THE CASE FOR SPIRIT CHRISTOLOGY: SOME REFLECTIONS THOMAS WEINANDY, O.F.M., CAP. Greyfriars Hall, University of Oxford I N THE JUNE, 1992, issue of Theological Studies Roger Haight, S.J., of the Weston School of Theology, authored an essay entitled "The Case for Spirit Christology." 1 In the December, 1992, issue of the same journal John Wright, S.J., of the Jesuit School of Theology at Berkeley, wrote a critical response entitled: "Roger Haight's Spirit Christology." 2 While I fully endorse Wright's reservations, here I wish to offer some of my own criticisms as well as expand upon some of his. 3 In order for a Spirit Christology to be viable Haight believes that it must fulfill six criteria: 1) It must adequately explain why Christians believe that their salvation is found in Jesus; 2) It must be faithful to the Bible; 3) It must uphold the teaching of the Councils, especially Nicaea and Chalcedon; 4) It must be intelligible and coherent; 5) It must respond to contemporary concerns, specifically the relationship of Jesus to the founders of other 1 Roger Haight, S.J., "The Case for Spirit Christology," Theological Studies 53(1992): 257-287. Hereafter referred to in the text by page numbers. 2 John Wright, S.J., "Roger Haight's Spirit Christology," Theological Studies 53(1992) : 729-735. 3 While this article will focus exclusively on Haight's Spirit Christology, much of what will be said here, by way of criticism, can be applied equally to other expressions of Spirit Christology, since the various forms are quite similar. Haight himself relies heavily upon and substantially agrees with G. W. H. Lampe, " The Holy Spirit and the Person of Christ," in Christ, Faith and History, ed. S. W. Sykes and J. P. Clayton (Cambridge: University Press, 1972) 111-130; and God as Spirit (Oxford: Clarendon, 1977). For other recent examples of Spirit Christology see Haight's footnote 1, p. 257. 173 174 THOMAS WEINANDY, O.F.M., CAP. religions; 6) It must be able to stimulate and empower Christian life (see 260-262). As in Wright's response, I wish to examine I-Iaight's Spirit Christology in light of these criteria. I will begin with an extensive examination of Haight's second criterion-faithfulness to scripture-for it is most central to his whole enterprise. Then, more succinctly, I will address his other criteria. Biblical Revelation and Religious Language The central, and therefore fatal, flaw within Haight's Spirit Christology is that his understanding of '.' God as Spirit," upon which the whole of his Christology is founded, is itself non-biblical. To discern Haight's understanding of " God as Spirit," we must first examine his notion of religious language and the philosophy sustaining it. For Haight, "the medium through which religious experience takes place may be called a symbol, making all religious knowledge symbolic knowledge. A symbol is that through which something else is made present and known; a symbol mediates a perception and knowledge of something other" (263). While the symbol makes the presence of God known, yet, precisely because it is a symbol, God is beyond or transcends what is symbolized. The symbol " both makes God present and points away from itself to a God who is other than itself" (263). Thus the symbolized " is" and " is not" the symbol (263). Haight argues then that the biblical symbol, " the Spirit of God " refers to God and is " materially and numerically identical with God. God as Spirit is God" (266). However, God as Spirit " indicates God at work, as active, and as power, energy, or force that accomplishes something" (266-267). God as Spirit refers not to God as he is immanent in himself, but to God as he is "outside of himself," within the order of time and history. Haight recognizes that the Old Testament also uses " Word" and " Wisdom" as symbols along with " Spirit," but " all of these symbols are basically the same insofar as they point to the same generalized experience of God outside of God's self and im- THE CASE FOR SPIRIT CHRISTOLOGY 175 manent in the world in presence and active power" (267). While Haight acknowledges that these symbolic expressions were at times personalized in the Old Testament, it would be wrong to hypostatize them, that is, conceive them as objective and individual. To do so detracts, Haight believes, from the fact that they are symbols of God himself and do not designate some intermediary between the world and God. Thus, " in order to preserve this primal quality of the biblical symbol Spirit, against the tendency of objectifying a personification, I use the phrase God as Spirit" (268). 4 Haight is correct that all religious language is, in some sense, symbolic. However, his understanding of symbolic language is not without ambiguity and error. This leads him to misrepresent biblical language, and thus biblical revelation itself. Firstly, he speaks, at times, of religious symbolic language as being metaphorical. For example, Jesus as Savior is a "metaphor of understanding" (264). "God as Spirit" is a " metaphorical symbol" (267). The Old Testament use of "Word" and " Wisdom " are " metaphors [which] contain imaginative virtualities that reveal aspects of God" (267). He refers to the " metaphorical and symbolic character of this term Spirit " (267). Now a metaphor is a word, phrase, action, etc., that is not literally applicable, such as " raining cats and dogs," or " a glaring error." The Bible does use metaphor-God is said to be a rock, or anthropomorphically, to possess eyes and ears. The statements themselves are not literally true though they do express something that is true about God-that he is steadfast and faithful or that he perceives human thought and action. However, while terms, such as " the Spirit of God," "Wisdom," and " Word," are symbolic, they are not metaphors, for they are stating something that, in some sense, is literally true-God acts in time and history by his Word, Wisdom, and Spirit in a way analogous to the way human beings speak and act. There is something literally 4 Haight is closely following Lampe here and refers to his God as Spirit, 37, 115-116, 179. 176 THOMAS WEINANDY, O.F.M., CAP. true about what is expressed, even if what is said is not the whole truth. Missing here in Haight's understanding of symbolic language is the traditional notion of the analogical use of religious language where what is said about God is not just a metaphor, but rather what is said actually lays hold of and literally corresponds to something true about God in himself and his activity. This ambiguous understanding of symbolic language, however, allows Haight to regard symbolic religious language as merely metaphorical when he wishes to deny something within the Bible that contradicts his notion of " God as Spirit," such as the personification of "Spirit," " Word," or " Wisdom." Secondly, this leads to a more serious problem. Haight does wish to maintain, as the above exposition of his thought confirms, that his notion " God as Spirit" actually does symbolize, and thus truly express, the reality of God and his activity in the world and within history. For Haight, however, the symbol itself " mediates " or " makes present and known " God. While Haight then professes that " God as Spirit points to God as active" (268), underlying his understanding of the symbolic nature of religious language is a philosophy that does not see God as actually acting in distinct and different kinds of ways in the world or within history. (This becomes most evident when Haight compares Jes us with the founders of other religions. All religions embody " God as Spirit," that is, God's universal and generic activity. There may be a difference of degree but not of kind.) Rather the symbolic language itself mediates God's presence and merely articulates and expresses the continuous, generic manner in which God is always "present" and "active." "The metaphorical symbol of God as Spirit expresses the experience of God's power and energy in creation; this power is seen in its effects. The verbal or conceptual symbol points to the way God is present in the world" (269). Thus the symbolic, for Haight, expresses not a new and specific action of God as such, but rather human insight into the transcendent nature of finite reality. The symbolic gives utterance not to a new action of God, but to an new insight of man. Because God's generic presence is perceived THE CASE FOR SPIRIT CHRISTOLOGY 177 in a new way, God is said, symbolically or metaphorically, "to act." The philosophy behind Haight's understanding of religious language then is hardly biblical. The Old Testament, when it speaks of God ratifying a covenant with the Israelites, or inspiring the prophets, or forgiving sins, or answering the prayers of the poor is symbolically expressing, not just some human insight (although human beings did have to grasp what was happening), but God's distinctive activity within history and in the lives of individuals. The Israelites came to new knowledge because God acted in a new way. Equally, the primary presupposition of the New Testament is that God acted in a distinctive and new kind of way in and through Jesus. In summary-for Haight, human insight, expressed symbolically, is the immediate justification of revelation, and thus man is the primary source of its meaning. Within the Bible, God's specific and distinct action is itself revelatory, and therefore the source of its meaning, which is experienced and then expressed in a symbolic manner. For the Bible, God (by his revelatory action in word and deed) defines, specifies, and interprets the symbol. For Haight, the symbol (of human origin) defines, specifies, and interprets God. The Spirit of God vs. God as Spirit What has been said so far now converges upon Haight's use of the term "God as Spirit." Despite Haight's continual appeal to the necessity of a biblical perspective, the phrase " God as Spirit " never once appears in the Bible. The Bible does speak of " the Spirit of God " and Jes us tells us that " God is Spirit " (Jn 4 :24), but scripture never employs the idiom " God as Spirit." This biblical absence does not necessarily discredit the expression, for the Church does use non-biblical words and concepts to declare what it believes to be biblical revelation, such as Nicaea's In this situation, homoousios and Trent's "transubstantiation." however, its absence is significant. 178 THOMAS WEINANDY, O.F.M., CAP. The Old Testament's perception of the " Spirit of God" differs in three ways from Haight's understanding of "God as Spirit." Firstly, "Spirit of God" refers to God's distinctive activity in history, and not just to human insight into God's generic presence in history "as Spirit." Secondly, while " Spirit of God" in the Old Testament is used to protect God's transcendence, yet it is used precisely to affirm that the wholly other, as the wholly other, (without losing his wholly otherness) is in our midst and acting, and not the wholly other manifesting himself in some lesser degree or form " as Spirit." " God as Spirit" makes a non-biblical separation between the wholly transcendent God and his lesser manifestations in history "as Spirit "-as force, energy, power. Thirdly, " Spirit of God" specifies the personal nature of the God who acts in history. God personally acts in the Spirit and not impersonally "as Spirit." " God as Spirit" subtly, but effectively, depersonalizes God. " God as Spirit " is no longer an acting subject. Rather "God as Spirit" becomes the symbolic expression of a philosophical principle-there is something transcendent or beyond (not necessarily a personal God) within the realm of the historically finite that human beings can personally embody, symbolically express, and so come to know. Haight's understanding of " God as Spirit " is closer then to the metaphysics of Hegel and to the religious philosophy of Schleiermacher than to the revelation of the Bible. 5 Jesus and God as Spirit Because Haight's basic concept of " God as Spirit" is nonbiblical, his Spirit Christology is not founded upon the New Testament proclamation. Haight states that by Spirit Christology he means one " that ' explains ' how God is present and 5 While Haight continually appeals to the importance of historical revelation and our contemporary historical consciousness in order to advocate his notion of "God as Spirit" and his Christology, yet his theology levels history. History is only the backdrop for man to discern God's generic presence, rather than the divine drama in which God himself acts in new and distinctive kinds of ways. History no longer bears a divine expectancy. THE CASE FOR SPIRIT CHRISTOLOGY 179 active in Jesus, and thus Jesus' divinity, by using the biblical symbol of God as Spirit, and not the symbol Logos" (257). Jesus then is not the eternal Son of God who came to exist as a man; rather he is a man who incarnates in a pre-eminent manner " God as Spirit." 6 Haight believes that this is more in keeping with the Synoptic portrayal of Jesus as speaking and acting by the power of the Spirit. Also, " God as Spirit " gives rise to his filial consciousness and sense of mission (see 269). Equally, the apparent equating of the Spirit and the risen Christ within the early Church tends to confirm this understanding (see 270271 ). 7 [Thus] the symbol of the Spirit more forthrightly makes the claim that God, God's very self, acted in and through this Jesus. This stands in contrast to the symbols of God's Word and Wisdom which, insofar as they became personified and then hypostatized, tend to connote someone or something distinct from and less than God that was incarnate in Jesus even though it is called divine or of God. By contrast the symbol of God as Spirit is not a personification of God but refers directly to God, so that it is clear from the beginning that nothing less than God was at work in Jesus (272). Haight argues, in the above quotation, that "God, God's very self, acted in and through this Jesus." He believes that this adequately accounts for Jesus' divinity. This understanding, however, is scripturally deficient in three ways. Firstly, this " self" is not God as he exists in himself wholly as God, but the lesser expression of himself "as Spirit." Thus, while Haight claims that it is "nothing less than God at work in Jesus," it is not the " whole fullness of deity " that dwells in him bodily (Col 2 :9). Secondly, as Wright in his response emphasizes, Haight neglects significant portions of the New Testament, specifically the heart 6 Lampe states: " In this continuous incarnation of God as Spirit in the spirits of men the Jesus presented to us by the Gospels holds his unique place. . . . In Jesus the incarnate presence of God evoked a full and constant response of the human spirit. This was not a different presence, but the same God the Spirit who moved and inspired other men, such as the prophets " (God As Spirit, 23-24). 7 Again, Haight is much indebted to Lampe's exegesis, Cf, God As Spirit, 62-94. 180 THOMAS WEINANDY, O.F.M., CAP. of the New Testament proclamation that Jesus is the unique Son. That Jesus is Son of God is declared or implied throughout the New Testament. Jesus is not just a son of God like every other believer, but God's 'beloved Son' (Matthew 3 :17), 'his own Son' (Romans 8:3), to whose image we are predestined to be conformed (Romans 8:29), 'his only begotten Son' (John 1:14; 3:16). Paul's preaching of the gospel ' concerns his Son ' (Romans 1 :3). This Son is involved in the creation of the world: e.g. 1 Corinthians 8 :6; Colossians 1 :15-17; Hebrews 1 :2; John 1:3). 8 Moreover, even within the Synoptics, Jesus' divinity is implied and revealed in such passages as the Infancy Narratives, in his unique authority as Son to forgive sins and to augment God's commandments, etc. (see Lk 1 :32-35, Mt 1 :23, Mk 2 :1-12, Mt 5 :21-48). Furthermore, and most obviously, as Wright also notes, " Haight does not take serious account of the Christology of John." 9 Thirdly, while Haight speaks of Jesus' filial consciousness and of " God as Spirit in his life " as the " ground of Jesus' sonship" (269), yet the concept "God as Spirit" necessarily brings to Haight's Christology an impersonalism that is totally absent in the New Testament. Jesus is not the eternal Son who now as man relates to the Father in love and obedience, but becomes " son " by incarnating " God as Spirit," that is, the force, energy, and power of God. Despite Haight's disclaimer, this is adoptionism, or rather "symbolic adoptionism." 10 What Jesus is actually doing is embodying the philosophical principle that there is something transcendent within the finite which is symbolically called " God as Spirit." Because of the impersonal nature of Haight's Christology, it is not surprising that he never once refers to the Father. Significantly too, the ·emerging and even developed personal subjectivity of the Holy Spirit within the New Testament is completely lost s Wright, 730-731. 9 Wright states: "It is not only that he [Haight] neglects John's teaching on the Logos with God in creation (John 1 :1-3) and the affirmation of the incarnation of the Logos (John 1 :14), but he also takes no account of the 'I am ' assertions of the J ohannine Jesus " (731). 1.-0 Both Haight and Lampe believe that by saying Jesus embodied " God as Spirit" from the first moment of his existence they have freed themselves THE CASE FOR SPIRIT CHRISTOLOGY 181 within Haight's Christology. The Holy Spirit is not a divine subject who anoints Jesus and sanctifies his followers, but the impersonal force or energy of the transcendent God which Jesus and others embody and so " personalize " in themselves. Jesus and Salvation Given Haight's Christology, it is easy to discern his soteriology. Jesus brings salvation in that through embodying " God as Spirit" he discloses in a preeminent manner, and so becomes the paradigm for, how God has always acted and is present. This revelation in turn empowers his disciples to follow his example. It is a " revelational and exemplary theory of salvation" (278). "Jes us saves by being the revealer of God and God's salvation which God as Spirit has effected from the beginning, the revelation of what human life should be, and the empowering example of life for disciples " ( 278). Haight again professes that this soteriology is biblical in nature. While containing biblical elements, it is far from the whole truth, and by what it lacks it completely distorts New Testament soteriology. Haight does not address the biblical notion of sin and its radical effect upon our relationship with God and others. Nor does he envision the devastating effect that sin has upon us as human beings. Because of this, his notion of salvation is Pelagian and Gnostic. Jes us is the Gnostic redeemer who reveals to us and is the paradigm for how we are to relate to God and so become human. Once we have learned the lesson, we can do it on our own. Equally, Haight reduces the Gospel to pure moralism, for we are justified and saved not through faith, but merely by imitating Christ through our ethically good actions (see 278). from adoptionism. Cf. Haight, 277; Lampe, " The Holy Spirit and the Person of Christ," 125-126. The issue of adoptionism, however, is not a question of timing, but a question of who ] esus is. Is the historical ] esus the eternal Son of God existing as a man? Or, is he a man who is in some manner united to God and so constituted his son? If the latter is the case, the time or manner does not ultimately matter. It is still adoptionistic. If the Son is not God, then the sonship is always one of adoption. Only if ] esus is the eternal Son of God, and therefore needs no adoption, since he is Son by nature, can adoptionism be overcome. 182 THOMAS WEINANDY, O.F.M., CAP. Moreover, once Jesus has revealed to us how we are to live and so furnished the ultimate salvific clue of the universe, his importance ceases. The historical Jesus in himself is not the Savior. He is purely a Gnostic functionary who performed his task of putting us in the know. Gone is the biblical, historical Jesus who took the sins of all upon himself and died, and now, as the risen Lord, pours out his Spirit, intercedes for us in heaven, personally acts within the Church and sacraments, and who will come again in glory. In contrast, the New Testament professes that through Jesus' historical death and resurrection our relationship with God and with one another changes not in degree (from good to better), but in kind (from bad to good). Jesus did not supremely reveal an already founded relationship with God, and thus enable those who follow to utilize better the pre-established salvific program; rather through his death and resurrection, he changed in kind our relationship with God. A whole new salvific order is initiated. We go from being enemies of God to being children of the Father. Moreover, those who now live in Christ possess a relationship with one another that differs in kind from their relationships with those who do not believe. Furthermore, because of and simultaneous to our new relationship to God, those who believe are changed, not in degree, but in kind. We become a new creation in Christ, for the Holy Spirit now dwells in us in a new way. 11 Jesus' lack of contemporary importance can also be seen in Haight's view of Christian prayer. Because Jesus is a human being who incarnates " God as Spirit," one does not really worship Jesus, but worships God through Jesus (see 283-284). Haight admits that there are a few instances of prayer to Jesus in the New Testament. Here again, however, he misrepresents the scriptures. The recognition of Jesus as Lord means that our relationship to him as Lord is one of worship (see Jn 20 :28, Phil 2 :10-11). Moreover, the whole of the Book of Revelation 11 For a fuller expression of how salvation "differs in kind" see: T. Weinandy, In the Likeness of Sinful Flesh: An Essay on the Humanity of Christ, (Edinburgh: T & T Clark, 1993), pp. 85-88. THE CASE FOR SPIRIT CHRISTOLOGY 183 is a portrayal of heavenly worship of the Father and the Son. Not to worship Jesus, besides being contrary to the whole Christian tradition, radically transforms the nature of Christianity. Christians, by definition, worship, adore, and glorify Jesus as their Lord and God.12 In light of these criticisms, we are compelled to conclude that Haight's Spirit Christology does not fulfill his second criterionthat of being faithful to the scriptures. Spirit Christology and the Councils Haight believes that his Spirit Christology is fully in keeping with the doctrines enunciated at the Councils of Nicaea and Chalcedon, namely that Jesus is truly God and truly man. In claiming that by hypostatizing the Logos one runs the risk of imposing a lesser intermediary between God and man, and by emphasizing instead that " not less than God was present to and operative in Jesus," Haight actually circumvents the heart of Nicaea' s teaching. Nicaea precisely proclaimed (against Arius) that the Son was not some semi-divine intermediary, but that he was fully divine, homoousios with the Father. While Haight consistently quotes Chalcedon's statement that Jesus is homoousios with man, he never quotes Nicaea's that the Son is homoousios with the Father. The reason for this is simply discerned. H omoousios bears upon one's ontological status. Haight does want to say that Jes us is man, but he does not want to say that Jesus actually is God. This is, however, expressly what Nicaea wishes to ensure. The historical Jesus, as the Son, is not only " not less than God," he also ontologically is God. All that the Father is, the Son is. The Son is not just "adverbially" God, as Haight maintains (287) .18 12 Wright comments : " Christian experience of Jesus is expressed in doxologies given to him in the New Testament (e.g. Heb 13 :21; 2 Pet 3 :18; Rev 5 :13) and found in Christian worship ever since. An experience of Jesus is expressed in Thomas's profession of faith repeated by countless believers after him: 'My Lord and my God! ' CJ ohn 20 :29). These expressions are not directed simply to God as Spirit dwelling in him, but to Jesus himself. Haight's Spirit Christology does not justify this aspect of Christian experience" (730). 13 As Haight notes, he obtains this notion of Jesus being " adverbially " divine from Lampe. Cf. " The Holy Spirit and the Person of Christ,'' 124. 184 THOMAS WEINANDY, O.F.M., CAP. He (verbally) is God. This, Haight's Spirit's Christology will not allow. Jesus may incarnate " God as Spirit" to the highest degree possible, but God himself, in the whole of his reality as God, is not man. On the question of preexistence, Haight argues that in order to assure that Jesus is thoroughly like us, one cannot " really think of a preexistence of Jesus," since that would demand that he be substantially different from us. As preexistent he would be a different kind of man (276) .1 4 This argument misses the point entirely. The eternal Son, as God, preexists; not Jesus as man. As Wright remarks : " No one ever understood preexistence in this way, so why trouble to refute it? " 15 We must remember though that for Haight, if Jes us did preexist, he would necessarily preexist as a man, since within his Christology there is no preexistent divine Son. Nonetheless, Haight attacks this bogus heresy precisely because it helps to undermine the preexistence of the Son as God and provides a platform for insisting that Jesus incarnates "God as Spirit," which then guarantees that Jesus is not only fully man but also only a man. This same contrived confusion is evident on the question of whether or not Jesus differs from us in kind or in degree. For Haight, to say that Jesus is qualitatively different from us would be " directly contradictory to the doctrine of the consubstantiality of Jesus with other human beings " (279) .16 Again, no orthodox theologian or council ever held that Jesus' humanity was different in kind from ours. What the Christian tradition has always insisted upon, and which Haight denies, is that Jesus' sonship differs from us in kind since he is the eternal Son, and therefore that God is present in Jesus in a different way, that is, as incarnate. Haight's philosophy will allow only one kind of relationship with argues in a similar vein. Cf. God As Spirit, 120-144. Wright, 731. 16 It is interesting that those segments of the tradition with which Haight agrees are called " doctrines," such as Jesus being homoousios with us, but not those with which he disagrees, such as Jesus being homoousios with God. 14 Lampe 15 THE CASE FOR SPIRIT CHRISTOLOGY 185 God, that is, the embodying of " God as Spirit," and therefore, by necessity, Jesus can only differ from us by degree in that he incarnates " God as Spirit " more than we do.17 Haight, obviously, wishes to ensure the full humanity of Jesus and believes that the traditional understanding of the Incarnation jeopardizes this since the personhood of Jesus is the eternal Son. While a discussion of this cannot be fully undertaken here, it must be said that to specify the divine subjectivity of Jesus in no way implies that he is less than human. He possess all that pertains to being human, including a human self-conscious "I." What the councils and the tradition wished to ensure was that the subjective identity of that human "I" was the eternal Son of God. Not to acknowledge that Jesus is truly the Son of God thoroughly abandons the significance of the full humanity and thus of the Incarnation itself.18 With regard to the Trinity, Haight admits that the traditional language about three persons in one God " is not directly reflected in Spirit Christology " and that " more speculation will be needed" (285-286). He denies that there is any intrinsic or necessary relationship between the developed trinitarian doctrine and the New Testament (see 285). Moreover, "the economic Trinity is distinct from the doctrine of the immanent Trinity . . . and the former does not necessarily entail the latter" (285). Here, in speaking about the Trinity, Haight exposes how truly non-biblical is his Spirit Christology. The personalism and the communion of life between persons, which is so prevalent in the Bible, is absent. Not only is the being of God no longer a communion of life and love between the Father, Son, and Holy Spirit, 17 While Haight states that he does not hold that the traditional Logos Christology is wrong, but rather wishes " to characterize a Christology that is more adequate to our situation" (259), actually the traditional Logos Christology is the only Christology that is ruled out of court. 18 For a fuller discussion of how the eternal Son can become man without diminishing his humanity, see T. Weinandy, Does God Change?: The Word's 'Becoming' in the Incarnation (Petersham: St. Bede's Press, 1985), 96-100, 184-186; and In the Likeness of Sinful Flesh, 11-13. See also Jean Galot, The Person of Christ (Chicago: Franciscan Herald Press, 1983), and Who Is Christ? (Chicago: Franciscan Herald Press, 1981), 279-311. 186 THOMAS WEINANDY, O.F.M., CAP. but also God no longer shares this communion of life with us. " Father," " Son/Word," and " Spirit " only function as symbols or metaphors of our human perception of a solitary "transcendent being." He is not a God who acts, much less a trinity of persons who desire to form a common life with us. Haight is less than an Old Testament monotheist. He is simply, at best, a unitarian. 19 Thus Haight does not meet his third criterion of being faithful to the tradition and to the councils. Nor then is his fourth criterion feasible for the viability of his Spirit Christology-intelligibility and coherence. Wright is correct when he writes : " It seems to me that Haight's position is coherent within itself, but not with the experience of most Christians, with the teaching of the New Testament, nor with the Councils of the Church and the Great Tradition generally." 20 Jesus and Other Salvation Bringers Haight's fifth criterion, that Christianity must take into account other religions and their founders can now be briefly examined. Haight writes : " In an historicist framework and on the basis of a Spirit Christology one also confesses that Jesus is an ontological mediation of God that is decisive, definitive, final, and even absolute, provided that these determinations are not construed exclusively, as negating the possibility that God as Spirit is at work in other religions " ( 282). Jesus may be decisive and absolute for Christians, but this decisiveness and absoluteness is relative because God is working in the same kind of way in other religions-as Spirit. However, this again is contrary to the New Testament and to the Christian tradition. Granted that God can and does work in other religions, yet Christians believe that Jesus, as the Son of God incarnate, differs from other founders of religion not only in degree (as Haight maintains), but in kind. Moreover, unlike 19 In response to Lampe's God As Spirit, E. L. Mascall wrote an essay "Quicunque Vult ... ? Anglican Unitarians," in his Whatever Happened to the Human Mind? (London: SPCK, 1980), 97-127. 20 Wright, 733. THE CASE FOR SPIRIT CHRISTOLOGY 187 the founders of other religions, who in themselves are unimportant, but function as couriers of an important religious message which is not about themselves, Jesus is himself fundamentally significant and not just a proclamation about something apart from himself. Jesus is himself the message. He is the way, the truth, and the life CJ n 14 :6). He is the resurrection and the life (Jn 11 :25). The Church preaches Jesus Christ and him crucified ( 1 Cor. 1 :23). Before him every knee is to bend and every voice proclaim that he is Lord (Phil 1 :10-11). Jes us himself was important within his earthly life because only in his death and resurrection is sin and death vanquished so that now in him, as the risen Lord, we have a new kind of life with Father, the fullness of the Holy Spirit and the promise of eternal life. Many people from other religions may get to heaven, but they will do so because in Jes us' name alone do we have salvation (Acts 4: 12). 21 Reason and Inspiration In light of all that has been said, Haight's position does not uphold his first and sixth criteria-that Christology justify our faith in Jesus and inspire Christian life. Within Haight's Spirit Christology there is little reason to believe in Jesus. Actually, as noted earlier, the biblical concept of faith has been abandoned. Faith is not an intellectual acceptance of nor a personal commitment to Jesus as Lord and Savior by which we are justified and made holy, but is reduced merely to imitation. What we truly require is the means to discern how to live a " good life " and then live it. A noble philosopher could do as well as Jesus, although he would inevitably not practice what he preached. Jesus' perfect example may then inspire us, but he is not the eternal Son of God who has actually experienced our human plight, nor is he our Savior who has radically changed our desperate condition. 22 21 Wright believes that Haight's Spirit Christology "seems to undercut radically the mission of the Church" to preach the gospel to all nations (734). 22 Wright states: "At least for myself, as I contemplate a purely human Jesus, though one in whom the Spirit is fully operative, I experience an immense sadness and sense of loss : for this would mean that God after all did not love us enough to become one of us and die for us. But Haight thinks that such a Jesus is one we can follow more readily " ( 734) . 188 THOMAS WEINANDY, O.F.M., CAP. In a world racked with so much injustice and war and in the pain of sin and death that inflicts our personal lives we need a God who does more than provide us moral encouragement. This essay could be construed as being merely negative. 23 However, my goal has not been just to demonstrate the inadequacy of Haight's Spirit Christology, but to defend the gospel as it has been passed down to us through the Church. The only message that gives life is this gospel, revealed and protected by the Spirit of truth and lived out by the saints of all ages. 23 This essay should not be interpreted as implying that I see no role for the Holy Spirit in the life of Jesus. Actually, I believe traditional Christology and soteriology have been quite deficient in their understanding of the position of the Holy Spirit. See Weinandy, In the Likeness of Sinful Flesh, 59-60, 97, 102, 150-151. UNDERSTANDING THE DIFFERENCE OF BEING: ON THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN METAPHYSICS AND THEOLOGY HELMUT HOPING University of Tubingen, Germany T: Introduction HE PHILOSOPHY of the twentieth century has been o no small extent a critique of metaphysics. Admittedly, philosophical programs have been developed in which the tradition of metaphysics survives. Yet the position of metaphysics in the modern age is disputed even today-as is demonstrated by the recent controversy between Jiirgen Habermas and Dieter Henrich about the possibility of metaphysics after Kant. 1 Since 1 See J. Habermas, "Ruckkehr zur Metaphysik: Eine Tendenz in der deutschen Philosophie?" Merkur 439/440, 39 (1985): 898-905; "Metaphysik nach Kant," in K. Cramer et al., eds., Theorie der Subjektivitiit: Dieter Henrich zum 60. Geburtstag (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1978), 425-443. (Both articles are reprinted in J. Habermas, Nachmetaphysisches Denken: Philosophische Auf siitze [Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1988], 18-34; 267-279.) Henrich replied to Habermas's critique in the article "Was ist Metaphysik, was Moderne?: Thesen gegen Jurgen Habermas," Merkur 440, 40 (1986): 495-508 (reprinted in D. Henrich, Konzepte: Essays zur Philosophie der Zeit [Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1987], 11-43). On the controversy between Habermas and Henrich, see V. Gerhardt, " Metaphysik und ihre Kritik: Zur Metaphysikdebatte zwischen Jurgen Habermas und Dieter Henrich," Zeitschrift fur philosophische Forschung 42 (1988) : 45-70. Habermas's notion of a " return to metaphysics " undoubtedly has a certain diagnostic value; after all, there has indeed been a recent " discovery " of metaphysics. But Habermas's criticism of the concept and content of metaphysics-i.e., his thesis that after Kant metaphysics is impossible-not only contradicts the self-understanding of modern philosophy for which metaphysics is essential; it also fails to recognize the metaphysical implications of his own theory of communicative action. See W. C. Zimmerli, "Kommunikation und Metaphysik: Zu den Anfangsgrunden von Habermas ' ' Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns,' " in W. Oelmuller, ed., M etaphysik heute? Kolloquien zur Gegenwartsphilosophie, vol. 10 (Paderborn: SchOningh, 1987), 97-111. 189 190 HELMUT HOPING metaphysics has been indispensable for the self-understanding of philosophy in the modern age up until Hegel, this controversy cannot be reduced to the simple disjunction: either the "end of metaphysics" or the "return to metaphysics "-as Habermas has suggested. The task of philosophy today lies in a metaphysical form of thinking that remains possible even after the critique of metaphysics in Kant and Heidegger. Until recently, the current debate about metaphysics has not been adequately addressed by theology. That is surprising because metaphysics is also indispensable for theology. 2 But in the light of the modern critique of metaphysics, the self-understanding of theology and its relationship to metaphysics cannot remain unchanged-just as the self-understanding of metaphysics itself cannot remain unchanged. Yet at least in the realm of Catholic theology, the traditional doctrine of the praeambula fidei has not been abandoned. The aim of the following reflections is to show that the determination of the relationship between metaphysics and theology depends upon how metaphysics understands the " difference of Being" that is given with the manifold of beings. I will introduce four different understandings of the " difference of Being": that which is found in Aquinas's metaphysics; that in Kant's transcendental philosophy; that in Heidegger's thinking of Being; and that in the metaphysics of the absolute projected by Henrich. In some concluding reflections, I will then try to draw out some implications of these understandings of the " difference of Being " for the determination of the relationship between metaphysics and theology. I. Metaphysics of God and Creation : Theological Difference (Aquinas) It is well-known that Thomas Aquinas defines metaphysics as the science of being qua being. The subject-matter that dis2 See W. Kasper, " Zustimmung zum Denken: Von der Unerlasslichkeit der Metaphysik fiir die Sache der Theologie," Tiibinger Theologische Quartalschrift 169 (1989) : 257-271. RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN METAPHYSICS & THEOLOGY 191 tinguishes metaphysics from all other sciences is the ens inquantum est ens 3 or the ens commune. 4 Contrary to later concepts of metaphysics, this is not an abstract-universal, for " the term ' a being' [ens], which is applied to a thing by reason of its being [esse], designates the same thing as the term which is applied by reason of its essence." 5 Now the ratio entis of metaphysicsbased on a negative judgment that Aquinas calls separatio 6-is not simply the same as the concept of being that " the intellect first conceives as most known." 7 The discovery of metaphysics leads to the knowledge of the principles of its subject-matter. And it is well-known too that according to Aquinas the understanding of being qua being is ultimately only possible in relation to a divine being. Although the divine being does not fall under the enl> commune, 8 metaphysics deals with everything that is called "being." And theology is the goal and the conclusion of metaphysics. Therefore, theology can be another name for first philosophy. 9 So both metaphysics and theology signify one and the same science. If metaphysics deals with everything that is called "being," then a higher science going beyond that science seems to be impossible, for a science can only exist about being. 10 Now besides InDe trin.,q. 5, a.4c (ed. Decker, 194:23-27). In Met. Prooem. (ed. Marietti, 2). 5 In IV Met., lect. 2 (ed. Marietti, n. 558). 6 In De trin., q. 5, a. 3c (ed. Decker, 186 :13-16). 7 Illud autem quad primo intellectus concipit quasi notissimum et in quod omnes conceptiones resolvit est ens (De ver., q. 1, a. le [ed. Leonina XXII/1, 5 :100-102]). 8 Ens commune est proprius effectus causae altissimae, scilicet Dei (Sum. Theo. I-II, q. 66, a. 5, ad 4 [ed. Leonina VI, 436]). 9 Prima philosophia tota ordinatur ad Dei cognitionem sicut ad ultimum finem uncle et scientia divina nominatur (III Cont. Gent., c. 25 [ed. Marietti, n. 2063]). 1 0 Non entis non est scientia (In Sent., pro!., a. 1, ob. 1 [ed. Mandonnet]). See also : Praeterea, doctrina non potest esse nisi de ente: nihil enim scitur nisi verum, quod cum ente convertitur. Sed de omnibus entibus tractatur in philosophicis disciplinis, et etiam de Deo . . . Non fuit igitur necessarium, praeter philosophicas disciplinas, aliam doctrinam haberi (Sum. Theo. I, q. 1, a. 1 ob. 2 [ed. Leonina IV, 6]). 3 4 192 HELMUT HOPING the theology that is "part of philosophy," Thomas recognizes the theology of "Sacred Scripture." Theology or divine science is twofold : one in which divine things are considered not as the subject of the science but as principles of the subject-matter, and this is the theology pursued by philosophers, which by another name is known as metaphysics; the other kind of theology considers divine things themselves as the subject of the science, and this is the theology which is treated in Sacred Scripture. 11 The two theologies are generically distinct,1 2 for they belong to different sciences, which Aquinas calls metaphysica and sacra doctrina or (rarely) theologia. So metaphysics and theology signify not only one and the same science but also two different sciences. The theology that is different from metaphysics is-like metaphysics-wisdom, ordering knowledge the basis of knowing the first causes and highest principles of everything. Yet it is not metaphysics but rather theology as scientia prinicipalis that has sovereignty over all other sciences subordinate to itself.13 The reason for this is that theology deals with the truths of the incomprehensible God towards whom man is directed " as to an end which surpasses the grasp of his reason." 14 But metaphysics has a knowledge about God only as the "first principle" of all beings 15 and this knowledge of God is known only by a few, after 11 Sic igitur theologia, sive scientia divina, est duplex. Una in qua considerantur res divinae, non tamquam subiectum scientiae, sed tanquam principia subiecti, et talis est theologia quam philosophi prosequuntur, quae alio nomine metaphysica dicitur. Alia vero quae ipsas res divinas considerat propter seipsas ut subiectum scientiae, et haec est theologia quae in sacra scriptura traditur (In De trin, q. 5, a. 4c [ed. Decker, 195 :6-11]). See also In I Sent., pro!., a. 1, sol. (ed. Mandonnet, 7-8); In De trin., q. 2, a. 2c (ed. Decker, 87:7-15); I Cont. Gent., c. 3 (ed. Marietti, nn. 21-27); Sum. Theo. I, q. 1, a. le (ed. Leonina IV, 6). 12 Unde theologia quae ad sacram doctrinam pertinet, differt secundum genus ab ilia theologia quae pars philosophiae ponitur (Siiin. Theo. I, q. 1, a. 1, ad 2 [ed. Leonina IV, 7]). 13 In I Sent., pro!., a. 1, sol. (ed. Mandonnet, 8) . 14 Homo ordinatur ad Deum sicut ad quendam finem qui comprehensionem rationis excedit (Sum. Theo. I, q. 1, a. le [ed. Leonina IV, 6]). 1 5 I Cont. Gent., c. 3 (ed. Marietti, n. 16). RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN METAPHYSICS & THEOLOGY 193 a long time, and with the admixture of many errors. 16 Theology makes up for these inadequacies of philosophy.17 The unity of theology as a science different from metaphysics cannot result from the ratio entis; otherwise there would not be two different sciences. The proprium subiectum 18 through which the theology of Sacred Scripture is distinguished from all other sciences,19 i.e., the formal object that constitutes its unity, is God himself.20 Contrary to metaphysics, which considers everything inasmuch as it is "being," Le., sub ratione enJtis, theology considers everything sub ratione Dei. 21 Moreover, the subject-matter of the theology that is different from metaphysics cannot simply be the divine being insofar as it is known through natural reason, but rather the divine being insofar as it is knowable through revelation. 22 The subject-matter of the theology of Sacred Scripture is a quidam credibile 23 for which there exists no ratio demonstrativa but only a ratio persuasoria.24 16 I Cont. Gent., c. 4 (ed. Marietti, n. 22-25) ; Sum. Theo. I, q. l, a. le (ed. Leonina IV, 6). 11 In I Sent., pro!., a. 1, s.c. (Ed. Mandonnet, 7). 1s In I Sent., pro!., a. 4, ob. 3 et s.c. (ed. Mandonnet, 8) . 1 9 In I Sent., pro!., a. 4, sol. (ed. Mandonnet, 15-16). 20 Sum. Theo. I, q. 1, a. 3c et ad 1 (ed. Leonina IV, 12). 2 1 Omnia enim quae in haec scientia considerantur, sunt aut Deus, aut ea quae ex Deo et ad Deum sunt (In I Sent., pro!., a. 4, sol. [ed. Mandonnet, 16]). 2 2 Sum. Theo. I, q. 1, a. 3c (ed. Leonina IV, 12). Thomas speaks of "inspiration" in In I Sent., prol., a. 4, sol. (ed. Mandonnet, 16). 2 3 In I Sent., pro!., a. 4, sol. (ed. Mandonnet, 15). 24. In De trin., q. 2, a. 1, ad 5 (ed. Decker, 84 :3-4). The theology of "Sacred Scripture " is a science sui generis based on the " science of God and the Blessed" (Sum. Theo. I, q. 1, a. 2c [ed. Leonina IV, 9]). Aquinas avoids speaking of the theology that is different from metaphysics as a "dialectical science,'' as Al-Farabi and Avicenna speak of kalam. Both classic kalam and falsafa do not distinguish between philosophy and theology as did Christian theologians in the Middle Ages (see R. M. Frank, "The Science of Kalam,'' Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 2 [1992]). According to Al-Farabi and Avicenna, the difference between kalam and falsafa is that in kalam there exist only " dialectical arguments,'' i.e., arguments based on opinions. Since the theology of Sacred Scripture cannot regard the articles of faith as mere opinions, Aquinas therefore also avoids calling the arguments of the theology that is different from metaphysics " dialectical arguments "; instead, he speaks 194 HELMUT HOPING Now Aquinas's metaphysics does not lead-like Aristotle's metaphysics-to a divine being that is, as the highest instance of being, simultaneously a genus of being, albeit the " worthiest genus of being." 25 God, or better, the divine, of Aristotelian metaphysics is that necessary being upon which depend nature and the heavens, the other genera of being. 26 Yet the divine being itself is a part of the whole of beings and so seems to be a finite being. 21 By contrast, Aquinas's metaphysics leads to a divine being that as the highest principle of existence is beyond the whole of beings, i.e., beyond the difference of Being: Deus nJon est in ge1i:ere. This understanding of the difference of Being depends on a proof for the existence of God that determines the relationship between metaphysics and theology. Thus the existence of God does not belong to the " articles of faith " but rather is a about rationes probabiles (see I Cont. Gent., c. 9 [ed. Marietti, nn. 51-56]); only once does Aquinas use the term "dialectical argument " to signify the character of an argument of probability of Christian faith, namely, in an article about the fourfold function of Christian faith as an argument (De ver., q. 14, a. 2, ad 9 [ed. Leonina XXII/2, 444:369-390]). Yet Aquinas's distinction between the ratio demonstrativa and the ratio persuasoria shows that he recognized that for the authentic truths of faith there exist no apodei:ris but rather that the arguments of the theology of Sacred Scripture-like the arguments of the Aristotelian Topics-have the goal of persuasion and thus require free agreement. A ratio demonstrativa for an authentic truth of faith would eliminate the merit of faith: " Si autem talis ratio ad probanda ea quae sunt fidei, induceretur, evacuaretur meritum fidei, quia iam assentire his non esset voluntarium, sed necessarium" (In De trin., q. 2, a. 1, ad 5 [ed. Decker, 84 :7-10]). 25 Meta. VI, 1, 1026a 21-22. 26 Meta. XII, 7, 1072b 10-14. 27 Aristotle's divine being belongs to that Being which is a priori present in all genera (Meta. IV, 2, 1004a 4-5). According to J. Owens the divine being of the Aristotelian metaphysics is not an infinite being as is the God of Christian belief (see "The Relation of God to World in the 'Metaphysics,"' in P. Aubenque, ed., Etudes sur la Metaphysique d'Aristote. Actes du VI• Symposium Aristotelicum [Paris: Vrin, 1977], 213, 219-221. On this see also R Sokolowski, The God of Faith and Reason: Foundations of Christian Theology [Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1982], 12-20; "Creation and Christian Understanding," in D. B. Burrell and B. McGinn, eds., God and Creation: An Ecumenical Symposium [Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press], 1990, 179-196), RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN METAPHYSICS & THEOLOGY 195 " preamble of faith " which is proved in philosophy and necessarily presupposed in the science of faith. 28 Among Aquinas's different proofs for the existence of God in both of his Summae, the most important is the one based on the contingency of beings; this proof is important because of its inner connection with the center of Thomistic metaphysics, the thinking of the difference of existence ( esse) and essence ( essentia) that determines the whole of beings. This proof is also the authentic metaphysical proof for the existence of God, if Kant's thesis in his Critique of Pure Reason is correct, namely, that every metaphysical concept of God presupposes the concept of an ens necessarium.29 Admittedly, that concept appears as such first in the ontological proofs for the existence of God in the modern age; 30 and Aquinas does not understand God as causa sui. But Aquinas already refers to the divine being as that being which is necesse-esse 31 or, more precisely, per se necesse-esse.32 In this 28 Ad primum ergo dicendum quod Deum esse, et alia huismodi quae per rationem naturalem nota possunt esse de Deo, ut dicitur Rom. 1,19, non sunt articuli fidei, sed praeambula ad articulos (Sum. Theo. I, q. 2, a. 2, ad 1 [ed. Leonina IV, 30]) ; Primo ad demonstrandum ea quae sunt praeambula fidei, quae necesse est in fidei scire, ut ea quae naturalibus rationibus de Deo probantur, ut Deum esse, Deum unum, et alia huiusmodi vel de Dea vel de creaturis in philosophia probata, quae fides supponit (In De trin., q. 2, a. 3c [ed. Decker, 94 :27-95]). At the end of the methodological introduction to his Summa contra Gentiles, Aquinas even maintains that without the proof for the existence of God every consideration of divine things would be nullified and that therefore the proof is the necessary basis of that work. " Inter ea vero quae de Deo secundum seipsum consideranda sunt, praemittendum est, quasi totius operis necessarium fundamentum, consideratio qua demonstratur Deum esse. Quo non habito, omnis consideratio de rebus divinis tollitur" (I Cont. Gent., c. 9 [ed. Marietti, n. 58]). 29 Critique of Pure Reason, B 611-619. so See D. Henrich, Der ontologische Gottesbeweis: Sein Problem und seine Geschichte in der N euzeit, 2nd ed. (Tiibingen: Mohr, 1967) ; Proofs for Eternity, Creation and the Existence of God in Medieval Islamic and Jewish Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987), 378-406. 31 I Cant. Gent., c. 15 (ed. Marietti, n. 124). 32 II Cant. Gent., c. 15 (ed. Marietti, n. 927). Aquinas speaks also about a primum necessarium that is per se necessarium. See I Cont. Gent., c. 15 (ed. Marietti, n. 124); Sum. Theo. I, q. 2, a. 3c; tertia via (ed. Leonina IV, 31). 196 HELMUT HOPING Aquinas is following Avicenna,33 who seems to be the first in the history of philosophy for whom the necesse-esse per se, the later ens necessarium, becomes the substantial concept of the absolute. In Aquinas's S14mma contra Gentiles and his Summa theologiae we find three different versions of the proof for the existence of God based on the contingency of beings: I Cont. Gent., c.15, II Cont. Gent., c.15, Sum. theo. I, q. 2, a. 3 (tertia via). In all three versions there is a distinction drawn between things that are generated and corruptible and things that are not. Things falling under the latter category are the angels, the celestial bodies, and the human souls. They are necessary, but do not exist through themselves, so that they are in themselves contingent. The first and the third versions of the proof begin with things that are generated and corruptible. But the proof in its second version begins with beings that are possible considered in themselves and according to their existence or non-existence, i.e., contingent beings. The second version of the proof leads-just like the other versions of the proof-to something necessary that is the cause of the existence of all contingent beings. Yet the second version is closest to Avicenna's proof for the existence of God and shows that Aquinas's proof is in itself independent of its theological framework. According to Aquinas, in all contingent beings, their essence does not include their existence. The contingency of beings depends on the difference between ·existence and essence. Therefore it is not surprising that that difference itself is the starting-point for another proof for the existence of God. It is the proof (or, as 33 Meta. I 6-7, fol.73va-74ra (van Riet, 43 :2-55 :55) ; Meta. VIII 4-5, fol.98vb-99vb (van Riet, 397 :53-411 :48). See Thomas Aquinas, De pot., q. 5, a. 3c (ed. Marietti, 135: "Avicenna namque posuit [lib. VII Metaph., c.VI] quod quaelibet res praeter Deum habebat in se possibilitatem ad esse et non esse. Cum enim esse sit praeter essentiam cuiuslibet rei creatae, ipsa natura rei creatae per se considerata, possibilis est ad esse; necessitatem vero essendi non habet nisi ab alio, cuius natura est suum esse, et per consequens, est per se necesse esse ; et hoc Deus est." RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN METAPHYSICS & THEOLOGY 197 some would insist, the alleged proof) in De ente et essentia that leads Thomas directly to his actual metaphysical concept of God, the concept of ipsum esse subsist ens.34 This proof depends on a B4De ente, c. 4 (ed. Leonina XLIII, 376:127-377:146). On the systematic connection between the proof for the existence of God in De ente, c. 4 and the tertia via, see J. F. X. Knasas, "Making Sense of the Tertia Via," The New Scholasticism 54 (1980) : 489-511. Among Thomists there is a controversy as to whether or not De ente, c. 4 contains a proof for the existence of God. According to M. S. Gillet, De ente, c. 4 contains both the most direct and the soundest proof for the existence of God in Aquinas, one that has to be preferred to the proofs of the quinque viae (see Thomas d'Aquin [Paris: Dunod, 1949], 67-68). Besides Gillet, also F. van Steenberghen, J. Owens, and J. F. Wippel see in De ente c.4 a proof for the existence of God, yet van Steenberghen maintains that the proof for the existence of God in De ente, c. 4 is unsuccessful because it is based on an unsuccessful attempt to demonstrate a real distinction between existence and essence in finite beings. See F. van Steenberghen, "Le probleme de !'existence de Dieu clans le 'De ente et essentia' de Saint Thomas d'Aquin," in Melanges Joseph de Ghellinck, Vol. II: M oyen age. Epoques moderne et contemporaine (Louvain: Duculot, 1951), 837-847; J. Owens, An Elementary Christian Metaphysics (Milwaukee: University of St. Thomas, 1986), 80-81, 337-338; "Quiddity and Real Distinction in St. Thomas Aquinas," Mediaeval Studies 27 (1965): 17; J. F. Wippel, Metaphysical Themes in Thomas Aquinas (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1984), 107-132. By contrast, E. Gilson and A. Maurer deny that there is a proof for the existence of God in De ente, c. 4. See E. Gilson, "La preuve du 'De ente et essentia,'" Doctor Communis 3 (1950)) : 257-269; "Trois le<;ons sur le probleme de !'existence de Dieu," Divinitas 1 (1%1) : 6-8; A Maurer, Introduction to On Being and Essence, trans. A Maurer, 2nd. rev. ed. (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1968), 25-26. Their reason is that the argument of De ente, c. 4 appears neither in I Cont. Gent., c. 13 (ed. Marietti, nn. 81-115) nor in Sum. Theo. I, q. 2, a. 3c (ed. Leonina IV, 31-32). That reason is not entirely convincing. First of all, it rules out a development in Aquinas's attempts to prove the existence of God. Second, it does not recognize that the tertia via in the Summa theologiae and the corresponding versions of the proof in the Summa contra Gentiles presuppose a concept of the contingency of finite beings that cannot be thought without a difference between existence and essence in such beings, a difference that is more than merely conceptual. Admittedly, Owens denies that the proof for the existence of God in De ente, c. 4 presupposes a real distinction between existence and essence in finite beings. Yet Wippel disputes this interpretation of De ente, c.4 with convincing arguments (see Metaphysical Themes in Thomas Aquinas, 120-132). S. Macdonald also argues for a real distinction between existence and essence. See MacDonald, " The Esse/ 198 HELMUT HOPING logical and metaphysical argument for the difference between existence and essence in all finite beings. The logical argument is that the essence of any finite being can be understood without its existence because the essence can be considered absolute in itself. 35 The crucial metaphysical argument is that there can be no more than one being whose essence is Being itself, i.e., in which essence and existence are identical. This would be Being itself ( ipsum esse) or pure Being ( esse tantum) beyond all differences of genus, species, and individuals in which Being is multiplied. Being itself or pure Being would neither admit a multiplication through such differences nor could it be multiplied in itself, because such a multiplication would require something potential receiving Being which could only be a possible essence or form. Therefore in all beings apart from the assumed Being itself or pure Being, existence and essence must be different. 36 But in all finite beings Essentia Argument in Aquinas's De ente et essentia," J ourna:l of the History of Philosophy 22 (1984) : 157-172. Owens has repeated his position in "Aquinas' Distinction at De ente et essentia 4.119-123," Mediaeval Studies 48 (1986): 264-287. 35 Quicquid enim non est de intellectu essentiae vel quiditatis, hoc est adveniens extra et faciens compositionem cum essentia, quia nulla essentia sine his quae sunt partes essentiae intelligi potest. Omnis autem essentia vel quiditas potest intelligi sine hoc quad aliquid intelligatur de esse suo : possum enim intelligere quid est homo vel phoenix et tamen ignorare an esse habet in rerum natura; ergo patet quod esse est aliud ab essentia vel quiditate. N isi forte sit aliqua res cuius quiditas sit ipsum suum esse (De ente, c. 4 [ed. Leonina XL III, 376 :94-104]). 36 ••• et haec res non potest esse nisi una et prima: quia impossibile est ut fiat plurificatio alicuius nisi per additionem alicuius differentiae, sicut multiplicatur natura generis in species ; vel per hoc quod forma recipitur in diversis materiis, sicut multiplicatur natura speciei in diversis individuis ; vel per hoc quod unum est absolutum et aliud in aliquo receptum, sicut si esset quidam calor separatus esset alius a calore non separato ex ipsa sua separatione. Si autem ponatur aliqua res quae sit esse tantum ita ut ipsum esse sit subsistens, hoc esse non recipiet additionem differentiae, quia iam non esset esse tantum sed esse et praeter hoc forma aliqua; et multo minus reciperet additionem materiae, quia iam esset esse non subsistens sed materiale. Unde relinquitur quod talis res quae sit suum esse non potest esse nisi una; unde oportet quod in qualibet alia re praeter earn aliud sit esse suum et aliud quiditas vel natura seu forma sua; unde oportet quod in intelligentiis sit esse praeter formam, et RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN METAPHYSICS & THEOLOGY 199 their existence cannot be caused by their own essence or quiddity or form-otherwise they must be their own cause, which is impossible.37 Therefore their existence must be traced back to a primum ens that is the cause of existence (cause essendi) : pure Being ( tantum esse), 38 Being itself ( ipsum esse), 39 or more precisely that being which exists as Being itself ( ipsum esse subsistens) .40 With the difference between existence and essence and the two above-mentioned proofs for the existence of God in Aquinas, metaphysics reaches an understanding of the difference of Being that is unknown in Aristotle's metaphysics. 41 For Aristotle's ideo dictum est quod intelligentia est forma et esse (De ente, c. 4 [ed. Leonina XLIII, 376 :104-377:126]). For the correct understanding of the different arguments, see Wippel, Metaphysical Themes in Thomas Aquinas, 129-132. 87 Omne autem quod convenit alicui vel est causatum ex principiis naturae suae, sicut risibile in homine vel advenit ab aliquo principio extrinseco, sicut lumen in aere ex influentia solis. Non autem potest esse quod ipsum esse sit causatum ab ipsa forma vel quiditate rei, dico sicut a causa efficiente, quia sic aliqua res esset sui ipsius causa et aliqua res se ipsam in esse produceret : quod est impossibile (De ente, c.4 [ed. Leonina XLIII, 377 :127-135]). ss De ente, c. 4 (ed. Leonina XLIII, 377: 145). 39 De ente, c. 4 (ed. Leonina XLIII, 376 :104)). 40 Ergo oportet quod omnis talis res cuius esse est aliud quam natura sua habeat esse ab alio. Et quia omne quod est per aliud reducitur ad id quod est per se sicut ad causam primam, oportet quod sit aliqua res quae sit causa essendi omnibus rebus eo quod ipsa est esse tantum; alias iretur in infinitum in causis, cum omnis res quae non est esse tantum habeat causam sui esse, ut dictum est. Patet quod intelligentia est forma et esse, et quod esse habet a primo ente quod est esse tantum, et hoc est causa prima quae Deus est (De ente, c. 4 [ed. Leonina XLIII, 377 :135-146]; see De ente, c. 4 [ed. Leonina XLIII, 377:115]). 41 According to D. Henrich this applies to the whole of Greek philosophy (see Der ontologische Gottesbeweis, 264). Henrich labels the difference between existence (esse) and essence (essentia) an "ontological difference." But that difference is not simply identical with Heidegger's "ontological difference." When Heidegger speaks about the " ontological difference," he means the difference of Being itself as Ereignis. Yet according to Heidegger the distinction between existence and essence in all finite beings leads to the thinking of the "ontological difference"; it touches upon that difference. See The Basic Problems of Phenomenology [Grundprobleme der Phiinomenologie, 1975], A. Hofstadter, trans. (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1988), 78, 120. 200 HELMUT HOPING question of Being 42 inquires about substance as the "first cause of being"; 43 but Aristotle does not ask what it means for something to be a being at all. Yet if human reason gained something by thinking of the difference between existence and essence, it cannot stop there. Human reason must transcend the whole of beings towards something beyond itself, which Aquinas sometimes calls absolute Being ( esse absolutum) or infinite Being ( esse infinitum )-as distinguished from beings whose existence is limited through their essence. 44 Now Aquinas's understanding of the difference of Being effectively deals with the whole of beings in relation to the God of Jewish-Christian monotheism. The difference of Being is understood on the basis of the difference between the one God and the world as His creation, 45 a difference that we can call the "theological difference." Yet Aquinas's above-mentioned proofs for the existence of God do not in themselves lead to the God of JewishChristian monotheism. Neither proof can give an answer to the question of how necessary Being or pure Being has to be thought in itself and in its relation to the whole of beings. In order to answer this question, both concepts would have to be determined not only in contradistinction to contingent beings but in an actual definition. But this is impossible, not only according to Kant but also according to Aquinas. 46 Instead, Aquinas starts by identifying the highest object of metaphysics with the God of Jewish-Christian monotheism. The crucial argument for that identity is meant to show that we have 42" In short, the question that has always been asked and is still being asked today, the ever-puzzling question 'What is being? ' amounts to this : ' What is primary being?"' (Meta. VII, 1, 1028b 2-4, Richard Hope, trans. [Ann Arbor, Mich.: University of Michigan Press, 1960], 131). 43 Meta. VII, 17, 1041b 27-28. 44 See In I Sent., d. 8, q. 5, a. 1, sol. (ed. Mandonnet, 226-227); In I Sent., d. 43, q. 1, a. 1, sol. (ed. Mandonnet, 1003). 4 5 See I Cont. Gent., cc. 23-24 (ed. Marietti, nn. 981-1008). 46 See Exp. Peri herm. I, 14 (ed. Leonina I*l, 73-74). According to Aquinas, we have no comprehensive and defining knowledge of God. For more on this, see Wippel, Metaphysical Themes in Thomas Aquinas, 215-241. RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN METAl>HYSICS & THEOLOGY 201 to ascribe all perfections found in the whole of beings to its origin. The basis of that argument is Aquinas's application of the Aristotelian omne agens agit sibi simile to the origin of the whole of beings. That principle leads Aquinas to extend his metaphysics of the one God and His creation beyond the concept of the ipsum esse subsistens. And it is that extension which determines Aquinas's authentic view of the relationship between metaphysics and theology. Thus what is proved in philosophy and what must be presupposed by the science of faith is the existence of that God who is one, 47 having intellect,48 will,49 and free choice,50 and who is the creator of all things. 51 The God of the " I am "-at least with regard to truths of the praeambula fidei-is a common object of metaphysics and of the theology of Sacred Scripture. 52 Yet the crucial argument leading to Aquinas's metaphysics of God and creation does not have the same cogency as the abovementioned proofs for a divine being beyond the whole of beings. Of course certain perfections are to be ascribed to the divine being, first of all the perfection of Being, which according to Aquinas is the first non-univocal analogical name. 58 But it is not at all conclusive that the origin of everything is individuated by 47 Sum. Theo. I, q. 11, a. 3c (ed. Leonina IV, 111). 4BSum. Theo. I, q. 14, aa. 1-4 (ed. Leonina IV, 166-172). 49 Sum. Theo. I, q. 19, a. 1 (ed. Leonina IV, 231). 50 Sum. Theo. I, q. 19, a. 10 (ed. Leonina IV, 248). 5 1 See In De trin., q. 2, a. 3c (ed. Decker, 94:27-95 :7), where Aquinas distinguishes between a threefold use of philosophy in the theology which is different from metaphysics : " Sic ergo in sacra doctrina philosophia possumus tripliciter uti. Primo ad demonstrandum ea quae sunt praeambula fidei; quae necesse est in fidei scire, ut ea quae naturalibus rationibus de Deo probantur, ut Deum esse, Deum esse unum et alia huismodi vel de Deo vel de creaturis in philosophia probata, quae fides supponit. Secundo ad notificandum per aliquas similitudines ea quae sunt fidei, sicut Augustinus in libro De trinitate utitur multis similitudinibus ex doctrinis philosophicis sumptis ad manifestandum trinitatem. Tertio ad resistendum his quae contra fidem dicuntur sive ostendendo ea esse falsa sive ostendendo ea non esse necessaria." 52 Sum. Theo. I, q. 13, a. 11 (ed. Leonina IV, 162). 53 Sum. Theo. I, q. 13, a. 5, ad 1 (ed. Leonina IV, 147) : "in praedicationibus omnia univoca reducuntur ad unum primum, non univocum, sed analogicum, quod est ens." 202 HELMUT HOPING itself 54 and has to be thought as the one God with the whole of beings as His creation. The " theological difference " of Aquinas's metaphysics is a distinction that belongs to Christian belief.55 Aquinas's crucial argument for the identity of the highest object of metaphysics and the God of Jewish-Christian monotheism is at most an argument of probability. But if the God of Jewish-Christian monotheism cannot be a common object of metaphysics and theology, then their relationship cannot be determined the way Aquinas determines it, namely, through his twofold notion of theology. At the same time, however, there can be no alternative to Aquinas's understanding of metaphysics and theology as different sciences that both constitute wisdom and deal with the origin of everything. For it is impossible to return to the patristic view that the sapientia christiana is a higher form of philosophy. 56 II. Critique of Metaphysics: Transcendental (Kant) Difference Kant's critique of metaphysics is not directed against metaphysics at all. Yet this critique asks about the possibility of metaphysics in general. In this sense, the Critique of Pure Reason is a theory of metaphysical knowledge. Kant can therefore call it the " metaphysics of metaphysics." 57 The basis of this " metaphysics of metaphysics " is a " revolution in thinking " that gives human self-referentiality a priority that had never been acknowledged before. Thus Kant's transcendental philosophy is based on a strong philosophical notion of self-consciousness, or the notion of trans4De ente, c. 5 (ed. Leonina XLIII, 378:21-24); Sum. Theo. I, q. 3, a. 3c (ed. Leonina IV, 39-40); Sum. Theo. I, q. 13, a. 11, ad 1 (ed. Leonina IV, 162). 55 For more on this, see R. Sokolowski, The God of Faith and Reason, 2130, 41-52; "Creation and Christian Understanding," 181-184, 188-190. 56 For the patristic view, see An Early Christian Philosopher: Justin Martyr's Dialogue with Trypho, Chapters One to Nine, Introduction, Text, and Commentary by J. C. M. van Winden (Leiden: Brill, 1977). 57 Letter to Marcus Herz from May 11th 1781, in Kant's Gesammelte Schriften, ed. Prussian Academy of Sciences ( = Acad.), (Berlin: W. de Gruyter, 1902-), Vol. X, 269. 5 RELATIONSHIP :M:ETAPHY'SlCS & THEOLOGY 203 cendental apperception, 58 from which empirical apperception is distinguished. 59 This distinction makes it clear that for Kant selfconsciousness is not merely a psychological problem. 60 The word " I " stands for a self-relation that goes beyond the self-relation of a merely empirical and sensible self-possession. The transcendental unity of self-consciousness in the " I think " is the ground of the possibility that something can be thought and known by me as an object. Any relatedness to an object is nothing other than the "correlate of the unity of apperception." 61 But since this in itself reveals no object, the subject of transcendental apperception, though unconditioned, cannot be an absolute subject. The knowing subject is a subject of facticity. The facticity of transcendental subjectivity is expressed in various places. In his Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics, Kant refers to transcendental apperception as a " feeling of existence " that is " without the slightest concept" and that is merely a " representation of that to which all thinking stands in relation." 62 In his Critique of Pure Reason, he refers to transcendental apperception as the act of determining one's own existence.68 " Existence is already given thereby, but the mode in which I am to determine this existence, that is, the manifold belonging to it, is not thereby given." 64 Kant sees in transcendental apperception something quite real. 65 Yet the subject of this consciousness is not empirical. 66 On the contrary, it is essential : " in the consciousness of myself in mere thought I am being itself." 61 58 See Critique of Pure Reason, B 133a. 59 See Critique of Pure Reason, B 132. 6 0 See R.-P. Horstmann, "Gibt es ein philosophisches Problem des Selbstbewusstsein? " in Theorie der Subjektivitiit, 228-231. 61 See Critique of Pure Reason, A 250. 62 Prolegomena, Acad., Vol. IV, 334a. 68 See Critique of Pure Reason, B 158a. 6 4 Ibid. 65 See Critique of Pure Reason, B 419-420. 66 See Critique of Pure Reason, B 158. 61 Critique of Pure Reason, B 429. Therefore transcendental apperception is not merely a principle of transcendental analysis. See D. Henrich, Identitiit und Objektivitiit: Eine Untersuchung iiber Kants transzendentale Deduktion (Heidelberg: C. Winter, 1976), 83, 111. 204 HELMUT HOPINC Even if transcendental apperception is in itself a consciousness of existence, Being cannot coincide with empirical Being. There must then be two different kinds of Being, namely the Being of the " I " and the Being of the things within the world. Only this transcendental difference of Being makes it possible for the critique to take the object " in a twofold sense, namely as appearence and as thing itself." 68 But how are we to understand this difference of Being in relation to Kant's well-known thesis concerning Being? According to this thesis, stated in Kant's refutation of the ontological proof for the existence of God, 69 Being is not a real predicate, but rather the positing of a thing as itself. This simply means that Being is not something that can be predicated of something else. Being, of course, can be used as a logical predicate, but Being cannot occur in a judgment as a determination of the subject of the sentence. If Being does not simply mean the logical relation between the subject of the sentence and the predicate in judgment, then Being means the same thing as existence, and precisely as the positing ( S etzung) of something, not only relatively but in itself, absolutely, 70 a positing that Kant therefore calls absolute. 71 The sentence " God is " is used in this sense. But what does "absolute positing" mean with regard to the meaning of Being? In the context of his refutation of the ontological proof for the existence of God, Kant does not provide an answer. 72 But the Critique of Pure Reason, B XXVII. Critique of Pure Reason, B 620-630. For arguments similar to Kant's thesis concerning Being from the Critique of Pure Reason, see the first section of The Only Possible Argument for a Demonstration of God's E:ristence from 1763 (Acad., Vol. II, 70-92) and the Essay concerning Being (=Essay) from the Herder-estate, which is probably related to Kant's lecture on metaphysics (Acad., Vol. XXVIII/2.1, 949-961). See G. Lehmann, "Einleitung," in Acad., Vol. XXVIII/2.2, 1353. 70 Through the "it is," I think something as "given absolutely" (Critique of Pure Reason, B 627). 71 The Only Possible Argument, Acad., Vol. II, 73. 12 Also, in the The Only Possible Argitment Kant fails to say what "absolute positing " means. 6s 69 See RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN METAPHYSICS & THEOLOGY 205 " transcendental deduction of the pure concepts " does help here. It labels the " is " of an existential proposition as that which is represented in the " objective unity of apperception." 73 Since transcendental apperception is the possibility of all thought and knowledge, Being here cannot simply mean the logical relation within judgment, but rather must have the meaning of existence. According to the central theoretical part of Kant's philosophy, Being as absolute positing (existence, e:risten'tia) has its place in the transcendental unity of self-consciousness-but that means in thinking. So Kant's thesis concerning Being becomes a thesis about the relationship of Being and thinking. 74 If Being and thinking belong together, Being cannot be a matter of something that can be absolute, according to the original sense of the word. When Kant speaks of Being as absolute positing, he uses " absolute" in the sense of " unconditional " and he means by this that something is posited in itself and for itself in its existence. But what is posited in this way through transcendental apperception is the empirical existence of things of the world. But how are we to think of the existence of the " I " itself in relation to Kant's thesis concerning Being? To give an answer to this we must return to the refutation of the ontological proof for the existence of God. What is important for this refutation is not-as is often assumed-the logical argument according to which the conclusion from the concept of an ens realissimum to its e:ristence constitutes a metabasis eis allo gen:os [change into another genus]. This argument ultimately plays, like the empirical argument, only a subordinate role. In its main point, Kant's critique of the ontological proof for the existence of God is reducible to the objection that the metaphysical concept of an ens necessarium cannot be thought in a determinate manner and is thus contradictory as a concept in an actual definition. 75 According to the only possible 73 Critique of Pure Reason, B 141. See M. Heidegger, Kants These uber das Sein (Frankfurt am Main: V. Klostermann, 1963), 17-32. 75 See D. Henrich, Der ontologische Gottesbeweis, 137-188. 74 206 HELMUT HOPING verbal definition, an ens necessarium is something whose nonbeing is impossible.76 But it cannot be shown that the concept of an ens necessarium is identical with the concept of a highest divine being, which is like an individual, i.e., the ens realissimum of Kant's transcendental ideal. Now all existence that is known by us, including our own existence, is in itself contingent. This is shown by the possibility that such existence can be conceived as negated without contradiction. In the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant labels such a negation " transcendental negation " in opposition to mere " logical negation. " 77 Since all existence that is known by us is contingent, it is a natural process for our reason to seek the ground of all that exists in a being that is necessary in all respects. Although the thought of such a being represents an abyss of human reason, 78 it is nevertheless a limiting concept for reason that can be avoided only when thought is broken off in an arbitrary manner. And the concept of an ens necessarium-as a limiting concept-can be thought without contradiction. For acc?rding to Kant, there is "a difference between assuming the necessary being with a view to an other, and knowing a being through its concept as necessary." 79 But "we must regard what is absolutely necessary as being outside the world." 80 The opposite of the negation of Being in the transcendental or absolute negation is the " transcendental affirmation " 81 or the absolute positing of Being. 82 But the absolute positing of Beingjust like the absolute negation of Being-is possible only in thought which always already presupposes itself.83 Now Kant 76 Critique of Pure Reason, B 620. 77 See Critique of Pure Reason, B 602-603. The Essay refers to it as " absolute negation" (Acad., Vol. XXVIII/2.1, 955). 78 See Critique of Pure ReaSO'n, B 641; Metaphysics KS, in Acad., Vol. XXVIII/2.1, 784. . 1 9 Reflection 5783, in Acad., Vol. XIX, 354. 80 Critique of Pure Reason, B 645. 81 See Critique of Pure Reason, B 602. 5 2 Essay, in Acad., Vol. XXVIII/2.1, 955. 83 Being therefore, according to the Essay, " is the foundation of all our thinking and the element by which we are filled" (Acad., Vol. XXVIII/2.1, 956). RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN METAPHYSICS & THEOLOGY 207 argues in the Critique of Pure Reason that a being that is thought only through the concept of existence does not differ from a merely possible being, and thus that objects of pure thinking cannot be known in their Being. 84 Yet transcendental apperception is not an object of thinking, but rather the thinking in itself. Kant therefore can say without contradiction that in transcendental apperception I am aware " that I am " 85 and can understand that as a consciousness of existence. The transcendental difference of Being is thus not incompatible with Kant's thesis concerning Being. With regard to objects (things) of thinking, the consciousness of existence belongs without doubt " exclusively to the unity of experience." 86 But the unity of experience itself is established through transcendental apperception in which an "I" is distinguished from all possible objects within the world. Only in the horizon of this transcendental difference can it be said that something " is." Kant's refutation of the ontological proof for the existence of God and his thesis concerning Being show that that which comprehends both the " I" and all objects of the world must be conceived as the in-itself-unknown One that lies beyond all differences, the authentic absolute. Yet the absolute that lies beyond the transcendental difference cannot merely be a regulative ideaotherwise the truth of the transcendental difference itself would be a delusion. But this is the insight of a thinking that Henrich called the " third reflectedness " ( dritte Refiektiertheit). 81 In the irrefutable metaphysical "rising above" (Oberstieg) 88 beyond the " I " and the things within the world we are certain of the absolute in its existence, even though its essence remains concealed from us. 84 See Critique of Pure Reason, B 629. Critique of Pure Reason, B 157. Critique of Pure Reason, B 629. 8 7 D. Henrich, Fluchtlinien: Philosophische Essays (Frankfurt Suhrkamp, 1982), 51. 88 Ibid., 17-18. 85 86 am Main: 208 HELMUT HOPING III. Return to the Ground of Metaphysics : Ontological Difference (Heidegger) Reflections on the transcendental difference of Being have not yet brought us to an understanding of Being itself in the identity of Being and thinking. To achieve this, it is necessary to consider Heidegger's "step back" into the essence of metaphysics. 89 Systematically viewed, this " step back" is that transcendence that leads to the " essential origin of identity " 90 to which both Being and thinking belong and that Heidegger calls Ereignis. Ereignis here has to be understood as a singulare tantum. It is not an occurrence within the world, but rather the basic happening of Being as Ereignis. 91 According to Heidegger, Ereignis refers to the task that remains for thought after the end of onto-theology: This is the task of thinking Being out of difference and as difference. 92 The term " onto-theology " first turns up in Kant and means theology based on the ontological proof for the existence of God. 93 Heidegger uses the term "onto-theology" in a wider sense to signify the basic constitution of Western metaphysics up until Hegel, which is, as the science of being, simultaneously a science of God as the cause of all beings different from Him. Even though Heidegger's critique of Wes tern metaphysics and his thesis concerning its "forgetfulness of Being" does not do justice to the history of metaphysics, the characteristic of Western metaphysics as may be irrefutable-at least since Aristotle's metaphysics. 94 89 Identity and Difference [ldentitiit und Differenz, 1957], J. Stambaugh, trans. (New York: Harper & Row, 1969), 50-51. In the following quotations from the translated work of Heidegger I have slightly altered the translations in part. The German words Ereignis and Dasein remain untranslated because there are no adequate words in the English language. 90 Identity and Difference, 39. 91 See On Time and Being [Zur Sache des Denkens, 1969], J. Stambaugh, trans. (New York: Harper & Row, 1972), 19-21. 92 See Identity and Difference, 61-65. 93 Critique of Pitre Reason, B 660. 94 See G. Picht's informative remarks on the concept of the absolute in Plato and Aristotle in Aristoteles "De anima" (Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta, 1987), 4786. According to Picht, metaphysics has had an onto-theological character from the time of Aristotle onward. BETWEEN :METAPHYSICS & THEOLOGY 209 Heidegger's thinking of Being is not a move away from metaphysics. Admittedly after the "turn," Heidegger does reject concepts such as " metaphysics " and " philosophy " ; but thinking should not simply be identified with philosophy. 95 Heidegger seeks to overcome onto-theological metaphysics in a new thinking. Therefore his statements about the " end of metaphysics " 96 are far more nuanced than is often assumed. Heidegger is not of the opinion that metaphysics is at the "end" at all. 97 Heidegger's thinking about Being seeks "to save metaphysics in its essence." 98 Therefore Heidegger's thesis about the "end" of metaphysics is not incompatible with his earlier claim " that philosophy ultimately cannot do without its genuine optics-metaphysics." 99 If one does not restrict the notions of metaphysics and philosophy to the Western tradition of thinking up until Hegel-and there seems to be no reason why such a restriction is obligatory-then one can apprehend Heidegger's thinking of Being itself as a crucial contribution to a changed metaphysical form of thinking. 100 With Being as Ereignis Heidegger thinks his only thought. 101 9 5 See Letter on Humanism [Brief iiber den Humanismus, 1947], trans. F. A. Capuzzi in collaboration with J. G. Gray and D. F. Krell, in M. Heidegger, Basic Writings, ed. D. F. Krell (San Francisco: Harper, 1977), 236-242; On Time and Being, 55-73. 96 Nietzsche, Vol. IV: Nihilism [Nietzsche II, 1961], F. A. Capuzzi, trans. (San Francisco: Harper & Row, 1982), 147-149. 97 Already in Being and Time the postulated "destruction" of metaphysics is meant to be at the same time a " construction " as the " positive acquisition of the past " so that it might be brought into the " full possession of the most characteristic possibilities of questioning" (Being and Time [Sein und Zeit, 1927], J. Macquarrie and E. Robinson, trans. [New York: Harper & Row, 1962], 41-42). 98 The Question of Being [Zur Seinsfrage, 1956], W. Kluback and J. T. Wilde, trans. (New York: Twayne, 1958), 93. 99 Die Kategorien- und Bedeutungslehre des Duns Scotus (Tiibingen: Mohr, 1916), 235. L. Oeing-Hanhoff holds a different position in this issue. See "Metaphysik," in Historisches Worterbuch der Philosophie, Vol. 5, 1269-1270. 100 See R. Maurer, " Thesen zu: Heidegger und die Metaphysik," in Metaphysics of physis " ( 46-49). io1 See 0. Poggeler, "Sein als Ereignis," in Heidegger und die hermeneutische Philosophie (Freiburg-Munich: Alber, 1983), 118. 210 HELMUT HOPING This thought concerns nothing other than the difference of Being itself, a difference that Heidegger calls the " ontological difference." It is the foundation of every difference in the realm of being, including the difference between myself and all the things within the world. According to Heidegger, this difference is the difference between the Dasein of man and all beings whose beingness is mere existence in the sense of being-available. Heidegger's Dasein and the " I" of Kant's transcendental apperception are not simply the same. But both describe a being that in its Being is substantially different from the Being of the things within the world. The Being of the ontological difference is not something " being-like"; it " is," but not in the way a being " is." Being goes beyond all beings. Similarly, the Being of the ontological difference is not the Being of God. Heidegger says explicitly: "Being -is not God," 102 because Being " is in essence finite." 103 The Being of the ontological difference is the prevailing difference of Being itself, within which the being-understanding Dasein of man emerges. So Being-that with which all philosophy must begin according to Hegel 1° 4-amounts to a quite simply unavailable W egmarken (Frankfurt am Main: V. Klostermann, 1967), 162. What is Metaphysics? [Was ist Metaphysik?, 1929], D. F. Krell, trans., in Basic Writings, 110. The Being of the ontological difference is not the ipsum esse subsistens of Aquinas's metaphysics. According to M. Muller (see E:ristenzphilosophie: Von der M etaph}1sik zur M etahistorik, 4th ed. [Freiburg-Munich: Alber, 1986], 87) the Being of the ontological difference resembles the actualitas omnium rerum (see Sum. Theo. I, q. 4, a. 1, ad 3 [ed. Leonina IV, 50]). On the relationship between Heidegger's thinking of Being and Aquinas's metaphysics of being, see T. Prufer, "Heidegger, Early and Late, and Aquinas," in R Sokolowski, ed., Edmund Husserl and the Phenomenological Tradition: Essays in Phenomenology, Studies in Philosophy and the History of Philosophy, Vol. 18 (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1988), 197-215. Like Muller, Prufer compares the Being of Heidegger's ontological difference with Aquinas's esse commune, which is not self-sufficient-unlike the ipsitm esse subsistens of God in Aquinas's metaphysics of creation (212). 104 See the Introduction to Wissenschaft der Logik, Erster Band: Die objektive Logik (1812/1813), F. Hagemann and W. Jaeschke, eds., Gesammelte Werke, vol. 11 (Hamburg: Meiner, 1978), 15-29. 102 1o 3 RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN METAPHYSICS & THEOLOGY 211 ground that is presupposed in all thinking, even in speculative thinking. 105 Because Being itself is finite according to its very essence, Being and nothingness belong together. Therefore one can ask: " Why are there beings at all, and not rather nothingness? " 106 The primeval ground of everything must lie beyond the Being of the ontological difference, and that means beyond time. 107 Yet, as such a ground, it is to be understood as the nameless abyss of Being. 108 This is the real reason why " the onto-theological character of metaphysics has become questionable for thinking." 10 g Heidegger's philosophy is not a philosophy against God. Admittedly, this thinking stands before a decision on theism; yet this is " not because of any indifferent attitude, but rather out of respect for the limits that have been set upon thinking as thinking, and indeed through that which gives itself to us as that which has-to-be-thought, i.e., through the truth of Being." 110 Hence it is understandable that Heidegger prefers " to keep silence about God in the realm of thinking." m Yet Heidegger is convinced that his " god-less thinking giving up " the God of philosOn Time and Being, 49-50. What is Metaphysics?, 112. 107 See On Time and Being, 19. ms According to an announcement to M. Miiller, Heidegger in his first drawing up of the third section of Part One of Being and Time wanted to articulate a threefold difference: " the ' transcendental ' or ontological difference in the narrow sense : the distinction of the being from its beingness; b) the ' transcendent-like ' or ontological difference in the wider sense: the distinction of the being and its beingness from Being itself; c) the 'transcendent ' or theological difference in the strict sense: the distinction of God from the being, from beingness and from Being" (Existenzphilosophie, 86). But Heidegger abandons this as still onto-theological because a theological difference, which remains a possibility and task after the " end " of Western metaphysics, is not experienced in thinking. The unfinished third section of Part One of Being and Time was to have been titled " Time and Being " and might have accomplished the so-called "turn," which was brought about in Heidegger's later essay On the Essence of Truth [Vom Wesen der Wahrheit, 1943], J. Sallis, trans., in Basic Writings, 117-141. 109 Identity und Difference, 55. 110 Letter on Humanism, 230. lll Jdentity and Difference, SS, 105 See 106 212 HELMUT HOPING ophy "-is perhaps closer to the " divine God " and is perhaps "more free for him, than onto-theo-logy might want to admit." 112 Heidegger's thinking about Being claims rather to think in that dimension within which alone we today can ask meaningfully about God.113 " Only from the truth of Being can the essence of the holy be thought. Only from the essence of the holy can the essence of divinity be thought. Only in light of the essence of divinity can we think and speak about what the word ' God ' is to signify." 114 After the end of onto-theology, the question about " God " can be no longer be pursued on old paths. We must achieve a new understanding of what is brought up in the question of God.115 Thus according to Heidegger, we have to return to the genuine "matter of thinking, whose revealedness remains a mystery." 116 Even though onto-theology has become questionable for thinking, there remains for thought the very task that, according to 11 2 Ibid., 72. According to Pannenberg, Heidegger claims that Christian theology after the end of onto-theo-logy can no longer be the "science of God" (see Metaphysics and the Idea of God, P. Clayton, trans. [Grand Rapids: W. B. Eerdmans, 1990], 8-10) . In making this claim, Pannenberg refers to Heidegger's treatise on the onto-theological basic constitution of Western metaphysics (in Identity and Difference) and the treatise Phenomenology and Theology [Phiinomenologie und Theologie, 1970]. Yet I think that neither the theology in Phenomelogy and Theology nor the critique of the onto-theological metaphysics in Identity and Difference can support this thesis. Of course Heidegger's statement, "Theology is not speculative knowledge of God" (Theology and Phenomenology, in The Piety of Thinking: Essays by Martin Heidegger, J. G. Hart and J. C. Maraldo, trans. [Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1976], 15), is not without problems. But if Heidegger understands theology as reflection on Christian belief, then he recognizes that, according to Christian belief, the cross and resurrection go ahead of this belief as its object and foundation (see Phenomenology and Theology, 8-11). When Heidegger speaks in Identity and Difference about god-less thinking, he is refering to philosophy not to theology. 11 3 See Letter on Humanism, 230; The Essence of Reasons [Vom Wesen des Grundes, 1929], T. Malick, trans. (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1969), 91, note. 1 14 Ibid. See also Metaphysische Anfangsgrunde der Logik im Ausgang von Leibniz, Gesamtausgabe, vol. 26 (Frankfurt am Main: V. Klostermann, 1978), 211, n. 3. 115 See Letter on Humanism, 492. 11 6 On Time and Being, 82. RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN ME'l'Al'E:YSICS & THEOLOGY 213 Plato, is the purpose of philosophy: Philosophy is a sea-journey in search of ground 117 and leads to the absolute, the origin of everything. 118 Admittedly, Heidegger's thinking about Being includes the thought of the absolute in the thought of the abyss-like ground of Being. Yet in Heidegger's thinking about the Ereignis of Being as the essential origin of that identity within which Being and thinking belong together, Being will be returned to its finitude. 119 " What remains to be said? Only this : Ereignis occurs. In saying this, we say the Same in terms of the Same about the Same." 120 But the ontological difference itself cannot be the concluding thought of thinking. 121 Beyond it, the thought of the absolute is inevitable if we want to understand subjectivity in the Dasein of man. Although man belongs to the Ereignis of Being, he emerges therein as subject. Yet in his position as subject, he rises above Ereignis. Heidegger's critique of the modern philosophy of subjectivity leads him in his later thinking to dissolve human subjectivity in the truth of that very Being that has been returned to its finitude. 122 But the identity in which Being and See Phaedo 99D. Politics SllA. Plato's "absolute" might be seen as the idea of the good beyond being. See Politics 509B. 119 See On Time and Being, 49, 54. 120 Ibid., 24. 121 Pannenberg is right to recognize here the limit of Heidegger's thinking of Being. See Metaphysics and the Idea of God, 17-18. 122 See W. Marx, Is There a Measure on Earth? Foundations for a Nonmetaphysical Ethics, T. ]. Nenon and R. Lilly, trans. (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1977), 34-39, 126-146; H. Ebeling, Das Verhiingnis: Erste Philosophie (Freiburg-Munich: Alber, 1987), 21, 31-34; "Das Subjekt im Dasein. Versuch iiber CAUS:!t 273 be able to identify with God. The argument thus fails of its purpose. If the argument is not to fail of its purpose, the possibility of there being more than one uncaused cause, and of the uncaused causes belonging to the natural world, must be ruled out. i) Immateriality of uncaused causes I take it that the "natural world " means the physical world, the physical universe. Contemporary science ascribes causal liabilities of some sort or other to all physical things. By " causal liability " I mean a propensity to be causally affected in one way or another. For instance, anything that has mass has the power to affect causally other things with mass-by attracting themand has the liability to be causally affected by them in turn. Another example would be things with a positive electric charge. Having positive electric charge means that other things with positive charge have the power of repelling you, and things with negative charge have the power of attracting you. If we accept that all physical things are capable of being causally affected in some way, we must also accept that an uncaused cause is not physical. For an uncaused cause is by its nature incapable of being causally affected in any way. And the statements of contemporary scientific theories are not the only grounds for holding that all physical things are capable of being causally affected. It seems conceptually necessary that physical things have causal liabilities of some sort-it is impossible that they be without them. Not just contemporary scientific theories, therefore, but any scientific theory that could ever be thought adequate is going to ascribe causal liabilities to physical things. 11 11 Someone might object to the conclusion that uncaused causes cannot be physical on the grounds that science postulates physical events that cause but are not caused; the decay of an atom of a radioactive isotope is not caused, though it conforms to certain probabilistic laws. However, it is wrong to describe these events as being incapable of being causally affected in any way, and thus wrong to describe them as uncaused causes. The decay of an atom of uranium 235 at a particular time t depends on the existence of that atom. It could be prevented, through the destruction of the atom before t. It is thus 274 JOHN R. T. LAMONT If we accept the first and third ways, we will have two more arguments for believing the uncaused cause to be immaterial. Physical things are essentially subject to change. Even if they do not actually change, it is always possible for them to do so. An unchanged changer is essentially incapable of change, so the unchanged changer cannot be physical. Physical things are also essentially contingent. The necessary cause of all non-necessary things, which cannot be contingent, thus cannot be physical. ii) Number of uncaused causes Even if uncaused causes cannot be part of the natural world, why may there not be more than one of them? A case can be made for believing that there is only one uncaused cause, in this fashion: -We know that there is at least one uncaused cause. In the absence of any evidence to the contrary, we ought to believe that there is no more than one uncaused cause, because that is the simplest available hypothesis. -We cannot have any evidence in favor of there being more than one uncaused cause. An effect has several causes when ( i) there is no one thing that has brought it about, and (ii) there are several different things, each of which contributed to its happening, none of which is sufficient by itself for its happening, and all of which together have brought it about. There are two different ways in which several things can combine to cause an effect. Each of the things can be a partial cause of the effect, in the sense that each one of them is in certain circumstances necessary for any part of the effect's happening. Without every one of the partial causes the effect will not happen at all, so none of the partial causes is sufficient for the effect. An example would be the different items loaded on a camel's back. Suppose a number of items are loaded on to a camel's back; not immune to any causal influences. However, the uncaused cause established by Aquinas's argument must be immune to any causal influences; so the decay of a radioactive atom cannot be an uncaused cause of that sort. AN ARGUMENT FOR AN UNCAUSED CAUSE 275 when the last item, a straw, is loaded on, the camel's back breaks. None of the items by itself is enough to cause the camel's back to break. All of the items together are needed to break the backif only part of them, and not all of them, had been loaded on, the back would not have broken. Each item makes its contribution to breaking the camel's back, though, and all of them together are enough to cause the back to break. Call these partial causes " partial 1 causes." Another sort of partial cause is a cause that brings about part, but not all, of the effect. If it were not there, a part of the effect would not have occurred, but the other parts would still have taken place. An example would be a single bomber plane that took part in the destruction of Hamburg in 1943. If that plane had been missing, a part of the destruction caused by the bomber force as a whole-the part caused by that plane's bombs-would not have occurred. This sort of partial cause is a full cause of part of an effect. We can call these partial causes "partial 2 causes." The way to determine whether an effect has several causes in either sense, and not just one cause, is by using Mill's methods. Mill's method of difference is used to determine if a factor is a sufficient cause of an effect. If something is the sufficient cause of the whole of an effect, it is the full cause of that effect. The method of difference involves taking a situation where an effect is present and comparing it to situations where the effect is absent. If a factor can be found in situations where the effect is absent, it is not a sufficient cause of the effect. If a factor is found only in situations where the effect is present, and never in situations where the effect is absent, it may be a sufficient cause of the effect. If we look at all the factors in a situation where the effect is present, and find that there is only one factor that cannot also be found in situations where the effect is absent, we can conclude that one factor is the sufficient cause of the effect. Alternatively, if it is in our power to produce the factor that we suppose to be a sufficient cause of the effect, and we find that whenever we produce the factor the effect happens, that is also grounds for sup- 276 JOHN R. T. LAMONT posing that the factor is a sufficient cause of the effect. If we produce the factor, and the effect does not happen, that means that the factor is not a sufficient cause for the effect. Looking for sufficient causes in these ways will enable us to find out if an effect has a single full cause, or if it has partial 2 causes. To find if something is a necessary condition, we can use Mill's method of agreement. This involves taking numerous instances where an effect occurs and seeing what those instances have in common. If a certain factor is common to all the instances, the instances are evidence for it being a necessary condition. If the effect is ever-present without the factor, the factor is not a necessary condition. This gives us a way of testing whether a factor is a necessary condition; we can take a situation where the effect occurs and alter it in only one way, by removing the factor we think is a necessary condition. If the result is that the effect does not happen, the factor is not a necessary condition. These methods, combined with the methods used for identifying sufficient causes, can be used to determine whether an effect has partial l causes. But all these methods are useless when it comes to the question of how many uncaused causes there are. Since the effect we are interested in is the group of all effects, we can never compare situations where the effect is present to situations where the effect is absent. There are no situations where the group of all effects is absent, and if there were one, we would not be there to observe what it was like. Since the causes we are trying to count are by their nature uncaused causes, we will be unable to produce them and see what happens. Nor will we be able to remove them and see if any or all of the effects disappear. We will not be able to compare different situations where the effect occurs, since there is only one situation where the group of all effects occurs. Even if per inipossibile we could apply these methods to the uncaused cause or causes of all effects, the methods presuppose that the things to which they are applied have been clearly identified. But there are no means available for distinguishing one p9ssible uncaused cause from another. We cannot distinguish AN ARGUMENT FOR AN UNCAUSED CAUSE 277 them by their physical locations, because they are immaterial. We cannot distinguish them by causally affecting them in some way. We cannot distinguish them through their different effects, because we do not yet know what those different effects might be; that is what the methods are trying to find out. All these methods are thus doubly useless. We can therefore never have reasons for thinking that there is more than one uncaused cause. Given that we have reasons for thinking that there is at least one uncaused cause, Ockham's Razor tells us to believe that there is one and only one uncaused cause. The fact that we could never have reasons for thinking that there is more than one uncaused cause raises doubts about whether it even makes sense to suppose that there might be more than one uncaused cause. Aquinas's argument for an uncaused cause thus rests secure. Someone might object that although the purpose of Aquinas's arguments is to prove that God exists, the being established by Aquinas's first, second, and third ways-the uncaused cause of all effects, which is unchanging and exists necessarily-is not the same as God. This uncaused being has some of the attributes that are usually ascribed to God, since it is all-powerful, necessary, and the creator of everything that exists besides itself. But Aquinas has not shown it to have other attributes that are thought of as essential to divinity, like infinite knowledge, personality, or perfect goodness. His first, second, and third ways do not show that the causing of the group of all effects is in any way purposive. Aquinas does indeed try to establish that the other divine attributes follow from the ones demonstrated by the arguments he uses as his starting points. However, his efforts to do this are beyond the scope of this paper. INTENTIONAL ACTIONS AND THE MEANING OF OBJECT: A REPLY TO RICHARD McCORMICK MARTIN RHONHEIMER Roman Athenaeum of the Holy Cross Rome, Italy I N HIS ARTICLE, " Some Early Reactions to Veritatis Splendor," 1 Richard McCormick discusses my article on V eritatis Splendor and its teaching about intrinsically evil acts. 2 He challenges my defence of the encyclical's views and poses some concrete questions for me. At the same time, McCormick complains once more about what he calls the encyclical's misrepresentation of the proportionalists' views, as well as about a general misunderstanding on the part of critics of what proportionalism, consequentialism, and their teleological approach are really about. To begin with, I find it somewhat surprising that McCormick presents intentional understanding of human acts and their objects as something discovered by proportionalists. By this he obscures the fact that most critics of proportionalism, consequentialism, and so-called " teleological ethics " (I will not further distinguish these different labels) work with what is precisely an intentional conception of moral objects. 3 For example, my own 1 Theological Studies 55 (1994): 481-506; see 500-502; 504. Rhonheimer, " ' Intrinsically Evil Acts' and the Moral Viewpoint: Clarifying a Central Teaching of Veritatis Splendor," The Thomist 58 (1994) : 1-39. 3 There may be some exceptions, for example, Russell Rittinger; see his article, "The Pope and the Theorists," Crisis 11 (December 1993) : 31-36. G. E. M. Anscombe, one of the first and most incisive critics of consequentialism, attacked it on the grounds of an intentional concept of action, developed in her famous study Intention (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1957; 2nd ed. 1963). Cf. Anscombe, Contraception and Chastity (London: Catholic Truth Society, 1975). 2 Martin 279 280 MARTIN RHONHEIMER position, situated in the context of virtue ethics, 4 is one in which an intentional conception action plays a crucial role. McCormick seems to evade this level of argument, however, and in this way appears to beg the question about one of the central issues in the debate. At the same, it is not entirely surprising that McCormick had some difficulty in dealing with the central point of my argument (and of similar arguments), 5 because his methodology is so entangled in the categories of the strongly legalistic and casuistic manual tradition. 6 In my article, I explicitly dealt with the difficulty of understanding a virtue and first-person-centered view from the perspective of the manual tradition: It will, however, never be possible to render intelligible this moral methodology on the grounds of an ethic which from the beginning is concerned with justifying " moral norms." This is so because in such an approach the distinction between " object" and further intentions necessarily drops out of view. The only thing which a norm ethic can produce in the way of an action theory are the particular " occurrences " ("actions ") on the one hand, and the consequences 4 See Martin Rhonheimer, "'Ethics of N arms' and the Lost Virtues. Searching the Roots of the Crisis of Ethical Reasoning," Anthropotes IX, 2 (1993) : 231-243; La prospettiva della morale. Fondamenti dell'etica philosophica (Rome: Armando, 1994) ; Praktische Vernunft und Verniinftigkeit der Praxis. Handlungstheorie bei Thomas van Aquin in ihrer Entstehimg aus dem Problemlwntext der aristotelischen Ethik (Berlin: Akademie Verlag, 1994). Contrary to the impression which McCormick gives in his article, I do not share the Grisez-Finnis theory about basic goods and practical reason, nor do I argue on its grounds, in spite of many important common views. 5 See William E. May, Moral Absolutes. Catholic Tradition, Citrrent Trends, and the Truth (Milwaukee, Wisc: Marquette University Press, 1989) ; John Finnis, Moral Absolutes: Tradition, Revision, and Truth (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1991); Alasdair Macintyre, "How Can We Learn What Veritatis Splendor Has To Teach?" The Thomist 58 (1994) : 171-195. See also Robert P. George's and Hadley's Arkes's contributions to " The Splendor of Truth: A Symposium," published in First Things (January 1994) and rather unfairly criticized in McCormick's article. 6 This is also the case with Bruno Schuller and his disciples; see the recent paper by Werner Wolbert, " Die 'in sich schlechten' Handlungen und der Konsequentialismus," M oraltheologie im Abseitsf Antwort auf die Enzyklika "Veritatis Splendor," ed. Dietmar Mieth (Freiburg: Herder, 1994), 88-109. A REPLY TO RICHARD MCCORMICK 281 brought about by them, on the other. If an agent intmids the best consequences, then it is these which come to be designated the " object" of his "act." (21-22) McCormick's article thus confirms this assertion, since the author finally arrives at the conclusion that talking about " objects " and wrongness e:r obiecto is not a helpful terminology and should be abandoned. 7 I shall return to this point. The questions put to me by McCormick, and which I shall try to answer, deal with the following issues : 1) The meaning of "object" (which is, as he rightly states, the central point) ; 2) the closely related " question of intentionality " ; and 3) what is according to McCormick " a key question " for my position : " Why in choosing to kill a person or deceive a person, does one necessarily 'take a position with his will with regard to " good " and " evil" ' ? " 8 Finally, I shall also have to say something about what McCormick falsely calls the encyclical's misrepresentation of proportionalism, because this is intimately connected with all the rest. "Object" in Veritatis Splendor: Not Just a "Kind of Behavior" Let me start by specifying some points about V eritatis Splendor's teaching. In his presentation of the encyclical's understanding of the "object," McCormick says that according to the encyclical (and presumably also to me) an object simply is " a freely chosen kind of behavior." But it seems that he fails to grasp what the encyclical's text wants to stress in this passage. Its intention is not to tell the reader that objects are "kinds of behavior," but that objects are to be understood as something related to the acting person's choices. Therefore, the point made by the encyclical is about intention involved in choice of kinds of behavior and not about "kinds of behavior " as such. 7 He had already drawn the same conclusion in his article, " Document Begs Many Legitimate Moral Questions," National Catholic Reporter (October 15, 1993) : 17. s McCormick, " Some Early Reactions to V eritatis Splendor," 501. 282 MARTIN RHONHEIMER The entire text (which I quoted at the very beginning of my article) runs as follows : In order to be able to grasp the object of an act which specifies that act morally, it is therefore necessary to place oneself in the perspective of the acting person (VS, n. 78). What V eritatis Splendor is saying is this: Do not look at human acts " from outside "; do not focus only on what happens, what is the case, and on the state of affairs brought about by a behavioral performance; but rather put yourself in the perspective of the acting subject, for whom "actions" or "behaviors" are objects of choice, informed by reason, as immediate goals of the will. Thus the encyclical continues : The object of the- act of willing is in fact a freely chosen kind of behavior. . . . By the object of a given moral act, then, one cannot mean a process or an event of the merely physical order, to be assessed on the basis of its ability to bring about a given state of affairs in the outside world. Rather, that object is the proximate end of a deli.berate decision which determines the act of willing on the part of the acting person. (VS, n. 78, emphasis added) In his reading of this passage, McCormick's attention seems to be entirely conditioned by his own methodology-which adopts the standpoint of the observer, as is typical for norm-ethics and casuistry-and by the argumentative problems that logically arise in this perspective. Therefore he does not enter at all into the rather sophisticated argument set forth by the encyclical. It is significant that immediately after this statement Veritatis Splendor quotes n. 1761 of the Catechism of the Catholic Church (which also focuses on choice). " There are certain specific kinds of behavior that are always wrong to choose, because choosing them involves a disorder of the will, that is, a moral evil." In n. 1755, the Catechism gives an example, fornication, to illustrate its teaching. Clearly, " fornication" is not simply a material behavioral pattern (this would be " sexual intercourse between male and female "). The encyclical's verdict about moral evil is not about this pattern, but about the choice of it, that is, about a spe- . cific case of this choice, called " fornication," that is describable A REPLY TO RICHARD MCCORMICK 283 in universal terms (as a " species " of human act), a description that applies to a multiplicity of particular acts independently from further circumstances or consequences. Notice that the description of an (observable) behavioral pattern as such and the description of the choice of this behavior may be two quite different things. 9 Let me spell this out in more detail. When Jim chooses to have sexual intercourse with Jane, Jim actually not only chooses a behavioral pattern (to have intercourse with a female, or with Jane), because Jane either is or is not his wife. This is a circumstance relevant for practical reason that judges about the corresponding behavior as a practical good to be either pursued or avoided. It is a circumstance that, in this specific situation, is given and is thus prior to choice. It is not, however, inherent in the behavioral pattern as such; it is recognizable only by reason and it confers on the chosen behavior an inherent, though not simply naturally given, " form." The behavior could not be chosen at all apart from this "form." 10 Therefore, provided Jim and Jane are not married, Jim necessarily chooses, not just " intercourse with a female," but "fornication." 11 Accordingly, the concrete behavior considered as an object of choice is much more than merely a material behavioral pattern. In choosing a concrete behavioral pattern, one necessarily chooses it " under a description," which is precisely the description of an intent formed by reason. Sexual intercourse, as a chosen kind of behavior, is the object of a judgment of reason of the following sort: " Having sexual intercourse with Jane, who is 9 The problem is that in common speech the choice and the corresponding act tend to be lumped together under a common designation derived from some characteristic behavioral aspects of the act. In reality, however, the two can never be equated one with the other. Here, as John Finnis has pointed out, "common speech ... is not a safe guide" (Moral Absolutes, 72). 10 That is why (as I pointed out in sections four and six of my article) Aquinas calls objects "forms conceived by reason." 11 If Jim or Jane is (or both are) married, but not with each other, Jim and Jane choose what one calls "adultery." That is the classic example mentioned by Aquinas (Summa theologiae, I-II, q. 18, a. 5 ad 3) ; it illustrates well the difference between genus naturae and genus moris. 284 MARTIN RHONHEIMER not my wife (or even is another's wife, etc.), is a good here and now to be pursued." This precisely indicates an intention that defines the act in question. If there were no intention-which is impossible-there would be no reason, nor would there be a perceived good to be pursued. There would exist nothing but an observable behavioral pattern, not a human act. Thus the chosen act is precisely what Veritatis Splendor calls the " proximate end of the [choosing] will." As such, the very act indudes an intention, formed by reason, without which it could not be described as a human act. This intention (choice) of Jim to have intercourse with somebody who is not his spouse is perfectly describable and morally qualifiable independently from further intentions (e.g., the intention of doing it for the sake of obtaining some information necessary to save the lives of others). The encyclical's understanding of the object of a human act explains the formulation in n. 79, which I quoted in the opening section of my article. This sentence, which contains the key formulation, is, however, mostly ignored by revisionists. The verdict here concerns " choice of certain kinds of behavior." In VS, n. 80, "intrinsical evil" is referred to the object, and this again means: to kinds of behavior, insofar as they are objects of choice. What is called " intrinsically evil," therefore, is concrete choice, describable in behavioral terms, that cannot be reduced to simple " behavior," however, because every choice includes an intention of the will and a corresponding judgment of reason. That is also the reason why the encyclical speaks here about ulterior intentions, and not about intention as such: because " object " and intention are not mutually exclusive terms. There is some intentionality required so that an object of a human act can be constituted. 12 12 If it is said that the "object is a chosen act, describable only by referring to an intention, one might wonder how one can then simultaneously affirm-as does Veritatis Splendor, along with traditional moral theology-that the goodness of the (choosing) will depends on the object. Someone might claim that we should be able to describe the object as something "given" and without immediate reference to an intention. The solution of this apparent puzzle, how- A REPLY TO RICHARD MCCORMICK 285 McCormick affirmed in his article that proportionalism makes precisely this point, imputing to Veritatis Splendor, and to critics of proportionalism generally, a different view, one rather easy for him to criticize. In this way he avoids the real issue and conceals the weakness of proportionalism and consequentialism. This weakness, however, is that a consequentialist refuses to speak about "actions " or about intention involved in the choice of concrete actions; he or she only talks about intentions as related to foreseeable consequences, thereby describing, aud continuously redescribing, " actions " from the standpoint of a value-balancing observer; in this way he arrives at what he calls the " expanded notion of object." When McCormick says, " Intention tells us what is going on,'' he is perfectly right. But he neglects to ask: How are intentions shaped? Upon what do they depend? and, finally, What is, not intention and intentionality, but intentional action? Intentionality and " Intentional Actions ": The Implicit Physicalism of Proportionalism Perhaps the reader of my article on Veritatis Splendor will remember the ·example of " arm rising," " greeting," and so on. It was a simple example-inspired by Wittgenstein and Anscombe -of showing how intentional actions are structured. I asserted: ever, is easy: The object, its intentional element included, is first an object of reason, and in this sense it is prior to choice, insofar as choice is an act of the will shaped by reason. That is the point of Aquinas's teaching. See the following statements from the Prima secundae: bonuni per ration em repraesentatur voluntati ut obiectum; et inquantum cadit sub ordine rationis, pertinet ad genus 111oris, et causat bonitatem moralem in actu voluntatis ( q. 19, a. 1, ad 3) ; bonitas voluntatis dependet a ratione, ea niodo quo dependet ab obiecto (q. 19, a. 3); actus exterior est obiectum voluntatis, inquantum proponitur volitntati a ratione ut quodda1n bonum apprehensum et ordinatur per rationem (q. 20, a. 1, ad 1). Again, the object, like the "spec_ies," is a forma a ratione concepta which includes the cognitive or rational element of intention, purpose. For more details, see Rhonheimer, Natur als Grund/age der l\!loral: Eine Auseinandersetzung mit autonomer Moral und teleologischer Ethik (Innsbruck-Wien: Tyrolia, 1987), 317 ff., and also Praktische Vermmft imd Verniinftigkeit der Praxis. 286 MARTIN RHONHEIMER The so-called " absolute prohibitions," that is, normative propositions which indicate that certain, describable actions may never be licitly chosen and willingly performed, therefore relate to actions described intentionally. It is impossible to do this independently from the content of the acts of choice which relate to such actions. (32) I have always conceded that proportionalism and consequentialism in Catholic moral theology have aspired to overcome the limitations and flaws of a traditional physicalist understanding of the "moral object." 13 At the same time, however, I have contended that they have not succeeded because they have overlooked, and thus conserved, the basic error inherent in this tradition: to fail to understand human acts as embedded in an intentional process, that is, to fail to understand them from the perspective of the acting person. This can be seen very well in the case of Josef Fuchs (one of McCormick's chief witnesses for the proportionalists' innocence). According to my judgment, Fuchs speaks about " intentions," but he does not seem to have a notion of what an intentional action is. He speaks only of (premoral) " physical acts " or behavioral patterns (realized, performed, etc.) to which he adds intentions (as a " premoral " element!). What Fuchs calls the " act " in itself or the " act as such " has no moral identity. Only the combination of the three premoral elements " act,'' " circumstances," and " intentions " becomes for him a moral whole. The problem is that " physical act " plus " intention " (defined by some " reason ") will never result in an " intentional action." " Intentional action " is a concept belonging to action theory, not to moral casuistry. It is not part of a theory about how to combine "reasons" and " intentions" in order to justify an action normatively (that is, to know whether it is "allowed " and right or " illicit" and wrong). The concept of " intentional action " expresses the very nature of human acting. So one has to talk about the acting person and about what is going on in his or her will when he or she acts. The discourse will be about choice and 13 See Rhonheimer, " Intrinsically Evil Acts; and the Moral Viewpoint," 27, and the Introduction to N atur als Gritndlage der Moral. A REPLY TO RICHARD MCCORMICK 287 about intention involved in human acts, that is, in chosen acts (or behaviors, to use the encyclical's term). Let us have a look at Fuchs's well-known article, "The Absoluteness of Moral Terms." 14 In this article, Fuchs argues that "human acts" are composed of three elements: the (physical) act; special circumstances; and the intention. He first points out correctly that: " Morality, in the true (not transferred or analogous) sense, is expressible only by a human action, by an action which originates in the deliberate and free decision of a human person." 15 So a human action, Fuchs continues, must be performed "with the intention of the agent." He then adds the following example : One may not say, therefore, that killing as a realization of a human evil may be morally good or morally bad; for killing as such, since it implies nothing about the intention of the agent, cannot, purely as such, constitute a human act.16 The problem here is that " killing as such " is not an act, not even an " act as such," because " as such " it is not described as a chosen: act, that is, as an act that is the object of choice. Of course, "killing" as behavioral pattern (putting another person to death) could also be the performance of a robot. Considered on this level, " killing " is nothing but a behavioral pattern defined by a specific outcome. But, we should ask, what is going on when John chooses to kill Harry (for whatever reason: either because John simply wants Harry to be dead; or because John wants his uncle Harry to be dead for the sake of getting an inheritance, or for the sake of revenge, or for the sake of marrying Harry's wife) ? The point is that " killing as such " is not conceivable as a describable action, as if this could be understood apart from intention. If John kills Harry, he already has, in choosing the kill14 Gregorianum 52 (1971) ; reprinted in Readings in Moral Theology No. I: Moral Norms and Catholic Tradition, ed. Charles E. Curran and Richard McCormick (New York: Paulist Press, 1979), 94-137. 15 Fuchs, "The Absoluteness of Moral Terms," in Readings in Ji![oral Theology No. 1, 19. 16 Ibid. 288 MARTIN RHONHEIMER ing, an intention: he wants Harry to be dead (this independently of whether he chooses " killing Harry " for its own sake or as a means to a further end). Fuchs, however, falling into the trap of dealing with acts as if they were pure events (" realizations of goods and evils "), continues : The conclusion in definitive terms is: 1) An action cannot be judged morally in its materiality (killing, wounding, going to the moon) without reference to the intention of the agent; without this, we are not dealing with a human action, and only with respect to a human action may one say in a true sense whether it is morally good or bad.17 From this it obviously follows that, prima facie, any "act" (in his sense of performing a behavioral pattern) can be justified, even if it brings about a (premoral) evil (e.g., " death "). This brings us to Fuchs' second criterion : 2) The evil (in a premoral sense) effected by a human agent, must not be intended as such, and must be justified in terms of the totality of the action by appropriate reasons.18 Therefore, if I do not kill just for killing-without further reason besides the victim's death itself -, then any killing could be, on principle, morally justified, provided there are "appropriate reasons." Or do I somehow grossly misunderstand Fuchs? In this way, we are presented with an action analysis in which " acts " are simply physical events (" realizations of goods and evils " or of " lesser evils ") to be given a moral character by intentions that justify these performances on the ground of "appropriate" (commensurate) reason. The acting subject focuses exclusively on the overall outcome of his or her doings, not on what he or she concretely does. The acting subject disappears as a subject that chooses and thus willingly performs concrete acts, acts that are not simply events causing consequences, but proximate ends of a choosing will. 19 11 Ibid., 120. 18 Ibid. 19 Of course, I have never said that proportionalists explicitly hold such a causal-eventistic concept of action (since it is obviously absurd). Rather, my criticism was based on showing that they hold such a concept implicitly-be- A REPLY TO RICHARD MCCORMICK 289 Fuchs sums up his argument by asserting: A moral judgement is legitimately found only under a simultaneous consideration of the three elements (actions, circumstance, purpose), premoral in themselves; for the actualization of the three elements (taking money from another, who is very poor, to be able to give pleasure to a friend) is not a combination of three human actions that are morally judged on an individual basis, but a single human action.20 The example given by Fuchs, of course, is revealing and confirms what I reproach. The problem is that " taking money from another" is not a good description of a "chosen kind of behavior." A better description would be: "Appropriating money, taking it from its legitimate owner, against his will." This is an intentional description of an action called "theft." It has its moral form independently from whether the acting person has this or another " purpose " (intention), and from whether the outraged person is poor or not. Provided he or she in fact is poor, then the theft may be more condemnable and called "mean." If the purpose is frivolous (" to give pleasure to a friend "), then the whole theft will be a frivolous action in addition. Such a theft, however, will not only be a frivolous one, but also, by its very object, an unjust one! If the purpose ("further intention") is laudable, the intention remains laudable, but not the action as such, which remains unjust, though it probably will be, despite its wrongness, more understandable. In any case, on the whole it will be an evil action, maluni ex quocumque def ectu. On the grounds of Fuchs's and McCormick's methodology, however, these kinds of differentiations are completely ruled out in favor of a uniform overall judgement about " rightness " or " wrongness " of the act. To sum up, this methodology has three main characteristics. First, it confounds the intentionality involved in actions with the cause otherwise their position would not be coherent-and that this demonstrates that their position is erroneous. Consequently I argued that they should pay more attention to action theory. See Rhonheimer, " Intrinsically Evil Acts' and the Moral Viewpoint," 27 ff. 20 Fuchs, "The Absoluteness of Moral Terms," 121. 290 MARTIN RHONHEIMER reasons one might have to judge certain outcomes as desirable. Proportionalism, of course, does not forget intention or intentionality, but it reduces " action " to " intending" and to " having appropriate reasons." What is lacking is an intentional concept of action itself. For proportionalists, action remains a purely physical event that realizes the state of affairs one has a " reason " to bring about. Splitting up human acts into "acts as such," on one side, and " reasons " and " intentions related to foreseeable consequences," on the other, proportionalists seem to assert that choice proceeds on a double track : One first chooses, on the grounds of appropriate reasons, the state of affairs to be brought about, and afterwards the physical " act as such " that will cause it (e.g. " killing as such ") is chosen. The second choice-according to the theory-receives its moral species exclusively from the first ("as such," it has none); it has a purely instrumental relation to the first. That is precisely what I would call an " eventistic " and thus non-intentional notion of action. The second characteristic derives from this : The " basic action," the concrete act or behavior immediately chosen and then referred to whatever end, is not conceived as an intentional action. This is a very important point, because I take the "object" of a moral act to be precisely the content of what I have called an " intentional basic action," 21 which itself can be distinguished from further intentions. This inability to isolate the basic in.tentional content of actions in relation to further intentions leads to the third feature of proportionalism, what McCormick calls the " expanded notion of object," an " object " that is to be understood as being already the result of a process of weighing and " commensurating " all foreseeable consequences. The " expanded object " thus contains the intentions that define what in a morally significant sense the acting person is doing (and so, prima facie everything becomes morally possible, provided there is an ap21 See Rhonheimer, La prospettiva della morale, 39, 85 ff., 239 ff. The term "basic action" was first introduced by A. C. Danto ("Basic Actions," American Philosophical Quarterly 2 [1965] : 141-148), but in quite another sense, i.e. not referring to intentional action. A REPLY TO RICHARD MCCORMICK 291 propriate reason). The expanded notion of object, however, in reality is equivalent to the abolition of the notion of object altogether, for the very notion of " object" necessarily implies a distinction between the basic intention that characterizes the object and further intentions. McCormick's "Expanded Notion of Object" The problem of the proportionalist " expanded notion of object" can be well illustrated with the case of Paul Touvier, a French Nazi collaborator in the Vichy regime, recently condemned, who was ordered to shoot seven Jews on June 28, 1944. On trial fifty years later, Touvier argued that both he and the chief commander of the militia of Lyon knew that Gestapo chief Werner Knab was planning to execute a hundred Jews in reprisal for the Resistance's killing of Philippe Henriot, the head of Vichy's propaganda organization. By convincing Knab to execute only thirty, and then in fact executing seven Jews, Touvier argued that they had in fact prevented the execution of one hundred desired by the Gestapo Commander. The key point here is their argument that what they did in reality (the morally relevant " object" of their doing) was not kill seven Jews, but save the lives of ninety-three of them. That is an argument based on an " expanded notion of object." 22 The corresponding reasoning that would, in proportioninalist terms, justify such an action begins by affirming that " killing as such "-that is " without reference to the intention of the agent "-is neither good nor evil, but only the " realization of a (premoral) human evil" that can be justified, provided one does not directly intend this evil as the goal of the action, and that there be a "commensurate reason." Taking into account " the whole of the action," circumstances and foreseeable consequences, Touvier came to the conclusion: If I do not kill the seven, then one hundred (these seven probably included) will be killed. Therefore, in killing the seven (which as such is beyond good and evil), I can save ninety-three Jews. Thus Touvier rea:22 Or was it, mistakenly, not expanded enough? 292 MARTIN RHONHEIMER soned: the morally relevant "object" of my action-that is, what I am really doing-has to be called meritorious or at least responsible and justified as life-saving. Although a proportionalist can produce reasons why Touvier should have refrained from killing the seven Jews, this will be a consequentialist argument and will be accomplished by an even greater expansion of the object. For example, one could argue: " Acting in that manner could have foreseeably weakened consciousness of the criminal character of the Nazi Regime, which would have cost the lives of even more Jews in the long run." The problem here is not the result of the proportionalist reasoning, but rather its very structure. It is precisely the methodology of weighing the consequences, taking into account premoral " values "-in this case, lives of innocent human beings-so as to determine whether or not there is a " commensurate " reason for " realizing the premoral evil " of killing them. Why not simply admit that the intentional killing of innocent persons is immoral, unjust, criminal, that one is never allowed to do such a thing? According to proportionalism, however, what one chooses are mainly the consequences of one's actions (actions therefore conceived as simple behavioral performances), but not the actions themselves. As Fuchs put it: The object of the ethical decision for an action is, therefore, not the basic (e.g. physical) act as such (in its ethical relevance, such as killing, speaking falsehood, taking property, sexual stimulation), but the entirety of the basic act, special circumstances, and the chosen or (more or less) foreseeable consequences.23 A problem here is that everything depends on your preferencesincluding the determination as to which reasons are commensurate and which are not. Yet is preference ever sufficient as a basis for moral judgement? Who would not prefer the killing of only 2a Josef Fuchs, "Das Problem Todsiinde," Stimmen der Zeit 212 (February 1994): 83 (the English translation is that offered by McCormick in "Some Early Reaction to Veritatis Splendor," 500). In this 1994 article about Veritatis Splendor, Fuchs restates the same basic position he had presented in his article written more than twenty years earlier. A REPLY TO RICHARD MCCORMICK 293 seven, instead of a hundred innocent people? Who would not, to use McCormick's famous wording, prefer "to choose the lesser evil " ? 24 Of course, I prefer the lesser evil, too. I am happy when I learn that not one hundred but only seven innocents were killed, as I am happy to know that only seven instead of one hundred persons were killed in an air crash or by an earthquake. But I will not choose and willingly perform an evil action because I think it to be less evil then another and because otherwise foreseeably somebody else would commit the greater evil (I shall try to prevent that, of course). The proportionalist will rebut : " Sorry, you did not understand me. I meant that choosing the lesser evil signifies that this action was precisely the good one." I then would reply: "So you really think that when choosing and freely performing an action, nothing else happens than what happens in an air crash or an earthquake? Are the evil results of certain actions somehow simply given, beyond both my power to change and my responsibility? Or are they rather intrinsically bound up with the action that I perform? " On the grounds of this and similar examples, we can better understand why V eritatis Splendor, n. 77 pronounces a very important warning, a warning overlooked, it seems, by most proportionalists : The weighing of the goods and evils foreseeable as the consequence of an action is not an adequate method for determining whether the choice of that concrete kind of behavior is "according to its species," or "in itself," morally good or bad, licit or illicit. Of course, in the light of the preceding example this statement is perfectly intelligible. The proportionalist " expanded notion of object," however, renders it meaningless because in proportion24 Cf. John Finnis, Fundamentals of Ethics (Washington: Georgetown, 1983), 93 ff. For McCormick, choosing the lesser evil is simply a self-evident principle, "beyond debate: for the only alternative is that in conflict situations we should choose the greater evil, which is patently absurd" (Doing Evil to A chi eve Good, ed. Richard McCormick and Paul Ramsey [Chicago: Loyola, 1978], 38). This of course also means that we choose and therefore are responsible for the foreseen consequences of our omissions. 294 MARTIN RHONHEIMER alist terms there simply is no possible choice of a concrete kind of behavior that could be called morally bad " by its species " or " in itself " before the foreseeable consequences have been weighed-consequences that change from case to case-and before a judgment about commensurate reasons has been reached. The problem here is with what are called intrinsically wrong or evil actions; in such cases already the very object should serve as an indication that one should not persist along this line of action. McCormick avoids facing this problem directly by employing examples like "one takes a vacation trip in order to commit adultery " to maintain that only in such cas·es can one discern " an intention in addition to the object," because " there are two distinguishable actions here, each with its own object." 25 This is then a simple means-end relation. In the example, the basic action is perfectly indifferent or even good, but not the end. Yet is not the situation radically different in the case, for example, of one who commits adultery in order to rescue an innocent person and save his life and one who kills seven Jews in order to save the lives of ninety-three? Are there not also " two distinguishable actions here, each with its own object"? McCormick's choice of examples serves to avoid the real issue. Proportionalists thus describe and redescribe concrete chosen basic actions, without looking at what the acting person chooses on the level of action (or " means ") ; rather, they concentrate on what he or she chooses in the order of consequences and on the corresponding commensurate reasons, all of which finally constitute the "expanded object." As we have seen, however, the expanded notion of object is in reality not a notion of "object" at all, but precisely its abolition, because "object" means the basic intentional content of a human act, distinguishable from further intentions. 26 To borrow an example from William May, it would be more truthful to say that Macbeth killed Duncan instead of saying that McCormick, "Some Early Reactions to Veritatis Splendor," 498. of course, are also " objects " of the will. See John Finnis, " Object and Intention in Moral Judgments According to Aquinas," The Thomist 55 (1991): 1-27. 25 26 These, A REPLY TO RICHARD MCCORMICK 295 Macbeth stabbed Duncan and as a result Duncan died. Stabbing Duncan " as such " is not a sufficient description of a chosen kind of behavior or of an action. A description of the object must include, in Aquinas's terminology, both the materia circa quam, 21 " matter about which," and the " form" of the action: Macbeth stabbed Duncan for the sake of causing his death, or, because he wanted him dead (that was precisely his reason and his intention or purpose). We rightly call this kind of act an act of "killing." That is what he chose and what he did; that is the object of his action. In order to express our moral disapproval we also call it "murder." It would not make any sense to say: Macbeth chose stabbing Duncan with the further intention of causing his death, of killing him. You cannot describe " stabbing Duncan" as a reasonable, freely chosen action without indicating an intention. This way of describing an act by the intention involved in it is not always truthful. Thus it is not truthful to say that Touvier " saved ninety-three Jews " instead of saying that " Touvier killed seven innocent Jews, and as a result ninety-three were saved." We cannot call this action an act of " life saving " merely because the foreseeable result (the sparing of the ninety-three) was a " commensurate reason " for shooting the seven, and thus " life itself " was " better served." We are not calculating with quantities of the " good of life," but relating to concrete living persons. To speak truthfully, Touvier killed seven innocent people (he shot at them with the intent of ending their lives) which is murder-with the further intention of preventing the killing of a hundred. Thus it is not truthful to say that abortion, given that it means killing an innocent human being, is either an act of life saving when done for the sake of saving the mother's life or an act of saving family stability in certain difficult family situations. Nor can the manipulation and sacrifice of human embryos for the sake of health research (considered as a commensurate reason) be taken as simply an act of health care by virtue of its (expanded) 27 Summa theol., I-II, q. 18, a. 2, ad 2. 296 MARTIN RHONHEIMER object. The notion of expanded object does not work; or, better, it works for anything whatsoever. Again, everything depends on the preferences one has. 28 McCormick conceals the problem by adopting examples that, in themselves, are precisely not examples of " expanded objects" (and that I would call intentional basic actions). Let us take the example of masturbation. 29 Of course, stimulation of the genital organs " as such " is not a kind of behavior that can be chosen or willingly performed by a human person; a basic reason, intent, or purpose is needed. 30 That is why the Catechism of the Catholic Church very correctly writes in n. 2352: "By masturbation is to be understood the deliberate stimulation of the genital organs in order to derive sexual pleasure." That seems very clear. If one chooses the same behavioral pattern (stimulating genital organs) in order to get semen for fertility analysis, then one simply chooses an action that is different by its object. What happens, however, if one chooses to masturbate for the sake of psychological release? Is the action properly described by calling it " deliberate stimulation of the genital organs in order to have psychological release ? " I think not. Rather, what one deliberately chooses is " the stimulation of the genital organs in order to derive sexual pleasure" (=object), and this with the further intention of getting psychological release. The key here is that the release obviously does not derive from stimulating genital organs " as such," but from the corresponding sexual pleasure. Thus what the intentional basic action (or its object) turns out to be is not simply a question of preference. 2s In the proportionalist schema, one simply calls "object" what one concludes to be morally relevant, " what one wanted to condemn as wrong ex objecto" (McCormick, "Some Early Reactions to Veritatis Splendor," 504). In this way, one can simply keep expanding the object of one's action so as to justify one's preferences and reach the result corresponding to one's personal intuitions about what is morally relevant. 2 9 Cf. his example of organ transplantation, as distinguished from " killing for world peace" ("Some Early Reactions to Veritatis Splendor," 504). so Likewise, one simply cannot choose to " remove a kidney from a living donor " purely "as such," without any reason that constitutes it as a human act. A REPLY TO RICHARD MCCORMICK 297 At the same time the behavioral pattern alone does not decide everything and is sometimes ambiguous. Consider the following situations. John, a college student, for the sake of forgetting his girl-friend troubles drinks lots of whisky in order to induce a temporary loss of consciousness; in other words, he gets drunk. This is an act of intemperance, drunkenness. On the other hand, Fred, a soldier, for the sake of avoiding the pain of an emergency operation, drinks the same amount of whisky in order to induce a temporary loss of consciousness; in other words, he undergoes anesthesia. The behavioral pattern may be exactly identical, 31 but without indicating an intention (a " Why? "), it is impossible to describe properly what John and Fred are doing, i.e., what, in a basic sense, they choose. 32 If you remove any intention or purpose whatsoever, there is no action. Thus in every case you arrive at a basic level, which is the level of intentional basic actions. 38 There are also adherents of a non-intentional concept of object who fear that this consideration of intention opens the way to subjectivism: 84 Any behavioral pattern, they object, could serve for any object whatsoever: "by shifting intention to and fro, the agent constitutes out of whole cloth the moral properties of his act." 35 Moreover, their concern is "whether the norm of acts exists prior to human choice, or whether it only comes into being with our consideration of proportions, circumstances, and consequences." 36 And finally: Is it possible to say that intention is so important; should we not hold " that the concrete nature of acts tells us whether an intention is morally good or bad " ? 87 31 For an intentional notion of contraception, see Rhonheimer, "Contraception, Sexual Behavior, and Natural Law. Philosophical Foundation of the Norm of 'Rumanae Vitae,'" The Linacre Quarterly 56, 2 (1989) : 20-57. s2 Cf. G. E. M. Anscombe, Intention,§ 22. 33 The opposite is also possible, i.e., different or even contrary behavioral patterns, but the same intentional action, e.g., " the action of killing" and " the omission of a possible action of life saving." The objects of both choices are identical. 34 E.g., Russell Rittinger; see his article, " The Pope and the Theorists," Crisis (December 1993) : 31-36. 85 Rittinger, " The Pope and the Theorists,'' 34. 36 Ibid., 33-34. s1 Ibid., 34. 298 MARTIN RHONHEIMER These formulations are, however, somewhat misleading. First, the " nature of an act " necessarily includes an intention, because there is no human act without an intention formed by reason. And that is precisely why Aquinas calls the species of an act, which is determined by its object, a forma a ratione concepta, a "form conceived by reason " ; 38 likewise, he defines the good that is by nature specific to each virtue as a good formed " e.r qitadam commensuratione actus ad circumstantias et finem, quam ratio facit, " from a certain commensuration of the act to circumstances and to the end, a commensuration produced by reason." 39 Such formulations seem to justify the position of Fuchs and McCormick, but only seemingly, however, because the underlying understanding of human action is different. What Aquinas and the tradition say is: One cannot simply "choose" a (physical) act and additionally order it to any intention formed by commensurate reasons that would justify the act. To deny this does not mean, however, that a human act could be described without referring to intention altogether. Secondly, we have quite an extended power to organize our actions intentionally, and thus in a sense to constitute the moral properties of our acts. But there are what I would call naturally given limits to this. Therefore, (provided sound perception) I cannot shoot at a person's heart and truthfully say, "I love you," meaning that I am doing this with the intent of doing good to this person. What is crucial to recognize is that not every behavioral pattern fits for any intention. For example, I cannot shoot at a person and, e.g., have the intention of healing his wound. To have a human act one needs to have a basic intention; on this much we agree. But can one, as Bittinger fears, simply " shift intention to and fro "? Given a determined situation (which is precisely given and does not depend on the subject's will or preferences), it is not simply up to me to decide whether my shooting at a person's heart is or is not an action of punishment. theol., I-II, q. 18, a. 10. In II Sent., d. 39, q. 2, a. 1. "Act" here means the physical or "material" part. 38 Summa 39 A REPLY TO RICHARD MCCORMICK 299 And John who drinks to forget his girl-friend troubles simply cannot reasonably intend his act to be an act of anesthesia. Fred, on the other hand, who "does the same thing" cannot intend that what he does be an act of drunkenness. There are given contexts (shaped by circumstances and recognizable, as a morally significant contextual unity, only by practical reason) that, in a basic sense, decide what kind of intentions we reasonably can have if we choose a determined "kind of behavior," independently from further intentions. From this it follows that even if there is no act (and no object) possible without an involved intention, what the intention reasonably can be does not depend on pure preferences, or decisions, or any other power of the subject. This is (in many cases, but not always) simply given. 40 Thus Paul Touvier had no power to decide what would be his basic intention in killing seven innocent people. To describe his action properly, one must include the purpose or the intention, " wanting them to be dead" (even if he would regret it; that is only a motivational side-feature, but not the very intention of his acting). Touvier clearly wanted the seven to be killed; he chose their deaths for the sake of some greater benefit. 41 If someone should wonder why " intention " should be included in the "object" or in the " intrinsical nature of an act," he also should wonder why generally things like " will," " intellect," " reason," etc., should be included in human nature. It seems rather obvious that the very " nature " of the acts of a spiritual being-moral acts-includes spiritual elements as "purposes " or " intentions " of the will, shaped by reason, and not only observable behavioral patterns. Is this not precisely the constant teach40 It belongs to the virtue of prudence to understand the contexts in which we act; see my N atur als Grundlage der Moral, 346 ff., and La prospettiva della morale, 288 ff. 4 1 This is precisely what does not occur in the case of capital punishment (the argument applies also if one is for other reasons opposed to capital punishment), nor in that of legitimate self-defense, nor in that of killing in a just war (which must always have a defensive, anti-aggression character). 300 MARTIN RHONHEIMER ing of Aquinas? 42 Why should " realizing the evil of death " as such be taken as the adequate description of the object of a human act or express its " intrinsical nature," when exactly the same thing could be brought about by an earthquake or by a robot? Why should simple " solitary stimulation of genital organs as such" be the definition of the object and the intrinsical nature of a human act, when this contains absolutely no indication as to why one would do such a thing? One can therefore describe concrete choices of kinds of behavior as wrong or evil independently from further intentions. Such descriptions, however, always include a basic intention, an intention that itself presupposes a given ethically relevant context without which no intention, formed by reason, could come into being. This has nothing to do with the "expanded notion of object." But it includes a certain complexity that is due to the plurality and multiplicity of virtues that in turn reflect human life and its richness in relations between persons, including the differences of ethically relevant practical contexts. The Shaping of Intentional Basic Actions and the Virtues : Some " Manual Cases " To explain accurately what I have just said at the end of the preceding section, I should explain how practical principles are generated in a moral theory based on the " ends of virtues." 43 While my approach grows out of a tradition rooted in classical virtue ethics, proportionalism is entirely situated in the context of the manualistic tradition. 44 In opposition to this classical tradi42 See Summa theol., I-II, q .1, a. 3 ad 3: Fines morales accidunt rei naturali; et e converso ratio naturalis finis accidit morali. 43 See La prospettiva de/la morale, chapter five. 44 In order to understand correctly the Catholic tradition of moral teaching, however, one must recover the classical standpoint of virtue ethics. From this standpoint, actions are not considered from the outside-as processes that cause, by combining (premoral) goods and evils, foreseeable states of affairs-but rather in terms of " my " intentional relating to good and evil in different ethical contexts (relations between persons, to community and communities, to A REPLY TO RICHARD MCCORMICK 301 tion, proportionalism provides, on the basis of modern consequentialism, a relatively uniform theory of decision making, one that can be summed up in some very simple key principles : " What one does, considered as such, is not yet morally decisive; whatever one does, however, one ought never directly to intend premoral evil; rather, one should always act with a commensurate reason, so as to maximize benefit and/or to minimize harm or evil." In order to justify his position, McCormick adduces a whole range of classical examples, self-defence, masturbation, lying, contraception, sterilization, theft. 45 Insofar as he deals with these problems as a proportionalist, however, he simply begs the question. By affirming that to describe a moral human action an intentional element is required, McCormick asserts what nearly all hold. There is more, however, to the proportionalist position. McCormick affirms that proportionalists " are saying that an action cannot be judged morally wrong simply by looking at the material happening, or at its object in a very narrow and restricted sense." 46 Yet by identifying the "object in a very narrow and restricted sense " with the " material happening," he has already accepted the physicalist fallacy.47 So he is necessarily unable to understand how an intentional basic content can be formed. Like Fuchs, Knauer, et al., he will only look at material happenings (the act " as such ") and then at all the intentions (among myself and my body, to God etc.), so that in choosing certain concrete acts or behaviors my will becomes an evil will, whatever the consequences. Only in this perspective can one understand the shaping of " intentional basic actions " (which correspond to different "moral species" of acts and "moral objects"). 45 See also his article, "Killing the patient," The Tablet (October 30, 1993): 1410-11. 46 McCormick," Killing the patient," 1411. 47 McCormick commits the same error, even more explicitly, in his article, "Geburtenregelung als der Enzyklika," where he asserts that the "object in a narrower sense" is identical with the Thomistic materia circa quam (Moraltheologie im Abseits? 271-284). This is clearly false and shows a physicalist reading of the tradition. 302 MARTIN RHONHEIMER which those that will be morally decisive will be those for which one is able to adduce commensurate reasons) .48 What I maintain is that it is possible both not to be a proportionalist and simultaneously to assert that there is a difference in basic intentional content, i.e., the object, in the case of the following actions : -simple killing for any end whatsoever (an action against justice), even if the ulterior end is saving one's life (this is illicit murder); -(legitimate) killing in self-defense (killing praete·rintentionem) ; -(carrying out of) capital punishment (an act of punishment, which may be regarded as unjust, but which is by its object different from simple killing for any further end whatsoever) ; -killing of combatants in war, on the battlefield. These are not actions to be defined differently only because of different " reasons " one might have for realizing them. Not only their intentional content, but also their very intentional structure is very different in each case. Since they represent different intentional basic actions, they also are different by their object. Take for example the difference between " self-defence " and " the choice of killing in order to save one's life." On the level of " reasons " regarding the further end, both cases are identical : the reason for acting is to save one's life. But if you look at the action not from outside, but from the acting person's perspective, you will notice that there is a different choice (and so there is a different object, too). In legitimate self-defence, what engenders my action is not a will or a choice for the aggressor's death. A sign of this is that I only use violence proportionate to stop his aggression. This may lead me to kill him (praeter intentionem), but the reason for my action is not wanting him to be dead (for the sake of saving my life) ; rather it is wanting to stop his aggression. Thus there is a difference of intention on the level of 48 We have already seen in the Touvier case that this methodology does not work. Nor did it work in the case of masturbation, or drunkenness. The problem with killing is that there are some apparent "exceptions," like capital punishment, killing in war, and killing the aggressor in self-defense. A REPLY TO RICHARD MCCORMICK 303 concrete chosen behavior, and that means, on the level of the object. 49 Or, take " killing on a battle-field " : Am I a murderer or simply a soldier who is fighting against an aggressor? Provided the war is what one calls a just war ( ultima ratio-defence against an aggression), it entirely depends on what is going on in my heart, i.e., whether I want the enemy soldier to be dead, or simply to stop his aggression and to win the battle. Therefore, if as a soldier you do not want to be a murderer, you must care for wounded enemy soldiers. This shows that the object of your acting-the intention involved in your action-obviously was not wanting them to be dead, not even in the moment of battle, even if killing them in the moment was the foreseeable and necessary physical outcome of violence proportionate to stop their aggress10n. With theft it is slightly different. Theft refers to property. Property is not a natural or physical entity, but a moral and legal one. Property is not simply " what I have in my hands," but " that to which I am entitled " or " that to which I have a right." Such entitlement and rights, in a given situation, do or do not exist (and this precisely does not depend on consequentialist reasoning). But situations may change: they are contingent. Unlike a person's life, property is not an unchangeable matter. It is a contingent matter, relativized by higher principles of justice. So there are situations of extreme necessity in which no one is reasonably entitled to say to the starving: " This is my property; you have no right to it." If the starving one takes what he needs 4 9 This corresponds to the traditional distinction between "direct" and "indirect " killing, a distinction that reflects the easily misleading ambiguity of the word "killing." This is precisely what Aquinas very explicitly explains in the famous article 7 of Summa thcol., II-II, q. 64. What proportionalists never understand in their reading of this article is that Aquinas here not only maintains that actions are morally shaped by id quad intenditur, but also that the shaping of intentions depends on what yon are doing, in this case-on the amount of violence you use to stop the aggression. But in any case he says : illicitum est quad homo intendat occidere hominem itt seipsum defendat. It is not a question of " proportionate reason," but of intention involved in action. 304 MARTIN RHONHEIMER to survive, it will simply not be the action we call " theft," meaning an action that is contrary to justice. Therefore one has to analyze intentional contents as belonging to the structure of virtues. Admittedly, the traditional manuals were not very careful in this. Their methodology was rather legalistic, focusing on the external features of actions, referring them to positive law, and only secondarily applying some corrections to recuperate important intentional aspects. 50 In any event, it seems clear that justice related to property and related to life are two quite different matters. Notice that my arguments adopted so far have nothing in common with a proportionalist reasoning. The question was not whether there was a commensurate reason to realize the premoral evil of appropriating another's property, so that the act would not be "theft" anymore. Rather, the question was whether or not in a given practical context there existed a title of property (this certainly is not a question of commensurate reason or of utility). Once the question of rights is settled, however, these rights may not be overruled by consequentialist reasoning. 51 If one applies the proportionalist methodology of decision-making to these questions, one will never discern the differences, even though in certain more simply structured cases one will probably arrive at the same result. As a consequentialist, one arrives at this result by speaking only in terms of physical acts, foreseen consequences, and commensurate reasons, a level of discourse that will prove profoundly misleading in more serious questions, as 50 Thus St. Alphonsus de Liguori treated natural law as if it were a positive legal codex, teaching that epieikeia could be applied to it; this meant, however, not negative precepts but those positive precepts that Aquinas describes as valid only ut in pluribus (as deposita sunt reddeiida). Alphonsus' spirit is absolutely correct, but his methodology is of course misleading (he tries to argue within a legalistic framework). St. Alphonsus is today abused by authors who are nevertheless interested in maintaining the "legalistic" approach, so as to apply epieikeia even to negative precepts, without however noting the enormous difference. See Gunter Virt, " Epikie und sittliche Selbstbestimmung," Moraltheologie im Abseitsf 203-220. 51 See Macintyre, "How can we learn what Veritatis Splendor has to teach? " 179-182. A REPLY TO RICHARD MCCORMICK 305 illustrated by the Touvier case. Moreover, that is not how upright people really act and live. We act in given circumstances and personal relationships that form basic intentional contexts and corresponding intentional basic actions. Some of them are simply evil by their basic content. They divert the acting person from human good, and make the will and the heart evil. The "Key Question" and the Encyclical's Alleged " Misrepresentation " of Proportionalism At this point we finally arrive at what McCormick calls the "key question." Why, he asks me, in choosing to kill a person or deceive a person, does one necessarily "take a position with one's will with regard to ' good ' and ' evil ' "? While some elements of my answer are contained already in what I have explained in the foregoing sections, to answer the question systematically I would have to repeat all that I have said about the misleading distinction, fundamental for proportionalists, between " rightness " and " wrongness " of actions, on the one hand, and the " goodness " and " wickedness " of persons and their actions, on the other. I invite the reader to have a second glance at the original article. Let me add, however, the following. Proportionalists say that an action is right if what one does is justified by commensurate reason. In this view, a person is a good person if he or she does not directly intend to realize a premoral evil, but intends to act so as to maximize goods or to minimize evils ("in the long run," Knauer would add), meaning to act responsibly by commensurate reasons. I consider this to be simply erroneous. In my article I wrote : It is one of the most important assertions of classical virtue ethics that there exist conditions for the fundamental rightness of actions which depend on basic structures of the " rightness of desire " and that it is therefore possible to describe particular types of actions, the choice of which always involves wrong desire. (20) With regard to proportionalist decision-making theories (and their characteristic as " rule ethics ") I then added that these theories 306 MARTIN RHONHEIMER may not, on the level of the concrete performance of actions, include in their reflection the acting subject and his willingly " taking a position " with regard to " good " and " evil " in choosing this or that particular action. So, if I choose to kill P, I simply set my will against a fundamental right of P, which is moral evil; if I choose to have intercourse with Q, to whom I am not married, I act against the truth of sexuality, harming my own integrity (in the case of simple fornication), or, in the case of adultery, I moreover violate faithfulness due to the person to whom I am married. This implies disorder of my free will, and exactly this we commonly call an evil will. If I choose to utter falsehood to a person, given a practical context in which speech acts are meant to be acts of communicative justice (which is not the case in war situations, aggression, etc.), then I am lying to my fellow man. This means setting my will against social ties due to this person, and this is disorder in my will, moral evil. The same, obviously, applies to theft. At the same time, the one who carries out a capital punishment does not do what he does because he wants the executed to be dead (this could be a further motive, but a condemnable one) ; he may even do it after having done everything to liberate him. This is an act of punishment, that is, of retributive justice. 52 Following proportionalist methodology, one will not see, or not concede, the point because one omits focusing on what is going on in the acting and choosing person, precisely where moral evil comes about. Proportionalists are concerned with the reasons one might have to bring about certain state of affairs as the consequences of one's doings; and only this allows a judgement about "right" and "wrong." That is why consequentialists discuss for example the question of whether it could be right to execute the innocent, instead of simply asserting : to execute an innocent per52 See Rhonheimer, La prospettiva della morale, 283; also, the helpful analysis by Agnes Heller, Beyond Justice (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1987), 156 ff. I want to repeat that my argument does not yet settle the question whether capital punishment is a good or proportionate, and in this sense, just punishment; it only settles the basic objective meaning of the corresponding acts as actions of punishment or retributive justice. A REPLY TO RICHARD MCCORMICK 307 son for whatever reason is evil by its object. Thus precisely what proportionalists do not want to acknowledge is that, according to the encyclical's quotation of n. 1761 of the Catechism of the Catholic Church there are certain specific kinds of behavior that are always wrong to choose, be-cause choosing them involves a disorder of the will, that is, moral evil, and that, according to V eritatis Splendor's key sentence in n. 79, one must therefore reject the thesis, characteristic of teleological and proportionalist theories, which holds that it is impossible to qualify as nwrally evil according to its species-its "object "-the deliberate choice of certain kinds of behavior or specific acts, apart from a consideration of the intention for which the choice is made or the totality of the foreseeable consequences of that act for all persons concerned. Obviously, the encyclical goes right to the point, and McCormick's reaction, along with similar reactions, confirms that the Pope was right. This relates to that for which McCormick most reproaches Veritatis Splendor, its "misrepresentation" of proportionalism, 53 namely, the encyclical's assertion in n. 76: " Such theories however are not faithful to the Church's teaching, when they believe they can justify, as morally good, deliberate choices of kinds of behavior contrary to the commandments of the divine and the natural law." McCormick repeatedly says that with this the encyclical gravely misrepresents the proportionalists' views, reproaching them falsely "that [the proportionalist position] attempts to justify morally wron:g actions by a good intention." This is simply not true. McCormick's complaint would be justified if the Pope held the same understanding of the nature of natural and divine law that is proper to revisionist moral theology. Unlike proportionalists, however, the encyclical holds that in natural and divine law there are included certain negative preto certain kinds of behavior cepts that precisely refer that one never may choose. The encyclical does not reproach 53 McCormick, "Some Early Reactions to Veritatis Splendor," 490 ff., 497; "Killing the Patient," 1411. 308 MARTIN RHONHEIMER proportionalist theologians for wanting to justify by good intentions what is already determined to be morally wrong. The reproach is that proportionalism is a theory by which, in concrete cases, you can justify as morally right what the Church teaches to be universally, semper et pro semper, wrong. The Pope therefore reproaches proportionalism for denying that there are certain negative precepts that refer universally to certain kinds of behavior that one may never choose (killing the innocent, adultery, fornication, theft, contraception, abortion, lying, etc.). In fact, what the encyclical rejects is the proportionalist notion of expanded object that allows one in every concrete case to "redescribe" concrete actions, reducing the commandments of law simply to forbid certain immoral attitudes, but not choices of determined and intentionally describable behaviors or acts. Therefore V eritatis Splendor does not here affirm something about the formal structure of proportionalist moral judgement (imputing to proportionalists a theory that seeks to justify the principle, " One may do good evil that good come about") ; the reproach is a material one, that is, that proportionalism is a theory according to which such universal negative norms cannot exist, so that, according to this theory, one comes to declare to be morally right what natural and divine law, according to the Church's teaching, declares to be morally wrong and evil. Thus V eritatis Splendor's assertion in n. 76 does not characterize proportionalism as a theory, but it characterizes the result of this theory, its material implications, as leading to moral judgments explicitly contrary to what the Church teaches as morally wrong and evil. As evidence for this judgement, I refer again to the example of Fuchs, who wrote in 1971: "What value do our norms have with respect to the morality of the action as such, prior, that is, to the consideration of the circumstances and intention? We answer: They cannot be moral norms, unless circumstances and intention are taken into account." 54 Some pages later, referring to norms related to actions that "could never be objectively justified," he concludes: 54 Fuchs, " The Absolutness of Moral Terms," 121. A REPLY TO RICHARD MCCORMICK 309 Viewed theoretically, there seems to be no possibility of norms of this kind for human action in the inner-worldly realm. The reason is that an action cannot be judged morally at all, considered purely in itself, but only together with all the " circumstances " and the " intention." Consequently, a behavioral norm, universally valid in the full sense, would presuppose that those who arrive at it could know or foresee all the possible coinbinations of the action concerned with circumstances and intentions, with (pre-moral) values and nonvalues (bona and mala ' physica '). 55 Of course, Fuchs-like others-neglects to distinguish here between negative (prohibitive) and affirmative norms, which would make all the difference. And so, in a recent paper, he even speculates that in a future, yet unknown time, the command " you shall not commit adultery" could change and no longer be valid without exceptions; there could be imaginable " rare exceptions, on the grounds of highly important reasons and with mutual consent." 56 Similarly, it is not surprising that with regard to " murder, adultery, stealing, genocide, torture, prostitution, slavery, etc." McCormick cites with approval the argument of Lisa Sowle Cahill : " These phrases, Cahill correctly notes, do not define acts in the abstract, ' but acts (like intercourse or homicide) together with the conditions or circumstances in which they become immoral.' " 57 In their view, precisely because these "conditions or circumstances " can be discerned only in each particular case, the general norm indicating a species or kind of behavior tells us nothing definitive about whether the act is right or wrong, but merely provides us with a name for something of which we disapprove. Yet McCormick misses the point when he complains that Robert P. George "misrepresents proportionalists as maintaining that rape, murder, and adultery could be justified by a Ibid., 124. Fuchs, "Die sittliche Handlung: das instrinsece malum," M oraltheologie im Abseils? 183. Of course, for Fuchs this should not be called "adultery" any more; one would have to devise another name for it. 5 7 McCormick, "Some Early Reactions to Veritatis SPiendor," 492; the quotation is from Cahill's article, "Accent on the Mascuiine," 1.:,,:: Tablet 247 (December 11, 1993) : 1618-19. 55 56 310 MARTIN RHONHEIMER proportionate reason," 58 for what the critics of proportionalism are arguing is that the acts that proportionalists would not designate as " adultery " or " murder " because of the " conditions or circumstances " are in fact precisely acts of " adultery" or "murder," regardless of the new names given to such acts by the proportionalists. McCormick's complaint simply begs the question. The notion of "expanded object" requires that any universally formulated norm be open to exception because of a "commensurate reason " that redescribes the act in question. Proportionalism thus teaches that precisely on the grounds of intention, determined behaviors that are held by the Church's teaching to be semper et pro semper immoral, evil, and wrong according to divine and natural law may be become " right," here and nowwhen the "expanded object" is taken into consideration. 59 The trick is precisely to affirm this by a theory that is immune against the reproach, "you are trying to justify evil means by good intentions," since the very theory eliminates even the possibility of doing such a thing, for it argues that only evil intentions render an act evil and that a well-intentioned act is necessarily good. And that is why this theory is not only erroneous, but moreover dangerously confusing moral reasoning. Proportionalism is a methodology by which one in fact always can with good conscience act according to the principle " let us do evil so that good come about," because the methodology gives one the conviction that, provided good comes foreseeably about, what you did was not evil at all, but just the morally right thing, so that the ominous principle does not apply in your case. Whoever nevertheless reproaches you for trying to justify, on the grounds of "good reasons," what in reality is morally evil, will be " misrepresenting" your position. "Some Early Reactions to Veritatis Splendor," 487. This is clearly seen in Veritatis Splendor, n. 56, where the encyclical points out that according to the methodology that it rejects "a certain concrete existential consideration . . . could legitimately be the basis of certain exceptions to the general rule and thus permit one to do in practice and in good conscience what is qualified as intrinsically evil by the moral law." 58 McCormick, 59 A REPLY TO RICHARD MCCORMICK 311 McCormick said that the reason for what he sees as my error was probably that I had " taken one general description of consequentialism and applied it indiscriminately to all recent revisionist analyses." I do not think this is the case. But even if it were true, McCormick's position is still included in what I criticized in my article. And I also think that his position is one of those reasonably rejected by V eritatis Splendor. BOOK REVIEWS The Love Commandments: Essays in Christian Ethics and Moral Philosophy. Edited by EDMUND SANTURRI AND WILLIAM WERPE· HOWSKI. Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press, 1992. Pp. xxii 307. $35.00 (paper). + The essays in this volume address numerous philosophic and theological issues surrounding the two commandments of love of God and love of neighbor. A brief review cannot do justice to the careful argumentatation contained in the essays. Forced to make an unhappy choice, I have decided to provide some sense of the main line of argument in each piece and to add a few general comments about the dominant approaches to Christian charity in the volume. Gene Outka's "Universal Love and Impartiality," which sets the stage for many of the other pieces, asks: Should there be " no disparity between our consideration of others and our consideration of ourselves? " ( 3) . On the basis of a sustained comparison of Christian universal love with impartiality, Outka concludes that, " while universal love allies itself with impartiality at certain junctures, it represents an advance over impartiality because it more readily accommodates differences between neighbor-love and self-love" (79-80). Christianity's normative emphasis on regard for others goes beyond impartiality toward altruism. Christian ethics is not, however, identical with altruism if the latter means that the " self does not matter." This would be contrary to the theocentric framework of the commandments, which refer directly to the "self's well-being" (82). In contrast to both impartiality and altruism, universal love accents " inclusiveness " over " comparative measurement." On a descriptive level, impartialists " fall to take seriously enough the power of self-preoccupation." The simple assertions of equal regard do not meet the need for ameliorative strategies to correct our tendencies toward selfishness and pride. There are other disparities between self- and neighbor-love and thus between universal love and impartiality. In contrast to impartiality, universal love includes "legitimate, normative self-regarding considerations." This provides a response to the criticism that Christian love involves selfannihilation. A complete passivity to others can result in a loss of a determinate sense of self; but, as Outka argues, such passivity is not 313 314 BOOK REVIEWS to be confused with Christian humility. Rather, it can be rooted in the sin of sloth, disguised as humility. The theocentric concern with the self avoids both pride and sloth through obedient willing. Finally, there are legitimate and ineradicable self-regarding considerations at the descriptive level: I cannot "promote and protect" the well-being of neighbor and self in " exactly the same way" (87). In "Who is My Neighbor? Love, Equality, and Profoundly Retarded Humans,'' Edmund Santurri contrasts the humanist and inclusive view of equal worth with the rationalist view, which identifies being a person with having a rational capacity to desire, choose, evaluate, and so forth. As a way of clarifying the Christian-humanist view, Santurri considers various interpretations of the scriptural language concerning man as an image of God. He argues that in the biblical narrative all beings born of humankind are created in God's image. He then addresses two rival construals of personhood. The first limits personhood to those who have the capacity to value their existence, while the second accords equal standing to those who can participate in communal deliberation. Both views abstract from historical and social con· nections embedded in species life ( 124) . The argument for inclusion of the severely retarded rests not on reductionist biological principles, hut upon social phenomena: " the retarded are born of us, look like us, and interact with us in a wide assortment of highly distinctive social settings " ( 126) . In "'Agape' and Special Relations," William Werpehowski begins by engaging Gewirth's attempt to justify ethical particularism on the basis of ethical universalism. While his view is not as susceptible to criticism as some have thought, Werpehowski is nonetheless sympathetic with the concerns of Amelie Rorty, who worries that a view like that of Gewirth " locates the focus of moral theory and moral action in the processes and rules for justification " which thus " underdescribe and underdetermine the detailed thoughtfulness required for appropriate action" (146-147). As a corrective, Werpehowski appeals to Christian moral discernment or prudence. In a number of ways, we can construe special relations in terms of neighbor love: each is a creature of God, a sinner for whom Christ died, and a companion in beatitude. Thus, there need be no incompatibility between Christian universalism and its particular narrative. David Little's "The Law of Supererogation" takes its point of departure from David Heyd's criteria for a supererogatory act: it is neither obligatory nor forbidden, its omission is not wrong, it is morally good, and it is done voluntarily for the sake of someone else's good ( 159) . Little brings out his own view by considering the views of R. M. Hare, who holds that " ought" applies only to acts that are uni- BOOK REVIEWS 315 versalizable, and Macintyre, who counters that acts of supererogation are precisely the sort of acts that cannot be universalized but that can nonetheless constitute an individual " ought" ( 164). Little proposes a distinction between mandatory and permissive oughts. He thus sides with Macintyre by affirming that the term " ought " applies to supererogatory acts, but against Macintyre he holds that these acts can be understood as in some sense "prescriptively universalizable" (169). The degree of permissibility accruing to an action varies and depends upon a number of factors; when the action requires little sacrifice and the benefit to the recipient is high, there is little permissibility. As the sacrifice increases and/or the benefit decreases, the permissibility increases. The " capacity, availability, and effectiveness" of the benefactor are also germane, but when these are high, the crucial categories have to do with benefit to the beneficiary and cost to the benefactor. Supererogatory acts are reserved for those acts that have a high grade of beneficence (174-176). In these cases, as when someone freely sacrifices his life for others, there can be an " agent-specific " or permissive ought. The criteria adduced by Little show that there are " transsubj ective judgments concerning the sort of ought that is warranted in given circumstances" (177). All of this is compatible with the apparently paradoxical Christian position that the law of love binds us to permissive action. In "Christian Love and Political Violence," Timothy Jackson advocates a version of Ramsey's Augustinian position on the complicated relationship between love and justice. On this view, love and justice are not necessarily opposed and thus there is no necessary connection between Christian ethics and nonviolence. The defense of the innocent need not be seen as a secular motive isolated from the motive of Christion charity: the " desire to protect the innocent is a part of love's inspiration" (192). He then contrasts the views of Ramsey and Segundo, both of whom see the scriptural admonitions to " turn the other cheek " and " resist not evil " as " tactical rather than in-principle " ( 197). Yet Segundo's radical contextualism, where the " only truth is liberation itself,'' eviscerates moral discourse, since there is no substantive account of liberation itself (198). An alternative to Segundo is the view that " one may not directly take innocent life even to ensure national survival, but one may restrain political aggression in a just cause." Thus, " agape is politically active but morally self-limiting" (202). Jackson also responds to three objections to the primacy of charity: Nietzsche's meritarian criticism of the denial of egoism as unjust; the naturalistic objection that charity entails the devastating repression of natural instincts; and the liberal objection that the ethic of love " generates intolerance" (205-206). He concludes that "love serves others most pro· foundly by making them loving in their turn" (213). 316 BOOK REVIEWS In "'Agape' and Self-love," John Whittaker generally agrees with Outka but is troubled by his reference to the commandment as a " substantive moral principle," which suggests that it can guide " specific actions." Whittaker counters that it "represents more of a dispositional guide than a rule for performance" (223). He addresses numerous dif· ficulties with construing how we are to love others as we love ourselves: To what extent should we attend to the freedom, the basic needs, and the moral life of the neighbor? This underscores the problem with understanding the commandment in terms of clear-cut principles. Whittaker distinguishes two senses of the desire for happiness or two ways we love ourselves. One consists in our desire for " particular ends," the other, in a longing for " fulfillment as an unfocused concern " (228). Concern for the satisfaction of the latter longing is the focus of the commandment of love. What makes this distinctively Christian is the particular source of the disposition underlying concern for others. A gracious response to an unmerited gift of happiness, a gift that satisfies the unfocused longing mentioned above, frees us from the anxious struggle for happiness and fosters in us a disposition to attend to the happiness of others ( 235) . Jean Porter's "Salvific Love and Charity" compares Rahner and Aquinas. The former focuses on our awareness of ourselves as inquir· ing and loving subjects, as beings capable of self-transcendence toward the infinite (242). Openness to God is present "pre-thematically" in genuine acts of love of neighbor. Thus, the realm of the moral and the realm of salvation "become co-extensive" (255). Porter worries that the detachment of salvation from Christian beliefs may impoverish Christian moral discourse (253-254). Aquinas's view that there can be morally good acts, not ordered to salvation, provides a useful distinc· tion. Aquinas's conception of Christian charity as a distinct virtue, as an " enduring trait of character," spells out "the kinds of dispositions and enduring orientations that it produces" (254). Thomas thus pro· vides a more adequate account of the intelligibility of the Christian life, of what is distinctive about it and why it might be a desirable way of life. In " Kant on Christian Love," Ronald Green attempts to rehabilitate Kant's position on our universal duties toward others. Noting passages where Kant suggests that moral feelings are not irrelevant to the moral life, Green holds that Kant's apparent dismissal of the role of feelings has to do with what can and cannot be commanded. Since the " emotions are beyond our control," these cannot be commanded; only ac· tions in accordance with duty can be ( 263) . While noting that there is some tension in Kant between " unaided duty " and a " qualified reliance on God's aid" (267), Green also points out that Kant's arguments BOOK REVIEWS 317 on behalf of " active regard for the neighbor " coincide to some extent with the Christian understanding of agape. Thus, " Christian ethics shares a commitment with an ethics based on reason and open to all who are human" (275). John Reeder's "Analogues to Justice" addresses the question whether a society governed by benevolence alone would have need of justice. He discuses the society on the "moon Anarres" in Ursula LeGuin's The Dispossessed. Since all members act out of benevolence, the society lacks what Rawls calls the "subjective circumstances of justice." Such a society, Reeder argues, would still have the "objective circumstances of justice," that is, moderate scarcity, and thus would need distributive policies. Although Reeder thinks that " under certain historical circumstances (Anarres) extensive benevolence can render justice otiose," he also admits that the present prospects for such a society do not warrant optimism. He adds that, " in theological language, given finitude and sin, love needs justice" (299). The essays in this volume are preoccupied with modern, secular doctrines of equal regard, impartiality, and altruism. These are perhaps necessary dialectical starting points for reflection on charity, given that our inarticulateness about charity arises in part from our inability to distinguish it from its modern, secular substitutes. Nonetheless, Green's assumption that "those interested in deepening their understanding ... of Christian neighbor-love will not do badly by starting their reading with Kant" (277) is problematic. I do not mean that Kant has noth· ing to teach us, hut rather that Kant, following numerous Enlightenment thinkers, replaces the notion of virtue, with its emphasis on excellence of character and on participation in a communal way of life, with that of universal law, with its accentuation of the formal and the procedural. Reflection on charity is, I think, better served by taking its point of departure from pre-modern Christian sources, which treat law as ordered to virtue. How would this he helpful? One pervasive concern of the volume, a concern which is the focus of Porter's essay, is the distinctiveness of Christian charity. That is, how does charity provide intelligibility to the Christian life? Porter's essay points up an essential feature of Thomas's account of charity, a feature that is absent in the other essays in the volume. For Thomas, charity finds its fullest expression less as a law than as a virtue. The account of charity as a virtue, an excellence of character peculiar to the Christian way of life, suggests a response to the growing and influential number of critics who follow Nietzsche in identifying Christian love as self-annihilation. Indeed, Thomas grounds his account of charity in analogues to the Aristotelian notion of friendship. Of course we owe all human beings certain things simply in virtue of their human na- 318 BOOK REVIEWS ture. But when it comes to love, " we should measure the love of different persons according to the different kinds of union." Thomas underscores what Outka calls the " inclusive " conception of universal love. God is to be loved as the supreme good, as the source of all happiness; the neighbor is loved as sharing in the happiness we receive from God. Charity eviscerates neither our natural inclination for happiness nor our natural associations with others. Rather, it " commands each act of other sorts of friendship " in relation to our friendship with God. Charity is inherently prudential and thus an account of " special relations,'' which Werpehowski and others address, is incorporated into the discussion of charity. Of course one might make the same objection against Thomas's appropriation of Aristotle that I have leveled against the appropriation of modern notions. But Aristotle is not so much a secular rival of Christianity as he is a philosopher of human nature. A return to Christian Aristotelianism is suggested by Kierkegaard's dictum that we have forgotten what it means to be Christian because we have forgotten what it means to be human. THOMAS HIBBS s. Boston College Chestnut Hill, MA The Trinity: An Analysis of St. Thomas Aquinas' Expositio of the "De Trinitate" of Boethius. By DOUGLAS C. HALL. Studien und Texte zur Geistesgeschichte des Mittelalters 33. Leiden/New York: Brill, 1992. Pp. vi 131. $40 (cloth). + Aquinas's expositio of the De Trinitate of Boethius is an admirable paradigm of profound analysis and interpretive genius. Adhering closely to a literal reading of the short sexpartite Boethian tractate, but breaking off his analysis (for reasons unknown) just before the end of section two where Boethius begins his ex professo treatment of the Trinity, Aquinas ends up mainly plumbing the depth of Boethius's prefatory remarks about the epistemological status of theology, and thus in six questions (comprising 24 articles) constructs the most extensive treatment in all his works of the nature and method of theology. Little wonder, then, that Leo Elders titles his introduction to the expositio of Aquinas Faith and Science (Rome, 1974) or that Armand Maurer names his two volume translation of it Faith, Reason and Theology and The Division and Methods of the Sciences (Toronto, 198687). In Thomas's commentary, only the fourth article of question three treats the doctrine of the Trinity directly, though the four articles of BOOK REVIEWS 319 question four also discuss the cause of plurality, a crucial topic for trinitarian theology. I was mildly surprised, then, that Douglas Hall gives the title The Trinity to what professes to offer a " careful textual analysis and criticism" (112) of the methods and contents of Aquinas's commentary. In this slender book of four chapters, Hall inserts, between a short introduction and a conclusion, a second chapter on all five of Boethius's tractates and a third on Aquinas's commentary on the De Trinitate. He has some interesting things to say about the dating and contents of the Boethian works, and also makes some good points about Thomas's commentary, especially as regards questions five and six. But the title is a misnomer, for Hall skips over lightly the five articles mentioned above where Aquinas treats trinitarian issues, devoting only three pages to them. Hall's main concern, like Aquinas's, is theological methodology and epistemology. Hall attempts a rather Hegelian, dialectical appraisal of Aquinaswhich stresses Aquinas's reconstruction of Boethius by highlighting their common methodological theme of agnosia-and links it with an integrative approach which grounds itself in " a transcendental reading of Aquinas, while retaining themes from participationist and analogical literature" (112). The first chapter discusses the participationist, analogical, and transcendental strains of contemporary Thomism, and evinces a certain predilection for Rahner (his influence is also evident on pages 50, 58, 92-95) . In sum, Hall combines a Rahnerian and dialectical reading of Aquinas. Due to his presupposition, however, he frequently does not engage Aquinas on his own grounds but burdens him with false problems and dubious theses as he seeks to sort out Aquinas's " dialectical tensions." Often the result is a rather gratuitous reading encumbered with unsubstantiated non sequiturs that obfuscates rather than clarifies Thomas's text. Some examples are in order. Aquinas and Rahner. Pages 49-53 comment on the following text from Thomas's prologue: Et ideo Deus humano generi aliam tutam viam cognitionis providit, suam notitiam mentibus hominum per fidem infundens .... Sicut ergo naturalis cognitionis principium est creaturae notitia a sensu accepta, ita cogni· tionis desuper datae principium est primae veritatis notitia per fidem infusa. . . . Philosophi enim, qui naturalis cognitionis ordinem sequuntur, praeordinant scientiam de creaturis scientiae divinae, scilicet naturalem metaphysicae. Sed apud theologos proceditur e converso, ut creatoris consideratio considerationem praeveniat creaturae. (Accordingly God has provided for the human race another, safe way of knowing, imparting his knowledge to the minds of men through faith .... Consequently, just as our natural knowledge begins with the knowledge of creatures obtained by the senses, so the knowledge imparted from above begins with the cognition of the first Truth bestowed on us by 320 BOOK REVIEWS faith .... Philosophers, who follow the order of natural knowledge, place the science of creatures before the science of God, that is to say, natural philosophy before metaphysics, but theologians follow the opposite path, placing the consideration of the creator before that of creatures " [Faith, Reason and Theology, Armand l\faurer, trans. (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies, 1987), 3-4].) Hall blunders into two unfortunate interpretations of this text. First, he hijacks the meaning of creature notitia a sensu accepta by assuring us, without any clear textual warrant, that Thomas is here teaching that abstract knowledge based on the senses is a necessary but not sufficient cause of the first principles of knowledge, of the notio entis which is equivalent to the notio creaturae. In effect, on the basis of just a few words read out of context he expresses the kernel of Rahner's transcendental interpretation of Aquinas's epistemology. It would be hard to imagine a more egregious eisegesis. Second, Hall convinces himself that in this text Thomas holds that faith and theology afford us an immediate knowledge of God which somehow precedes and circumvents the whole natural order of cognition-a position which he deems, a la Rahner, to be setting up a false wall of division between the natural and supernatural orders. In fact, however, it is clear from Thomas's corpus as whole that these orders are distinct without being existentially separate, and that faith and theology affirm true judgments about God which make use of rather than circumvent the natural order of knowledge. Thus, when Thomas says that the theologians' consideratio creatoris precedes their consideratio creaturae, he does not mean, pace Hall, that theologians possess a special branch of knowledge which entirely circumvents the natural order of knowledge based on experience, but that their discipline, grounded in a conjunction of revelation and reason, has God as its central, formal, and unifying focus. Elsewhere, in like fashion, Hall charges Aquinas with teaching that revelation has an independent " content " not based on abstraction from the senses or interpretation of experience (92, 108), and fallaciously interprets Thomas's statement that theologians may rightfully use philosophical arguments in their theology (2.3 ad5) , as giving " the impression that sacra doctrina is somehow constituted as a reflective reality in human consciousness prior to and independently of an engagement with natural knowledge" (77). In fact, however, what Thomas teaches, in a paradoxical manner which Hall does not appre· ciate, is that a theological judgment based on revelation-e.g., that Jesus is the human enfleshment of the Word of God-while its truth transcends what pure sensation or experience could give us on their own, is nevertheless constructed out of the content of concepts and images whose natural environment is the senses and human experience. BOOK REVIEWS 321 Aquinas and Boethius. Hall misunderstands Boethius and Aquinas on the nature of their agnosia. To begin with, in an interpretation largely unwarranted by the texts of the tractates themselves, Hall sees Boethius as imbued with a profound agnosia which has no great confidence in the ability of theology to formulate understandable propositions about God-even though Hall admits that at the end of his Utrum Pater et Filius et Spiritus Sanctus Boethius states that he wants to reconcile faith and reason as far as possible, and even though Hall describes in detail how the De Trinitate discusses such purely philosophical topics as plurality, substance, accidents, and the ten categories, especially relation (27-35). According to Hall, moreover, most of Aquinas's texts modify and water down Boethius's extreme dialectical tension and insist on a much cleaner reconciliation between faith and reason. In reality, however, Boethius and Aquinas do not seem that far apart on the reconciliation of faith and reason, though the texts of Thomas do demonstrate a more moderate negative theology than, for example, those of Pseudo-Dionysius. Hall is only speculating somewhat fancifully, therefore, when he writes: " Aquinas quite frequently presents formulations that seem to have clarity of surface structure and terminology, but these are structures for novices, because Aquinas thought that his own, overpowering agnosia in faith would cause too much scandal and harm to those who were lacking refined cultivation in philosophical knowledge and maturity of faith" (79). If this were the case then all of Thomas's writings would have been intended for novice theologians-which they were not-since all his writings manifest an equal clarity of structure and terminology. Aquinas and Theology. Because of his emphasis on Thomas's supposed agnosia, Hall is also committed to finding any indication in Thomas that theology is not a true affirmative science, even though he knows that this flies in the face of Thomas's many assertions to the contrary. " It has been a concern of the present investigation to show that if one follows Aquinas's methodology, one can say almost nothing about the Mystery itself" (120). For example, pages 110-11 argue that, in 6.4 ad3, Aquinas holds that theology is most properly under· stood as not being a speculative science, because there he states that in the heavenly vision of God's essence, the happiness of the blessed occurs not through some speculative science but through the light of glory. Hall first correctly notes that Thomas is here contrasting the beatific vision with the knowledge gained through speculative science, but next incorrectly argues that since the beatific vision is not properly scientia, then a fortiori, neither can faith or theology be properly scientia. In fact, however, Thomas would never deny that the beatific vision is some sort of scientia or cognitive assimilation of God's reailty; what he 322 BOOK REVIEWS denies is that it is a speculative scientia, i.e., a knowledge gained through the senses, images, and abstractive concepts. By equating scientia with speculative scientia, Hall has unwarrantably narrowed the rich ambiguity of Aquinas's use of this term. Hall also thinks that Aquinas's assertion that theology is a limited attainment of the divine is tantamount to the assertion that theology " cannot draw strict conclusions" (75), though the second assertion is neither tantamount to the first nor what Aquinas holds. The book's fundamental flaw is its lack of a solid, synthetic comprehension of Thomas's subtle and nuanced theological epistemology. Ironically, Hall is not dialectical enough in his appreciation of that epistemology. Thus, on pages 91-92, for example, it is clear he does not understand Thomas's distinction between a quidditative knowledge of God (which we cannot have in this life but which the blessed possess in heaven) and true judgments about God's very being (which theology possesses even in this life). Hall conflates the two, whereas Thomas asserts the paradoxical and dialectical view that theology knows truths about God's very being even though it has no quidditative insight into that being. Moreover, Hall shows no sensitivity as to how Aquinas's distinction between concept and judgment permits him to assert, paradoxically, that the truth of theological judgments outstrips the very meaning of the concepts used to construct those judgments. For Thomas, concepts gained from the senses and experience are necessary prerequisites for theological judgments, and thus theological judgments are simultaneously mediated by but also transcend the meanings of concepts and words grounded in reason and experience. Hall claims that his book surpasses Ralph Mcinerny's Boethius and Aquinas (Washington, 1990), as well as the works of Maurer and Elders mentioned above, by providing a more detailed analysis than their introductory treatments can, and by emphasizing more than they the deep dialectical structures of Thomas's thought. As more reliable guides to Thomas's expositio on its own terms, however, as well as more incisive discussions of its various themes, the reader will find those other works more profitable than this study. GREGORY Dominican School of Philosophy and Theology Berkeley, California P. ROCCA, O.P. BOOK REVIEWS 323 Person and Religion: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Religion. By ZOFIA J. ZDYBICKA, U.C.J.A. Translated by Theresa Sandok. New York: Peter Lang, 1991. Pp. xix+ 397 (cloth). Zdybicka's volume is the third in Peter Lang's series, "Catholic Thought from Lublin." A convenient way to display the contents of Person and Religion is to elaborate the meaning of " philosophy of religion " and its comprising terms. Philosophy of religion designates the attempt to arrive at an ultimate explanation of the empirically given and existentially apprehended fact of religion (p. 96). In other words, why does religion exist at all and what are its subjective and objective grounds? This endeavor Zdybicka understands to be a recent one. Despite a wealth of reflection on religion over the centuries (See her historical survey, pp. 1-49), only since the 19th century have there been separate disciplines with the phenomenon of religion as their object. Zdybicka also emphasizes that not any kind of philosophy is equal to the task of carrying out the above mentioned attempt. Since the ultimate explanation of religion as truth or fantasy will entail determining whether God exists, only philosophies capable of grasping the real can serve the interests of philosophy of religion. Forms of Kantianism and phenomenology are not equal to the task (p. 97). Only a realistic philosophy connected with a theory of being stands a chance of offering an ultimate explanation of religion. In particular, the metaphysics borne in mind here is that of Krapiec. Peter Lang has recently published an English translation of it under the title, Metaphysics: An Outline of the History of Being (see my review in the January issue of The Thomist.) This work is indispensable background reading for Part III of Zdybicka's volume. Though this metaphysics is existential Thomist, its employment in a philosophy of religion will not resolve the question of which religion is true, though some religions will be ruled out as unsuitable for the human being (p. 97). What is understood as "religion"? In its basic meaning the religious fact is the reference or orientation of the human being toward a transcendent reality (p. 109). Considered more closely, the religious fact is actually multiphasic. First, there is the experience of our own ontic insufficiency and the consciousness of our transcendence and search for a value capable of preserving us in being and giving us complete existential meaning. Second, there is the religious experience in its strict sense. This second phase is itself divided into three phases. First is some kind of revelation from the religious object. Zdybicka stresses that this revelation occurs through signs to which we respond in faith; there is no direct cognitive contact with the religious object. 324 BOOK REVIEWS Second, there is the active response of the one struck by this revelation. The response consists in pursuing union with the deity. This second phase involves purification. Finally, there is the realization of the bond with the sacrum. What is achieved in the human person is holiness. The book concludes (pp. 315-22) with an extended discussion of this value. In sum, the phases of the religious experience properly speaking are: encounter, dialogue, and union. Zdybicka regards religious cults and rites as simply the externalization of religious acts (p. 129). They complete the description of the religious fact. Zdybicka also takes some time to distinguish religious experience from cognitive, moral, and aesthetic experience. Finally, pp. 157-59 contain an interesting inductive argument that the object of religious experience has always been understood as personal. In Part III Zdybicka performs a philosophical assessment of the religious fact. Specifically, the assessment is of the above mentioned introductory phase. Also as mentioned, Zdybicka takes advantage of Krapiec's Gilsonian existential Thomism which has denominated "classical philosophy." This philosophy's analysis of the human person and of reality critically validates both the subjective and objective grounds for the fact of religion properly speaking. The philosophically established subjective grounds include the contingent ontic status of the human person as this is evinced in the presence of the essence/existence composition. They also include an analysis of the person's ability to know and will that reveals an orientation to an Absolute Thou as our only completion. The analysis thoroughly roots the activation of these activities in sense experience. They are generated a posteriori. They are not a priori as in Transcendental Thomism. Importantly, the analysis of knowing and willing establishes only the possibility of an Absolute Thou (p. 303). Its existence is known in metaphysics, the philosophy of being, as it is founded on the essence/ existence composition (p. 295). Zdybicka surveys Aquinas' quinque viae and in line with Krapiec regards them as metaphysical demonstrations. The philosophy of being also proves that the nature of the Absolute is infinite, immaterial, free, and has intellect and will. In sum, the Absolute is a living personal being. In these ways classical philosophy shows that the human person and reality itself are both such that they can support the religious relation. The book concludes with a re-expression of the religious fact properly speaking, i.e., the mentioned second phase. A new and especially arresting point (p. 314) is that if God decides to create the human person, then union with God is something God must offer the human person. Zdybicka says: BOOK REVIEWS 325 Because God created the human being out of love and God is love, the fullness of goodness and truth, God cannot not love the human being, i.e., God cannot not desire the fullest development of the human person. If, therefore, the human person attains the fullest development through union with God, then it is impossible for God not to desire this union, since God is, after all, the " author" of the human being's nature. To complete this summary, I also want to mention that on pp. 204-48, Zdybicka critically surveys 19th and 20th century theories of religion. These include psychoanalytic theories (Freud, Jung, Fromm); sociological theories (Marx, Garaudy, Bloch, Durkheim), and phenomeno· logical theories ( Scheler, Otto, Elia de, van der Leeuw) . To conclude this review I wish to mention three assorted points. First, extensive as Person and Religion is, the book strikes me as con· taining two significant omissfons. The first omission concerns the problem of faith raised by analytic philosophy of religion. In sum, the problem is that since assent should be proportioned to the evidence, then faith, viz., firm belief in the absence of irresistible proof, requires intellectual dishonesty. Zdybicka has very little to say about the act of faith (pp. 124-5), especially vis-a-vis this problem. [For a discussion of the issue, see Thomistic Papers V (Houston: Center for Thomistic Studies, 1990) .] The second omission concerns the commitment of the genetic fallacy by any sociological or psychological explanation of religion. To know the social or psychological origin of an idea says noth· ing about the truth or falsity of the idea in itself. Second, Zdybicka's claim (p. 314 and cited above) that i£ God creates the human being, then God must desire the human being's union with himself appears to be not a religious or theological claim but a philosophical one. As such the claim seems to be incompatible with the teaching of Humani generis (1950) that the gratuity of the super· natural order should not be destroyed by suggesting that it would be impossible for God to create rational beings without ordaining them for the beatific vision and calling them to it. In fact, a Thomist like Joseph Owens has argued that as far as Aquinas' philosophy is con· cerned, only the soul's incorruptibility is demonstrable, not the soul's continued activity apart from the body ["Soul as Agent," The New S'cholasticism 48 (1974): 70] Third, the chief and significant value in my eyes of Person and Religion is its rooting the possibility of religion in a realistic philosophy that is unmitigated in its aposteriorism. A careful reading of Zdybicka's philosophical validation both of the subjective and objective grounds of religion (especially in the light of Krapiec's metaphysics) shows no appeal to a priori factors. The dynamism of knowing and willing " kick in " and are " excited " by an encounter with being as 326 BOOK REVIEWS the notion has been abstracted from sensible things. Zdybicka's approach to religion, then, stands in contrast to Karl Rahner's in his Hearers of the Word which relies heavily upon the philosophy of transcendental method that he sets out in Spirit in the World. Gilson's interpretation of Aquinas, which appears to be operative in Lublin Thomism, has never been seriously taken up into Catholic systematic theology. Perhaps with the dissemination of Lang's "Catholic Thought from Lublin " this will change. JOHN F. x. KNASAS Center for Thomistic Studies Houston, Texas Problems of Authority in the Reformation Debates. By G. R. EVANS. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992. Pp. xvi & 328. $59.95 (cloth). In this attractively presented, carefully constructed, and clearly articulated study, G. R. Evans seeks to "piece together underlying connections and habits of thought in the huge collective endeavour of the theology of the Reformation period " in order to " glimpse the shadow of a systematic theology of authority and to begin to see why the sixteenth-century attempt to find a theological resolution which all sides could recognise was not successful." Although the content of her study focuses on the sixteenth century, she really has the contemporary ecumenical scene in mind as she writes this book. Thus the author seeks to make a contribution to twentieth-century efforts to remove the stumbling blocks in ecclesial relations which are still vestiges of the sixteenth-century heritage. The theme of authority, as that theme manifested itself in various ways, serves as the unifying thread in the author's exploration of crucial aspects of the theological debates during the Reformation era. Rather than examining all of the fine points of discussion, she focuses particularly on the thought processes and linguistic styles of the antagonists, thereby pointing to what she considers to be the ultimate explanation why the debates failed to foster understanding or resolve conflict. It is her underlying hope that the identification of the reasons for failure will facilitate the contemporary ecumenical agenda and prevent similar mistakes. Evans achieves her goal of clarifying " underlying connections and habits of thought " in the theological discussions of the Reformation era. The following are salient points in her presentation. Evans argues correctly that various methodological factors must be considered as one BOOK REVIEWS 327 seeks to understand the sixteenth-century context. Logic and language were decisive elements in defining the nature and content of the debates. The use of topics (loci) , articles, and disputations in focusing the discussion, identifying essentials, and serving as authoritative articulations of particular positions was also crucial. The proper under· standing of words such as fides, justitia, and justificatio, was essent· tial since it could clarify, divide, or unite. While the reformers sought to employ biblical terms rather than scholastic vocabulary, it became necessary to choose theological neologisms. That choice was a matter of great concern which required much care. In the area of epistemology, the precise relationship between words and things was also discussed. The central issues related to the question of authority are carefully examined in the course of the argument. Evans proceeds from the basic premise that the question of whether Christ's authority was at risk in the church's life and whether Christ's Word, Scripture, was disregarded by the ecclesiastical authorities stood at the center of the Reformation debate. Hence the authority of Scripture and its relationship to other textual authorities (the Fathers, decrees, canons, etc.) was a volatile issue as sixteenth-century theologians argued about the truth of the faith. Questions regarding the authoritative text of Scripture, its mean· ing, and appropriate hermeneutical methods resulted in much discord. While the reformers generally emphasized sola Scriptura, they did not thereby reject the usefulness or necessity of past and contemporary interpretations of Scripture. However, they were concerned that the church might abuse, indeed, had abused, its teaching authority by misinterpreting Scripture and by denying the individual believer's right to interpret and to judge the teachers' and preachers' interpretations. Such claims of authority for the universal priesthood concerned the ecclesial authorities and their theological defenders as the truths of the faith were discussed. Saving authority was still another focus of debate. As far as Luther was concerned this constituted the crux of the matter in his struggle with the Roman Church. In his doctrine of justification, he stressed that humans are declared righteous as the alien righteousness of Christ is granted freely through the gift of faith. While all human merit is rejected in the justificatory process, works of love are viewed as necessary expressions of faith. Although Luther and other reformers rejected the freedom of the will, which Trent affirmed, they did maintain that the regenerated will can choose to do good. The church's authority to reconcile, in particular the necessity and effects of the sacraments in the life of the believer, was a third major issue which inspired heated discussion. The reformers agreed with the 328 BOOK REVIEWS church that the sacraments are necessary, but they also asserted that salvation is possible without them. Baptism was not a major divisive issue between the magisterial reformers and Rome, although the radicals rejected infant baptism because of their denial of original sin. It should be added that their sacramental theology and their understanding of faith were also contributing factors. Regarding penance, substantial disagreements emerged. The reformers argued that the power of the keys has nothing to do with temporal power and that the keys do not belong to the priests or specifically the pope. Rather, they are a gift of Christ to the whole community of faith. Absolution is nothing else than the proclamation of the Gospel. Transubstantiation and sacrifice, both of which were intimately related to the understanding of priestly power, were major eucharistic issues during the sixteenth cen· tury. The nature of the real presence inspired debates not only between the reformers and Rome, but also among the reformers. As they discussed authority in the visible community, both ecclesial and temporal, the reformers repudiated the tendency to view the church's authority in a political way, especially in terms of the two· swords theory. Except for the radicals, they also recognized the author· ity of temporal government and the necessity of obedience on the part of the Christian citizen. In defining the doctrine of the ministry and the exercise of authority within the church, they abandoned the distinction between the so-called temporal and spiritual estates, affirmed the priesthood of all believers by virtue of baptism, and argued that the ordained are chosen to exercise authority which belongs to all. The Roman theologians stressed ordination as a sacrament, defended the notion of indelible character, and asserted that special potestas is given to priests sacramentally in ordination, not in baptism. Papal primacy was challenged by the reformers, episcopal collegiality promoted, and Christ confessed to be the only necessary Head of the church. Finally, the authority to make decisions within the church engendered lively debate. The sola Scriptura principle raised questions about how scriptural truth is to be determined and by whom. All sides viewed councils as decision-making bodies and as preservers of unity. Because decision-making was considered to be part of the ministry of oversight, bishops, functioning collegially, were given primary authority in this area. It should be noted, however, that defenders of papal power argued that conciliar decisions must be approved by the papacy in order to have authoritative status. Laity could be present at councils, but were not allowed to vote. The authority of conciliar decisions was not viewed uniformly, of course. The reformers continued to defend the individual's right to make theological decisions and posited the possibility of error, even on the part of councils, since the church consists BOOK REVIEWS 329 both of saints and of hypocrites. At the same time, the disputants main· tained that there is only one divine truth and consensus statements were produced periodically with the intention of articulating that truth. In spite of such efforts, it is apparent that the opposing sides viewed each other as enemies, manifested little patience when negotiating, and were clearly not sufficiently committed to the unity of the church. Thus the sixteenth-century debates failed to resolve disagreements or achieve mutual understanding. In the course of her presentation, Evans quite obviously focuses on crucial issues which divided the church during the century of the Reformation. While offering carefully nuanced and defensible interpreta· tions and explications, she fails to consider the passionate faith commitments of the sixteenth-century antagonists, nor does she recognize sufficiently the crucial role of theological conviction in the Reformation debates. Perhaps most importantly, the radical understanding of the Gospel, which Luther articulated and many others affirmed, is not sufficiently highlighted as the central issue of the Reformation struggle. For Luther, and for others, the Gospel was at stake, and that fact shaped their attitudes, their literary style, their ecclesiology, and their understanding of and response to all authority questions. Their evangelical perspective also informed the specific content of their theological proposals. This fact must always be kept in mind as the sixteenth-century conflicts are explored and analyzed. Passion for the Gospel should also inform and shape contemporary ecumenical efforts to achieve theological understanding, to address the question of authority in the church, and to overcome the divisions which are, unfortunately, part of the Reformation heritage and which obviously persist. Although Evans' analysis is an interesting and helpful one, her basic findings are not novel. The use of polemics during the sixteenth century, the rejection of hierarchical authority, the defense of individual judgment and interpretation, an ardent party spirit and a lack of appreciation for the ideals of catholicity and unity, the focus on sola Scriptura rather than traditio, the disinclination to dialogue and seek mutual understanding, the tendency to focus on differences rather than on baptismal unity are all well-known facts. Their reiteration and clarification is an important and helpful contribution of this study. However, simply recognizing these realities and analyzing their divisive effect during the sixteenth century will not foster the ecumenical agenda today, as Evans hopes and suggests. There must be a strong personal and ecclesial commitment, based on theological as well as practical con· victions, to pursue new methods of theological debate; to affirm the divine gift of unity which transcends all causes of division; to clarify what is essential and what are adiaphora; to expect and tolerate diversity within unity; and to seek agreement concerning the Gospel, which 330 BOOK REVIEWS is the power through which the Holy Spirit creates and nurtures the church, which is the source of all authority in the church, and which is the norm for all that the church teaches and practices. Only then will the use and abuse of power within the contemporary church be addressed in theologically sound and healthy ways. Only then will ecclesiastical divisions be healed and the common mission of the church pursued with faithful commitment. KURT K. HENDEL Lutheran School of Theology at Chicago Chicago, Illinois The Church in Latin America 1492-1992. Edited by ENRIQUE DussEL. Maryknoll, (cloth). N.Y.: Orbis Books, 1992. Pp. x + 501. $49.95 This volume is the result of an exemplary effort to stimulate the study of the history of Latin American churches, to communicate the results of historical scholarship across national lines, and to bring many persons of diverse tendencies and religious backgrounds together in a unified enterprise. Cooperation at the Latin American level has been made difficult at times due to repression, internal wars, and opposition by conservative church leaders. Heroic efforts by Enrique Dussel and the Commission for the Study of Church History in Latin America brought forth an eleven-volume General History of the Church in Latin America. The present volume benefits from this magnanimous enterprise and includes many contributors to the larger series. The result is a singlevolume history of the churches, Catholic and Protestant, with many strengths and weaknesses. The editor structured the work to provide a chronological survey of the region in its first section, one which is succinct and useful for understanding the distant roots of the Catholic church. The middle section takes up regional histories and generally succeeds in conveying well the history up to the contemporary period. Including the treatment of the church in Chile, however, with that in Argentina, Paraguay, and Uruguay does not work well. Their civic cultures and ecclesiastical histories differ greatly, especially in this century. The final part devotes itself to special topics and becomes less historical than descriptive and evaluative. Here themes such as theology of liberation, Afro-American slavery, and religious orders receive special attention. This section offers much less reliable guidance to Latin American history, in my view. BOOK REVIEWS 331 One of the distinctive marks of the collaboration has been a determined effort (although not uniformally carried out) to recount history from the underside, from the point of view of the poor and oppressed, as well as from the perspective of religious and secular elite members who are thought to make history. This is an admirable and egalitarian ideal, but much basic research from this point of view has not been done. Within this section, Moises Sandoval provides a view of Hispanic Catholicism in the United States. He manages to sustain a view from the grassroots. The chapter, one of the best in the volume, could be required reading for any student of Nor,th American history. A few chapters may be marred by revisionist frameworks. The chapter on Protestantism is one. In my view, Jean Pierre Bastian's ideo· logical simplification does not allow him to give adequate consideration to the contemporary theological iand ecclesiological convictions behind notably diverse Protestant positions. Pentecostals account for 75-90 percent of Protestants in most Latin American countries; yet much of the history of Protestant churches in Latin America, as Bastian has re· counted it, has been irrelevant for explaining Pentecostal growth. This is not a minor consideration, since ,the volume lacks a sense that Pentecostal churches are major religious organizations within Latin America. Similar tendencies mar the work of some Catholic writers who are wedded to the discourse of the " historical process of liberation." Such discourse leads to extravagant characterizations, as by Jose Comblin. He writes in the chapter on the church and human rights: "New democracies are totally unstable. Development has stagnated. There is no future in sight " (pp. 452-453) . Comblin, a highly regiarded theologian, not a social scientist or historian, does not account for the great expansion (more than 2,000) of human rights organizations in Latin America. Many of these groups are tied to the church and came into existence largely in response rto the factors Comblin described: ineffectual democracies and stagnant economies. Enrique Dussel and collaborators provide a work which is especially helpful for understanding the history of the Catholic church in the long period before 1964. The volume is less successful in dealing with contemporary history and special themes. The deficiencies of contemporary history can be made up by recourse to recent national analyses, published as separate works, by Brian Smith (Chile) , Jeffrey Klaiber (Peru), Thomas Bruneau or Scott Mainwaring (Brazil), and Daniel Levine (Colombia and Venezuela) . The Latin American church is the largest regional church within Catholicism and is assuming leadership within the larger church body. Making use of its past will aid in understanding its theologies, its pas- 332 BOOK REVIEWS toral inventions (such as basic Christian communities), and the religious backgrounds of millions who help to make up the churches, Catholic and Protestant, of the United States. EDWARD L. CLEARY, O.P. Providence College Providence, RI Springs of Action: Understanding Intentional Behavior. By ALFRED R. MELE. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992. Pp. 272 ix. $39.95 (cloth). + Alfred Mele's overarching aim in this book is to offer an account of the role of intentions in the explanation of intentional action. He works within the familiar terms of causal theories of action, and is particularly indebted to Donald Davidson. In Part I, Mele borrows a set of theses from Davidson's desire/belief model of intentional action, and in the process of addressing problems associated with these theses, he progressively refines an account of action that understands an agent's reasons to have explanatory force by virtue of being among the causes of action. In Part II, Mele argues that desire /belief models are insufficient as they stand and need to be filled out by recognizing that intentions provide a crucial link between reasons and actions. The discussion begins with the vexed question of how the content of mental states can be relevant to the causal explanation of action. We constantly appeal to our desires, beliefs, plans, and so on (i.e., to various propositional, or intentional, attitudes) in explaining our behavior. But how does, say, my appetite for good wine and my belief that the house chardonnay is such a wine figure in the causal order that brings about my act of ordering a glass of it? Presumably, these intentional states supervene upon certain physical states of my body, and the latter do the causal work of producing wine-ordering behavior. However, there are good reasons to think that, with certain sorts of changes in my history and environment (viz., of the sort described in twin earth thought experiments) , these physical states could be the realization of different intentional states. So can a causal theory of action actually accord my desires and beliefs any role in explaining my action? Mele argues that even if we hold (with externalists) that the agent's history and environment help to fix the content of her intentional states, we can nonetheless say that unless the agent had intended what she did, she would not have acted as she did. The behavior is intentional action by virtue of issuing (in the right way) from physical processes BOOK REVIEWS 333 that realize the agent's reasons for acting, and these processes realize these reasons only if the processes have an appropriate causal history. The result is that what we desire, believe, and intend does after all make a systematic difference in what we do. Mele makes some helpful refinements in the standard account of the causal role of desire in intentional action. It has typically been claimed that when an agent's wants compete, the "strongest" of them deter· mines the action; if an agent wants to do A more than anything else that she takes herself to be able to do, then if she acts intentionally she will do A. Mele points out that this general claim must be qualified so as to index desires to times, to accommodate both unsuccessful at· tempts and the agent's estimates of the likelihood of success, and to deal with the complex relations between desires. He explores the way in which agents are able to control the motivational strength of their desires, and he works out a definition of irresistible desire. One of the deepest challenges to the claim that action is caused by what we most desire arises in considering "motivational ties." How, on this account, is intentional action possible when we equally desire each of two incompatible alternatives? An arbitrary decision procedure can be adopted (e.g., a coin toss) , but this alone does not en· hance the attractiveness of the randomly selected alternative. Here Mele introduces his thesis about intentions: viz., that intentions have an "executive quality that is not reducible to desire-strength" (p. 72), so that even when there is no preponderant motivation to do A, an agent can form an intention to do A, and this intention initiates, sustains, and guides the act of A-ing. In Part II of the book, Mele develops and defends this view of in· tentions and their role in the generation of action. Intentions include both motivational and representational components. Intentions constitute a motivational step beyond desire; one can desire to do A (and perhaps believe that one will do A) without intending to do A. Desires, Mele contends, lead to action only by way of intentions. In intending to do A, the agent " settles upon " A, i.e., the agent commits herself (for however long this intention persists) to A-ing. When the inten· tion is for action here and now (a proximal intention), it "triggers the appropriate actional mechanisms and . . . causally sustains their functioning" (p. 180). Intentions also, of course, include a represen· tation of the action to be performed, and this functions as an action plan that guides and coordinates the agent's behavior. Mele is at pains to contend that intentions cannot be analyzed with· out remainder into complexes of desires and beliefs. There is, he argues, a distinctive and crucial causal role for intentions over and above the i:oles played by desire and belief, Mele presses this point by 334 BOOK REVIEWS arguing that desire /belief accounts are inadequate to explain inten· tional action in certain difficult cases. We noted above his remarks about motivational ties, i.e., circumstances in which the agent's reasons are evenly balanced both for and against some course of action. In introducing his discussion of intentions, he goes on to contend that both weakness of will and strength of will (e.g., continence in the face of temptation) pose important additional problems for desire/belief analyses. When an agent acts against his better judgment, he pursues a course of action even though, in his own estimation, there are better reasons to do otherwise. Mele suggests that there is no adequate rea· sons-explanation for why the agent acts on the one reason rather than the other (p. 122). When an agent resists temptation, on the other hand, there is a puzzle about how we can explain the agent's ability to form an intention to act against his preponderant motivation. Cases of this latter sort play a particularly prominent role in Mele's argument that intentions have an " executive " function. Mele's argument here is problematic. It is not clear that the kinds of cases he cites do in fact pose special problems for a desire /belief analysis of intentional action. First, with regard to motivational ties, it is open to the desire /belief theorist to argue that, given two equally motivated incompatible actions A and B, the agent wants to do one of A or B more than he wants to do any other action at that time, and that this is what motivates action in accordance with an arbitrary de· cision procedure. Second, cases involving weakness of will appear to yield readily to analysis in terms of competing motivational conditions; an agent may judge it best on moral or prudential grounds to perform one action, and yet be strongly inclined toward another, incompatible action. An agent's desire to do what he judges best (by some standard of practical reasoning) may well be overwhelmed by other, less well· credentialed desires. The possibility of such mismatches between rational assessment and preponderant motivation sets the stage for Mele's discussion of the third set of cases, i.e., those involving strength of will. Here he argues explicitly against the motivational strength thesis (MST), viz., that "whenever an agent acts intentionally, he is more motivated to per· form the intentional action ( s) that he performs than he is to perform any competing action that he takes to be open to him at the time " (p. 172) . We can, he contends, be preponderantly motivated to undertake some action A and yet resolve and intentionally undertake not to do A. This debate with the MST, which is a prominent part of the sec· ond half of the book, has an elusive quality about it. The disagree· ment may in part be verbal, turning on questions about what is included in "preponderant motivation." Our assessments of what we de· 335 BOOK REVIEWS sire, on Mele's account, play a role in motivating action. In contrasting assessment and preponderant motivation, therefore, he must he re· garding the latter as comprised of some (or perhaps all) motivational factors other than our assessments. But in that case, a defender of the MST need not disagree with Mele's claim that we can choose to act against our preponderant motivation (i.e., we will do so whenever our assessments carry sufficient motivational clout to overcome these other considerations) . If, on the other hand, preponderant motivation does include the motivational factors associated with our assessments, then Mele's rejection of the MST undercuts his causal theory of action, since if we can act against our preponderant motivation (in this inclusive sense), then our executive intention cannot itself he adequately explained. It is not clear, in the end, that Mele needs to make the arguments that provoke these objections. His central claim, viz., that intentions play an irreducible role in the production of intentional action, does not depend upon (and may not even he advanced by) the claim that desire/belief analyses fail in any of the ways noted above. That is, even if it were the case that whenever we act intentionally, there is something that we are preponderantly motivated to do and we act as we do because we are so motivated, it does not follow that intentions can he eliminated from the account of the causation of intentional action. Mele's key contention is that intentions have functional characteristics that desires lack; they occupy a crucial position in the transition from what we desire to what we do, and they sustain and direct action. It is possible to affirm this irreducible causal role for intentions, and therefore to hold that desire /belief theories are incomplete in this respect, without denying the motivational strength thesis. Mele is particularly deft at constructing interesting cases that elicit and shape philosophical intuitions. His argument often turns on such cases, incorporating the points they illustrate in a series of working formulas that he further tests and refines. He combines this technique with mastery of an extensive philosophical literature, and the result is a discussion rich in helpful commentary on some of the major issues in contemporary action theory. THOMAS Bates College Lewiston, Maine F. TRACY 336 BOOK REVIEWS The Nature of All Being: A Study of Wittgenstein's Modal Atomism. By RAYMOND BRADLEY. New York and Oxford: The Oxford University Press, 1992. Pp. xxi 244. $39.95. + Bradley offers as his point of departure this epigraph from Wittgenstein's Notebooks 1914-1916, written 22 January, 1915: My whole task consists in giving the nature of the proposition. the nature of all being. In giving (And here being does not stand for existence.) His aim in this contribution to the corpus of Wittgenstein scholarship is to " bring into sharp focus the crucial role which modal notions-the notions of necessity, contingency, possibility, impossibility, and so onplay in Wittgenstein's early thinking" (xiii). At this task the book is a clear success. I know of no other work on the Tractatus which is so thoroughly dedicated to the role of modal notions, nor of any which does so much to bring the early Wittgenstein into conversation with contemporary philosophers who work on modal logic and who talk about possible worlds. Bradley convincingly argues that Wittgenstein is not only the largely unrecognized Urvater of modal logic in the twentieth century, with a stature that ought to be equivalent to that of Leibniz, he also presented arguments that even now have an important role to play in contemporary debates among possible world theorists and practitioners of modal logic. Philosophers who are interested in modal logic, especially its history, or in the logical structures of the Tractatus, will find very much of interest in this book. Those who, on the other hand, are chiefly interested in Wittgenstein's views on ethics, the aesthetic, God, or the mystical, or who are interested in the relation between the Tractatus and his later work, will find little here to their taste. The book's structure perspicuously tracks Bradley's argument. Chapter One sets the reader straight on what modal atomism is, giving the history of Wittgenstein's association with Russell, and establishing that the atomism of the Tractatus is in fact modal in nature. Chapter Two argues that Wittgenstein is a possibilist, that is, that he asserts the reality of merely possible entities and that his work is consistent with the modern modal logic called SS. Chapter Three turns to the ontological side, showing how Wittgenstein's commitments to atomic objects as the " substance of the world " entails certain modal relations among objects and the complex facts which they may form. In Chapter Four logic and ontology are brought together in an account of the mirroring relation through which language depicts the world, with attention to a set of intricately argued principles that makes this relation possible. The final chapter brings Wittgenstein's thought to bear on the BOOK REVIEWS 337 whole range of contemporary problems and issues in modal logic, demonstrating by example the author's contention that the Tractatus, rightly attended to, contains important contributions, still unappre· ciated, to the field. Bradley's overall intentions could not be more clear. His strategy for each chapter is clear. Each chapter is divided into between ten and twenty short sections each of which has a specific and well-defined topic. The argumentation within each such section, with a pardonable lapse or two, is well-structured and easy to follow, even for one whose expertise in modal logic is not honed by regular practice. And yet the hook has, on reading, the feel of a very dense landscape of trees, with· out much overview of the forest. This impression is given, I believe, by the style of argumentation. While the topics are sequentially related and build to a general picture, the arguments that must be articulated and answered in each section have little relation, one to the next: a problem in this view, a contradiction or a paradox in that, a resolution, and then on to the next section, where an apparent inconsistency of some sort must be addressed, and so on. There is the feeling of dealing serially with connected topics, but not the feeling of cumulative argumentation building toward a conclusion. A conclusion, however, there is: that Wittgenstein was the modal logician par excellence of the early 20th century, who has much to teach contemporary philosophers. In order to establish this point, Bradley must first show that he was a modal logician. The beginning point of this effort is a review of readings of the logic of the Tractatus. Despite some attention to the modal element in Wittgenstein's thought by Stenius and von Wright, the dominant readings-whether Russell's early assimilation of the text to his own tendencies toward epistemological atomism and sense data or Anscombe's canon-setting non-epistemological reading-have left the modalism in relative neglect. Bradley finds a chief obstacle to appreciating Wittgenstein's modalism to he the tendency to assimilate his view of the truth-table to a Russellian material implication, which cannot distinguish between, for example, a conditional being always true in the actual world and being true in all possible worlds, or between the existential quantifier meaning "It is possible that ... " and "There are some ... " (52-8). Wittgenstein's modal atomism, by contrast, "treats modality and existence in possibilist terms," where "possibilism" is "the belief in things which are merely possible, ... non-actual possibilities" (29). Now the crucial question one wants to ask here is: What do you mean by belief in? And we get around to that. But first, we get arguments claiming to show that Wittgenstein accepted the tenets of possibilism in the first, second, and third degrees. These degrees are, unlike those of murder, ranked in ascending order of seri• 338 BOOK REVIEWS ousness. The first degree possibilist believes in non-actual states of affairs. Put maximally benignly, the first degree possibilist believes that there are ways things could have been that are different from the ways things are. Like so much of the discourse of modal logic, this way of putting it oscillates between a totally harmless and vacuous sense (that things could have been different) and a metaphysically loaded one (that out there somewhere there are lurking entities called" ways things could have been," non-actually existing, or subsisting, or existing but not actually existing). Moreover, Bradley shows Wittgenstein to be committed to second and third degree possibilism as well. Second degree possibilists must believe in non-actual complex objects-not really very different from non-actual states of affairs. But third degree possibilists also believe in non -actual simple objects; i.e., they think that in some possible worlds there are objects alien to our world. The argument that implicates the Tractatus in this view is a characteristically elegant one, beginning with the point that Wittgenstein held it a logically open question whether the actual world contains an infinite number of of objects. Since he did, he must also have held that it is logically open whether a world could exist with more objects than ours, and hence, it must be possible for there to be a world with some objects not in ours-" alien" objects. But then how could Tractatus 2.022-2.203 be true, in its assertion that objects constitute the logical form of all imaginable worlds? Bradley's answer is that Wittgenstein means all possible objects, not just actual ones. The form of all possible worlds is "the set of possibilities generated by the set of all objects, that is, by the set of all possible objects, that is, by the union of the sets of actual objects and non·actual but possible objects " ( 44). It turns out, on Bradley's reading, that the modal logic to which Wittgenstein commits himself is that generated explicitly later by C. I. Lewis, called SS. Mapping SS onto the Tractatus calls for close analysis. A number of different uses of the term "object" are distinguished, including a " non-contrastive use " in which it simply means " thing." " Simple " is also thoroughly explored through three senses: metaphysical, semantic, and epistemological. While Wittgenstein occasionally flirts with the last (see the Notebooks 64 [7]) and loosely uses the middle, it is the first to which he is systematically tied. Bradley explores two chief interpretations of Tractarian simple objects, phenomenological and physical, finding the preferable interpretation to he the latter, that objects are physical point masses (not particles) . It is hard to see what the point of this question is, since Wittgenstein ruled the issue out of the bounds of logic (it does not matter) and even if it did matter you could not say (for objects can only be named, not BOOK REVIEWS 339 described) . Bradley devotes much argumentation to showing what sorts of properties-formal, material, etc.-objects have, and how they, as the substance of the world, should be thought of as combining to make up states of affairs. He has an illuminating section on the mess made, first by Wittgenstein and then by translators, of the SachlageSachverhalt /fact-state of affairs issue, and of the fundamental inconsistency introduced into the Tractarian system by Wittgenstein himself in the contention that all states of affairs are mutually independent. Bradley shows how to tinker with truth tables in harmless ways to let him give up this implausible position and still salvage the system. In this stretch there are two small-scale problems. On p. 35, the formula given as "0 P > o P" should be "0 P o 0 P." And on p. 103, " Gewisheit " should be " Gewissheit." Of more moment is this oddity on p. 104: " More than twenty years after he had finished the Tractatus, in his 1929 paper 'Some Remarks on Logical Form,' he considered .... " By this reckoning Wittgenstein finished the Tractatus in 1909. In some possible worlds, yes, but not the actual one. The date was 1919. This is surely a slip, but Bradley elsewhere refers to the Tractatus and the Notebooks 1914-1916 as "both his early works,'' a way of speaking that ignores and obscures the tentative, not-for-publication character of the Notebooks, making it sound as if they were just another book. He also, incidentally, uses the Notebooks in just this way, lacking entirely the sort of caution with which philosophers usually approach the question of construing the Tractatus according to the early writing. These things add up to a particular sort of approachnon-historioal, attentive to small and well-defined problems of logic hut not to the larger context. For example, we find Bradley criticizing Moore for not getting the point when Wittgenstein gave him notes on logic in Norway in 1914. Specifically, a problem that these notes should have solved was bothering Moore, according to Bradley, "more than half a century later" (145). Well, Moore died on October 24, 1953. How can Bradley have believed that he was doing logic after 1964? The answer, surely, is that Bradley, to judge by his bibliography, relied on P. A. Schilpp's The Philosophy of G. E. Moore, published in 1952 but republished in 1963. Bradley's bibliography has the latter date, and this fact led him into the supposition that Moore was doing logic after his death. This point, trivial in itself, shows the limitation of the problem-oriented style that may have a wonderful analysis of someone's position, but no idea of when the position was articulated, or under what circumstances. Chapter Four takes us to the connection of logic and the world in language. There are useful discussions of the inconsistent use, in the Tractatus, of Satz and Satzzeichen, and of Gegenstand, Eigenschaft, 340 BOOK REVIEWS Relation, and einfach. Bradley does a nice job relating Wittgenstein's possibilism to the saying-showing distinction (126-9) and in general does a good job with the explication of the picture theory of language. Six principles are articulated: the familiar " Proxy Principle," according to which names "go proxy for objects:" the "Form-Signalizing Principle," according to which the form of the names in a proposition mirrors the form of the objects composing the possible fact which is its sense; the "Generalized Compositionality Principle," which states that the meaning of a complex expression is a function of the meanings of its constituents; the " Compositional-Freedom and -Constraint Principles," providing that names in language are open to any combinations possible to the objects named by them, and similarly closed; and the " Same Multiplicity Principle," the idea that propositions must have the same number of constituent items (names) as the facts they mirror (objects) . In this stretch there is little that expands our grasp of the Tractatus beyond familiar accounts of its theory of language, except for the elevation of these various aspects of Wittgenstein's views into "principles," an elevation that must be chiefly useful to make them more readily available for argument. There is a clear section here on the Theory of Types, Wittgenstein's response to it, and the Liar's Paradox generally. Bradley's last chapter, reiterating the conclusion that the early Wittgenstein is " a de re possibilistic atomist operating within the framework of a possible worlds ontology " ( 171) , brings his work into contact with current and recent issues in modal logic. Seriatim, he discusses the work of Robert Merrihew Adams, David Lewis, Rudolph Carnap (whose crediting of Wittgenstein with the genesis of much of his work in Meaning and Necessity has been largely ignored), Nicholas Rescher, Robert Stalnaker, and D. M. Armstrong. At last in this chapter we get a treatment of the question, " Just what is it that possibilists believe about the being of possibilia? " There turn out to be three schools of thought: nominalists, who believe that possibilia are merely ways of speaking reducible to things that actually exist; conceptualists, who believe that possibilia exist in mental realms as concepts or some other sort of mental structures; and realists, who have the good robust belief that possible things exist. One almost says " really exist " but that is what actually existing things do. Possibilia just exist, but realists think that they really do just exist. To borrow from the later Wittgenstein: How high the seas of language run here! In any case, Bradley's contention is not only that the early Wittgenstein was a realist about possibilia, but that the person in the street is, too. Somehow I doubt that the philosophically untutored are as metaphysical as all that. And I do not trust what you could get them to say BOOK REVIEWS 341 if you started asking them questions about possible worlds. But Bradley's contribution is to have given us a painstaking and thorough reading of some extremely tightly wound and important aspects of the Tractatus, to have brought that text into direct contaot with con· temporary issues, and to have made progress toward showing that how· ever remarkable we thought the Tractatus was, it is still more remarkable than that. JOHN CHURCHILL Hendrix College Conway, Arkansas The Human Person: Animal and Spirit. By DAVID BRAINE. Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press, 1992. Pp. xxv 555. $32.95 (cloth). + Any study in philosophical anthropology that rejects both mate· rialism and dualism, and seeks to set forth a " holistic " alternative, may be met in many quarters with some skepticism today-especially if that alternative seeks to accommodate itself to religious teaching regarding the soul's continued existence after death. For, it will be asked, on the one hand, how can it deny that the esse of the human being ceases at death ( 538) without affirming some sort of dualism? On the other hand, unless it is some sort of soft-headed New Age philosophy (which this most certainly is not) , how can it sustain its claim to "holism" while rejecting the monolithic materialism of those whom Walker Percy once described as our "brain engineers, neuropharmacologists, and chemists of the synapses " ? The challenge is " how to produce an account which allows the human person to continue exist· ing after death, and even to have body restored to it, while remaining completely faithful to the insight that it belongs to human nature to be bodily," and, at the same time, to " avoid reerecting the soul into a complete substance" (xix). The peculiar obstacle faced by such a project is the pervasive proclivity towards reductionism in modern accounts of human nature stemming from the impress of both materialism and dualism. Both analyze the human person into an aggregate of parts in certain relations, the behavior of the whole being ·the result of the interactions of these parts. " In all this the materialist has exactly the same picture as the dualist. Indeed, unless the mental can first be represented as inner, logically independent of anything in the ' outer man ' and the ' world,' there is no way in which it can be identified with a brain-process or 342 BOOK REVIEWS state" (3). So whether one thinks of the mind as an independent en· tity (as in dualism), or not (as in materialism), the body is left to be accounted for by the brain engineers and their aggregates of physi· ological, anatomical, neurological, and chemical causes. And since materialism involves no complicating questions about causal interaction between the physical and the mental (as in dualism), it is usually preferred on grounds of its simplicity-all causation being subsumed under the physical. In this ambitious tome, David Braine, a philosopher at the University of Aberdeen, offers a thoroughgoing analysis and critique of such views, whereby he undertakes to overturn these ways of viewing human nature and to offer a holistic alternative. He sets forth a framework for understanding things like perceiving, doing, and speaking as irreducibly the acts of the psychosomatically integrated beings to which we normally attribute them-an understanding that conforms to the ordinary experience of such acts in ourselves and in others. He seeks to expose how materialist arguments repeat the mistakes of the dualists by reducing human beings (and other animals) to their aggregate parts, segmented sequences, and their interrelations. He takes issue with the arguments of recent analytical philosophers (such as Davidson and Dummett) in detail, and sets forth a holistic alternative-both with re· spect to the human person as " animal" and as " spirit." As to the human as "animal," Braine notes, accordingly, that "it is the bodily animal being as such, not just its mind, which is an ' I ', a ' he or she ', a focalized subject in relation to the world. The primary reason why human behaviour cannot be simulated by a computer does not lie in things special to human beings, but in the fact that this fo. calized psychophysical structure which they share with the higher animals cannot be thus simulated " ( 5). As to the human as " spirit," it is language, in both its complexity and its flexibility, he says, that serves as the defining feature, differentiating human beings from other animals. This is not to "name some property (say intellectuality) independent of being an animal . . . but to name that particular form of intellectuality which fits human beings as animals" (351). Braine divides his work into two halves, the first devoted to the human as " animal," the second to the human as " spirit." In the first part, he explores the nature of psychophysical unity in acts of perception, intentionality, and action, which he regards as essentially the same for human and non·human animals alike. In the second part, he examines the particular human transcendence revealed in language, yet continuing to insist that even linguistic acts exhibit an animal form of intellectuality that calls for holistic understanding. His last two chapters take up alternative views of how linguistic behavior may be viewed as BOOK REVIEWS 343 betokening human transcendence of the body and continud existence (even if not as a " complete substance") after bodily death. A unique feature of Braine's approach is the way he combines the insights and modes of analysis of both the ordinary-language and phenomenological traditions with perceptive formulations of the Aristotelian and Thomistic positions. The fact that he is able to make philosophical bedfellows of the likes of Wittgenstein, Ryle, and Austin, on the one hand, with Husserl, Heidegger, and Merleau-Ponty, on the other-or, at least, to make cobelligerents of them against the com· mon foes of dualism and materialism-is a feat in itself. That he manages to bring together these two historically quite independent traditions with the no-less-independent Aristotelian-Thomistic tradition in order to develop fresh, insightful formulations of old, familiar problems is even more remarkable. The whole multi-perspectival project seems to be focused and animated by the assumption that the modes of analysis of phenomenology and ordinary-language are united in the approach of St. Thomas, who appeals to our phenomenal experience of acts of perceiving and thinking, as well as to the ordinary language by which we describe and refer to such acts. The result is a fascinating and provocative conjunction of traditionally unrelated approaches. Braine's basic thesis is that the human being (and other higher animals) cannot be understood properly as an aggregate of parts in certain relations, but only as a subject and agent. Likewsie, human and animal activity cannot be understood properly as an aggregate of segmented events-as chains of physiological, anatomical, neuro-chemical or psychological occurrences. Rather, it can be understood only when seen holistically-as " focalized " and discharged by centers of con· sciousness " in such a way that it can be attributed to such centers of consciousness and in such a way that consciousness enters into, not only the description, but also the explanation of the behavior " (4) . This is not to deny that operations such as perceiving, acting, or speaking do not involve constituent parts, but only that such operations cannot be understood as "focalized" acts of living subjects so long as they are approached as aggregates of independent events. The constituent parts of such operations, once isolated, no longer retain the same identity they had as parts of the integrated whole of the " focalized " act-life of the living agent. In Part One, this translates into the interesting argument that the material or physical aspect of animal and human life lacks self-sufficiency and has no existence or intelligibilty apart from the animating principle traditionally attributed to the soul (which leads Braine to em· brace a non-dualistic conception of " soul " whereby other animals may be understood as also having souls, somewhat after the fashion of an· 344 BOOK REVIEWS cient Hebraic conceptions). Any reductionist attempt to explain the act-life of living agents by exclusive reference to independent material (or mental!) operations threatens to destroy their psychophysical unity. For example, it could dissolve the integral act of perception into, first, a " perceptual experience " conceived as something entirely " interior " to the mind or brain, then into " external " occurrences in the sense organs and physical world, and, finally, into a causal relation between these. Against such tendencies, Braine seeks to reveal the animating principle that serves to integrate all such constituent elements in the animal and human esse. Thus, to stick with the perceptual example, the subsidiary physical processes involved in seeing-in the eye, the optic nerve, and the brain-remain " internal " to the act of seeing and therefore unnoticed by the subject. Even as Aristotle and St. Thomas observed, such physiological processes are not themselves the object of perceptual consciousness, nor even ordinarily available to our consciousness. What we are conscious of is simply the perceived object itself. The " internal " physiological processes are subsumed typically into an integrated act whose animating principle (anima) traditionally has been called the "soul "-though it should not be viewed as an independent entity and, if Braine is right, is no less evident in other higher animals than in humans. " The animal or human being is a 'focalized subject', not in having a head, brain, soul, or mind as a focal centre within it, but in having its relations with the world . . . focalized upon it as an anima, a psychological subject, as such undivided and indivisible" (318). What is true of perception is largely the case with intentional actions such as walking someplace. The subsidiary physical processes involved in walking-in the nervous system, muscles, joints, motion of our feet -are " internal " to the act of walking. They are subsumed into an integrated act, which is focalized by an intended end. Ordinarily, we are not directly aware of these aggregate processes, as becomes evident the moment we try concentrating our attention on the movement of our feet as we run down a flight of stairs and nearly trip over ourselves. When the subsidiary processes become detached from the intended end to which they are ordinarily subordinated, they literally dis-integrate. On the other hand, we become aware of our agency in an act such ·as walking, not through direct consciousness of any " mental " processes such as " intentions " or " volitions " occurring within us, but through our awareness of ourselves as intending the act. " I know why I did it, and that it was not, for example, like an involuntary twitch or spasm " (135). In Part Two, Braine carries this argument over into human ·Ian- BOOK REVIEWS 345 guage. As physical processes involved in perception and action are " internal " to them, so those involved in speaking and making sounds are " internal " to talking and thinking in the medium of words. The most ambitious modern form of materialism, "Artificial Intelligence," seeks a completely mechanistic account of human thought and language. But it does so only by ignoring mathematically proven results as to the impossibility of formalizing natural language or even elementary modes of proof available in natural arithmetic-ignoring Tarski and Godel as well as a multitude of philosophers from A11istotle to Wittgenstein. The unformalizability of natural language, as well as the relation of langue and parole implied by it, rule out any completely reductionist account of speaking and thinking in terms of digitized brain-processes (461) . This irreducibility, in turn, leads Braine to an account of human transcendence that is essentially sympathetic to Aristotelian and Thomist positions. Some activities of the human being in which its existing or esse may wholly or partly consist-such as thinking in the medium of words-are not operations of any bodily organ. It therefore follows that the human being has an esse which transcends the body and does not necessarily cease at death. "When one has died, one is not a nothing but one has no body: we could say that one is a soul, but this would not be a statement of what one is as if a soul were a sort of tl1ing " ( 51.0) . A person without a body is incomplete-not as an otherwise complete soul lacking a body to inhabit, but as an animating spirit lacking any subsidiary bodily operations to integrate into one's own life. It is as if, instead of the conventional dualist picture of the soul inhabiting a body, the body is meant to inhabit the soul. A fascinating and rewarding study. Highly recommended. PHILIP BLOSSER Lenoir-Rhyne College Hickory, North Carolina