freedom, Lottin argued again for a definite change in doctrine. 5 He was not concerned about the question of dating any longer because Glorieux had clarified the chronology of Aquinas's disputed questions and placed De Malo 6 to 1270. 6 He wanted, rather, to argue that the shift in teaching about intellect and will occurred not between ST I and De Malo but between De Veritate and ST. In Thomas's early works, Lottin argued, the will always follows reason; and especially in the De Veritate there is "un apparent determinisme psychologique." 7 This determinism disappears when we come to ST I because there the will, although subject to the influence of the object presented by reason, moves itself to action as an efficient cause. 8 Lattin pointed to the distinction between efficient and final causality with respect to the intellect in action. In De Veritate, Thomas had attributed formal and final causality to the intellect : 4 T. Deman, "Le 'Liber de bona fortuna' dans la theologie de s. Thomas d'Aquin," Revue des sciences philosophiques et theologiques 17 (1928) : 42. 5 0. Lottin, " Liberte humaine et motion divine de s. Thomas d' Aquin a la condamnation de 1277," Recherches de theologie ancienne et medievale 7 (1935) : 52-69, 156-173. 6 P. Glorieux, " Les Questions Disputees de Saint Thomas et leur suite chronologique," Recherches de theologie ancienne et medievale 4 (1932): 1-33. 7 Lottin, " Liberte humaine," p. 56. 8 Ibid., p. 55, referring to ST I, q.82, a.4. 44 DANIEL WESTBERG ratio illa ostendit quad intellectus movet per modum finis: hoc enim modo se habet bonum apprehen:sum ad voluntatem. 9 In De Mala 6, however, final as well as efficient cause now become " l' apanage exclusif de la volonte elle-meme" and thus removes from the reason " toute idee d'infiuence determinante." 10 Lottin sought to strengthen his case by unfairly stressing the aspect of intellectual determinism in De Veritate and by presenting a quite inaccurate emphasis on will in De Malo. Bernard Lonergan made use of Lottin's analysis in his articles concerning grace in St. Thomas. However, he completely polarized the difference supposedly to be found in Thomas. Lonergan alleged that in the De Veritate, De Potentia, and ST I, Aquinas had equated freedom with non-coercion, but later saw his mistake and retracted. As Lonergan put it: This lapse in the teeth of contrary theory was repudiated with extreme vehemence in the later De Malo as heretical, destructive of all merit and demerit, subversive of all morality, alien to all scientific and philosophic thought, and the product of either wantonness or incompetence.11 The strong opinion is indeed to be found in the words of Aquinas (near the beginning of his response), but we shall see below that the subject for attack was rather different from what Lonergan thought. The earlier writings on will by St. Thomas, said Lonergan, must be regarded by historians " as a momentary aberration." Along with the false view of freedom Thomas also " overcame the Aristotelian doctrine of passive potency " : in the De Mala and ST I-II, with passivity "transcended," Lonergan thought he saw that " the freedom of man yields place to the freedom of the will." 12 This is a misguided reading of Thomas by Lonergan. And how are we to regard his presentation to us of a truncation of 9 De Ver. 22.12, ad 3, cited by Lottin, "Liberte humaine," pp. 54-55, n. 11. lo Ibid., p. 163. 11 " St. Thomas's Thought on Gratia Operans," Theological Studies 3 (1942) : 534. 12 Ibid., p. 536. DID AQUINAS CHANGE HIS MIND 45 freedom-the reduction of the " freedom of man " to the " freedom of the will "-as a more attractive or positive move? This makes sense only if one takes the view of Duns Scotus that, since the intellect being a natural faculty is determined, only the will has free agency. This would support Vernon Bourke's contention that most Catholic understanding of Aquinas on the will has been Scotistic. 18 Such is the weight of authority, however, that several years later G. P. Klubertanz could say that Lottin and Lonergan "have proved that St. Thomas's theory of the will underwent a notable development from the Commentary on the Sentences to the Prima Secundae." 14 Lonergan's interpretation did not go uncriticized. Marianne Childress noted that Lonergan had treated final cause as the same as efficient cause-probably through a misreading of Lottinthus making it appear as though Thomas had made a shift from the intellect as final and efficient cause to the will as final and efficient cause. 15 A proper reading of De Veritate, Childress pointed out, does not sustain this interpretation. 16 In other words, since Thomas never assigned efficient causation to the intellect the change was not nearly as sharp as Lonergan alleged. R. Z. Lauer, though somewhat deferential to Lottin, questioned his thesis that Bishop Tempier's actions caused Thomas to change his view of will from passive to active. In Thomas's works "the thought that is expressed seems to be consistent throughout his writings"; and Lauer's summary is faithful to Thomas: "the intellect moves the will inasmuch as the intellect apprehends the object of election, apprehends it as having a ratio of good, which is the final cause of the will." 17 13 V. Bourke, Will in Western Thought (New York, 1964), p. 88. P. Klubertanz, "The Unity of Human Activity," The Modern Schoolman 27 (1949-1950) : 94. 15 M. Childress, "Efficient Causality in Human Actions," Modern Schoolman 28 (1951) : 191-222. 16 Ibid., p. 201, n. 39. Lottin himself was aware of this: cf. " Liberte humaine," p. 54. 17 R. Z. Lauer, "St. Thomas's Theory of Intellectual Causality in Election," New Scholasticism 28 (1954): 318. 14 G. 46 DANIEL WESTBERG Lottin wrote a brief reply, saying that there are two problems involved in the question of final causality: ( 1) the relation of reason and will; and (2) the influence of the object on the act of the will.18 Lauer confused these, Lottin said, not realizing that in the commentary on the Sentences and in ST I only the first problem is treated while the De Malo answers the second by showing that reason is not the final cause. Like a dog which will not surrender its bone, Lottin took his position even further in order to explain Thomas's doctrine of human freedom. To strengthen his case for change from De Veritate to De Malo, Lottin exaggerated (in the manner of Lonergan) the intellectual determinism of the earlier work : " le vouloir suit necessairement le jugement "; " le desaccord est impossible entre le choix et le jugement pratique qui l' a determine." 19 Other scholars expressed their disagreement with Lottin and Lonergan. Lebacqz distanced himself from Lottin's thesis, saying that it was based on "une meconnaissance fonciere." 20 The " determinism " supposedly characteristic of the earlier works is present in all his writings, and Lebacqz pointed to the fact that Thomas uses the supposedly deterministic teaching of the operative syllogism in ST I-II, q.13, a. 1.,21 showing that Thomas did not change his position between the prima pars and the prima secundae. It is significant that Klubertanz in 1961 revised his earlier position of agreement with Lottin and Lonergan on the matter of evolution in Thomas's thought and asserted that the " changes " were more apparent than real. If the teaching in the later works was expressed in the categories of the early works " the really significant differences could well disappear from view." 22 1 s 0. Lottin, Bulletin de theologie ancienne et medievale 7 (1954-7) : 579580. 19 0. Lottin, "La preuve de la liberte chez S. Thomas d'Aquin," Recherches de theologie ancienne et medievale 23 (1956) : 326. 20 J. Lebacqz, Libre arbitre et jugement (Paris, 1960), p. 35. 2 1 Ibid., p. 36. 22 G. P. Klubertanz, "The Root of Freedom in St. Thomas's Later Works," Gregorianum 42 (1961): 707. DID AQUINAS CHANGE HIS MIND 47 These notes of caution have been outweighed, however, by further repetitions of the thesis of change. In 1971 Bernard Lonergan's earlier studies on grace were re-edited and published as Grace and Freedom: Operative Grace in the Thought of St. Thomas Aquinas and expounded Lottin's theory of a marked change between De Veritate and De Malo. The wide circulation of this book has undoubtedly given fresh currency, in an exaggerated form, to the erroneous view of a massive shift from intellect to will in Thomas's thought without any qualification. The same year marked the publication of Riesenhuber's attempt to provide a metaphysical grounding for the superiority of the will, which was followed up by articles in which he argued for a shift in Thomas's later works to a doctrine of the autonomy of the will. 23 If the proper way to understand individual passages and the process of development in the Summa Theologiae has not been very clear to critics, there seems to be much less doubt about the De Malo. As we saw above, the teaching on the will in this question has always been the cornerstone of the thesis of change for Lottin and Lonergan and the point of comparison with the emphasis on the intellect in the commentary on the Sentences and the De Veritate. When we read De Malo, said Lottin, "nous sommes loin du determinisme qui, dans le De Veritate, reliait le vouloir au jugement pratique prealable." 24 Because emphasis in De Malo 6 on the will has been more congenial, and because it is among Thomas's later writings, scholars have urged us to consider it, whatever Aquinas may have said elsewhere, the final word on the subject of free choice. Some more recent criticism of Aquinas has tended to give up entirely on the Summa Theologiae and make the De Malo the 2 3 K. Riesenhuber, Die Transzendenz der Freiheit zum Guten: Der Wille in der Anthropologie und Metaphysik des Thomas van Aquin (Munich, 1971); " The Bases and Meaning of Freedom in Thomas Aquinas,'' Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 48 (1974): 99-111 and "Der Wandel des Freiheitsverstandnisses von Thomas von Aquin zur friihen Neuzeit," Rivista di Filosofia Neo-scolastica 66 (1974): 946-74. 24 Ibid., p. 328. 48 DANIEL WESTBERG only genuine presentation of Thomas's new understanding of the nature of the will's freedom. This is based on seeing the survival of some of the intellectualist elements in the discussions of human action in ST I-II, qq. 1-21 and on finding a new basis of discussion in De Malo 6. 25 Problems with the Theory The major difficulty in the theory of change is to indicate where the major shift in Thomas's thinking occurred. We have seen that various places have been proposed: after the prima pars of the ST, then before the Summa contra Gentiles, and then after the opening section of the secunda pars of the ST. The problem for advocates of the theory of a shift has always been that in all these works there are citations which seem to indicate that Thomas had not overcome his " intellectualist " view. Even after ST I-II, qq. 1-21 we may point to these elements: in ST I-II, q. 76, for example, in the section on sin, the relation of sin to ignorance is given an intellectualist base, using the practical syllogism as the basis for decision, and not giving the will the weight that one would expect if he had made the " shift " by this point. When we come to ST III, q. 18, a. 4, in the question whether there was liberum arbitrium in Christ, the discussion picks up the framework used in ST I, q. 83 without any indication that Thomas had a new way of looking at the will's role in decision. There is, further, quite a problem in dating implied by this revisionist program, especially by the enthusiasts for De Malo 6. There is little disagreement with Glorieux's or Lottin's date of 25 0. M. Pesch, in "Philosophie und Theologie der Freiheit bei Thomas von Aquin in quaest. disp. VI De Malo: ein Diskussionsbeitung," Miinchener Theologische Zeitung 13 (1962) : 1-25, sees the intellectualist links between the IaIIae and the pars Ia. More extreme is H.-M. Manteau-Bonamy, "La liberte de l'homme selon Thomas d' Aquin : la datation de la question disputee De Malo," Archives d'histoire doctrinale et litteraire du moyen age 46 (1979), who finds in ST I-II the same doctrine as in De Veritate, but in De Malo "la volonte de !'homme est une puissance radicalement active" (p. 22). The dating problems which this view involves will be considered below. DID AQUINAS CHANGE HIS MIND 49 late 1270, in Paris, for this disputed question; but this of course causes trouble for our treatment of the secunda pars of the Summa Theologiae which was being composed also during this period. If Thomas had had the breakthrough in his view of the freedom of the will which is alleged, then this should have shown up in the remainder of his work; but the evidence for the unity of treatment in the ST is far stronger than the evidence for a change in doctrine, as Pesch and Manteau-Bonamy admit. One way to deal with this is to say that Thomas simply carried on in the Summa with the old intellectualist way of looking at things, and did not bother to integrate his new insights on the will's freedom. At least one scholar is prepared to draw this conclusion and argues that for various reasons Aquinas decided not to modify ST I-II, qq. 9-10 along the lines of his thinking represented in De Malo 6. 26 No Thomist could be happy with the idea that the answer to a question as important as the role of the will in human action is answered adequately only in a short disputed question (and a single article at that). This would imply that whole tracts of the Summa Theologiae must be ignored (remember that Lonergan included ST I as part of Thomas' s " aberration ") or at best read with cautious qualification. There can be very little satisfaction to know that St. Thomas finally got the problem of free will right in the De Malo if this means that the centerpiece of the Summa, the treatment of human action, morality and virtue, is basically fl.awed. The value of Thomas as a theologian is immensely diminished if this theory is correct because it means not only that his Summa is immature in some important ways, but that by the end of 1270 he had the insights to improve his moral theology but failed to integrate these new principles into his work. There is a lesson to be drawn from J. B. Korolec's summary article on free choice in the Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy. Following Korolec the reader would think that 26 The only suggestion given by Manteau-Bonamy, in "La liberte de l'homme," p. 33, is " que la Somme s'adressait a des novices qu'il fallait introduire progressivement a la verite pleniere." 50 DANIEL WESTBERG Thomas emphasized the will in the commentary on the Sentences, that liberum arbitrium can be identified with the will which is the source of freedom in the De V eritate, and that it is in the ST that Aquinas stresses that the intellect and not the will " has the major role in the moral activity of human beings"; further, Korolec sees in the ST that final causality is attributed to the intellect. 27 The fact that Korolec could offer the opposite thesis to Lottin and Lonergan (without apparently realizing its implications) is not to be scorned so much as regarded as evidence for the dynamic interdependence of reason and will for which we would argue. The thesis of a major shift in Thomas's thought can be strongly challenged by considering texts from the De V eritate which emphasize the will, and from De Malo 6 which describe the role of the intellect. vVe saw above that in order to make his case Lottin ascribed to the De Veritate an intellectual determinism against which the De Malo 6 can appear voluntarist. Thomas, however, nowhere states that the will must accept the judgment of reason. In fact, even in De Veritate, he emphasizes their mutual interdependence : " the act of choice proceeds from each potency in relation to the other." 28 Completely counter to Lottin's interpretation of intellectual determinism, Thomas says that the "will moves the reason by ordering its action." 29 There is also full emphasis put on the will as early as the commentary on the Sentences: "Choosing is principally an act of the will." 30 Similarly in De i11alo 6 Thomas speaks of the way in which the intellect understands the interior act of the will in that through the act of the intellect the will is somehow moved. 31 27 J. B. Korolec, "Free Will and Free Choice," The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy, ed. A. Kenny, N. Kretzmann, and J. Pinborg (Cambridge, 1982), p. 635. 28 De Veritate 24.4. " Sic enim actus electionis progreditur, ab una scilicet earum per ordinem ad aliam." 29 "Voluntas movet rationem imperando actum eius" (De Ver. 24.6, ad 5). 30 "Eligere erit principaliter actus voluntatis" (II Sent d. 24, q. 1, a. 3). 31 De lvfalo 6, ad 18: "similiter etiam et interiorem actum voluntatis intelligit, in quantum per actum intellectus quodammodo movetur voluntas." DID AQUINAS CHANGE HIS MIND 51 Since there is evidence in all stages of Thomas's thought of a strong emphasis on both reason and will, the most reasonable and faithful explanation is not that of development or change from one to the other, but that of a constant doctrine of the intimate combination of the two forces. The Authentic Teaching of Aquinas The most essential point to grasp is that reason and will do not work in sequence but in harmony, at the same time. The intellectualist account pictures the will having to follow what the intellect concludes; the voluntarist account says that the will is free to decide on an action no matter what the intellect comes up with. Thomas's teaching is neither of these, but that both operate together: that when a decision is made it expresses the agent's understanding as well as his desires. This is definitely not the standard, "received" view of traditional scholastic commentators, but it has been noticed by several scholars including G. Verbeke who realized the importance of both cognition and volition in dynamic relationship. Verbeke correctly maintained that the emphasis on both reason and will is present in Thomas's doctrine throughout his writings. 32 This emphasis is characteristic not merely of Thomas's early stage, but also of ST I-II and De Malo. In the very first question which opens the discussion of human action Thomas writes that "humans have dominion over their actions through both their reason and will, which is why liberum arbitrium is called a fac32 " Les deux facultes superieures de l'homme se penetrent reciproquement," in G. Verbeke, "Le developpement de la vie volitive d'apres s. Thomas," Revue philosophique de Louvain 56 (1958) : 17. Servais Pinckaers made the relation of reason and will a major theme in a series of polemical articles in Nova et Vet era studying the decline of medieval moral theology, reprinted as Les sources de la morale chretienne: sa methode, son contenu, son histoire (Fribourg and Paris, 1985). Mention should be made of two earlier perceptive works: Joseph Glanz, Die Einheit des menschlichen Handelns bei Thomas von Aquin (Inaugural-dissertation at F. Wilhelms Univ., Bonn, 1932) ; and U. Serafini, "La liberta umana secondo Aristotele e le interpretazioni averroistica et tomista," Giornale critico della filosofia italiana 34 (1955): 167-185. 52 DANIEL WESTBERG ulty of the will and of reason." 33 Confusion is embedded in us right from the start when we translate liberum arbitrium as "free will." s4 There are different approaches and emphases in the various treatments by Thomas, and it is indeed possible to point to changes and improvements. One would expect to find, after all, a different emphasis on the will in a work devoted to the subject of truth from one dealing with the nature and causes of evil. With this said, the unity of conception and treatment of the question of the function of the will throughout the works is also remarkable. In the De Malo Thomas tells us that if we consider the activation of the potencies of the soul from the aspect of the specifying object, then the first principle of motion is from the intellect; for in this way the "understood good" moves even the will itself; if however we consider the movements of the soul's potencies from the aspect of the exercise of the act, then the principle of motion is from the will. 35 This teaching of Thomas is not very different from the position established in De Veritate where he taught that man does necessarily desire the good in general, 36 but that there is no necessity with respect to this or that particular good. 37 This is the same teaching as that found in the various treatments. What is stressed in De Malo 6 is that only the absolute good, beatitude, is desired by necessity, and thus every good actually apprehended by the intellect in this life is deficient in some respect and thus free from necessity. 33 ST I-II, q.1, a.1. "Est autem homo dominus suorum actuum per rationem et voluntatem, uncle et liberum arbitrium esse dicitur ' facultas voluntatis et rationis '." 34 As Timothy Suttor does at ST I, q. 84 in his volume (no. xi) of the new Blackfriars edition (London and New York, 1970). 35 De !Ylalo 6. " Si ergo consideremus motum potentiarium animae ex parte objecti specificantis actum, primum principium motionis est ex intellectu: hoc enim modo bonum intellectum movet etiam ipsam voluntatem. Si autem consideremus motus potentiarum animae ex parte exercitii actus, sic principium motionis est ex voluntate." 36 De V eritate 22.5, ad 12, "et sic eti::m voluntas de necessitate vult bonum." 37 De V eritate 22.6, ad 5 " sed non determinate hoc bonum vel illnd." DID AQUINAS CHANGE HIS MIND 53 Lottin's account of the liberty accorded to the will in De Malo is very different from Thomas's explanation. Lottin misunderstood completely Thomas's explanation of bonum quad non inveniatur esse bonum secundum omnia particularis. Instead of seeing the profound proof for the non-necessity of any bonum intellectum (other than beatitudo) Lottin says " Mais si ce bien presente quelque deficience, la volonte peut choisir un autre." 38 Instead of seeing the indeterminacy inherent in every decision to act, Lottin still continued to see reason and will in opposition, with will making the final choice after all, thinking all the while that this was Thomas's "new" teaching in De Malo. The mistake almost always made in understanding this is to impose a sequential model on the language of Thomas and have the will follow the intellect or make its own decision, when he wants us to see each guiding the other. The key to realizing this is the fact that intellect and will are not two similar but distinct faculties of the mind, one doing one job and one another (in which case they would operate sequentially), but are actually two different kinds of potencies according to Thomas. ag Using his metaphysical basis, the intellect is the term for a person's ability to recognize reality and truth, while the will is a person's ability to be attracted toward good specified in this way. In practical reasoning, both intellect and will need to be active at the same time. Apprehension and inclination are simultaneously necessary for action just as pitch and rhythm are both essential for music (which must involve sound frequencies as well as motion forward in time). The teaching of Thomas on intellect and will cannot be completely clear or convincing until its proper metaphysical foundations are presented, the relationships with Aristotle and Augustine are described, and the actual process of practical reasoning is explained. That will need to be done elsewhere.40 But we can 3 s Lottin, " La preuve de la liberte," p. 328. De Veritate 22.4, ad 4. Helpful on this point is Lawrence Dewan, "The Real Distinction between Intellect and Will," Angelicum 57 (1980) : 557-593. 4 0 My attempt at this appears in: Right Practical Reason: Aquinas on Prudence and Human Action (Oxford University Press, forthcoming). 39 54 DANIEL WESTBERG get some help by considering the two points which Lottin and Lonergan raised as the problems which they thought indicated change in Aquinas, namely the notion of the will as a potentia passiva and the attribution of final causality to the will. We saw that one of the key issues to which Lonergan objected was the notion of "passive potency." This is what he thought was "transcended" by Aquinas in De Malo 6, and others have thought that this work marks the place where he shifted to an " active " rather than a " passive " view of the will. This is interpreted to mean that the will is now self-activated, rather than being dependent on the determination of the intellect. This term potentia passiva should be interpreted in the framework of Aristotelian physics and metaphysics as Thomas developed it, and not given a psychological connotation which seems to make the agent " passive " with respect to his choices and actions. As Thomas develops the operations of the intellect and will as " passive potencies " he employs a technical expression indicating their relation to external reality. A passive potency, as he described it in his commentary on the Metaphysics, is " a principle by which something is moved by something else inasmuch as it is something else." 41 Both intellect and will are passive potencies with respect to an object (anything in the universe which it is possible to think or be attracted to), and therefore are in potency to change-to be "moved" by the object-but as potencies reduced to act they become active and enable a person to be an agent, that is to be free to think, desire, and do things. We expect this explanation of the function of intellect and will on this very Aristotelian basis to be difficult for the modern mind to accept; but it met with considerable opposition in Aquinas's time as well.42 If we consider the texts involved-the De Veritate, the condemned proposition, and its version in the De Mala-we will see 41 Metaphys. 9, lectio 1, no. 1777. 42 See Z. Kuksewicz, " Criticisms of Aristotelian Psychology and the Augustinian-Aristotelian Synthesis," in The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy, p. 623. DID AQUINAS CHANGE HIS MIND 55 that there was no abandonment of the prior Aristotelian metaphysics. In the earlier work Thomas, quoting Aristotle's De Anima, says that "the appetite is a passive potency, because it is moved by what is desirable." 43 Lattin has described for us the hostility to this on the part of Franciscans like Gauthier de Bruges, 44 and the general reaction that understood Thomas to be denying the freedom of the will. It is clear that they simply did not understand that Thomas was describing appetite in general, the metaphysics of teleology including the "natural appetite" of all creation as well as sensitive and rational appetite. In December of 1270 a number of philosophical errors were condemned by the Bishop of Paris, Stephen Tempier. The ninth seems to be directed at Thomas Aquinas : " That free choice is a passive potency, not active; and that it is necessarily moved by what is desirable," 45 but the substitution of liberum arbitrium for appetitus makes a considerable difference. For Thomas free choice is the principle of action, the product of both intellect and will in act. 46 Thomas is supposed (by those who follow the theory of change) to have been convinced by the pressure of opposition against him into changing his position in De Malo 6, disputed at about the same time the list of errors was published. In argument 7, one against free choice, Thomas expresses it this way: " it seems that the will is moved by necessity by what is desirable. Therefore there is no human free willing or not willing." 47 Thomas seems to be distancing himself from his former statement about the determination of the will, but notice that in the 4 3 De V eritate 25.1, " appetitus autem potentia passiva est, quia movetur ab appetibili." 44 Lottin, Psychologie et morale, I, p. 243 ff. 45 " Quod liberum arbitrium est potentia passiva, non activa; et quod necessitate movetur ab appetibili." Chartularium Universitatis Parisiensis, ed. H. Denifle, vol. I, (Paris, 1899), p. 48. 46 ST I, q.83, a.1, ad 3: " Dicendum quod liberum arbitrium est causa sui motus; quia homo per liberum arbitrium seipsum movet ad agendum." Cf. ST 1-11, q.l, a.l, 2. 47 De Malo 6, arg. 7. "Ergo videtur quod voluntas de necessitate moveatur ab appetibili. Non ergo est liberum homini velle vel non velle." 56 DANIEL WESTBERG De V eritate he spoke of appetitus, while here it is voluntas itself. Appetite is moved by what is desirable; the rational appetite is moved by (the good) in general. The metaphysical basis is the same, but in practice, the will is not moved by any particular good, because of the freedom we have to see things from different points of view. This is of course the heart of the argument of De Malo 6 and one that appears as well in his previous treatments. 48 In his reply to the seventh argument Thomas does not deny the doctrine of voluntas as a potentia passiva (in the technical sense) ; in fact he reaffirms the teaching, for since the will is related in potency with respect to universal good, no good can overcome the power of the will, as though moving it by necessity, unless it is something good in every respect. 49 Thus the will would still be necessarily moved by completely perfect good. There has also been misunderstanding of Thomas on the question of final causality on which Lottin based his theory of change. Thomas had always maintained that the intellect was the formal cause and the will the efficient cause (we saw that Lonergan was mistaken in thinking that Thomas had ever associated efficient causality with the intellect). The element of final causality seems to be shifted from intellect to will but this is because of understanding more precisely the connection of voluntas with bonum, and bonum with finis. As Verbeke puts it, the overall teaching remains the same, but in the De Malo it is " plus exacte" than in the De Veritate because of the clarification of final causality. 50 Free choice is a matter of choosing, on the part of both reason and will, the bonum intellectum. This never changes in Thomas. But he came to express more precisely that final causality had to do with the bonum aspect, and formal causality with intellectum. There can be no question, however, of the separation of final causality from intellect in order to show emphasis on the role of De V eritate 22.5; ST I, q.82, a.l ; I-II, q.9, a.1. De Malo 6, ad 7: " Cum autem voluntas se habeat in potentia respectu boni universalis, nullum bonum superat virtutem voluntatis quasi ex necessitate ipsam movens, nisi id quod secundum omnem considerationem est bonum." 5o G. Verbeke, " Le developpement de la vie volitive," p. 13. 48 49 DID AQUINAS CHANGE HIS MIND 57 the will because of the inherent connection between intelligence and finality. The essence of finality is the understanding of something done for a purpose or for a definite goal, which can be properly true only for rational agents, though analogically of all agents. 51 Far from shifting to an active notion of will, the intimate combination of intellect and will and of formal and final causality is strengthened in the teaching of De Mala 6. Good itself, with respect to its being a certain apprehensible form, is contained under the category of truth as a certain truth; and truth itself, to the extent that it is the goal of intellectual operation, is contained under the category of good as a certain particular good. 52 The introduction by Thomas of the Aristotelian text on God as mover of intellect and will demonstrates not a shift in his thinking as Lottin thought, but the difference in Aquinas from the emphasis of other theologians on the spontaneous action of the will. It actually underscores the need Thomas felt to provide a metaphysical explanation for the ultimate activation of intellect and will, and shows that he did not change his understanding of passive potency (the need for intellect and will to be moved to act by an exterior object) to a notion of radically free agency. When we come to later thinkers there is a real difference. There is no need in Scotus, for example, for God to be the first act, because he denies the principle "whatever is in motion is moved by another." 53 It is this Aristotelian principle, still clearly maintained by Thomas in De Mala 6, which sets him clearly apart from Henry of Ghent and the Franciscan voluntarists. We may thus approach the texts and affirm the basic unity 51 " Since finality is a participated perfection, it must be reduced to its most perfect source and cause, intelligence." L. Figurski, Final Cause and its Relation to Intelligence in St. Thomas Aquinas, Ph.D. dissertation, Fordham Univ. (New York, 1977), p. 192. 52 " Unde et ipsum bonum, in quantum est quaedam forma apprehensibilis, continetur sub vero quasi quoddam verum ; et ipsum verum, in quantum est finis intellectualis operationis, continetur sub bono ut quoddam particulare bonum." 5 3 Patrick Lee, " The Relation between Intellect and Will in Free Choice according to Aquinas and Scotus," Thomist 49 (1985) : 341. 58 DANIEL WESTBERG and consistency of teaching from the commentary on the Sentences to the ST II, and also explain the differing emphases. Throughout his works, Aquinas wanted to emphasize how reason and will both share in human action as the cognitive and appetitive aspects of an essentially united act. There may be other factors besides a change in the definition of the will to account for the apparent shifts. For example, if the certainty attaching to moral knowledge is reduced, this gives the effect of greater freedom. Intellectual determinism can also be reduced by giving more weight to the role of emotions and dispositions. A case can be made for these kinds of shifts in the thought of Aquinas, which then make the need to account for a change in his position on the will less compelling. 54 The Occasion and Purpose of De Malo 6 In some ways it is surprising that there is not a greater difference in the early and late works of Thomas on human action. One of Thomas's purposes in the commentary on the Sentences and in the De Veritate was to establish the proper role of intellect against the voluntarist emphasis common in the tradition of Philip the Chancellor and especially amongst the Franciscans. In the later part of the 1260s, with nearly everyone misunderstanding his doctrine of passive potency-despite his emphasis on the will's role in his treatment of liberum arbitrium in ST I, q. 83he came under increasing suspicion and attack by the traditionalist theologians. Being associated with the group of Siger of Brabant on other points of doctrine, Thomas had to take pains, especially in view of official action taken in 1270, to distance himself as much as possible from a deterministic position. Thomas thus had several items on his agenda in writing the De Malo 6: 54 Giuseppe Abba suggests that Aquinas moved from a conception of legalist morality to one governed by virtue in Lex et virtus: Studi sull' evoluzione della dottrina morale di san Tommaso d' Aquino (Rome, 1983). This book has exaggerated the shift, but it does indicate that an explanation of change need not involve a move towards " free will." DID AQUINAS CHANGE HIS MIND 59 ( 1) To confute Siger and those influenced by radical Aristotelian and Arabic determinism, using arguments from Aristotle (to which they would be open) in order to show why determinism was wrong. 55 (2) To convince his conservative opponents such as John Peckham that his own position was not determinist. The "extreme vehemence " noted by Lonergan was directed at the radical Aristotelians (not his own previous position !) and was to impress upon the theologians that he shared their convictions about the deep and important connection between freedom and moral responsibility. ( 3) To maintain and defend his own position on reason and will. Without substantially changing the teaching of choice by reason and will he stressed the indeterminacy of the will and refined his understanding of formal and efficient cause and his doctrine of the relationship between reason and will and verum and bonum. We should judge Thomas's treatment of the problem of reason and will in human action in De Malo and ST I-II a brilliant solution, and under the circumstances a tour de force. At the time, however, Thomas appears to have succeeded publicly only in his first objective, since it seems that Siger of Brabant may have been convinced by Thomas's logic and then modified his views. 56 John Peckham and the conservative theologians were not convinced, however, by Thomas's defense of the will's freedom. Aquinas was subject to deliberate misunderstanding and condemnation by the Franciscan school (if Thomas in fact had shifted to emphasizing the will his conversion to the Franciscan view would surely have not gone unacknowledged). It is probably fair also to add that, given the hostile situation around the year 1270, Thomas had to be careful in his descrip55 R. Hissette, Enquete sur les 219 articles condamnes a Paris le 7 Mars 1277 (Louvain and Paris, 1977), p. 230 ff., has a discussion of the condemned articles dealing with the will in relation to the teaching of Alkindi, Averroes, Siger of Brabant and others. 56 See F. van Steenberghen, Maitre Siger de Brabant (Louvain, 1977), pp. 401-403. 60 DANIEL WESTBERG tion of the role of intellect in human action. Thus the cognitive aspects of practical reason, such as the intellectual apprehension connected with intention and the important element of judgment and the syllogism connected with choice, are somewhat disguised in ST I-II, qq. 12 and 13. The difficult climate Thomas faced may well explain why the properly balanced roles of reason and will could not be described quite as clearly as Thomas would have liked, which in turn may be a factor in the tendency to misunderstand Aquinas still current in our day. GOD, EMOTION, AND CORPOREALITY: A THOMIST PERSPECTIVE 1 MARCEL SAROT University of Utrecht Utrecht, The Netherlands W I. Introduction HEN WE TAKE" impassibility" to mean" immutbility with regard to one's feelings or the quality of ne's inner life," 2 the number of adherents to the doctrine of divine impassibility has continuously decreased during the present century. Slowly but surely the concept of an immutable and impassible God has given way to the concept of a sensitive, emotional, passionate God. Before the Second World War this tendency was restricted to British theology, 3 but since then it has spread to the rest of Europe, notably to France and Ger1 A first draft of this paper was presented at a meeting of the Aquinas Research Group of the Catholic Theological University of Utrecht (The Netherlands) in May, 1990. I would like to thank the other participants for their useful comments. The paper also profited from the valuable comments of Prof. Dr. Vincent Brummer and Dr. Christoph Schwi:ibel. The writing of this paper forms part of a research project on divine passibility, supported by the Dutch Research Foundation for Theology and Religious Studies (STEGON), and funded by the Netherlands Organization for the Advancement of Research (NWO). 2 I have argued for this definition in my article " Patripassianism, Theopaschitism and the Suffering of God: Some Historical and Systematic Considerations," Religious Studies 26 (1990) : 363-375. a See A. van Egmond, De Lijdende God in de Britse Theologie van de Negentiende Eeuw: De Bijdrage van Newman, Maurice, McLeod Campbell en Gore aan de Christelijke Theopaschitische Traditie (Amsterdam: VU Uitgeverij, 1986); J. Kenneth Mozley, The Impassibility of God: A Survey of Christian Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1926), pp. 127-166; Doctrine in the Church of England: The Report of the Commission o·n Christian Doctrine Appointed by the Archbishops of Canterbury and York in 1922 (London: SPCK, 1938), pp. 55-56. 61 62 MARCEL SAROT many, to the United States and to Asia. 4 By now most of the theologians who explicitly state their views on divine impassibility hold that this doctrine is to a greater or lesser degree false, and Ronald Goetz rightly asserts "that the rejection of the ancient doctrine of divine impassibility has become a theological commonplace." 5 Nevertheless the debate on this issue is not yet closed. Recently Richard Creel published a thorough study in defense of divine impassibility, 6 which, I expect, will prove quite influential. Other theologians who defend the doctrine can be cited as well. 7 To a large extent, the arguments which these theologians put forward in favor of divine impassibility are taken from the classic Christian theological texts. Among these, the writings of Aquinas are not the least important and no one will be surprised to hear that he is frequently cited in this connection. However, what has surprised me in my study of the debate on the issue of divine impassibility is that one of the most important arguments Aquinas 4 On passibilist tendencies in modern theology, see Richard Bauckham, " ' Only the Suffering God Can Help ' : Divine Passibility in Modern Theology," Themelios 9 (1984) : 6-12; Warren Mc Williams, The Passio1i of God: Divine Swffering in Contemporary Protestant Theology (Macon: Mercer University Press, 1985); Van Egmond, De Lijdende God, pp. 28-31, and "Theopaschitische Tendenzen in de Na-Oorlogse Protestantse Theologie," Gereformeerd Theologisch Tijdschrift 79 (1979): 161-177; Marcel Sarot, "De Passibilitas Dei in de Hedendaagse W esterse Theologie: Een Literatuuroverzicht," Kerk en Theologie 40-3 (1989) : 196-206. 5 Ronald Goetz, "The Suffering God: The Rise of a New Orthodoxy," The Christian Century 103 (1986): 385. Also see the literature cited in the preceding note. 6 Richard E. Creel, Divine Impassibility: An Essay in Philosophical Theology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986). 7 See, for instance, Brian Davies, Thinking about God (London: Chapman, 1985), pp. 155-158; William J. Hill, "Does Divine Love Entail Suffering in God?," in: B. L. Clarke & E. T. Long, eds., God and Temporality (New York: Paragon House, 1984), pp. 55-71 ; id., " The Doctrine of God after Vatican II," The Thomist 51 (1987); pp. 412-414; Herbert McCabe, "The Involvement of God," New Blackfriars 66 (1985) : 464-476, reprinted in Herbert McCabe, God Matters (London: Chapman, 1987), pp. 39-51; JeanHerve Nicolas, "Aimante et Bienheureuse Trinite," Revue Thomiste 78 (1978): 271-292; John M. Quinn, "Triune Self-Giving: One Key to the Problem of Suffering," The Thomist 44 (1980): 173-218. GOD, EMOTION, AND CORPOREALITY 63 provides in favour of divine impassibility-the argument that bodily changes are necessarily involved in emotion-is almost completely neglected in the contemporary literature on this issue. 8 In my opinion one cannot come to definitive conclusions with respect to the issue of divine impassibility without paying attention to this argument. The present article should be read as a plea for the inclusion of this argument of Aquinas in the contemporary debate. I will proceed in the following way. The major part of this article will be devoted to an analysis of Aquinas's theory of human and divine emotion. This analysis should not be mistaken for a neutral and balanced introduction to Aquinas's theory of emotion in s I know of only four exceptions : Janine Marie Idziak, " God and Emotions" (Diss., Michigan, 1975); Nicholas Wolterstorff, "Suffering Love," in Thomas V. Morris, Philosophy and the Christian Faith (Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press, 1988), pp. 196-237; Charles Taliaferro," The Passibility of God," Religious Studies 25 (1989): 217-224; Robert Oakes, "The Wrath of God," Philosophy of Religion 27 (1990): 129-140. Idziak is of the opinion that an incorporeal God can have emotions, since physiological changes are, in her opinion, not necessary to emotion. Moreover, God "can experience something that at least bears some resemblance to our 'bodily' sensations," and this can be considered as " an appropriate substitute for the ' bodily ' sensations that are involved in human emotional experience." Wolterstorff thinks that God cannot have emotions, "for a person can have an emotion only if that person is capable of being physiologically upset. And God, having no physiology, is not so capable " ( p. 214). Nevertheless, W olterstorff thinks this leaves open the question whether God suffers, since suffering is a phenomenon distinct from emotion. Taliaferro (pp. 220-221) argues that attributing sorrow to God does not necessarily involve attributing bodily sensations to Him as well, since ( 1) "a non-physical being can have sensory experiences such as pain and pleasure" and (2) "sorrow is an emotion and there is no apparent absurdity in imagining someone to be in sorrow who is not thereby having any of the accompanying bodily associations of pain, her stomach ' turning over,' shedding tears and the like." Oakes argues that " while there appears to be an empirically invariant association between the possession of affective capacity and the possession of a neurophysiology . . . this clearly fails to entail that possessing a neurophysiology is conceptually necessary for possessing affective capacity" (p. 134). Moreover, he asserts that emotions are mental states and that, since traditional theism holds that an incorporeal God can have intellectual mental states, it would be arbitrary for a traditional theist to deny that God can have affective mental states (p. 134). 64 MARCEL SAROT general. On every page it shows the author's pre-occupation with the questions whether emotions presuppose corporeality and whether God could have emotions. I will show that for Aquinas bodily changes are essential to emotions and that this is one of the reasons why he holds that God cannot have emotions. In the last part of this article I will show that Aquinas's argument is still highly relevant for contemporary theology. In the present theological discussion on divine impassibility, however, this argument must be presented in a different, more concrete way. II. Thomas Aquinas on emotion human and divine 9 1. Aquinas on human emotion Aquinas's theological discussions on whether God could have emotions are profoundly influenced by the fact that he also made a serious study of human emotions in their own right. Therefore, for a proper understanding of Aquinas's views on the possibility of divine emotion, it seems necessary first to have a look at his theory of human emotions. o My rendering of Aquinas's views is based principally on the following texts: De V eritate XXV-XXVI, Summa contra Gentiles I, ch. 89-91, Summa Theologiae Ia, qq. 75-82, laliae, qq. 22-48. All quotations from the Latin text of the works of Aquinas are taken from S. Thomae Aquinatis, Opera Omnia, Vols. 1-7 (Stuttgart: Frommann-Holzboog, 1980). The English translation of texts from the Summa Theologiae is taken from the Blackfriars edition, the translation of texts from the Summa contra Gentiles is taken from that by Anton C. Pegis entitled On the Truth of the Catholic Faith, and the English translation of texts from De Veritate is taken from that by Robert W. Schmidt entitled Truth. With a view to the uniformity of the rendering of certain terms I have in some instances changed these translations. Beside these texts of Aquinas I consulted some of the most important studies on his theory of emotions : Eric d' Arey, " Introduction,'' in St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae [Blackfriars Edition] Vol. 19, "The Emotions" (London/New York: Blackfriars, 1967), pp. xix-xxxii; Richard R. Baker, " The Thomistic Theory of the Passions and their Influence upon the Will " (Diss., Notre Dame, 1941); Robert E. Brennan, Thomistic Psychology: A Philosophic Analysis of the Nature of Man (New York: MacMillan, 1960), pp. 147-168; H. M. Gardiner, Ruth Clark Metcalf, John G. Beebe-Center, Feeling and Emotion: A History of Theories (Westport, Connecticut: Greenwood Press, 1970), pp. 106-118; ]. M. Idziak, "God," pp. 9-10, 66-68, 86-88; Journet D. Kahn, "A Thomistic Theory of Emotion" (Diss. Notre Dame, GOD, EMOTION, AND CORPOREALITY 65 Dijf erent kinds of passion Aquinas uses the term passiones animae where we use the term "emotions." The term "passions of the soul" suggests correctly that there are other passions besides those of the soul. Aquinas distinguishes between three kinds of passions : passions in a general sense, passions in a (most) proper sense, and passions in a transferred sense.10 In the first and most common sense, passio is used whenever any quality is received, even if the recipient loses nothing in the process: for instance, one might say that the air ' suffers ' or ' undergoes ' illumination. However, this would be more properly styled 'acquiring' a new quality than 'suffering' something.11 In this sense anything that passes from potentiality to act may be said to undergo a passion. Therefore, passion in the first sense " is found in the soul and in every creature, because every creature has some potentiality in its composition ... " 12 Only 1957); Matthias Meier, "Die Lehre des hi. Thomas von Aquin de passionibus animae in quellenanalytischer Darstellung," Beitriige zur Geschichte der Philosophie des Mittelalters XI/2 (1912); H.-D. Noble, "La Nature de ]'Emotion selon les Modernes et selon Saint Thomas," Revue des Sciences Philosophiques et Theologiques 2 (1908) : 225-245, 466-483; id., "Passions," in A. Vacant, E. Mangenot, E. Amann eds., Dictionnaire de Theologie Catholique XI/2 (Paris: Librairie Letouzey et Ane, 1932), pp. 2211-2241; Remi Tittley, "La Douleur Sensible Est-Elle une Passion Corporelle ou une Passion Animale Selon Saint Thomas d'Aquin?" (Diss., Montreal, 1967); Howard Gil Weil, " The Dynamic Aspect of Emotions in the Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas" (Diss., Rome, 1966); Bernhard Ziermann, "Kommentar," in Thomas von Aquin, Die Menschlichen Leidenschaften [Die Deutsche ThomasAusgabe 10) (Heidelberg/Graz: Kerle/Styria, 1955), pp. 463-618. 1o On this distinction, see STh Ia, 79, 2; 97, 2; Iallae, 22.l ; 41, 1 ; De V eritate 26, 1 ; 26, 3. More references are provided by Tittley, " Douleur Sensible," p. 5, n.10, and by Kahn, "Thomistic Theory," pp. 8-20. See also Meier, "Lehre des hi. Thomas," pp. 14-28, and Weil, "Dynamic Aspect," pp. 52-56. 11 STh Iallae, 22, 1 c. : " uno modo, communiter, secundum quod omne recipere est pati, etiam si nihil abiiciatur a re, sicut si dicatur aerem pati, quando illuminatur. Hoc autem magis proprie est perfici, quam pati." See also STh Ia, 97, 2 c. 12 De V eritate 26, 1 c. : " passio igitur prime modo accepta invenitur in anima, et in qualibet creatura, eo quod omnis creatura habet aliquid potentialitatis admixtum, ratione cuius omnis creatura subsistens est alicuius receptiva." 66 MARCEL SAROT the Supreme Being is impassible in this sense of passion, since only in the Supreme Being is there no potentiality. 18 In the second and more strict sense, the word pati is used when a thing acquires one quality by losing another; and this may happen in two ways. Sometimes the quality lost is one whose presence was inappropriate in the subject: for example, when an animal is healed, it may be said to ' undergo ' healing, for it recovers its health by shedding its illness. At other times, the opposite happens: for example, a sick man is called a patient because he contracts some illness by losing his health. a This last kind of case is called passion in its most proper sense. Thus passion propriissime sumpta is an alteration in the subject that removes what is suitable to it, whereas passion proprie sumpta includes both alterations that are suitable to the subject and alterations that are harmful. In both cases one quality is lost and a contrary quality is gained. For Aquinas this means that this sort of passion is a kind of motion : motion with respect to quality. 15 Thus passion in its second sense is found only where there is motion and contrariety. Now motion is found only in bodies, and the contrariety of forms or qualities only in beings subject to generation and corruption. Hence only such beings can properly suffer in this sense. Consequently the soul, being incorporeal, cannot suffer in this sense; for even though it receives something, this does not happen by an exchange of contraries but simply by a communication from the agent, as air is lighted by the sun.16 1a See Sent II, 19, 1, 3 c.; cf. STh Iallae, 22, 2 ad 1. STh IaIIae, 22, 1 c.: "alio modo dicitur pati proprie, quando aliquid recipitur cum alterius abjectione. Sed hoc contingit dupliciter. Quandoque enim abiicitur id quod non est conveniens rei, sicut cum corpus animalis sanatur, dicitur pati, quia recipit sanitatem, aegritudine abiecta. Alio modo, quando e converso contingit, sicut aegrotare dicitur pati, quia recipitur infirmitas, sanitate abiecta. Et hie est propriissimus modus passionis." 15 For an illuminating discussion of Aquinas's views on motion and the connection between motion and passion in its proper sense, see Tittley, "Douleur Sensible,'' pp. 7-29. 16 De Veritate 26, 1 c.: "passio vero secundo modo accepta non invenitur nisi ubi est motus et contrarietas. Motus autem non invenitur nisi in corporibus, et contrarietas formarum vel qualitatum in solis generabilibus et corruptibilibus. 14 GOD, EMOTION, AND CORPOREALITY 67 With respect to passion in its third or transferred sense Aquinas writes: Because passion in its proper sense involves a certain loss, inasmuch as the patient is changed from its former quality to a contrary one, the term passion is broadened in usage, so that whatever is in anyway kept from what belongs to it is said to suffer. Thus we should say that something heavy suffers when prevented from moving downward, or that a man suffers if prevented from doing his own will.17 In this sense of passion, the soul can suffer a passion " ... in the sense that its operation can be hampered." 18 The distinction between passio animalis and passio corporalis In short, we have seen that Aquinas distinguishes between three senses of " passion," only the first and third of which can be suffered by the soul. This leads us to expect that the emotions or "passions of the soul " are passions in the common or in the transferred sense of the word. However, the contrary is true: the passions of the soul are passions in a proper sense. How can this be? How can the soul suffer a passion properly so called, a passion that can only be suffered by corpora? Aquinas answers that it is by the soul's union with a corpus. The soul can experience passions proprie dicta by virtue of its union with the body. This means that in such a passion the body suffers directly and Unde sola huiusmodi proprie hoc modo pati possunt. Unde anima, cum sit incorporea, hoc modo pati non potest: et si etiam aliquid recipiat, non tamen hoc fit per transmutationem a contrario in contrarium, sed per simplicem agentis influxum, sicut aer illuminatur a sole." On the fact that it is impossible for anything incorporeal to suffer a passion proprie sumpta, see also De V eritate 26, 2 c., and STh Ia!Iae, 22, 1 c.; 22, 3 c. 11 De Veritate 26, 1 c.: "quia ergo actio proprie accepta, est cum quadam abiectione, prout pa ti ens a pristina qualitate transmutatur in contrarium; ampliatur nomen passionis secundum usum loquentium, ut qualitercumque aliquid impediatur ab eo quod sibi competebat, pati dicatur; sicut si dicamus grave pati ex hoc quod prohibetur ne deorsum moveatur; et hominem pati si prohibeatur suam facere voluntatem." 1 8 De V eritate 26, 1 c.: "tertio vero modo quo nomen passionis transumptive sumitur, anima potest pati eo modo quo eius operatio potest impediri." 68 MARCEL SAROT the soul suffers only inasmuch as it is united to the body, and therefore indirectly. Now the soul is united to the body in two respects: ( 1) as a form, inasmuch as it gives existence to the body, vivifying it; (2) as a mover, inasmuch as it exercises its operations through the body. And in both respects the soul suffers indirectly, but differently .... A passion of the body is therefore attributed to the soul indirectly in two ways: ( 1) In such a way that the passion begins with the body and ends in the soul inasmuch as it is united to the body as its form. This is a bodily passion. Thus, when the body is injured, the union of the body with the soul is weakened and so the soul, which is united to the body in its act of existing, suffers indirectly. (2) In such a way that the passion begins with the soul inasmuch as it is the mover of the body, and ends in the body. This is called a passion of the soul. An example is seen in anger and fear and the like : for passions of this kind are aroused by the apprehension and appetite of the soul, and a bodily transformation follows upon them. 1 g However paradoxical it may seem, Aquinas's "passions of the soul " belong only per accidens to the soul. The soul suffers through its union with the body and " passion strictly so called cannot ... be experienced by the soul except in the sense that the whole person, the matter-soul composite, undergoes it." 20 Now 19 De Veritate 26, 2 c.: "unitur autem corpori dupliciter: uno modo ut forma, in quantum