AQUINAS ON THE EVALUATION OF HUMAN ACTIONS WILLIAM H. MARSHNER Christendom College Front Royal, Virginia A MONG THE questions dealt with in the Prima Secundae are those of what moral goodness "is" and on what basis it is attributed to some human actions but denied of others. Aquinas's answers are currently a matter of contention between the proportionalists and their critics, as is his answer to the question of how human actions are classified. The presentation in the Prima Secundae does give rise to problems, thanks in part to Aquinas's pedagogical procedure. That procedure can be described as bit-by-bit exposition. Rather than set forth his whole view of a topic in one place, in a synthesis of some sort, and applying it piecemeal thereafter as subsequent questions may demand, the Common Doctor keeps his whole view back, exposing no more of it than is needed to resolve the particular issue at stake in a given article. The result of this, quite often, is that qualifications crucial to a fair comprehension of what he holds are scattered over places far removed from each other. Because what he holds on the classification and evaluation of human actions consists of several parts, each complicated, and all connected, his solution is unsuited to bit-by-bit exposition. Genuine doubts as to what the parts are, and how they come together, can arise. The purpose of the present paper is to present a synthesis that lets the whole picture emerge; as it emerges, certain attempts to read Aquinas in a manner supportive of the proportionalist position will be shown to conflict with the design of the whole. In his preface to qq. 18-20 in the Prima Secundae, Aquinas 347 348 WILLIAM H. MARSHNER describes their subject matter as the goodness or badness (bonitas vel malitia) of human actions. These abstract nouns are derived from the corresponding adjectives, "good" and "bad," and the very first thing Aquinas tells us (in the first sentence of q. 18, a. 1) is that "good" and "bad" are to be asserted of human actions in the same way as they are asserted of other things.' So how is that? A BACKGROUND TOPIC: 'GOOD' AND 'BAD' IN GENERAL If one should take up any item at all-an apple, a shoe-and say that the item is good, would one be purporting only to describe it as it is, or would one be purporting also to evaluate it in light of how it ought to be? Differently posed, does a proposition of the form "x is good" represent a product of speculative reason alone, or does it include an element, at least, from practical reasoning? Recent analytical philosophy is quite clear that the latter option is correct. "Good" and "bad" are terms which express evaluation rather than some sort of disinterested, theoretical description. 2 Aquinas can be read, at least, as holding the same view. In a text in which he defined a completely general sense of "good" (more general, for example, than just "human good"), he said: ratio boni est quod aliquid sit appetibile. 3 To make out what this dictum means, two remarks are in order. First, the ratio of a term "T" is the reason anything is called T. Aquinas identified it as the aspect of things which the mind grasps and signifies through "T." 4 He meant the aspect which would be "what it takes" for a thing to merit or verify the term, in case the term is applied to it. Thus the ratio of "good" is what it takes for 1 Respondeo dicendum quod de bono et malo in actionibus oportet loqui sicut de bono et malo in rebus .... ' The analytical philosophers derive a portion of their clarity on this issue from the celebrated remarks of David Hume on the difference between "is" and "ought": A Treatise on Human Nature, III, i,l. 3 See ST I, q. 5, q. 1. corpus, and many other places. Aquinas often quoted Aristotle's definition of "good" as what all things seek or tend toward (appetunt); the Stagirite's text is in the Nicomachaean Ethics, book I, chapter 1. 4 Ratio enim significata per nomen est id quod concipit intellectus de re et significat illud per vocem (ST I, q. 5, a. 2). Elsewhere, the ratio of a term is more closely identified AQUINAS ON THE EVALUATION OF HUMAN ACTIONS 349 anything to be called good; and in that sense it is the reason anything is rightly called "good." Second, appetitus and appetibile are broad terms. The former means any sort of tendency or inclination whatsoever. 5 The latter (the appetibile) refers to anything which has what it takes to satisfy any sort of inclination of any sort of being. 6 So in the dictum at hand (ratio boniest quod aliquid sit appetibile), Aquinas is saying that, vis-a-vis any kind of thing, S, an object or state having what it takes to satisfy an inclination found in S-things is "good" to (or for) S-things.' with its definition (cf. ST I, q. 13, a. 1). The ratio of a term need not be its sense but can just as well be the real aspect of a thing which corresponds to that sense and so fits or verifies the definition. 5 Aquinas takes appetitus so broadly as to include even gravitational or inertial phenomena. Hence those phenomenologists who prefer to start their account of "good" with admiration are not, in fact, offering a rival starting point. For wherever there is an inclination to admire something, that inclination will be an appetitus. 6 Among these potential satisfiers Aquinas counts not only objects external to the being, such as food, shelter, etc., but also states internal to it. In biological kinds, the mature state of the individual satisfies tendencies which are present in, but not yet satisfied in, the larval or juvenile state of the individual. 1 This account coincides with Aristotle's definition, on the supposition that Aristotle was offering a contextual definition of the phrase "good of," as in "the good of a stone." For then he was saying that, for all things x, the good of x = what x seeks or tends toward. Notice that the instrumental sense of"good," found in "pots are good for cooking," is set aside by Aristotle and Aquinas as another (and secondary) affair. For pots do not seek cooking; and stones, though good for throwing at malefactors, do not tend towards that employment. Rather, the focal and primary sense of "good" is the sense in which a benefit is good to a beneficiary. Thus an elementary statement of goodness becomes something like "Milk is good for me." The shorter sentence, "Milk is good," can then be construed. It is either an abbreviation of "Milk is good for me" or else an implicit generalization of it, meaning that milk is good for my species (people). "It is good for the spider to eat the fly" is ambiguous. Taken one way, it means that eating the fly is goodfor the spider, which is true for the most part. Taken the other way, it asserts some larger interest in light of which it is good that the spider eat the fly. This larger interest might be the environment, or the global eco-system. Artistotle and Aquinas would have talked about the "common good" of the universe. If this larger system tends or inclines towards a balance in the numbers of the species, and this balance is served by the spider's (rather often) eating the fly, then the tendency of the system is what makes the spider's predation "good." Indirectly, the fact that we humans are part of the system makes the spider's diet good for us as well. Thus goodness claims which appear theoretical or "absolute" are found to retain a core of intelligibility which is practical and evaluative. A person who literally had no inclinations and who therefore could not experience anything as appetibile could not 350 WILLIAM H. MARSHNER Now, if there is a kind of being S0 which has only one inclination, the above remarks suffice to say all that can be said about "good" for that kind of being. But for kinds of beings Si which have more than one inclination, there is more to be said. An object or state may have what it takes to satisfy one inclination of an Si-thing but not its others. Such an object or state is only "good to some extent" or "good in some respect." By contract, an object or state which had what it took to satisfy all the being's inclination would be good "period."' Aquinas had inherited a famous thesis to the effect that good is coextensive with being-that is, that "good" would be applicable wherever "exists" is applicable. To make this thesis come out right, Aquinas posited in every being an inclination to stay in being. In that way, for every being, the fact that it exists would satisfy one of its inclinations, so that its sheer being would be, for it, "good in some respect." 9 By salvaging (even in this way) the coextensivity thesis, Aquinas escaped the "naturalistic fallacy." That fallacy consists in thinking that goodness is a nature which some things have and others lack. 10 If that view were correct, "good" and "bad" would work like any contrasting pair of descriptive adjectives, such as "colored" and "colorless" or "animate" and "inanimate." There would then be good beings and bad beings, just as there are animate beings and inanimate ones. And in that case, the class of good beings would be narrower than the class of beings, just as the class of animate beings is narrower than the class of beings. Aquinas rejected all such ideas with the sweeping declaration that good "adds" nothing to being-adds nothing like a form or nature." understand what was meant by any claim of goodness. As we shall see in a moment, claims about the goodness of existence are no exception. 8 ST I, q. 5, a. I ad 1. Aquinas often thought of a thing's full maturity as a state toward which it was inclined and in which it would find all its inclinations satisfied. Such a state would represent its "perfection" and "complete good." To reach this state would be the "ultimate purpose" of the thing's tendings, inclinings, striving, etc. Aquinas affirmed the same connection between "ultimate purpose" and "complete good" in the case of man (ST I-II, q. 1), though he could point to no non-theological or this-worldly state in which all man's inclinations would be satisfied. 9 STI, q. 5, a. 1. ' 0 The classic discussion is G. E. Moore, Principia Ethica (Cambridge, 1959), 73. 11 See STI, q. 5, a. 3 ad 1. AQUINAS ON THE EVALUATION OF HUMAN ACTIONS 351 This account of "good" comes closer to the topic of human action, of course, as Aquinas leaves behind the very wide use of "good" just discussed and turns to the more familiar use that arises from human experience of the human inclinations. In human beings, the inclinations are managed (or mismanaged) by the will. 12 So the reason we call something "good" is that it is desirable. 13 Again the evaluative rather than disinterestedly of "good" in Aquinas is unmistakable. descriptive Moreover, "desirable" is ambiguous as between "in some respect" and "period." Because the will manages all the inclinations in the light of reason, what would satisfy one of my lower inclinations may be desirable at first blush (and so good "in some respect") and yet may fail to be desirable "all things considered," that is, in light of my other inclinations, needs, or interests (and so may fail to be desirable "period"). There is thus a potential, at least, for a conflict to arise between the desirability which is just "there already,'' prior to a reasoned judgment, and the desirability which consists precisely in a conformity to such judgment 14 This potential for conflict lends human interest to the difference between the desirability which is the reason we call something good "in that respect" and the desirability which is the reason we call something good "period." All the more interest attaches to it, when one asks how the reasoned judgment just mentioned, which in man's case is supposed to make this difference, is itself to be made. How do we reach an overall assessment? How do we compare the desirability (goodness) which a thing may have "in one respect" with its undesirability in some per voluntatem utimur omnibus quae in nobis sunt (ST I, q. 5, a. 4 ad 3). On the connections and overlaps between appetitus, desiderium, and voluntas, see ST I, q. 19, a. 9; I-II, q. 30, a. 1 ad 2; q. 56, a. 5 ad 1, etc. 14 According to I-II, q. 50, a. S ad 3, the "object" to which the human will is inclined by its very nature is the good which consists in being in accord with reason (bonum rationis); cf I-II. q. 56, a. 6. By this Aquinas underscores the difference between the will (a rational faculty) and the sense appetites. The goodness which is desirability to a sense appetite is pre-rational and may be experienced as counter-rational, that is, as a pull felt in the teeth of rational refusal. But the goodness which is willability is based on reason; it cannot be experienced as against reason, though the accord with reason may be dishonestly contrived through "rationalization." 12 ••• 13 352 WILLIAM H. MARSHNER other respect, so as to judge reasonably whether it is desirable or not "all things considered"? On this topic, the logic of applying "good" according to Aquinas lines up perfectly with some modern accounts of "evaluation" and conflicts with others. Let us look at an account with which he could agree. In recent thought, an evaluation is a procedure in which items of some kind are compared to certain criteria ("standards") and are graded on how they measure up. Thus apples are compared to criteria having to do with size, flavor, freshness. Shoes are compared to criteria having to do with style, comfort, durability. Each criterion is applied to the thing by checking some facet or aspect of the thing. If the facet has the feature demanded by a criterion, then the thing has some property which it ought to have. It is as it ought to be, at least in that respect. If the thing (apple or shoe) has every feature demanded by the criteria applied to it, then it is as it ought to be in every respect. It is "all it should be." If the thing fails to meet some criterion, it is "lacking" in that respect and so is "not all it should be." After the thing is compared to the criteria by this sort of application (checking of features), the thing is graded, and this grade is its evaluation proper. 15 Notice that the term "good" (or its opposite) can appear at two different places in this procedure. It can appear at the end as a final grade (whether as one of many grades, like "excellent," "good," "fair," "poor," etc., or as one of only two, like "good"/ "bad" in the sense of pass/fail). But it can also appear earlier on, at the feature-checking stage. As each facet of the item is checked against a relevant criterion, satisfactory fulfillment of that criterion can be marked by saying that the item is "good" in that respect (and this preliminary goodness can again be one of many marks or one of only two). Thus far, the account corresponds exactly to St. Thomas 's discussion of evaluation. "Good" as a final grade he calls bonum simpliciter, and he says in a crucial text that its ratio includes 15 159. 1 am indebted for this accounttoJ. 0. Urmson, "On Grading," Mind 59 (1950): 145- AQUINAS ON THE EVALUATION OF HUMAN ACTIONS 353 debita plenitudo essendi. 16 This last translates exactly as "all it should be." So the reason we grade anything as "good" is that it is all it should be. 11 "Good" as a mark on a feature, by contrast, he calls bonum secundum quid. But now we come to the interesting question, on which varieties of evaluation (and modern accounts of them) divide. The fact that there are two places where the term "good" can appear demands a way of getting from the one to the other. That is, the marks given feature-by-feature must lead somehow to the final grade. One kind of evaluation procedure will sum and average the marks to reach the grade, and so it requires a commensuration of the features, and one will have had to import enough arithmetic to allow for computation. Another kind of procedure introduces an order of rank among the criteria (or, equivalently, among the features that fulfill criteria), so that if a thing is good in one feature and bad in another, its grade will depend upon whether it is good in any feature that outranks the ones in which it is bad. But it is also possible to have an evaluation procedure without numbers or measures or rankings of any kind. Such a procedure would be the following. No matter how many features need to be checked, the marks applicable to each feature are just two ("good"/"bad"), and the overall grades are just two ("good"/"bad'), and the rule for getting from the former to the latter is this: the overall grade is "good" if and only if the mark on every required feature is "good"; otherwise, the overall grade is "bad." (Hence the grade is "bad" if and only if the mark on some feature is not "good.") This extremely parsimonious example of an evaluation scheme is of special philosophical interest for three reasons. First, it allows "bad" to be defined entirely by negation. As a final grade, "bad" simply means "not good." As a mark on a feature, "bad" also means "not good" (so that the ratio of the term is the same in both places) and hence means that the feature ST1-11, q. 18, a. 1. does not forget that how-all-the-thing-is becomes how-all-it-should-be (debita plenitudo) by the thing's having what it takes (in being how-all-it-is) to satisfy the appetitive faculties. This point is made explicit in 1-11, q. 18, a. 5 corpus and ad 2. 16 17 Aquinas 354 WILLIAM H. MARSHNER demanded is "not there." Hence the famous neo-Platonic and Patristic thesis that evil is privation-privation of a good, hence absence of a "due" feature-is fully supported.'" Secondly, this scheme can be formalized in a modal secondorder predicate calculus using only the quantifiers "all" and "some." An object x of the kind Sis graded "good" if and only if, for all predicates , it ought to be the case that an S-thing is , and xis ." It follows by elementary logic that an object x of the kind S is graded "not-good" if and only if, for some predicate , it ought to be the case that an S-thing is and x is not . 20 The grade "bad" can then be introduced by definition as "not-good." Such a formalization confirms that no recourse to rank, number, quantitative, or arithmetical operation on measurements is required. Thirdly, the parsimonious scheme is explicitly that of Aquinas. His basic rule for getting from the marks to the grade is that a thing is malum simpliciter when it is merely bonum secundum quid (that is, good in some respect but not in every respect). This rule is stated in converse form at ST I, q. 11, a. 2 ad 1: if anything is merely bonum secundum quid, then it is malum simpliciter. But there is no question that he accepts the rule running the other way as well: if anything is malum simpliciter, then it is bonum secundum quid. For he holds that the bad thing at least exists, and that whatever exists is good to that extent (ST I, q. 5, a. 1 ad 1; a. 3 ad 2). For what fails to be good in even that respect is just "nothing" and is not evaluated; if it is 18 By contrast, an evaluation procedure which averages the marks has to set an arbitrary number n as the cut-off point, has to define "good" as "higher than or equal ton," and has to define "bad" as "lower than n." Thus the ratio of "good" and the ratio of "bad" include relatively opposed relations to n. An evaluation procedure which ranks the criteria has to define the grade "bad" as "lacking an important feature" or "not good in an important respect," whereas the mark "bad" just means "lacking a feature." The ranking relation enters, in other words, into the ratio of "good" and "bad" as grades but not into the ratio of "good" and "bad" as marks. Hence the two rationes split apart, even though, in each, "bad" might be defined as "not good." 19 In symbols: Sx ::::>(goodx = "ifq>(O((y)(Sy::::> q>y)) ::::> q>x)), where "0" is a deontic modal operator ("it ought to be the case that"). 20 That is: Sx ::::> (-good x = 34J(O((y)(Sy ::::> q>y)). -q>x)). AQUINAS ON THE EVALUATION OF HUMAN ACTIONS 355 not evaluated, it is not "bad." 21 In many places, Aquinas states the rule in the form in which he found it in his source, Denis: quilibet singularis defectus causat malum, bonum autem causatur ex integra causa. 22 In keeping with this formulation, he says innumerable times that malum is privatio boni. 23 Hence "bad" is defined by negation; "good" and "bad" as grades differ as "all demanded features are there" differs from "some demanded features is not there", and "good" and "bad" as marks on a facet as "the demanded feature is there" differs from "it is not there." From mark to grade, the ratio remains constant; "bad" is rigorously defined by negation of "good," in whose ratio no appeal to rank or measurement is made. Nor is any admissible. For a thing which is good overall has to have no less than every feature demanded by the relevant criteria. THE EVALUATION OF HUMAN ACTIONS With this background in place, St. Thomas 's opening declaration in I-II, q. 18, a. 1, that "good" and "bad" are to be asserted of human actions in the same way as they are asserted of other things, becomes informative. It allows one to predict much of what the articles in Question 18 will cover. One can predict that calling an action good will mean that it is good for man-a good way for a human to act. One can predict that something will be said about the "standards" or "criteria" by which human actions are judged to be good for man. One can predict that the facets upon which these criteria bear will be listed, so that one can see what will need to be checked in evaluating a human action. One can predict that the interesting goodness or badness of human actions-their moral goodness or badness-will be reached via marks on their features, in the parsimonious way already discussed. These predictions are quickly fulfilled. We are told in article 1 21 Si vero nihil haberet de entitate vel bonitate, neque malum neque bonum did posset (ST I-II, q. 18, a. 1). Notice again that the famous slogan, Bonum convertitur cum ente, concerns "good" as a mark on a feature-bonum secundum quid. It has nothing to do with "good" as a final grade, which emphatically does not apply to every being. 22 Pseudo-Dionysius the Areopagite, De divinis nominibus, chapter 4. See ST I-II, q. 18, a. 4 ad 3, for example. 23 E.g., ST I, q. 19, a. 9; I-II, q. 18, a. 2 ad 2; q. 21, a. 1 356 WILLIAM H. MARSHNER that a human action is not evaluated on the existential basis that it takes place or fails to take place. For, while an action can be called good just for existing (omnis actio, inquantum habet aliquid de esse, intantum habet de bonitate ), that talk is irrelevant. For whether the action happens will not turn out to be a feature that is marked in its moral evaluation. Rather, the basis for evaluation is whether the action is "all it should be" as a human action: inquantum vero deficit ei aliquid de plenitudine essendi quae debetur actioni humanae, intantum deficit a bonitate, et sic dicitur mala. We are told that this "all" of what an action should be is not reducible to causal issues like efficacy. For an action will have its causal efficacy through the positive being it has and not through what will make it bad, if it is bad (namely, its lack). The example given is adulterous intercourse, which is highly efficacious towards offspring and yet is not all a human action should be. We are told that what it lacks is "order of reason." 24 This is a first indication that the criteria for human actions are "ordinations" of reason, so that the features demanded in human actions are conformities to these ordinations. A long way ahead, in I-II, qq. 90ff., we shall be told that the "ordinations" set by reason are universal propositions of practical reason bearing upon actions and having what it takes to be called "laws" (having the ratio legis).25 We shall be told that these laws or precepts derive from first principles such as "Good is to be done and its opposite avoided" 26 and the Golden Rule 21 ; we shall be told that the derivable precepts include the moral content of the Decalogue,28 and that they therefore include precepts which admit of no exception or "dispensation." 29 Thus a human acton will be "good" in case (and only in case) it is "all it should be" in conforming to precepts derivable by rea24 Ad tertium dicendum quod actio mala potest habere aliquem effectum per se secundum id quod habet de bonitate et entitate. Sicut adulterium est causa generationis humanae inquantum habet commixtionem maris et feminae, non autem inquantum caret ordine rationis (I-II, q. 18, a. 1 ad 3). 25 1-11, q. 90, a. 1. 26 1-11, q. 94, a. 2. 21 1-11, q. 100, a. 3. 28 Ibid. 29 1-11, q. 100, a. 8. AQUINAS ON THE EVALUATION OF HUMAN ACTIONS 35 7 son. This conclusion makes sense, because a human action is not so much a good we seek (an object of inclination) as a way of pursuing a good we seek. The "good" actions will be the good ways of pursuing the things we seek. The "good" ways, in turn, will be those which have what it takes to satisfy a desire we have bearing upon our ways of pursuing things. Well, we have various desires bearing on these: we want our ways of pursuing things to be easy (if possible), efficient, enjoyable (if possible), not too tiring, and so on. But controlling all of these preferences, and generating them, is the constant desire which Aquinas calls the natural desire of our will, namely, that our ways of pursuing things make sense, that they be intelligent, that they be reasonable. 30 The features demanded of these ways, therefore, will not be physical features having what it takes to satisfy a drive but conformities-to-reason, having what it takes to satisfy a desire for practical reasonableness. Next, in articles 2, 3, and 4, we are quickly told which facets of a human action have to be checked to see if the conformities demanded are there. Three facets are listed: genus ex objecto, circumstantiae,finis. These amount respectively to: (1) the specific kind to which the action belongs, when it is classified according to the verb-and-object needed to express what the agent is choosing to do to what, or to whom; (2) the circumstances in which a token of that specific kind would be realized, if the agent were to perform the action as he has chosen; (3) the further purpose (if any) for the sake of which the agent would be choosing to do the action. These three facets are such that each can have the feature of conforming to reason through consistency with a precept of reason, and each can lack this feature; each mark of "good" (or "bad") means that a conformity-to-precept is there (not there) and hence is a moral mark; and the procedure for getting from the moral marks to the moral grade is just what we should expect-every facet has to be marked "good" (has to conform to precept), or else the action gets "morally bad" for its grade. 31 30 See above, note 14. 31 See 1-11, q. 18, a. 4 ad 3. 358 WILLIAM H. MARSHNER (Next, a graded action is subject to further classification into a "moral kind,'' according to article 5, as an act of some virtuea specific way of being completely reasonable--or as an act of some vice-a specific way of being unreasonable-but we shall not pursue that matter in these pages.) Such, at least, is the classical interpretation of Aquinas's remarks on the evaluation of human actions. Since it offers a trouble-free reading of I-II, q. 18, and connects well with St. Thomas 's more general goodness and badness, it has a degree of plausibility. Yet the interpretation just presented has a rival which deserves consideration. The rival has been advanced by Josef Fuchs, Louis J anssens, and Richard McCormick, three of the most eminent moralists writing in recent decades. A QUESTION OF CLASSIFICATION To introduce the view shared by these contemporary moralists, it is useful to note that, of the three facets which are to be marked, according to Aquinas, the first, the genus ex objecto, holds a special status. Aquinas says that a mark of "good" on this facet is the "first goodness" of a human action-first, because it is the goodness which the action has already in "being what it is." 32 Likewise, a mark of "bad" on this facet is the "first badness." 33 In the classical interpretation, what this amounts to saying is quite simple. Nothing can be evaluated unless and until it is classified. No hunk of stuff can have criteria applied to it, until we are told what it is. Moral evaluation, too, falls upon a classified act. I cannot tell you whether you did right or wrong without knowing what you did. But as soon as I know, I have something to mark. Now notice: if this first mark is "bad,'' I need not consider any further facet (circumstance or purpose) given Aquinas's evaluation procedure. For badness in this first facet is quidam defectus, 32 Primum au tern quod ad plenitudinem essendi pertinere videtur est id quod dat rei speciem .... Et ideo sicut prima bonitas rei naturalis attenditur ex sua forma quae dat speciem ei, ita et prima bonitas actus moralis attenditur ex objecto convenienti; unde et a quibusdam vocatur bonum ex genere (I-II, q. 18, a. 2). 3·3 Et sicut in rebus naturalibus primum malum est, si res generata non consequitur formam specificam, puta si non generetur homo, sed aliquid loco hominis; ita primum malum in actionibus moralibus est quod est ex objecto (I-II, q. 18, a. 2). AQUINAS ON THE EVALUATION OF HUMAN ACTIONS 359 and a human action is morally bad (grade) ex quocumque defectu. But this in turn means that a norm can be formulated, picking out a kind of action which is mala ex objecto, describing that action only in its genus ex objecto, and saying that an action of that kind is never to be done-and such a norm will be true. For any exercise done by anyone, in any circumstance, for any reason, which has what it takes to fall into that kind will have the defectum of that kind and so will be a morally bad action. 34 In a word: if Aquinas says that a moral mark can be put on an action's kind-from-its-object, then his teaching leads at once to "moral absolutes" of the sort which it has been fashionable to question recently.35 Moralists of a proportionalist bent, who wish to annex the prestige of the Common Doctor, must therefore find a way to eliminate this feature from his teaching. The move made by Janssens, Fuchs, and McCormick serves this purpose. It can be explained but taking a look at a key text in I-II, q. 1, a. 3. That article is about the classification of human actions. In it, Aquinas says that human actions get classified on the basis of their end. For if actions are looked at as man moving or changing himself, the end is their starting-point. For actions are human insofar as they proceed from deliberated willing; what gets willed (the objectum voluntatis) is the good and the end; hence the starting-point of human acts qua human is the end. Alternatively, if human acts are looked at as man moved or changed by himself, the end is their terminal-point. For that at which a human course of action terminates is that which the will intends as the end. In this article two of the objections are important. The first says that a thing has to get its species from something intrinsic to it; but the end is an extrinsic cause of the action; 34 In the language of his commentary on the Sentences, book II, d. 40, a. 2, such an actus will be de se malus, qui nullo modo benefieri potest. 35 John G. Milhaven, "Moral Absolutes in Thomas Aquinas," in Charles Curran, ed., Absolutes in Moral Theology (Washington, D.C.: Corpus, 1968), 1S4-18S;John F. Dedek, "Intrinsically Evil Acts: An Historical Study of the Mind of St. Thomas," The Thomist 43 (1979): 38Sff. For discusion and further bibliography see Patrick Lee, "Permanence of the Ten Commandments: St. Thomas and His Modern Commentators," Theological Studies 42 (1981): 422-443; William E. May, Moral Absolutes (Milwaukee, Wisc.: Marquette, 1989), and John Finnis, Moral Absolutes (Washington, D.C.: Catholic University Press, 1991). 360 WILLIAM H. MARSHNER so it cannot give it its species. Aquinas replies (adl) by denying that the end is entirely "extrinsic" to the action. For the action is a change, in which the end can be looked at either as startingpoint a quo or as terminal-point ad quem-neither of which is extrinsic to a change. The other important objection is the third, in which the issue is whether ends can secure uniqueness of classification. It reads: a thing can only exist in one "species," but numerically one and the same human act can be ordered to diverse ends; therefore the end does not give the act its species. St. Thomas replies by distinguishing the minor and then by bringing up a related item of business. So the reply (ad 3) falls into two parts. Here they are. (a) Numerically one action, as it flows from the agent at a unique moment, is ordered to just one proximate end and gets its classification from that; but it can be ordered to several more remote ends, of which each is for the sake of the next. (b) However, the following is possible. One and the same kind of action, typed by natural kind, can be ordered to diverse ends of the will [fines voluntatis, i.e. intended ends], and the result will be diverse actionsdiverse in moral kind. Thus the natural kind of action which is killing a man can be intended to preserve justice or can be intended to slake wrath. If intended the first way, it will be an act of virtue; if intended the other way, an act of vice. For a change is not classified by that which is its term per accidens but only by which is its term per se. Moral ends are accidental to a natural thing; but the reverse is also true: the natural basis for assigning an end to something is accidental to a moral thing. Hence nothing prevents acts which are the same in natural kind from being diverse in moral kind; and, vice versa, nothing prevents acts which are the same in moral kind from being diverse in natural kind. 36 The obvious (and traditional) way to line this text up with the Ad tertium dicendum quod idem actus numero, secundum quod semel egreditur ab agente, non ordinatur nisi ad unum finem proximum, a quo habet speciem; sed potest ordinari ad plures fines remotos, quorum unus est finis alterius. Possibile tamen est quod unus actus secundum speciem naturae ordinetur ad diversos fines voluntatis, sicut hoc ipsum quod est occidere hominem, quod est idem secundum speciem naturae, potest ordinari sicut in finem ad conservationem justitiae et ad satisfaciendum irae; et ex hoc erunt diversi actus secundum speciem moris, quia uno modo erit actus virtutis, alio modo erit actus vitii. Non enim motus recipit speciem ab eo quod est terminus per accidens, sed solum ab eo quod est terminus per se. Fines autem morales accidunt rei naturali; et e converso ratio naturalis finis accidit morali; et ideo nihil prohibet actus qui sunt idem secundum speciem naturae esse diversos secundum speciem moris, et e converso. 36 AQUINAS ON THE EVALUATION OF HUMAN ACTIONS 361 doctrine in I-II, q. 18 is to take one's clue from the part labelled (a). One identifies "object" and "proximate end," so that kindfrom-the-object = classification from proximate end. Then, since the proximate end is an intended end (finis voluntatis), it will follow that the action already classified by its object is a "moral thing"-a human, willed action-so that it can be evaluated morally, and the mark upon it will be a moral mark, just as articles 2-4 in q. 18 seem to say and were classically interpreted to say.31 But part (b) is the text upon which Janssens, Fuchs, and 37 In other words, Aquinas provides two major texts in the Summa Theologiae on the classification of human actions. In one he says that an action is put into its kind by its proximate end, and in the other he says that an action is put into its kind by its object. If these two texts are to hang together, there are three possibilities. Either (I) the kind based on the object and kind based on the proximate end are identical, or else (2) they classify on different levels, with one of them putting the action into a genus, the other putting it into its sub-genus or species, or else (3) the kinds are independent but both apply. Perhaps all three possibilities turn up, but the first is the common one-so common that Aquinas seems to have thought it needed no discussion. A simple example, such as washing the car, will serve to illustrate it. The proximate end is the agent's most immediate purpose in acting. Oftentimes, a statement of one's most immediate purpose will not differ (or will differ only slightly) from what one ordinarily thinks of as a statement of what one is doing. For example, if I am washing the car so as to get ready for a trip, the trip is my ulterior purpose, and to prepare for it or "get ready" is the intermediate purpose, but my immediate purpose in ading is to wash the car, or to get the washing over and done with. This is why I am bustling about in the driveway with a hose. Thus, if we call this end (to wash the car) ewe• we can say that it puts the bustling into the kind 'KwC' That is, the intended end classifies my bustling by putting it into the end-based kind ('K) which is washing the car. The object is the matter with which the action deals (materia circa quam). One should think of this "matter" in grammatical terms. I start with the verb that would be involved in expressing what I am considering doing, e.g., "wash." I add whatever nouns or nounphrases would be needed to complete the expression of what I am considering doing, e.g., "my car." This is the object, and "wash my car" is a kind of action (genus ex objecto). Suppose we call it °Kwc for short, and suppose I choose to do it. Do I also intend it? Do we have the result that °Kwc = 'Kwc in the case at hand? In the Commentary on II Sentences, d. 40, a. 2, Aquinas used objectus proximus and finis proximus interchangeably. For they mean the same whenever one uses one's proximate end to describe one's means. An action of the object-based kind "wash my car" could easily be chosen as a means in the project to get ready for a trip. Thus it is easy to see that one's "means" will often be an object-based kind of action. Aquinas says that, once a means is chosen, its execution becomes one's most immediate end, and in that capacity it is intended (I-II, q. 12, a. 2). Hence the frequent identity of kind-from-object and kind-from-proximate-purpose. See also I-II, q. 20, a. 4, and q. 72, a. 3 ad 2. These texts are discussed in Joseph Boyle, "Praeter intentionem in Aquinas," The Thomist 42 (1978): 649-665. 362 WILLIAM H. MARSHNER McCormick seize. They identify the "natural kind" mentioned here with the kind-from-the-object mentioned in q. 18.38 They identify the "end of the will" mentioned here with the "purpose" mentioned in I-II, q. 18, a. 4. It follows at once that the "object" pertains to a pre- or sub-intentional "materiality" of the act, such as bustling about in the driveway or causing a death-so that it cannot connect with a definite moral evaluation. 39 Hence different action-tokens of any one genus ex objecto can be ordered to different intended ends and thereby receive different and even opposite moral classifications. 40 And so no action, taken only in its genus ex objecto, will be open to receive a moral mark. McCormick writes: "Acts that have the same features as object-events can have a different morality." 41 Fuchs writes: "But now the critical question: what value do our norms have with respect to the morality of the action as such [he means, ex objecto ], prior, that is, to consideration of the circumstances and intention? We answer: they cannot be moral norms unless circumstances and intention are taken into account." 42 38 This move is most explicit in Louis Janssens, "Ontic Evil and Moral Evil," Louvain Studies 4 (1972): 115-156, at 123-124. 39 Janssens et al. do not acknowledge adequately the clash which their interpretation creates between these texts and the rest of Thomistic action theory. J anssens (Joe. cit.) recognizes that in Aquinas (I-II, q. 19) the agent's choice is the inner core of the action, so that what one has chosen to do is what kind of action one is doing. But Janssens et al. have to make this a secondary truth. For if the "object" gives the action its quiddity, but this quiddity is "natural kind," then every human action is in essence some kind of natural process, some kind of limb locomotion. Such bustle is already what-it-is prior to and independent of the agent's choice to do anything. The meaning given to the bustle by the agent's intention must be at best a secondary and supervenient "whatness," as when one reclassifies a rock as a sculpture, or an ink-spot as a symbol, by giving it a meaning. '° For Aquinas (I-II, q. 18, a. 6), some genera ex objecto are morally indifferent (so that there will be some cases in which action-tokens of a common genus ex objecto receive opposite moral evaluations, thanks to differences of circumstances or purpose); but the J anssens-Fuchs-McCormick interpretation requires all genera ex objecto to be of this nature. 41 Richard A. McCormick, Notes on Moral Theology, 1965-1980 (Washington, D.C.: University Press of America, 1981), 534. 42 Josef Fuchs, Personal Responsibility and Christian Morality (Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press, 1983), 138. Chapter 7 of this book, from which the quote is taken, bears the title "The Absoluteness of Behavioral Moral Norms"; it had been published separately in Gregorianum a dozen years earlier (1971). AQUINAS ON THE EVALUATION OF HUMAN ACTIONS 363 The violence which this "we answer" does to the Catholic moral tradition, destroying all moral absolutes at a single stroke, has been widely discussed. 43 The untenability of the basic move from which the "answer" follows, namely, the identification of object-kind with natural-kind, has been thoroughly established by William E. May. 44 I should like to highlight the impact upon Aquinas's evaluation procedure. THE "NUANCE" THAT ANNIHILATES If object-kind = natural-kind = behavior described in "brute" or sub-intentional terms, then the goodness or badness which Aquinas says an action can have "first" in its object-kind must be a pre-moral goodness or badness. The bustle produces this liked (or disliked) effect as a sheer causal consequence, and that is now the first goodness (or badness). What is the next? What about the other facets which are checked, according to Aquinas, before a grade is reached-the circumstances and purpose? Are their goodness and badness pre-moral, too? Yes, says Fuchs: "A moral judgement is legitimately formed under a simultaneous consideration of the three elements (action, circumstances, purpose), premoral in themselves."'' McCormick praises this drawing together of the three elements as a balanced "nuancing" of the tradition. 46 If that is so, then in successively checking object, circumstances, and end, one is registering pre-moral goods and bads. The moral evaluation has not begun yet. The evaluation-logic repeatedly stressed by Aquinas cannot be the moral evaluationlogic. It must be pre-moral. It must tell us that, if an action is pre-morally good in some respect but not in another, then the action is pre-morally bad "period." But since (the proportional43 See above, note 35; also John Finnis, Fundamentals of Ethics (Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press, 1983), chapter 4; Germain Grisez, "Moral Absolutes, A Critique of the View of Josef Fuchs, S.J.," Anthropos 112 (1985): 155-201. (This journal is now called Anthropotes .) 44 "Aquinas and Janssens on the Moral Meaning of Human Acts," The Thomist 48 (J 984): 566-606. 45 Fuchs, Personal Responsibility, 137. 46 Notes, 534. 364 WILLIAM H. MARSHNER ists think) an action can be pre-morally bad but morally good, this is only another way of saying that the moral evaluation has not begun yet. And if that is so then nothing which Aquinas tells us in I-II q. 18 pertains to moral evaluation. "Unlikely" is rather too mild a word for an interpretation which removes from the Prima Secundae all discussion of one of its most important topics. THE CONTROLLING BELIEF Unlikely theories are sometimes true, however; and what one thinks of the Fuchs-McCormick-Janssens theory will depend almost entirely on whether one believes that an action-evaluation is supposed to take one from a set of pre-moral goods and bads to a judgment of moral good (or bad). If one believes this, the account in Aquinas cannot seem complete. For a pre-moral bad is any damage whatsoever, including the unintentional, from a disappointment to a death, from a bruised tomato to a soul in hell. Aquinas can hardly have considered all such damages equal, but nowhere does he give us an explicit account of "greater" evil or good. Call this the missing piece. Now read q. 18 without the missing piece, as though it were intended to be complete without it, and yet were intended to take us from pre-moral marks to a moral grade. It would be saying that any pre-moral badness in any action-facet to be checked suffices to make the action itself morally bad. Aquinas would be giving a moral veto power to any damage done, intentionally or unintentionally, however slight. The Common Doctor would be a moralistic utopian. To save him from such an obvious blunder, one will entertain the hypothesis that Aquinas did not really mean to use his doctrine of evaluation, but meant to replace it with something more sensible, like a scheme in which the pre-moral goods are added up, the bads are subtracted, and the action is morally good as long as it scores above zero; alternatively, one might entertain the hypothesis that the entire text of I-II q. 18 was intended to cover a preliminary question only (how to get from pre-moral marks to a pre-moral grade). Either way, one will be insisting that Aquinas left the central question AQUINAS ON THE EVALUATION OF HUMAN ACTIONS 365 (how to get a moral grade) undiscussed. For then the undiscussed question can be answered by the missing piece. Tacit "weights" or "ranks" can serve to distinguish the greater from the lesser evil, and then those actions which do plenty of pre-moral evil can still get the moral grade of "good" in case the evil they do is "lesser evil" compared to the good they do, or compared to the damage their alternatives would do, or something of the kind. Many people writing about ethics today believe that an action evaluation must (in some such way) move from pre-moral marks to a moral grade. Fuchs and McCormick believe it. Therefore they supply the missing piece (the weights and measures) while still claiming to speak for the Catholic tradition. Fuchs writes: "Negative values are to be avoided ... and only for adequate reasons may they be actualized concurrently with relatively higher and more urgent values." 47 Higher values? Then there must be ranks. More urgent values? Then there must be weights. McCormick writes: "If it is only object-end-circumstances together that can yield a final moral evaluation, the implication is that it is a proportion within the entire action between the values and disvalues that justifies the causing or permitting of the disvalues. "' 8 McCormick is talking here about Fuchs's view, but he states several times that (certain matters of clarity aside) he shares the view. For both men (and for Janssens), moral evaluation is looking at all three facets simultaneously, and is weighing the pre-moral goods and bads found in each, and is assigning the moral grade "good" to the actions which sport a proportionate surplus of pre-moral value over disvalue. This last and crucial fact Aquinas merely neglected (in their view) to mention. But let us consider another possibility altogether. Suppose the controlling belief of the three recent moralists is wrong. Suppose the evaluation of a human action has nothing to do with premoral goods and bads in general, because such things are not even relevant except insofar as they are intended or chosen.4 9 Personal Responsibility, 141 Notes, 533. 49 Proportionalists assume that cases become "hard" independently of intentions because of sheer causal problems-as when some event involved in the execution of an 47 48 366 WILLIAM H. MARSHNER Suppose further that all humanly intendable goods are participations in certain basic forms of human flourishing. Suppose that all genuine precepts therefore take either (a) the positive form of directing one to choose an action in which one would be pursuing one of these forms of flourishing intentionally or else (b) the negative form of directing one not to choose actions which are such that, by choosing them, one would be damaging one of these forms of flourishing intentionally-so that no genuine precept directs one to count or weigh up pre-moral goods and bads in general, and so none directs one to abstain from doing any sort of pre-moral damage except in conjunction with some higherranked pre-moral good, and so none tells one to choose such actions as sport the better proportion or surplus of such things. In short, suppose that rational precept-formation simply does not generate any such precept as Fuchs et al. want to introduce. 50 Then no step in an action evaluation procedure will be an application of such a precept, and so no prior step will need to be an assessment of pre-moral goods and bads in general. Rather, an evaluation will move from preliminary moral judgments to a action causally damages one good in producing another. Thus Peter Knauer, "The Hermeneutic Function of the Principle of Double Effect," in Charles E. Curran and Richard A. McCormick, eds., Readings in Moral Theology No. 1 (New York: Paulist, 1979); Bruno Schiiller, "The Double Effect in Catholic Thought: A Revolution," in Richard McCormick and Paul Ramsey, eds., Doing Evil to Achieve Good (Chicago: Loyola University Press, 1978). Such authors ignore or dismiss the long and profound tradition which says that cases become hard because of complications in distinguishing between intending evil (choosing to produce evil in order to produce good, which is always wrong) and foreseeing evil (choosing to produce good when there will be a bad side-effect, which is not always wrong). See Germain Grisez, The Way of the Lord Jesus, vol. 1, Christian Moral Principles (Chicago: Franciscan Herald Press, 1983), chapters 8H, 9, and 12F; John Finnis, "Object and Intention in Moral Judgments according to Aquinas," The Thomist 55 (1991): 1-27; idem, "Intention and Side-Effects," in R. G. Frey and C. Morris, eds., Liability and Responsibility (Cambridge University Press, 1991). 50 Germain Grisez has argued that such a precept is without application because the "thing" it directs one to discover in a given case (the greater good, higher value, or better proportion) cannot be found in that case, nor in any case, because it is not "there" to be discovered; the terms "greater good," "higher value," and "better proportion" have neither clear sense nor objective reference; what they mean is rather a projection of the agent's own subjective preferences. See "Against Consequentialism," American Journal of Jurisprudence 23 (1978): 21-72; The Way of the Lord Jesus, vol. 1, Christian Moral Principles, 141-172. AQUINAS ON THE EVALUATION OF HUMAN ACTIONS 367 final and also moral judgment. And then the account in Aquinas's q. 18 will not seem incomplete. For a moral bad is a conflict with a moral precept-and in Aquinas's account such precepts identify the basic human goods and direct that they not be violated, by anyone, so that through one's actions one will "love" one's neighbor as one's self. A conflict with moral precept in any action-facet to be checked will make the action itself immoral. To see this, consider the project of throwing a party with plenty of liquor. One ought to be a generous host (precept); so the projected action is good in its genus ex objecto (preliminary moral judgment). But what if the invited guests are recovering alcoholics? One ought not subject vulnerable people to needless dangers (precept). So there is an immorality under that circumstance (preliminary moral judgment). Or what if circumstances are fine, but one's further purpose is to enroll the invitees in a fraudulent business scheme? One ought not steal (precept). So there is an immorality in that motive (preliminary moral judgment). Would either immorality suffice to make the partyproject as a whole immoral (final judgment)? The account of action evaluation in I-II q. 18 is about exactly such a question, and the Common Doctor's answer is yes. Does it any longer seem utopian? Is there any longer room, or need, for a missing piece? FIRST CONCLUSION Neither Janssens nor Fuchs nor McCormick offers a reasoned case that action evaluation does take one from the pre-moral goods and bads to the moral. They just assume that it does. They import their assumption into a matter of Thomistic interpretation. Under the influence of their assumption, the obvious and traditional sense of I-II, q. 18 is swept away, to be replaced by a sense which cannot be made plausible without the further importation of weights or ranks plus a controversial sort of precept to go with them. Yet any alleged precept which directs one to realize a weighted good (the greater good or the better proportion of good over evil) is inadmissible within the ethics of Aquinas. It cannot be a missing piece of his doctrine, which he would have supplied, if 368 WILLIAM H. MARSHNER he had had occasion to do so, or which we can patch into his system as a part consistent with the remainder of it. For as seen above, Aquinas has an account of good (and of evil as a privation of good) which depends upon a single, parsimonious account of evaluation, applicable across the board to anything whatsoever, including human actions. Formalizable entirely with "all" and "some," this account allows no room for either a ranking of criteria or a commensuration of values and disvalues. If Aquinas is right in his parsimony, then no application of a precept such as Fuchs, McCormick, and Janssens want would be a case of practical reasoning. For practical reasoning is reason evaluating, while any such precept would direct one not to evaluate (precisely not to do what Aquinas calls evaluating) but instead to do something else-e.g. to prefer, so as to realize the results one prefers to realize. Thus, in order to support their interpretation, Fuchs, Janssens, and McCormick need to import a sense of "evaluate" which has no foundation in Aquinas, and which is in fact inconsistent with his theory of the good. SECOND CONCLUSION Is a proportionalist sense of "evaluate" really so unassimilable as all that? Every teacher with a grade book, who averages test scores at the end of the semester, proves in practice that there is a richer and more nuanced evaluation procedure than the one Aquinas espoused. Would it not be possible to replace the Common Doctor's procedure with another one-if not in the name of "interpreting" him, then frankly in the name of improving on him? And could not one manage some such replacement without destroying, perhaps, the larger architecture of Thomism? Let us begin the answer with an elementary distinction. The "good" is what we reasonably desire, and the "endurable" is what we put up with. What we reasonably desire is one thing, and what we will find endurable is often another: 5 ' 51 A teacher reasonably desires each of his students to acquire and display a mastery of the course material-which is, in effect, to earn an A. Yet a teacher will find C work, or even worse work, endurable. AQUINAS ON THE EVALUATION OF HUMAN ACTIONS 369 Any evaluation procedure which uses in a significant way a ranking of the criteria or a commensurating and averaging of the features looked for is a procedure to find the endurable. For what one reasonably desires is articulated in the whole set of criteria and would be realized in their joint satisfaction. The point of ranking or averaging is rather to allow some criteria to fail of satisfaction without losing more than one will find endurable. A "richer and more nuanced" evaluation procedure, then, reconciles its user to a poorer outcome. That is its whole purpose. 12 Proportionalists insist on using such a procedure because they think that good human actions differ from evil ones not as the rational (in every relevant respect) differs from the irrational (in some relevant respect) but as more differs from less along a scale, somewhat as one student paper offers more correct answers than another. Proportionalism (1) posits such a scale in pre-moral damages, and then (2) imagines that worse actions differ from better ones as more damage differs from less along this scale, and then (3) imagines that moral goodness consists in an action's being better than (or no worse than) its alternatives by that measure. Thus, if taken seriously as an account of moral evaluation, proportionalism identifies what we reasonably desire with an impossible ideal of doing no damage (including no unintentional damage), and so directs us to distinguishes the unattainable good from the attainable but endurable evil, and then directs us to choose those actions which are endurable. In so doing, proportionalism detaches moral goodness from reasonable desirability 52 Insofar as a teacher's familiar grading system is used to determine who gets an A and who does not, it measures whether all the teacher reasonably desires is present in the student's work. But insofar as the grading system is used to determine who passes or fails, it measures whether a mere portion of what is reasonably desired is there. This portion is what the teacher will find endurable (putting up with the absence of the rest). So if the teacher used his grading system to determine only A's and non-A's, his procedure would be substantially the same as Aquinas describes. By contrast, the use of numbers, the weighting of answers so as to map them to larger or smaller numbers (of points taken off), and the averaging of numbers-these features play a significant role only in discriminating less-than-good-but-still-endurable papers from those which are not even endurable. 370 WILLIAM H. MARSHNER and attaches it instead to possible or preferable endurability. Endurability becomes the ratio bani moralis. If that move is accepted, "good" as applied to human actions will not have the ratio bani which is applied elsewhere in Thomism, and nothing of its axiological architecture will survive. For under St. Thomas's ratio, the "good" (of a being) has what it takes to be the object of an inclination (in that being). In the universe of natures, every being has its inclinations, but no being strives, inclines, or tends merely to what it will endure. Each strives for a flourishing. 53 In the larger architecture of Thomism, man forms a part of the universe of natures. Man, too, has appetitus, and his distinctively human mode of appetition is reasonable desire. Therefore, in the larger architecture of Thomism, man not only desires to flourish (rather than just endure) but also finds his desire fulfilled when he abounds in reasonableness. The distinctively human strength (virtus) is the strength of character whereby a human can keep all of his or her actions in accord with rationally derived precepts or can even exceed those precepts in the direction of a God-given charity. Hence by no stretch of the imagination will man flourish by declining to abound in reason, e.g., by settling for an endurable level of irrationality. Therefore, in the larger architecture of Thomism, proportionalism directs man to act against his nature. Proportionalism counsels a certain moderation in the pursuit of virtue, and Thomism construes such moderation as unnatural vice. 53 Darwin would agree. In the bruising competition of the species, each plant and animal secures its hold on life only by striving for more than it will find endurable. Survival depends on striving to flourish. ST. THOMAS'S FOURTH WAY AND CREATION LAWRENCE DEWAN, 0.P Dominican College of Philosophy and Theology Ottawa, Ontario, Canada E XPLAINING that what he means by "creating" is "causing things ex nihilo," Jacques Maritain, the renowned twentieth-century interpreter of Thomas Aquinas, says: ... it is clear that this very fact, that things are created, is only known by us once we know that the First Cause exists; consequently, we cannot make use of it in order to demonstrate the existence of that First Cause. All we know from the outset is that things are caused. 1 This remark is made concerning all five ways. At the same time, Maritain presents the five not only as "typically distinct" from each other, but as ... distributed in a certain order in which the depth of thought and the complexity of the discussion increase. In proportion as the mind delves deeper into the world of experience in order to reach the first starting point of its thinking, it discerns in the First Being more and more meaningful aspects, and richer perspectives are disclosed to it. 2 Now, I agree entirely as to the depth of the starting-points and the progressively richer perspectives,' but I disagree with Maritain as to the role of the creature's createdness in leading to the knowledge of God in the Fourth Way. How is it "clear" that the createdness of things is only known once we know that a first cause exists? How, in general, does the createdness of things 1 Maritain, Jacques, Approaches to God, tr. Peter O'Reilly (New York: Collier Books, 1962), 64; see Approches de Dieu (Paris: Alsatia, 1953), 79.-ln this paper, "ST'' and "SCG" stand for Thomas Aquinas's Summa theologiae and Summa contra gentiles. 2 Maritain, Approaches, 63; Approches, 76-77. 3 See my paper, "The Number and Order of St. Thomas's FIVE WAYS", Downside Review 92 (1974): 1-18 371 372 LAWRENCE DEWAN, O.P. come to light, and why should it not come to light in things and so lead to the knowledge of the existence of the proper cause of such an effect? Indeed, can one really arrive at a knowledge of the existence of a "First Being" without having seen, by priority, the createdness of being? Let us recall the general plan for a way to God, as presented in the Summa theologiae. We are to reason from the existence of an effect, better known to us than its proper cause, to the existence of that proper cause. 4 What is the effect, seen as an effect, in the Fourth Way, and to what "proper" cause does it lead us? The Fourth Way leads to a maximal being, which is cause of being for ALL beings. The universality of this effect is to be noted. The cause in question is viewed as the cause of a universal effect. Thomas does not content himself with saying that there is a first being which is the cause of being for all other beings. That, I would say, would not be wrong, but it would be mild and apt to mislead. Rather, he "goes out of his way," one might say, to establish that the cause of which he is speaking is such as to dominate an entire field in what I would call a "formal" way. After reasoning to the actual existence of the maximal being, by what is clearly an efficient/exemplar causal route,S he adds that such a maximal item is the cause of all things which belong to the same order. He then comes to God, named precisely as he wished to arrive at God in this Fourth Way, viz. as "cause of being for all beings." The importance of the incorporation of this point about the universality of the effect can be better apprec\ated if one looks back at the Summa contra gentiles. The SCG 1.13 argument which corresponds to the Fourth Way does not mention the point about universality at all. It uses Aristotle's Metaph. 2 only to 4 ST 1.2 .2: "From any effect one can demonstrate the existence of its proper cause, if, of course, its effects are better known to us; because, since effects depend on a cause, the effect being posited, the cause must, by priority, exist." 5 Here, I am in disagreement with Leo ]. Elders, The Philosophical Theology of St. Thomas Aquinas (Leiden: Brill, 1990), 115, who sees in the first stage of the Fourth Way only formal causality. See my review-article of this work, in Science et Esprit 44 (1992): 205-220. So also I am in disagreement with Louis Charlier, "Les cinq voies de saint Thomas. Leur structure metaphysique," in L'Existence de Dieu (Tournai: Casterman, 1963), 213 n. 96. ST. THOMAS'S FOURTH WAY AND CREATION 373 assure the move from truth to being, and then uses M etaph. 4 to prove the existence of a maximally true thing. It is content to conclude to God as to a maximal being. 6 Then, in SCG 2, in the presentation of God as creator, Thomas proceeds very gradually. Chapter 6 only goes as far as saying that God is cause of being for some things other than himself. Chapter 15 goes on to show that everything other than God comes from him. Now, ch. 15 is well known precisely as the place where one can see the fundamental "Fourth Way" thinking more thoroughly worked out. We have an argument which concludes that God, as maximal being, is the cause of all the items of which "being" (ens) is predicated. 7 What Thomas Aquinas has done in the Fourth Way, as contrasted with its SCG 1.13 counterpart, is to add the considerations worked out in SCG 2.15. Now, it is a fact that in SCG 2 Thomas does not use the term "creation" (creatio) until he has added 2.16, viz., that God used no pre-existent matter in the universal production. This is of course quite in accord with serious ecclesiastical usage, which links the vocabulary of "creation" with the formula: "to introduce something into being without any pre-existing matter." 8 However, the omni-penetrating character of the proper effect, i.e., its peculiar universality, is already abundantly clear in 2.15. The point about matter is no more than a corollary, though one requiring heavy insistence because of the problem of the difficulty for the human mind to take up the properly metaphysical standpoint. There is also the enormous contextual weight of the authority, at that point in the thirteenth century, of the remarks of Averroes at the beginning of the In Phys. 8." One can see the presence of this problem, not only in SCG 2.16, the first paragraphs of which take the trouble to argue SCG 1.13 (ed. Pera, #114). See especially SCG 2.15 (# 924). 8 See SCG 2.16 (# 944) and 2.17 (# 946). It is interesting that in# 944 Thomas uses the word producere rather than the customary facere. At ST! .45 .1 sed contra and 1.45.2 sed contra, we see the more usual formula. Thomas criticizesfacere in ST 1.45.2 ad 2, and already at SCG 2.37 (# 1130 e and f), we see why philosophers who saw the createdness of things might refuse to call it a "making" lfactio ). 9 See Averroes's remarks in his commentary on Aristotle's Physics, where he criticizes the Islamic teachers for their doctrine of generation where there is no matter involved: Averroes, In Phys. 8.4 (ed. Venice, 1562, t. IV, fol. 34lrC-F). 6 7 374 LAWRENCE DEWAN, O.P. the mere possibility of production without use of matter, but also in the approach taken in ST 1.44.2, where the history of the human mind regarding modes of production is given great prominence (it is not presented in SCG 2 until chapter 3 7, on duration and creation). The ex professo reply to Averroes, in Thomas's own In Phys., accuses him precisely of failing to view being universally, falling to take the properly metaphysical standpoint, failing to rise to a knowledge of the cause of "that which is, inasmuch as it is that which is" (ens inquantum est ens). 10 In fact, the whole positive issue concerning God as cause even of matter is contained in one tiny paragraph of SCG 2.16, which simply points out that matter, after all, does have being attributed to it. 11 In ST 1.44.2, similarly, the point is that, once one has really risen to the properly metaphysical outlook, the causing of matter by God has already fallen into place.12 What is remarkable about the Fourth Way is its capacity to combine the formal universality of the aspect of things taken under consideration with the manifestation of the effect status of that aspect. It differs from the Third Way in this, that in the latter the features considered were differences of being, i.e., the possible and the necessary. The effect character was first seen in the 10 Thomas, In. Phys. 8.2 (ed. Maggiolo, 974 [4]-975 [S]). For the vocabulary of causality with regard to ens inquantum est ens, see especially 975: "sed si fit totum ens, quod est fieri ens inquantum est ens, oportet quod fiat ex penitus non ente: si tamen et hoc debeat dicijieri." Here, we see once more Thomas's reserve on the wordsjieri and the like as regards creation. II SCG 2.16 (# 943). 12 ST 1.44.2 (ed. Ottawa 281al8-26) and ad 2. This is also the line taken in the direct criticism of Averroes in Thomas's In Phys. 8.2 (ed. Maggiolo, 974): "Nor is [Averroes's contention] in accordance with Aristotle's intended meaning. For he [Aristotle] proves in Metaph. 2 that that which is maximally true and maximally a being [maxime ens] is the cause of being for all existents [causa essendi omnibus existentibus]: hence, it follows that the very being in potency [esse in potential, which prime matter has, is derived from the first principle of being [essendi], which is the maximal being [maxime ens]." Also of considerable interest for the general point of this paper, is the approach taken in Thomas's Compendium theologiae 1.68-69. In ch. 68, the conclusions are practically verbally identical with the conclusion of the Fourth Way; then, the first lines of ch. 69 speak of this already described role of God as "creating": in creando (ed. Leonine, ch. 69, line 1). ST. THOMAS 'S FOURTH WAY AND CREATION 3 75 possible, and was then extended to the necessary almost merely by hypothesis. 13 In the Fourth Way, we have moved beyond such "differences" to consider the form itself in its universality-we consider goodness, truth, nobility or perfection, and being. They are what Thomas calls, on at least one occasion, "universal form" uvmov (EE,1223b9-10). See also a bit later: iiµa apa 0 io amo Eterov teat iitemv (EE,ii,7,1223b17). We find similar language also at EN,vii,2,1146a27-31 (see also 1146a5-6). 452 KEVIN L. FLANNERY, S.J. Especially noticeable here is the language of formal proof. What is impossible? For the same man at the same time to act both voluntarily and involuntarily. 11 Why is this impossible? Since "no one wishes what he thinks to be bad" and "what a man does voluntarily he wishes, and what he wishes to do he does voluntarily." All this recalls the most succinct of the formulations of PNC: "the same attribute cannot at the same time belong and not belong to the same subject in the same respect" ( M etaph.,iv,3, 1005b 19-20). In fact, in the chapter of the Metaphysics immediately following this formulation of PNC, Aristotle comes very close to saying that PNC applies in the moral sphere. In ridiculing those who deny PNC, he says: Why does [a man] not walk early some morning into a well or over a precipice, if one happens to be in his way? Why do we observe him guarding against this, evidently not thinking that falling in is alike good and not good? (Metaph.,v,4,1008b15-17) 1" In effect, Aristotle is here restating the Socratic Principle: what a person regards as good he cannot also, at the same time, regard as not good. If, however, M etaph. ,iv,4, seems to suggest identity between the Socratic Principle and PNC, atEN,vi,2 Aristotle makes quite explicit how they differ. What affirmation and negation are in thinking, pursuit and avoidance are in desire; 19 so that since moral excellence is a state concerned with choice, and choice is deliberate desire, therefore both the reasoning must be true and the desire right, if the choice' is to be good, and the latter must pursue just what the former asserts. Now this kind of intellect and of truth is practical; of the intellect which is contemplative, not practical nor productive, the good and the bad state are truth and fal- For similar language, see EN,v,11,1138a18-24. Both intellectual parts, i.e., the epistemikon and the logistikon, aim at truth: EN,vi,2,1139b12. 19 See also DA,iii,7,431A9-10 where Aristotle also says that to perceive pleasure and pain is something like affirming and denying. 17 18 FIRST PRINCIPLE OF PRACTICAL REASON 453 sity (for this is the function of everything intellectual); while of the part which is practical and intellectual the good state is truth in agreement with right desire. (EN,1139a21-31) The differences between theoretical and practical reason must certainly determine ways in which their respective non-contradiction principles have effect. The objects of theoretical reason have an existence independent of the subject; accordingly, if a person holds contradictory propositions, the effect is that it becomes impossible for him to have a fully comprehensive grasp of objective truth. The objects of practical reason, on the other hand, are things yet to be: they are, that is, objects of deliberation.20 The effects of contradicting oneself in the practical sphere cannot therefore be to diminish one's grasp of objective truth; they show up rather in the way the person is oriented, practically, toward the future. He will be divided within himself with respect to desires, wishes, and beliefs, such as have a bearing on what he should and would do. 21 He will be, that is, in varying degrees, psychologically fragmented. Practical self-contradiction can have an effect in the theoretical sphere. As Aristotle notes in M etaph.,iv,4, if a person enunciates his inconsistent understanding of what is good, he will violate PNC. Within the practical sphere itself, however, there is a separate first principle-as there must be, since its objects, not yet being the case, cannot be said to be either true or false 22 ' 0 EN,vi,1,1139a3-8; see Carlo Natali, La saggezza di Aristotle, vol. 16 of Elenchos: collana di testi e studi sul pensiero antico (Naples: Bibliopolis, 1989), 75-6. Aristotle does however acknowledge at EE,i,8,1217b25-41 that the objects of ethics are not unconnected with the objects of the other sciences-i.e., being as found in the various categories. As he says at EE,1217b29-30: "the good is in each of these modes." At MM,i,17, 1189a12ff., Aristotle emphasizes that choice is among alternatives. See especially MM,i,17,1189a27, where he says that the options open to choice set up a controversy: i.e., an avn/..oyiav: ·teiiv avnA.oyiav itapaotoovi:wv 7t01:Epov i:oui:o ij 1:0\Ji:o aipei:ov. 21 "[A) man's friendship toward himself is at bottom friendship toward the good" (EE,vii,6,1240bl 7-18). 12 See Int.,ix; cp. G. E. M. Anscombe, "Aristotle and the sea battle," in Collected Philosophical Papers of G. E. M. Anscombe (Oxford: Blackwell Publishing/Minneapolis: University of Minnesota press, 1981), v.1, 44-55. For this general understanding of practical reason, see in the same volume, 66-77, "Thought and action in Aristotle: What is 'practical truth'?" 454 KEVIN L. FLANNERY, S.J. B. An incorrect interpretation of the square of opposition The psychological fragmentation of those who contradict themselves practically turns up any number of places in Aristotle. An especially clear statement is found at EE,vii,6: [L]oving and being loved ['to tA.e'icr0m1cal. tAf:'iv] requires two separate individuals. Therefore a man is a friend to himself rather in the sense in which we have described the incontinent and continent as willing or unwilling, namely in the sense that the parts of his soul are in a certain relation to each other. (EE1240al4-17)' This splitting of the soul into an active and a passive part is, of course, reminiscent of the square of opposition. 23 Slightly later, Aristotle relates it directly to the personal fragmentation of those who are less than good: All these things [i.e., marks of unity] we find in the relation of the good man to himself. In the bad man, e.g., the incontinent, there is variance, and for this reason it seems possible for a man to be at enmity with himself; but so far as he is single and indivisible, he is an object of desire to himself. Such is the good man, the man whose friendship is based on excellence, for the wicked man is not one but many, in the same day other than himself and fickle. (EE,vii,6,1240bll-l 7) But this approach raises certain questions about how we are to understand this fragmentation-and indeed how we are to understand the square of opposition. Two chapters after the square of opposition, Aristotle seems to identify the parts involved in injustice toward oneself-that is, the active and passive parts, which he also in EN,v,9 associates with akrasia-as the rational and non-rational parts of the soul: Metaphorically, and in virtue of a certain resemblance there is a justice, not indeed between a man and himself, but between certain parts of him; yet not every kind of justice but that of master and servant or that of husband and wife. For these are the ratios in which the part of the soul that has reason stands to the irrational part; and it is with a view to these parts that people also think a man can be unjust to himself, viz. 23 At EE,vii,1240al 9-20 Aristotle says explicitly that this question of Jove of self is to be treated in the same way as the question whether one can do oneself injustice. FIRST PRINCIPLE OF PRACTICAL REASON 455 because these parts are liable to suffer something contrary to their desires; there is therefore thought to be a mutual justice between them as between ruler [apxovtt] and ruled [apxoµ£vcp]. (EN,v,11,1138b5-13) As tidy an account as this provides, it presents a number of conceptual difficulties if it is to be connected up with the square of opposition of EN,v,9. Consider again that square: A]' PJV Presuming that the parts of the soul of the akrates are to be fit into this schema, with which of the sectors shall we associate his "reasoning part"? With which the irrational? It would seem at first that the rational part should be located at AJv-for it (voluntarily) seeks to impose the right thing-to-do on the irrational part. But in that case, since the passive element must obviously fall beneath the active, akrasia would not be doing oneself injustice-which is the basic presupposition of Aristotle's treatment. So, let us say that in akrasia the rational part finds itself in the position of PI;. But Aristotle says repeatedly in his ethical works that the rational part of the soul is predominant. 24 Indeed, this principle seems to be his second great inheritance from the Academy: reason is not "dragged about like a slave." 25 On the other hand, if the irrational part of the soul must always be in the passive position, it is difficult to see how we can be held responsible for its actions, since we are responsible only for those actions of which we are the authors (i.e., for which we are active). 26 The problem, though, is not in the square of opposition but in the introduction of the rational and irrational parts of the soul. This only becomes clear in EE-where we also learn that the square of opposition can be used to analyze not only public jus24 For instance: EN,i,13,1102b30-l, 1103al-3; EE,ii,l,1219b36-1220a4, 10-11, viii, 1, 1246bll-12. 25 EN,vii,2,1145b21-24, vii,3,1147b13-17; EE,viii,1,1246b19-21,34. His first inheritance is the Socratic principle itself which is not, however, unconnected with the second. 26 EN,iii,1. 456 KEVIN L. FLANNERY, S.J. tice and injustice and akrasia but also continence in spite of temptation (i.e., egkrateia). Although in EE,ii,l, Aristotle puts forward his standard analysis of the soul whereby the intellectual part governs the irrational, 21 in EE,ii,8 he makes it very clear that in akrasia and egkrateia we must maintain the unity of the soul. He says: Whence men apply the language [of compulsion] to the soul as a whole, because we see something like the above in the elements of the soul. Now of the parts of the soul this may be said; but it is the whole soul, whether in the continent or the incontinent, that voluntarily acts; and neither acts on compulsion, but one of the elements in them does, since by nature we have both. (EE1224b24-29) Aristotle takes a similar position at EE,vii,6,1240a13-2 l, where he discusses love toward oneself by dividing the soul into two parts, since (as he says) love involves relations between two elements. He is very careful to say that this is merely an analogy (EE,vii,6,1240a13) and concludes the section by remarking: "so far then as the soul is two, these relations can in a sense belong to it; so far as these two are not separate, the relations cannot belong to it." 28 If we apply these ideas within the square of opposition, the difficulties we experienced understanding akrasia in its left-central column disappear: the rational part is not relegated to the Pii position, since the soul acts as a whole. This is necessary in fact precisely in order to maintain responsibility of the agent for his own incontinence. That Aristotle makes the remarks he does at EE,ii,8 both about the akrates and about the egkrates also suggest a solution to the difficulties we experienced on the right side of the square of opposition. That side of the square comports more readily 27 EE, 1220a4-12. EE,vii,6,1240a20-21. Also in EE,viii,1 Aristotle appears to criticize the notion of explaining akrasia in terms of the rational working against the irrational in any strong sense. At EE,1246b12-25, he toys with this approach, throwing it over as absurd at EE,1246b26. AtEE,ii,8,1224a30-b15 he argues that it is not appropriate to speak of force with respect to the egkrates and the akrates, force being what comes from outside a person. The akrates seems to be subject to force, but we can speak this way only 1ca6' oµot6tTlta. Note the similar expression at EN,v,11,1138b5-6. See also EE,ii,8,1224b2925a2. 28 FIRST PRINCIPLE OF PRACTICAL REASON 45 7 with the concepts of egkrateia and phronesis. That is, when a person does justice to himself, although reluctantly, we have an instance of A}" combining with PJ;; when a person gladly does himself right, we have an instance of A}" combined with P]'. The square of opposition then does not represent the internal conflict of the akrates or egkrates at all but is simply an aid in understanding what an actual instance of akrasia or egkrateia is-and how it is possible. It seemed to me when I first began studying these texts that all this constituted evidence that EE contained in this respect a more developed theory than EN,v,9 and therefore EE might be later than EN. It is true that even in the passage quoted above from the end of EN,v,11, about the rational and irrational parts of the soul, Aristotle sounds a cautionary note, saying that he speaks "metaphorically, and in virtue of a certain resemblance"; but this chapter bears marks of having been added later. 29 What demonstrates clearly, however, that Aristotle, even in EN,v,9, did not conceive of the soul as split are his remarks on Glaucus at EN,1136b9-13. For there he says that Glaucus's giving away "gold for brass" is not truly an act of injustice since "there must be someone to treat him unjustly." Clearly he wants to maintain the unity of the acting person even within the square of opposition; and, in fact, it is on account of this unity and the fact that a single (unified) person cannot voluntarily do himself injustice that the square of opposition takes the shape that it does. 30 If the akrates, for example, could within himself accommodate the voluntary suffering of injustice, there would be no need to set Plv off to the side. 29 The cobbled-together nature of the chapter is widely acknowledged: see Alexander Grant, The Ethics of Aristotle, 2 vols., 4th revised ed. (London: Longmans, Green & Co., 1885), 97; see also Franz Dirlmeier, Aristoteles: Nikomakische Ethik, 435-9; see also Dirlmeier, Aristoteles: Magna Moralia (Berlin: Akademie Verlag, 1958), 328. 30 It seems to me that someone connected with MM does not have this well worked out. Natali, La saggezza di Aristotele, 72-3, perceptively calls attention to a confusion in MM about where to put phronesis: in the upper or lower part of the soul. The answer is either "in neither" or "in both." The soul acts as a unit. (On the genuineness of MM, see note 14.) 458 KEVIN L. FLANNERY, S.J. Ill. PSYCHOLOGICALACCOMMODATIONS What then are the effects of a violation of FPPR on the subject? We are now in a position to assess Aristotle's position more knowledgeably. It will be useful, however, before proceeding further, to remind ourselves of something that Thomas says about FPPR, which is part and parcel of the analogy he draws between it and PNC. That is, for Thomas FPPR is not simply a rule which we are free to follow or not, as we wish. As with PNC, it is in a sense impossible to violate FPPR-in the sense, that is, that we can violate, for instance, the moral precept "thou shalt not commit adultery." Speaking of PNC, Aristotle says that it is "impossible for anyone to believe the same thing to be and not to be ... ; for what a man says, he does not necessarily believe." 31 A similar thing can be said with respect to FPPR: it is impossible for anyone at the same time both to regard something as good and in the same respect as not to be pursued. It is easier to get this idea across if we think of the effects of self-contradiction on a person. These effects in either the theoretical or the practical sphere are in certain respects very similar. To assimilate a theoretical contradiction into one's thinking, one must break the system containing it into two parts. It is impossible in the strongest sense to hold 'p, q, r, s, t and not-P'-for it is impossible to conceive of what the world would be like if both p and not-p were true in the same respect. But one can in a weaker sense hold (for example) 'p, q and r' and 's, t, and not-p,' not bothering-or not knowing how-to reconcile the inconsistency. 32 So also with practical reason: a person is able to assimilate a practical contradiction-considering something as to-be-pur- Metaph.,iv,3,1005b23-25. Aristotle devotes An.Pr.,ii,21, to a consideration of cases of just this sort-i.e., to the question of how a person can in fact hold an inconsistent set of propositions. His answer is the one I give here; see, for example, An.Pr.,ii,21,67a5-8. The final section of the chapter (An.Pr.,ii,21,67b12-26) is especially interesting insofar as there he asks whether someone can believe that "the essence of good is the essence of bad." His answer is that one can do this, although only Kata (An.Pr.,ii,21,67b25). And he adds, "we must consider this matter better." Perhaps we have the fulfillment of this promise in one of the texts considered in the present study. 31 32 FIRST PRINCIPLE OF PRACTICAL REASON 459 sued and not-to-be-pursued in the same respect-only insofar as he is able to tolerate internal division. He does not bother or does not know how to get rid of the inconsistency; he simply puts his different practical attitudes toward g into different categories. 33 But what does this mean, to put opposing attitudes into "different categories"? This is precisely the question we encountered above when we considered the square of opposition in connection with the "parts of the soul." It is again in EE that Aristotle's most direct confrontation with this issue occurs-that is, in a very compressed passage in EE,vii,6. Aristotle begins the passage (at EE,1240b12-14) by saying quite explicitly that it is only insofar as a person is fragmented that he can be incontinent: "In the bad man, e.g. the incontinent, there is variance, and for this reason it seems possible for a man to be at enmity with himself. " 34 Then Aristotle proceeds to explain how in effect this occurs. He concedes for the sake of argument that it is possible to divide a person into units, in the manner of certain unnamed Sophists. 35 A good man, says Aristotle, has no argument with any of his own units. The good man does not revile himself at one and the same time, as does the incontinent man, nor does the later revile the earlier as does the regretter, nor does the earlier revile the later as does the liar. In gener- 33 For the sake of simplicity, here and in what follows I assume that g is a "basic good"-i.e., something that is always good. FPPR applies, however, also to non-basic goods. For instance, it may be good on Monday to visit Mr. M but (for some reason) without value to visit him on Friday. Nonetheless, it is impossible at the same time (e.g., _Monday) to regard in the same respect as good and not-good visiting Mr. M. In the above paragraph, it should also be understood that at least p and not-p are necessary propositions. See on this note 39, below. The notion of basic good I am operating with here is developed in John Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980), 59-99. I think that the notion of basic goods can be found in Aristotle. I shall not argue for this position here, except to point to some pertinent passages on the basis of which I would argue: EN,i,7,1097a25-b5; i,8,1099al5-16; iv,7,ll27a28-30; v,l,ll29b4-8; MM,i,18,ll 90a3-4. 34 Notice here that Aristotle considers all the bad to be at variance with themselves. (See also Plato, R.,352a5-8.) This must include the akolastos who does what he should not without the regrets experienced by the akrates. 35 For another (somewhat less vague) report of this type of argument see Philebus 14cll-e4 460. KEVIN L. FLANNERY, S.J. al, if it is necessary to define things as the Sophists do, it is as if 'Coriscus' was also good Coriscus-for it is clear that the same unit 36 of them all is good. For when they accuse themselves, they kill themselves; but each seems to himself good.37 I give the Greek as well, since it is not easy: 6 B' a:yaeos ou0' aµa AOlBopELTat EaUTwTal Blop((oualv, warrEp To Kop(aKos Kal Kop(aKos arrouBa'ios. BilXov yap ws To ffUTO rroaov arrouBruov aUTWV, EiTEL OTaV E)'KaAEO"WO"lVffUTOLS, aTIOKTlVVUaO"lV auTous· ciUa BoKEl rras auTOS aimji ciya06s.38 The text raises a number of questions, the addressing of which will tell us a great deal about how Aristotle understands the psychology of his various ethical types. The questions center around the words 'tO au'to nocrov ("the same unit"-EE,vii,6,1240b26)--which have good manuscript backing, although in one manuscript nou ("somewhere"?) is found after nocrov. The word nocrov ("unit"-or, perhaps, "quantity") suggests that Aristotle is conceiving of a time-line (t 11 t 21 t3 , t 4 , etc.).39 Assuming again that g is something to be pursued, the regretter says to himself, for example, at t 1 that he wants not-g but at t 4 that he wants g-and he reviles at t 4 his former "self." The liar on the other hand says to himself at t 1 that he wants not-g and at t 4 that he wants g but he despises at t 1 the prospect of wanting g at the (or perhaps a) later time. This approach 36 Franz Dirlmeier, Aristoteles: Eudemische Ethik: (Berlin: Akademie-Verlag, 1962), 79, translates to auto 1t6aov(EE,vii,6,1240b26) as dasselbe Quantum-which works better in German than in English. 37 A similar passage is found at EE,ii,8,1224b16-21. 38 EE,vii,6,1240b21-28. R. R. Walzer and ]. M. Mingay, Aristotelis: Ethica Eudemia (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991), put oA.roc; te ... <11toooa1ovai.>trov in round brackets. I do not think this helps make sense of the passage at all. Plato uses the word A.otooperoin a very similar context at R.,iv,440bl. 39 Unless we are dealing, for example, with necessary propositions, in the theoretical sphere, locating contradictory propositions at different positions on a time-line is not an assimilation. It may be that at t 1 pis true but at t4 false. In the practical sphere, however, with the sort of practical entities I am concerned with here-i.e., basic goods-, this expedient is not available. See above, note 33. FIRST PRINCIPLE OF PRACTICAL REASON 461 works fairly well with the regretter and the liar but not with the akrates who, it seems, at the same time wants both g and not-g. It seems to me therefore that it is not quite right to associate rt6crov strictly with time. But with what should we associate it? In other places in Aristotle, Coriscus (employed as an example) is segmented sometimes according to time-units ("Coriscus in the Lyceum,'' "Coriscus in the agora"-Phys ., vi, 11,219b20-21), sometimes according to qualities that apply to him ("musical Coriscus,'' "musical and just Coriscus"-Metaph.,v,6,1015b1920).40 I would propose therefore that the units of which Aristotle speaks in this passage in EE are references to Coriscus (or whomever). 41 Thus, with respect to the passage under consideration, the regretter might include "Coriscus at t 1 wanting not-g" and "Coriscus at t 4 wanting g and regretting his former self"; and the akrates might include "Coriscus wanting g" and "Coriscus wanting not-g but subordinating this want." The second problem has to do with the word a\no in the same phrase (-co au-co rt6crov-EE,vii,6, 1240b26). Aristotle says that the unit "Coriscus" (what I shall call "unqualified 'Coriscus' ") represents good Coriscus "for it is clear that the same unit of them all [i.e., of the akrates, the regretter, the liar, and the good man] is good." We find the unqualified unit in several of the Aristotelian texts which deal with the sophistry. 42 Here Aristotle tells us that this unqualified "Coriscus" represents good Coriscus. He gives a reason for this: "For when they accuse 40 See also An.Post.,24,85a24-5: GA,iv,3,767b24-32; Metaph.,vi,2,1026b16-18; SE,i,S,166b28-36, i,14,173b26ff, i,22,178b39-179al, i,24,179b26-33. For a device of this type using the names MiIC1caA.o<; and i\ptcrroµEVT\<; instead of the more common KopicrICo<;, see An.Pr.,i,33,47b15-32. There Aristomenes appears as "Aristomenes" and "Aristomenes as an object of thought"; Miccalus appears as "Miccalus," "musical Miccalus"-and dead Miccalus! 41 I speak here of "references" rather than "referring expressions," since in this whole discussion, as often in Aristotle, we encounter an ambiguity between expression and thing referred to. The paradoxes generated by the segments of Coriscus do not arise if we consider only the expressions. We should assume too that these references are true: that, for example, when talk is of "musical Coriscus," it picks out Coriscus at a time when he is musical. 42 For instance: An.Pr.,i,33,47b29-32; Metaph.,vi,2,1026b16-18; SE,i,S,166b32-33, i,24,178b39-179al. 462 KEVIN L. FLANNERY, S.J. themselves, they kill themselves; but each seems to himself good." Our first inclination is certainly to associate unqualified "Coriscus" (="good Coriscus") with the Coriscus-unit in each of the ethical types in which a good Coriscus reviles his other self, the idea being that the reviling is what makes him good. But this cannot be right for a number of reasons. First, the only reviling that we know the liar does he does at t 1 when he is reviling himself as wanting g-and at that point he is not being good but lying. Nor is there reason to assume that at t 4 he (having become good) reviles his former self: he might, for instance, want g at t 4 for base motives and be unconcerned about his previous state. Second, although, for instance, the regretter and the akrates seem each to contain a good unit, it is not the same unit in both cases-or, at least, it is not clear how it could be. Third, the phrase "each seems to himself good" does not really call for the location of "good Coriscus" at one of the specific units already spoken of. The idea seems to be rather that, whatever Coriscus does, he considers himself good. This attitude would seem to extend over Coriscus's whole lifetime. I would suggest therefore that, for Aristotle, if not for the Sophists, unqualified "Coriscus"-who is "good Coriscus" in the sense that he "seems to himself good"-is present in each Coriscus-unit. 43 We might indeed think of unqualified "Coriscus" as "Coriscus himself." All this has bearing, of course, on how Aristotle conceives of the psychology of his various ethical types. In the first instance, we have confirmation that, although he does conceive of the ethical types with the exception of the good man as fragmented, Aristotle is insistent always that they not be conceived of as so fragmented that they become disunited (and thereby forfeit culpability). Secondly, although this fragmentation is associated with the passions, it is not constituted by a separation between the ratio43 It is probably right therefore not to read nou at EE,vii,6,1240b26. The manuscript that has this seems (understandably) to be presupposing a time-line of some sort and to be attempting to bring sense to the passage by locating "good Coriscus" not at any one time-point but "somewhere" along the line. FIRST PRINCIPLE OF PRACTICAL REASON 463 nal and irrational parts of the soul. Aristotle mentions at EE,vii,6,1240b34-i.e., almost immediately after the passage we have been analyzing-the way in which the mind can be out of harmony with the passions; but the gist of EE,vii,6,1240b11ff. is certainly that fragmentation occurs not between such parts but between the various aspects of a person of which we might speak. These aspects involve desires and wants-in short, practical orientation-and might also involve talk of either the same or different times. The only other stipulation is that they involve "Coriscus," i.e., the person who, as one person, always pursues the good (or what he regards as good). CONCLUSION Our results are somewhat negative in character. We know that the souls of the akrates and egkrates are fragmented without being fragmented into parts-in any case, certainly not into rational and irrational parts. A segmentation, it would seem, might occur anywhere that it might truthfully be said of "Coriscus" that he has a practical attitude toward something in the possible future. In order to avoid the suggestion that psychological fragmentation is into parts, we might speak rather of "aspects." 44 But it must also be acknowledged that the nature of these aspects is not entirely clear in Aristotle. What we do know about them is that, insofar as one puts into them opposing practical attitudes, they allow one to assimilate practical contradictions. That is: they allow one to "avoid violating FPPR," insofar as such violation is even possible. How does this work? One cannot within the same aspect want both of two incompatible things: if I might use some unconventional language by way of analogy, both of two incompatible possibilities cannot be "lit up" in one's soul. If a person could be two persons, incompatible wants would present no problem: person1 could want g and person 2 could want not-g. But since a single, unified person cannot (in a strong sense) both want and not want g, when he acts with respect tog, he must turn one want 44 I suspect that our difficulty in grasping Aristotle's point is connected with the Aristotelian confounding of linguistic entity and thing spoken about. See above, note 41. 464 KEVIN L. FLANNERY, S.J. off. This, I think, is what Aristotle has in mind when, in EE,v,9, he puts off to one side of the square of opposition certain practical attitudes, calling them incidental. A person might be voluntarily on the passive end of an injustice but only insofar as he considers it (in some aspect of himself) not an injustice. A person might do himself injustice (i.e., fall prey to akrasia) insofar as when he acts against g his orientation toward g is not active. A person on the passive end of a just act, if he is so involuntarily, does not appreciate the act for what it is: something to be pursued. For him, it is that only incidentally. 45 If this just act is something he (as egkrates) imposes on himself, it is all the more obvious that he should remove this contradiction in his practical thought. It is clear from this analysis, I think, that, first, the aspects of a soul that are in conflict have nothing at all to do with the way the square of opposition is divided into active and passive sectors. The use of active and passive sectors is rather a way of speaking about akrasia and egkrateia (etc.) in terms of justice and injustice. Secondly, the square of opposition is put forward by Aristotle in order to preserve what he, like Thomas Aquinas, regards as the truth that is the basis of all moral action: "that good is to be done and pursued, and evil is to be avoided." 45 Aristotle says at EE,vii,6,1240b33-34 that the self-contradiction that comes with akrasia is only possible with choice: children, for example, are not subject to akrasia. Thus, in a fuller treatment we would have to tie practical reason to choice. But that is the subject of another essay. THE SPLENDOR OF ACCURACY.· HOW ACCURATE? WILLIAM E. MAY Pope John Paul II Institute for Studies on Marriage and Family Washington, D.C. I N THE introduction to the collection of essays published under the title The Splendor of Accuracy: An Examination of the Assertions made by Veritatis Splendor,1 Joseph Selling and Jan Jans write that the "central question that needs to be posed to the text of Veritatis Splendor" concerns the audience and situation its author has in mind (p. 9). They maintain that it appears to be addressed to "universal pastors (priests trained in seminaries) who (should) have one set of universal solutions to every conceivable pastoral problem one might face, anywhere, anytime" (p. 9). Assuming that this is indeed the case, they then say that the "best way to interpret what Veritatis Splendor says" is "from the point of view of the pastors and their educators" and that the Encyclical finds serious problems here (p. 9). Notwithstanding the unmistakable implication of the book's title, the subtitle, and, as we shall see, several of its main essays, the editors claim that neither they nor the contributors to the volume "wish or intend that this study be understood as a challenge or a rebuke to the teaching of the magisterium in the encyclical" (p. 10). Rather, they wish to "respond to the assertions made in the encyclical that give the impression of pointing to serious problem areas in contemporary Roman Catholic moral 1 Joseph Selling and Jan Jans, eds., The Splendor of Accuracy : An Examination of the Assertions made by Veritatis Splendor (Kampen: Kok Pharos Publishing House; Grand Rapids, Mich.: Eerdmans, 1994). 465 466 WILLIAM E. MAY theology as it is being researched and taught in any number of seminaries, universities and institutions of higher learning" (p. 10). I believe that Selling and Jans seriously misconstrue the purpose of Veritatis Splendor. It is surely not intended to equip priests trained in seminaries with "one set of universal solutions to every conceivable pastoral problem one might face, anywhere, anytime." Rather its stated purpose is to set forth clearly "certain aspects of doctrine which are of a crucial importance in facing what is certainly a genuine crisis" (VS, n. 4) and to address this crisis by presenting "the principles of a moral teaching based upon Sacred Scripture and the living apostolic Tradition, and at the same time to shed light on the presuppositions and consequences of the dissent which that teaching has met" (n. S). In particular, the "central theme" of the Encyclical, as identified by John Paul II himself, is to reaffirm the Church's teaching that there are "intrinsically evil acts" prohibited "always and without exception" by universally valid and immutable moral prohibitions (n. 115). John Paul II likewise emphasizes that the "morality of the human act depends primarily and fundamentally on the 'object' rationally chosen by the deliberate will" (n. 78) and that "reason attests that there are objects of the human act which are by their nature 'incapable of being .ordered' to God because they radically contradict the good of the person made in his image" (n. 80). Human acts specified by objects of this kind are the intrinsically evil acts prohibited by absolute moral norms, the teaching which constitutes, as has been noted, the "central theme" of the Encyclical. Thus the pope repudiates, as incompatible with Catholic teaching, those moral theories which deny that one can judge an act immoral because of the kind of "object" freely chosen and consequently deny that there are intrinsically evil acts of this sort and, corresponding to them, absolute moral norms (cf. nn. 74-77, 79). While repudiating these theories, John Paul II does not name any contemporary Catholic theologians who espouse them. Some contemporary moral theologians who advocate the proportionalist method of making moral judgments are among the THE SPLENDOR OF ACCURACY 467 contributors to this volume, namely, Joseph Selling himself, Louis Janssens, and Bernard Hoose. In their contributions, Selling and Hoose name other theologians known for their advocacy of this moral theory, e.g., Joseph Fuchs and Richard A. McCormick. The purpose of the essays by Selling, J anssens, and Hoose seems to be, as shall be seen, to show that John Paul II, in his "assertions," has misunderstood what is going on in contemporary moral theology. Thus this review of The Splendor of Accuracy will focus on the contributions by these authors, centering on their examination of the "assertions" in Veritatis Splendor to the effect that there are certain sorts of human acts, specified by the objects freely chosen, that are intrinsically evil and that, corresponding to these intrinsically evil acts, there are absolute moral norms. Before considering them, however, some brief comments should be made about the other essays in the volume. Of these, the one by Brian Johnstone is quite different in tone from the others; those by Gareth Moore and Jan Jans, however, seem intended to call features of the Encyclical into question and, in the case of Jan Jans 's contribution, indirectly to support the positions of the theologians associated with the views espoused by Selling, J anssens, and Hoose. Gareth Moore's essay is called "Some Remarks on the Use of Scripture in Veritatis Splendor" (pp. 71-98). Moore argues that John Paul II's use of the story of the rich young man in Matthew 19:16-21 "appears motivated by a desire.not simply to listen to what Jesus says, but to stress one particular mode of biblical discourse among several, namely, the legal" (p. 81). He tries to show that this approach "distorts the natural sense of the passage" {p. 81), whose "central meaning," according to Moore, is to show that the encounter between Jesus and the rich young man "provides an example of the power of riches over those who own them and an occasion for the teaching of Jesus on how hard it is for the rich to enter the kingdom of heaven {l 9:23ff.)," a central meaning that "the encyclical all but ignores" (p. 74). Moore's critique here focuses on the alleged "legalistic" use of this passage by John Paul II, but this distorts the use to which John Paul II puts the passage. In reality, the pope repeatedly 468 WILLIAM E. MAY emphasizes, in his reflection on this passage from Matthew's Gospel, the religious and existential significance of the question addressed to Jesus by the rich young man when he asked, "Teacher, what good must I do to have eternal life?" (Matt 19: 16). The pope explicitly says, "For the young man the question is not so much about the rules to be followed, but about the meaning of life. . . . This question is ultimately an appeal to the absolute Good which attracts and beckons us; it is the echo of a call from God who is the origin and goal of man's life" (n. 7). It is, he continues, "an essential and unavoidable question for the life of every man, for it is about the moral good which must be done and about eternal life" (n. 8). He emphasizes that the question is in reality "a religious question . ... the goodness that attracts and at the same time obliges man has its source in God and indeed is God himself" (n. 9). It is surely true that, in reflecting on this passage, John Paul II stresses the importance of keeping the commandments. Nonetheless, he is at pains to show that the commandments, in particular, the precepts of the Decalogue concerning our neighbor, are not legalistic prohibitions arbitrarily imposed on us. Rather, they "are really only so many reflections on the one commandment about the good of the person, at the level of the many different goods which characterize his identity as a spiritual and bodily being in relationship with God, with his neighbor, and with the material world .... The commandments of which Jesus reminds the young man are meant to safeguard the good of the person, the image of God, by protecting his goods" (n. 13). More could be said on this point, but it should be plain enough that the Encyclical is not here using Scripture legalistically. Brian Johnstone's "Erroneous Conscience in Veritatis Splendor and the Theological Tradition" (pp. 114-135) is, as noted already, quite different in tenor from the other contributions. Johnstone in no way criticizes "assertions" in the Encyclical. Rather he simply wishes to present the Encyclical's teaching on erroneous conscience and to situate it in relation to a wider moral theological tradition. He points out that in the Encyclical John Paul II says that "the Church's Magisterium does not intend to impose on the faithful any particular theolog- THE SPLENDOR OF ACCURACY 469 ical system, still less a philosophical one" (VS, n. 29, cited by Johnstone on p. 114). He shows that the teaching of the Encyclical on erroneous conscience strongly reflects the influence of the theology of St. Thomas Aquinas (pp. 118-123). Although the Encyclical does reject some contemporary understandings of conscience, it does not repudiate all nonThomistic theological understandings of erroneous conscience and its binding character, for example, the teaching found in the writings of St. Alphonsus di Ligouri, whose own understanding of this matter differs from that of St. Thomas and whose position was adopted by many authors of approved manuals of theology in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. The school of St. Alphonsus and other schools of thought on erroneous conscience, while providing accounts of the erroneous conscience different from that of St. Thomas followed by John Paul II, are not incompatible with magisterial teaching and raise important questions that merit consideration (pp. 124-134). Johnstone's essay is, in short; an instructive study and is not intended to call into question the substantive claims of Veritatis Splendor. Jan Jans's contribution, the final essay in the volume, is entitled "Participation-Subordination: (The Image of) God in Veritatis Splendor" (pp. 153-168). According to Jans, the relationship between God and man (or the way in which man is the "image of God") is presented in two quite different ways in the Encyclical. According to one model, which he calls "participation," "God only proposes in the commandments what is good for human persons" so that "the proper contribution of the Magisterium is to make visible those truths which Christian conscience already ought to know" (pp. 166-167). On this model, which could also be called the participated theonomy model, God, through the natural law, "calls man to participate in his own providence, since he desires to guide the world-not only the world of nature but also the world of human personsthrough man himself, through man's reasonable and responsible care" (VS, n. 43, cited on p. 157). But according to another model which Jans believes he finds in the Encyclical, and which he calls "subordination," John Paul 470 WILLIAM E. MAY II, following in the footsteps of Leo XIII, stresses "the essential subordination of reason and human law to the Wisdom of God and to his law" (VS, n. 44, cited on p. 15 7). On this model, God has the authority to "impose duties, to confer certain rights and to sanction certain behavior" (VS, n. 44, cited on p. 157). This "subordination" model is rooted in a hierarchical view of reality which, Jans asserts, is "in the last resort ... based upon the antagonism 'not human persons, but God': God alone-not the human person-has the power to decide what is good and evil, and since God is the Author of the Law and the Commandments these are to be accepted and submitted to" (p. 163). Jans acknowledges that "one might argue that such moral voluntarism must not in and of itself mean heteronomy"-a heteronomous morality was rejected by John Paul II himself inn. 41 of the Encyclical (p. 163). But Jans believes that he can detect the tension between these two models in the Encyclical, which clearly favors the "participation" model. According to him the passages in the document reflecting the "subordination" model are principally those critical of some "contemporary" developments in moral theology. Jans holds that some of the theologians "whose work is 'evaluated' by Veritatis Splendor" are actually engaged in overcoming the "antagonism between God as ruling king and human beings as obedient servants" (p. 168), and that overcoming this antagonism "calls for a revision of some traditional understandings and interpretations of God's creative presence in the realm of 'nature', as well as a revaluation of the concrete norms following from this perspective" (p. 169). He suggests, in short, that in reaffirming some "traditional understandings" John Paul II is, despite·the general thrust of the Encyclical toward the "participation" model, echoing the "subordination" model. Jans believes that the "hermeneutical key" to understanding the Encyclical and the "tension" in it between the participation and subordination models is to be found in an address given by the pope to the participants of the second international congress on moral theology, held in Rome to celebrate the twentieth anniversary of Humanae vitae in 1988. In that talk John Paul II affirmed that the teaching of Paul VI is not invented by human THE SPLENDOR OF ACCURACY 471 beings but inscribed by God's creative hand into the nature of the human person and confirmed in revelation. He likewise held that those who repudiate the norm taught by Humanae vitae refuse the obedience of their intelligence to God, preferring the light of their own reason against the light of divine Wisdom.Jans holds that this address reflects the "subordination" model and that its echoes are found in Veritatis Splendor. Jans's essay is of remarkable ingenuity. Nonetheless, his analysis of the Encyclical is questionable. The pope certainly affirms that God is the sovereign arbiter of good and evil and that human persons are to obey his law. Jans regards this as a kind of "moral voluntarism." But there is not a trace of voluntarism in the Encyclical. In affirming that God's law is the supreme norm of human life, John Paul II does no more than did the Fathers of Vatican Council II in Dignitatis humanae, n. 3. In maintaining that we are to obey this law, he does no more than the Fathers of Vatican II in Gaudium et spes, n. 16, where they say that "in the depths of his conscience man detects a law which he does not impose upon himself and which he must obey." Here it seems worth noting that both the Old Testament and the New Testament are full of language that makes it clear that human reason is subordinate to the wisdom of God and his law. Jans considers this position, which he attributes to Leo XIII and which he believes he finds in Veritatis Splendor, a "moral voluntarism." He nevertheless admits that this view does not of necessity lead to the heteronomous morality which the Encyclical rejects. The "tension" Jans discovers in the Encyclical between the "participation" and "subordination" models is, I suggest, his own invention. There is no inner tension or contradiction between "participation" and "subordination." For example, through God's grace we, his creatures, really become divinized, sharing in his divine nature just as surely as his only-begotten Son-mademan truly shares in our human nature. We are in truth members of the divine family by reason of our sharing, our participation, in God's divine nature. Yet within this family we remain creatures, with created human natures, just as God's only-begotten Son-made-man remains God, with his uncreated nature. And as 472 WILLIAM E. MAY creatures, as children of God, we are in truth subordinate to him. Now to the essays of Selling, Janssens, and Hoose, which directly confront the "central theme" of the Encyclical, namely, the reaffirmation of "the universality and immutability of the moral commandments, particularly those which prohibit always and without exception intrinsically evil acts" (VS, n. 115), i.e., kinds of human behavior specified by the object of moral choice which "are by their nature 'incapable of being ordered' to God because they radically contradict the good of the person made in his image" (n. 80). Selling's essay, the longest in the volume, is called "The Context and Arguments of Veritatis Splendor" (pp. 11-70). In sketching the background and context to the Encyclical, Selling flatly states that those who accepted the challenge of Vatican II and "began the work of reconstructing moral theology on the basis of scripture and tradition rather than natural and canon laws ultimately came to be known as 'revisionists"' (p. 12). In other words, according to Selling the only theologians who seriously sought to renew moral theology according to the mind of Vatican Council II are the "revisionist" theologians, unnamed in the encyclical but identified by him as including people like Louis Janssens, Joseph Fuchs, and Bernard Haering. According to Selling, consequently, only "revisionist" theologians have sought to carry out the task assigned moral theologians by Vatican II. It is also surprising that Vatican II, according to Selling's account, thinks that moral theology sho.uld disregard natural law as one of its sources; the actual documents of the Council frequently appeal to the "universally binding principles of natural law" (cf. Gaudium et spes, nn. 74, 79-80), refer to the "law" men discover in the depths of their conscience (ibid., n. 16), and speak eloquently of mankind's intelligent participation (=natural law) in the "highest norm of human life," namely God's "divine laweternal, objective, and universal, whereby he governs the entire universe and the human community according to a plan conceived in wisdom and in love" (Dignitatis humanae, n. 3). Selling's observations here indicate his way of approach. Equally surprising is his claim, in the introductory material, THE SPLENDOR OF ACCURACY 473 that "nearly everything that" Pope Pius XII's Encyclical "Humani Generis stood for was reversed by the close of the Second Vatican Council" (p. 19). Selling here implies that the notion of theology and its work set forth in that Encyclical was repudiated by the Council Fathers. But a Council document explicitly concerned with the teaching of theology, not least of moral theology, makes the teaching of Pius XII's Encyclical its own. Optatam totius emphasizes that in order for the work of Catholic theology to be carried out rightly, it must be done "in the light of faith and under the guidance of the Church's Magisterium" (n. 16). Precisely at this point in the directives for the "renewal" of theology, we find a footnote referring to the teaching of Pius XII in Humani Generis. Moreover, the passage in this Encyclical to which Optatam Totius explicitly calls attention contains the following statements of Pope Pius XII: Nor must it be thought that what is contained in encyclical letters does not of itself demand assent, on the pretext that the popes do not exercise in them the supreme power of their teaching authority. Rather, such teachings belong to the ordinary magisterium, of which it is true to say: 'he who hears you, hears me' (Lk 10:16); very often, too, what is expounded and inculcated in encyclical letters already pertains to Catholic doctrine for other reasons. But if the supreme pontiffs in their official documents purposely pass judgment on a matter of debate until then, it is obvious to all that the matter, according to the mind and will of the same pontiffs, cannot be considered any longer a question open to discussion among theologians Selling's strategy is evident. In his view John Paul II's Veritatis Splendor is a document analogous to Pius XII's Humani Generis. Just as the latter has now, so Selling avers, been rejected, so too, the implication goes, will John Paul II's Encyclical be repudiated in the future. With regard to the question of human acts and their moral assessment, Selling finds "rather bizarre" the concepts of freedom and the will found in the following statement of Veritatis Splendor: "Some authors do not take into sufficient consideration the fact that the will is dependent upon the concrete choices which it makes: these choices are a condition of its moral goodness and its being ordered to the ultimate end of the person" (n. 474 WILLIAM E. MAY 75, as given in the translation provided by Selling, p. 4 7). Here I want to note that the Latin text (and the official English translation) is more precise than the translation Selling provides. The Latin reads: "Nonnulli non satis aspiciunt voluntatem definitis implicari delectionibus, quas ipsa operatur" (translated, in the authorized translations, as "some authors do not take into consideration the fact that the will is involved in the concrete choices which it makes"). The point is that the person's moral character is dependent on his specific free choices. Selling believes that the idea that the action of the will is dependent upon its choices for its goodness is a "relatively new idea that has developed in the literature in order to substantiate the theory of the 'basic goods"' (p. 47). The position found in Veritatis Splendor, n. 75, however, is hardly a "relatively new idea." Earlier in the Encyclical, John Paul II had stressed that we determine ourselves through our freely chosen acts. He emphasized that "freely chosen deeds do not produce a change merely in the state of affairs outside of man but, to the extent that they are deliberate choices, they give moral definition to the very person who performs them, determining his profound spiritual traits" (n. 71). They are a "decision about oneself and a setting of one's own life for or against the Good, for or against the Truth, and ultimately for or against God" (n. 65). The pope notes that the precise point he is making has been "perceptively noted by Saint Gregory of Nyssa." The pope then cites a beautiful passage from Gregory's De Vita Moysis (II, 2-3, PG 44, 327-328): All things subject to change and to becoming never remain constant, but continually pass from one state to another, for better or worse .... Now, human life is always subject to change; it needs to be born anew . . . . But here birth does not come about by a foreign intervention, as is the case with bodily beings ... ; it is the result of free choice. Thus we are in a certain way our own parents, creating ourselves as we will, by our decisions. (VS, n. 71) Moreover, St. Thomas's entire understanding of morality involves, centrally, the concept that Selling finds bizarre and novel: good acts build up the virtues, which are precisely what constitute the goodness of the person; vice consists precisely in THE SPLENDOR OF ACCURACY 475 bad actions, considered independently of any other effect (cf. Summa contra Gentiles, III, c. 10). In short, the understanding of free choice and its relation to the will found in John Paul Il's statements is neither as "bizarre" nor as "relatively new" as Selling asserts. As noted, Selling believes that the "bizarre" and "novel" notion of the significance of free choices in determining man's moral character has been developed to substantiate the theory of the "basic goods." He contends (p. 67) that the use of the term "good" as a substantive in the Encyclical, i.e., to designate "goods" of human persons that one ought not freely choose to damage, harm, or destroy, signifies that the Encyclical has been profoundly influenced by the "novel" doctrine of "basic goods" developed principally by Germain Grisez and John Finnis (cf. p. 6 7, note 5 2). Selling says that he and other theologians are "comfortable" with using the word "good" as an adjective, but that its use as a substantive is unusual. But the use of "good" as a substantive identifying real goods perfective of human persons is not novel; it is central to the thought of St. Thomas. In fact, St. Thomas held that "God is offended by us only because we act contrary to our own good,'' 2 and in discussing the primary precepts of the natural law he said that, since the very foundational practical proposition on which the whole natural law is founded is that "good is to be done and pursued and evil is to be avoided,'' "reason naturally apprehends as good, and thus to be pursued by action everything for which man has a natural inclination." 3 He goes on to list one bonum (substantive, not adjectival) after another (human life itself, knowledge of the truth, especially truth about God, life in fellowship with others). In many places in the Summa theologiae he 2 Non enim Deus a nobis offenditur nisi ex eo quod contra nostrum bonum agimus (Summa contra gentiles, III, c. 122). 3 Omnia ilia ad quae homo habet naturalem inclinationem ratio naturaliter apprehendit ut bona, et per consequens ut opere prosequenda ... (Summa theologiae, 1-11, q. 94, a. 2). Here "bona" probably is used adjectivally, but, as noted in my text, St. Thomas goes on immediately to enumerate one bonum (substantive) after another. 476 WILLIAM E. MAY refers to "goods,'' i.e., bona, which have and bona which do not have a necessary connection with beatitude (e.g., I, q. 82, a. 2), temporal bona (e.g., life) and spiritual bona (11-11, q. 11, a. 4), etc. Indeed, his whole treatment of law and of the goodness of the will is placed under the aegis of the Psalmist's question, often repeated by St. Thomas, "Quis ostendit nobis bona?" (Ps. 4:6; cited in Summa theologiae, 1-11, q. 19, a. 4; q. 91, a. 2; also I, q. 84, a. 5). In addition, St. Thomas is very clear that one loves one's friends by seeking what is good for them, the goods perfective of their personhood (cf. 1-11, q. 28, a. 4). Thus Selling's claim that the Encyclical's use of the term "good" as a substantive, i.e., to identify real goods of human persons (e.g., innocent human life, the marital communion, and so forth) is novel and unique to the recent "basic goods" theory is simply false. It is important to recognize that the inaccuracy of Selling's characterization of the position of the Encyclical corresponds to the inaccuracy of his portrayal of the theory of basic goods. In fact, in his antipathy to the line of reasoning that underlies the theory of basic goods, Selling distorts it beyond recognition. For example, in one passage he lists various beliefs, such as that it is natural to accumulate possessions beyond one's needs, to stratify society into leaders and followers, to destroy one's enemies, to accept that whites are superior to nonwhite persons, and then declares: "That is the 'basic goods theory'-when one looks below the surface" (p. 68). Such a characterization of the theory of basic goods is simply untenable. Selling's interpretations, both of the Encyclical and of the theory of basic goods, can thus be seen to be quite unreliable. Louis Janssens, emeritus professor of moral theology at the University of Leuven, contributes an essay entitled "Teleology and Proportionality: Thoughts About the Encyclical Veritatis Splendor" (pp. 99-113). The Encyclical, as we have seen, teaches that one can judge that an act is intrinsically evil if the moral "object,'' i.e., the object rationally chosen and willed, is not referable to God because it radically contradicts the good of the person made in his image, and that it is not necessary to consider circumstances THE SPLENDOR OF ACCURACY 477 and the end for whose sake the act is chosen in order to recognize acts of this kind as immoral. The thrust of Janssens's paper is to argue that the Encyclical is mistaken in its central teaching-and mistaken in its rejection of the theory that one can judge an action morally bad only if one takes into account not only the object but also the circumstances in which it is done and the end for whose sake it is chosen. (The Encyclical, of course, teaches that one can judge an action to be morally good only if all its elements, object, end, and circumstances, are good.) Janssens's thesis is that an appeal to proportionality is "unavoidable for evaluating human acts," and that this assessment of proportionality is teleological in character, i.e., that it can be made only by taking into account the end for whose sake the action is undertaken, and that one cannot judge an act to be morally bad without making this teleological assessment of the proportionality of the means, i.e., of the object, to the end. In developing this thesis, Janssens first appeals (pp. 100-102) to the Vatican Declaration on Euthanasia (1976) for support. He emphasizes that this document sharply distinguished between "disproportionate" and "proportionate" treatments of dying persons. The latter are morally obligatory, whereas the former can be rightly withheld or withdrawn. Moreover, the judgment that a particular treatment is "disproportionate" or "proportionate" can only be made by assessing and balancing the harms and benefits it promises. Janssens thinks that this proves his point. It is, however, pertinent to ask whe'ther the use of the terms "disproportionate" and "proportionate" in this Vatican document requires acceptance of the moral methodology Janssens advocates and which the Encyclical rejects, since the Encyclical holds that one can judge an act intrinsically evil on the basis of its moral object, i.e., the object rationally chosen, without considering circumstances and the end for whose sake it is chosen, if this object is known to be contrary to the good of human persons. If we examine the document to which Janssens appeals for support, we find that this document does not support the methodology Janssens advocates. For prior to considering the reasons for judging that some means of medical treatment are 478 WILLIAM E. MAY disproportionate or proportionate, the Declaration had affirmed that euthanasia or mercy killing is intrinsically immoral, not because it is "disproportionate" but simply because it is the inten.tional killing of an innocent human being: "nothing and no one," the document maintained, "can in any way permit the killing of an innocent human being." 4 J anssens appeals to the teaching of the Declaration on Euthanasia to support his claim that one can judge actions to be morally good or bad only by assessing teleologically the overall benefits and harms of an action. For him this is the criterion for making all moral judgments. Clearly this is not the methodology employed by the Declaration because, as has just been seen, it rules out absolutely as intrinsically immoral any act specified by its object as the killing of an innocent human being. There is no need of a "teleological assessment" in making a moral judgment of this kind. The Declaration surely speaks of means that are "proportionate" or "disproportionate," but in doing so it is no way employing "proportionalism" in the same way as is J anssens. Not all appeals to "proportionate" reason are proportionalistic in Janssens's sense of that term. John Finnis puts the matter well. He notes that this Declaration makes three references to proportion. (i) Medical experts can judge when the pain and suffering imposed on a patient by certain techniques are "out of proportion with the benefits which he or she may gain from such techniques" [graviora quam utilitates quae inde ei afferri possunt]; as the reference to medical expertise makes clear, this judgment about 4 Here I should note that when the Declaration was published in 1976 I wrote to Archbishop Jerome Hamer, then secretary of the Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith. I thanked him for the document and its reaffirmation of the intrinic evil of all acts of intentionally killing innocent beings, even for reasons of mercy. But I said that, although I understood how the document used the terms "proportionate" and "disproportionate," I was concerned that some proponents of the proportionalist method of making moral judgments ( e.g., J anssens) might appeal to this language of the document to support this moral position. In his reply Archbishop Hamer, after thanking me for my letter, stressed that the Congregation repudiated proportionalism (as was evident in its affirmation of the moral absolute proscribing intentionally killing innocent human beings) and that any appeal to the document to support this moral theory would be utterly inappropriate. THE SPLENDOR OF ACCURACY 479 disproportion pertains to points on a single scale, i.e., the scale of pain and suffering: the matters on each side of the comparison are restricted to pain and suffering and relief from pain and suffering. (ii) Medical experts may also judge that "the investment in instruments and personnel is disproportionate to the results foreseen" [non respondet effectibus qui praevidentur]; this should be regarded as an invitation to the medical expert (whose judgment is being discussed at this point in the Declaration) to consider the proposed "investment in instruments and personnel" in the light not of an open-ended calculus of all the good effects of keeping this patient alive (which would involve a senseless weighing of incommensurables), but rather of his normal system of priorities-a system which is established not by calculus but by commitment. (iii) Refusal to undergo risky or burdensome treatment is not the equivalent of suicide, but rather may be a "wish to avoid the application of a medical procedure disproportionate to the results that can be expected" [cura vitandi laboriosum medicae artis apparatum cui par sperandorum effectuum utilitas non respondeat]; this, too, should be taken as a reference, not to a calculation of moral obligation by weighing the incommensurable goods of a longer life and freedom from pain, but to a person's choice (not unrestrained by consideration of his existing moral responsibilities, e.g., to his family), a choice by which that patient establishes for himself what counts (for him) as par utilitas (literally: equivalent benefit) in these respects. 5 In short, an appeal to proportionality is not proportionalist in the sense in which J anssens uses this term if it expresses some prior moral judgment or assessment or refers to the implications of some prior commitment relative to which a proposed choice would be proportionate or fitting, or disproportionate or unfitting. This distinction between an appeal to proportionality understood as a norm necessary to evaluate the morality of all human acts (Janssens's claim) and making some judgments of proportionality in the light of moral priorities is clearly made by the bishops of the United States in their Pastoral Letter on War and Peace, The Challenge of Peace: God's Promise and Our Response 5 John Finnis, Fundamentals of Ethics (Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press, 1983), 106-107. On legitimate uses of"proportionalism" and how such uses are profoundly different from the use of "proportionalism" as a method for making moral judgements, see Germain Grisez, "Against Consequentialism," American Journal of Jurisprudence 23 (1978): 49-62 480 WILLIAM E. MAY (1983). The bishops, appealing to the norm that military force must be used discriminately, first rule out as absolutely immoral intentionally attacking noncombatants, i.e., innocent human beings. An intrinsically evil act of this kind is absolutely excluded by the principle of discriminate use of force. But they go on to discuss the principle of "proportionality." In explaining it they say: When confronting choices among specific military options, the question asked by proportionality is: once we take into account not only the military advantages that will be achieved by using this means but also all the harms reasonably expected to follow from using it, can its use still be justified? We know, of course, that no end can justify means evil in themselves, such as the executing of hostages or the targetting of noncombatants [i.e., acts intrinsically evil by reason of the object rationally chosen and willed; cf. Veritatis Splendor, n. 78]. Nonetheless, even if the means adopted is not evil in itself, it is necessary to take into account the probable harms that will result from using it and the justice of accepting those harms. (n. 105) Here the bishops are clearly not advocating the moral methodology championed by Janssens, namely, that "an appeal to proportionality is unavoidable for evaluating the morality of human acts" (Janssens, p. 100). They hold, with the entire Catholic tradition, which Veritatis Splendor correctly summarizes, that one can know that it is always wrong intentionally to kill innocent human beings without appealing to proportionality. But they are maintaining that, in the light of moral norm of justice, one can determine whether or not unintended harms, i.e., unchosen harms anticipated to result as an unintended effect of one's freely chosen act, can be tolerated or accepted. In the balance of his essay Janssens basically reiterates the thesis of his enormously influential 197 2 article "On tic Evil and Moral Evil" (Louvain Studies 4 [Fall, 1972): 115-156) in which he argued that the proportionalist method of making moral judgments (the method he advances in this article and the method repudiated in Veritatis Splendor) was central to the teaching of St. Thomas. According to Janssens, for St. Thomas one could not make a moral judgment about a human act without taking into account not only the "object" (which J anssens in his 1972 article THE SPLENDOR OF ACCURACY 481 identified with the "external act" considered as a material event) but also the proportionality of the means chosen (the "object") to the final end intended by the agent, which served as the "form" of the entire moral act. Here J anssens basically reiterates this thesis, illustrating it by St. Thomas 's teaching on killing in selfdefense (p. 109). According to Janssens in his 1972 article, Aquinas taught that one could rightly "intend" the death of the assailant (an ontic evil) as the "means" to defend oneself from unprovoked attack, an interpretation of the relevant Thomistic text (Sum. theo., II-II, q. 64, a. 7) not faithful to the text. It is not necessary to treat this matter at length here. I have previously shown in detail how Janssens has radically misconstrued Thomas's teaching on the morality of human acts 6 and need not here rehearse what was said there. Briefly put, while insisting that one must consider not only the object chosen but also the circumstances in which it is chosen and the end for whose sake it is chosen in order to determine whether an act is morally good (bonum ex integra causa), St. Thomas, contrary to J anssens 's contention, taught that if one knows that any element in the act is bad, one can judge the act morally bad ( malum ex quocumque defectu), and he insisted that the morality of the act derives first and foremost from the object freely chosen. If this object is bad, then it cannot be made good by reason of the end for whose sake it is chosen. In his contribution Janssens insists that "official church documents [=documents of the Magisterium] maintain that contraception ... and homosexual acts are intrinsically evil according to their object. All of these terms refer simply to factual events" (p. 110; emphasis added). This is patently false. These terms do not refer simply to mere factual events but to making a choice of a "factual event." As we have seen already, John Paul II explicitly denies that the "moral object" refers to factual events. Rather it refers to the intelligible proposal adopted by choice (what St. Thomas called the external act as specified morally by the "sub6 See my "Aquinas and Janssens on the Moral Meanung of Human Acts," The Thomist 48 (1984): 566-606. 482 WILLIAM E. MAY ject matter with which it is concerned" or the materia circa quam, not the mere material event, or materia ex qua). Thus contraception is not a material event but is rather any freely chosen act which, either in anticipation of a genital act, in its accomplishment, or in its natural consequences, "intends to impede procreation" (cf. Humanae vitae, n. 14). Thus, Janssens is setting up a straw man in his critique of the Encyclical. He fails to show inaccuracies in its "assertions." In summary, Janssens's contribution plays on the differences between legitimate uses of "proportionality" and the use to which he seeks to put it. It seriously misinterprets the teaching of St. Thomas to support the thesis that an appeal to proportionality is necessary to evaluate a human act morally, and fails to come to grips with the central teaching of the Encyclical. Bernard Hoose's essay, "Circumstances, Intentions, and Intrinsically Evil Acts" (pp. 153-168) is an effort to show that, pace the contrary teaching of John Paul II in Veritatis Splendor, one can make moral judgments only by considering circumstances and (further) intentions. Hoose centers attention on n. 80 of Veritatis Splendor where John Paul II appeals to the teaching of Vatican Council II in Gaudium et spes, n. 2 7 to show that there are "intrinsically evil acts" specified by the objects rationally willed and chosen. This text from Gaudium et spes includes some actions described in morally evaluative terms (e.g., "subhuman living conditions," "arbitrary imprisonment," "degrading conditions of work'). It also includes others described in merely descriptive terms (e.g., "abortion," "euthanasia," "voluntary suicide'). Among the acts described in non-morally evaluative language are "deportation" and "mutilation." It should be noted, however, that "deportation" appears immediately after "arbitrary imprisonment," so that one might infer that the "deportation" deemed immoral by Gaudium et spes is "arbitrary deportation." Nonetheless, Hoose focuses on the fact that no morally descriptive adjective precedes "deportation" and "mutilation," and he then goes on to argue that one cannot say that "deportation" is intrinsically evil insofar as there can be just deportations. Similarly, he argues that in the Catholic tradition THE SPLENDOR OF ACCURACY 483 approved authors had spoken of justifiable "mutilation." He then concludes that, since these kinds of actions cannot be determined to be immoral without taking into account circumstances and ends, no actions can be determined intrinsically evil merely on the basis of the object chosen (e.g., deportation), but can only be evaluated morally if one takes into account not only the object chosen but also the circumstances and intentions (i.e., the moral method repudiated by Veritatis Splendor). I think it is easy to see the glaring non sequitur involved in Hoose's argument. He rightly notes that some actions, described in non-morally evaluative terms (e.g., deportation) cannot be judged morally wrong without considering circumstances and intentions, but then concludes that no actions described in such way can be judged immoral without considering circumstances and intentions. From all that has been said, one can conclude, I believe, that the essays by Selling, Moore, Jans, Janssens, and Hoose contained in this collection are seriously flawed and thus fail in their attempt to show inaccuracies in "the assertions made by Veritatis Splendor." BOOK REVIEWS The Perfection of the Universe According to Aquinas: A Teleological Cosmology. By OLIVA BLANCHETTE. University Park, Penn.: The Pennsylvania State University Press, 1992. Pp. xvii + 334. $35.00 (cloth). This work represents a significant and most welcome contribution to Thomistic interpretation as well as to the broader study of medieval philosophy. While its tone is unpretentious, its theme, the structure and purpose of the whole created universe, is crucial for Aquinas's philosophy. Those familiar with Thomas's corpus know how often this theme appears-frequently supplying the foundation for the argument-and know equally well how elusive it becomes when one seeks an extended treatment of it. Hence, to have recognized the chief elements of the larger picture, to have identified and collected the pertinent texts, and to have ordered and synthesized them as this book has done represents a major and lasting scholarly achievement. Moreover, while primarily concerned with Aquinas's own philosophical thought, the book also places him in conversation with a number of classical and modern thinkers, from Plato and Aristotle to Hegel and Collingwood. Blanchette begins his study by clarifying the very notion of perfection (Chapter 1). It first refers, in the order of our conceptions, to the completion of a process. A thing is perjectum, "thoroughly made," when its process of generation is finished. Motion, in fact, is precisely a passage from imperfection to perfection. By extension, the term can then be applied apart from motion to anything which lacks nothing it should have, or, as in the case of God, which lacks nothing at all. Analyzing the Greek and Latin terms connected with generation and perfection (poiein/facere; genesthai/fieri; teleion/perfectum; telos/finis; teleiosislperfectio) Blanchette shows why it is that for the Greeks the infinite usually signified imperfection, while Aquinas was able to conceive of an infinity which was perfection. For the present study, a crucial distinction among the kinds of perfection is that between first and second perfection, i.e., between a being's "ontological" perfection, the complete generation of its nature with all its natural powers, and its "operational" perfection, the activities carried out by means of those powers. Only in its operations does a being attain its ultimate perfection, which always lies in a relation to something exterior to itself. This fundamental distinction between first and second perfection underlies the basic 485 486 BOOK REVIEWS structure of the book. Part One describes the universe in its first perfection, i.e., the constituent parts whose presence gives it its integrity. Part Two takes up the activities of the parts which taken together constitute the order within the universe and by which the universe attains to its external good, God himself. At the level of first perfection, the universe is considered to be perfect first of all simply because it is the universe, i.e., the whole of what is (Chapter 2). As a whole, it is perfect (complete) in comparison to any of its parts. Thus it is a priori impossible to have plural universes, since each "universe" would in fact be only a part of the whole which was the universe. Second, simply as a body, the universe enjoys the perfection of having all three dimensions. Third, not having any bodies outside it, the universe does not share the imperfection of being limited by bodies external to it, as does every particular body. Finally, in containing the perfection of each kind of being, the universe possesses a universal perfection not shared by any one kind of being. These perfections belong to the universe simply qua universe. Beyond these, however, we can speak of the perfection of this universe. As Blanchette points out, for Aquinas there is no "best of all possible worlds" in the sense that God could not create a better one. Yet we can speak of the perfection (or completeness) of this world that God, for reasons not accessible to human reason, actually chose to create. The perfection of this universe is such that were any new essential parts, i.e., new species, added, it would no longer be the same universe, but rather a new universe of which the old now constituted a part. One could, however, increase the accidental (improve or increase the number of individuals within species) and so increase the intensity of the perfection, but the essential structure would remain unchanged. As Blanchette points out, this seems to disallow the possibility of an evolution of species within Aquinas's universe. The following chapter shows how the perfection of the universe requires integrity, the condition of all its parts coming together suitably. This implies on the one hand that there be some one principle which causes the universal order, and, on the other hand, a diversity of parts (species) and even a multiplicity of individuals. The diversity of species, intended by God for the perfection of the universe, implies a hierarchy in which some beings will be better than others. The final cause of diversity, ultimately, is to have the universe represent the divine goodness; since no one creature can accomplish this fully, diversity is called for. Aquinas distinguishes between perfection in the present state of the universe wherein all species constitute essential parts, and that of its final state at the end of time when there will remain only the principal parts: the separate substances, the heavenly bodies, human individuals, and the four elements. Blanchette concludes his description of the universe's first "ontological" perfection with an analysis of causality (Chapter 4). Inasmuch as the universe is ordered and this order arises in the action of some beings on others (action BOOK REVIEWS 487 and passion), causality provides, as it were, the texture of the universe. Of particular importance here is the universal causality of the heavenly sphere which is the cause of the universal order in the terrestrial world. The recognition of a universal order requires positing such a cause beyond all particular causes; Blanchette remarks here that it is characteristic of modem Darwinism to restrict its explanations to particular causes. The theme of causality leads into that of activity, and this is treated in Part Two according to three different levels which together make up the universe's second perfection. First is the activity of physical bodies as such, that is, their local motion (Chapter 5). Simply as a body, each body attains its perfection by achieving its natural place. The inclination to this place produces the natural rectilinear motions of the simple elements toward or away from the earth's center. In contrast, the circular motions of the heavenly bodies are not directed to any one place and so cannot be natural; hence the need for an exterior mover. These basic motions give rise to all other motions, including those of generation. Seen from this perspective an evolution of species might be possible as part of the temporal process through which the essential species of the universe are generated. The second order of activity is that of generation as it occurs over time (Chapter 6). Aquinas accepted Aristotle's understanding of the heavenly sphere as the universal cause of all generation; nevertheless, he departs significantly from Aristotle in that the generations occurring in the terrestrial realm are not just a sort of by-product of the sphere's motion but rather its primary goal. Moreover, all of material generation from the lowest level upwards aims at the production of rational beings. Thus, on Aquinas's view, the purpose of the motion of the heavenly sphere is ultimately the production of a determinate number of human beings. When that number is reached, the motion of the sphere will end. As Blanchette points out, this view of motion and generation clearly puts man at the middle of the universe and demotes the heavenly bodies to a sub-human level. There is, for Aquinas, an anthropic principle informing the whole universe. Given this last view, it becomes clear that the most perfect activity of the universe, that in which its perfection principally lies, is the activity of its principal parts, the rational beings (Chapter 7). Intellectual beings, being. both material and spiritual, occupy a central place in the universe. As immaterial and capable of intellectual activity, the soul can become all things (quodammodo omnia); in so doing it overcomes the particularity of each created being and gathers the universe together, so to speak, within itself. In this way the rational being has a special affinity with the whole universe and its perfection, for through it the universe achieves a unity beyond what it could achieve by its physical interactions. It is not only by intellectual activity, however, that the rational creature perfects the universe. It is called to participate in divine providence and activity to promote the good of the materi- 488 BOOK REVIEWS al world and of other rational beings. This latter is accomplished by adhering to justice, dedicating oneself to the common good of all rational creatures. Through the knowing and loving of rational beings, which constitutes the universe's intrinsic common good, the universe attains its extrinsic common good which is God himself. Thus Blanchette can give the following summary of the Thomistic universe: "For him (Aquinas], the universe is ultimately a community of intellectual beings, each intelligent and free, all capable of the highest good, moving toward completion through an activity in which this community expresses and perfects itself' (300). We have, in the end, a sort of "kingdom of ends," a universe which is, at its peak, ethical. It is worth noting a few key ideas that run throughout Blanchette's treatment. First, the notion that human intelligence cannot explain the universe as a whole. This particular universe is created as a result of God's free-will (vs. all emanationist accounts) and hence there is no necessary rational explanation available to the human intellect for its being as it is (vs. Hegel). This is the "voluntaristic" side ofThomas's account. Still, it is possible, given this universe, to say why such or such thing is required for the perfection of a being or even for the universe. This gives rise to Thomas's "rationalism," his conviction that the intellect can penetrate the world and arrive at necessary truths about it. Second is the understanding of how the unity of a whole that is made up of several distinct substances rests on the interaction of these substances. A universe of multiple beings without activity would not be a true universe. Neglecting this point, one might consider the order of the universe, its highest perfection, in a static sense, and then take it as distinct from the activity of the rational beings. Rather, the order of the universal is found most fully in the very activity of its rational members. Third is the distinction Blanchette draws between the idea of the universe with its perfection and the model which at a given historical period represents that idea. This distinction allows him to speak of those elements of Aquinas's larger view which remain valid when some particular understanding of the universe is altered or even replaced by discoveries in the physical sciences. Given the replacement of the Aristotelian cosmology which Aquinas largely accepted, this is clearly necessary if the book's theme is to have a more than historical value. Such a distinction, moreover, highlights the real philosophical issue of what constitutes a universe as such and what sort of perfection must it have. Here, one wishes that Blanchette might have said a bit more about how and to what extent the idea, the "logic of perfection," is independent of a given model. For example, he makes it clear that when the universe is said to be perfect because it contains all that is, this sort of perfection would apply to any model of the universe (102-3). But this independence seems to derive from the almost tautological nature of such perfection (94). It seems, however, more problematic when we come to the perfection which the BOOK REVIEWS 489 universe enjoys as an ordered whole. What happens if the model does not present a universal order, as seems to have been the case for the last three centuries? Should we then remove the corresponding perfection from our idea of universe's perfection? Or is there some metaphysical reason for asserting that the universe is an ordered whole, regardless of any particular model? If the latter, it would be interesting to have at least a sketch of how we would arrive at this position. On the whole, certainly, the book provides an invaluable overview of the Thomistic universe for anyone working on Aquinas's cosmology, metaphysics, or even ethics. Blanchette is to be commended for his clear and orderly presentation of the material, especially the many subdivisions within the chapters. The quotations of Thomistic texts are almost all in English, well translated by Banchette himself. The placing of key phrases in Latin within parentheses helps in some measure to overcome the lack of the original text in the footnotes. Finally, the book's selected bibliography as well as its indices (index of names, analytical index, and index of citations) render the book an even more useful tool. DAVID M. GALLAGHER The Catholic University of America Washington, D.C. Freedom and Creation in Three Traditions. By DAVID B. BURRELL, C.S.C. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1993. Pp. xi + 225. $29.95 (cloth). According to the author, this book, Freedom and Creation in Three Traditions, is a comparative work designed "to illustrate the worth of explicitly tradition-directed inquiry, as well as the fruitfulness of comparative inquires in philosophical theory" (6). In addition, among other things, the author contends that, "because the pressure of comparative perspectives demands that we mine hitherto unsuspected reaches of what we have thought we know," not only the author but also the "traditional disciplines of philosophy and theology may each be enriched by the forays of such inquiry" (6). Specifically, the three traditions to which Burrell is referring are the Jewish, Islamic, and Christian; and, as the title of this book suggests, the central topics of consideration used as the basis for a comparison among these traditions are the respective notions of freedom and creation. In order to achieve his goals, Burrell places his discussion within the general context of the notion of creation, which, as he rightly observes, "is notoriously difficult to classify" (7). In so doing, he divides the work into nine chapters; which he entitles as follows: 1) "The Context: Creation"; 2) "On 490 BOOK REVIEWS Characterizing the Creator"; 3) "On Characterizing Creation"; 4) "On Characterizing the Relation: Jewish, Christian, Muslim"; 5) "God's Acting in the World God Creates"; 6) "Creatures Acting in a Created World"; 7) "On the Relations between the Two Actors"; 8) "Sin and Redemption"; 9) "The God Realized in Renewed Creation." Having placed his discussion within the general context of the notion of creation, Burrell begins his analysis by comparing and contrasting this notion in St. Thomas and Moses Maimonides vis-a-vis the necessitarianism of Aristotle as interpreted by lbn Sina. In so doing, Burrell stresses that what predominates in both Maimonides and Aquinas is a notion of God as a "free originator" of all creation not in relation to an "exegesis of the opening chapters of Genesis" but in relation "to the rest of the Bible and the subsequent tradition of Judaism and Christianity" (12). This "distillation" having been noted, Burrell then examines the distinctive features of the notion of creation as this is influenced by the "faith assertion" of the three respective religious traditions-Jewish, Christian, and Islamic. Within Judaism Burrell finds emphasis placed upon the need to interpret creation against the background of the "covenant" with Israel (19). In Aquinas and Barth he understands this activity to be interpreted against the background of the relation of the Father to His Eternal Word (19-21); and within Islam he finds the regulating theme in the conviction of God's absolute sovereignty vis-a-vis the created order. In chapter 2, Burrell goes into more precise detail regarding the specific ways in which God is characterized as a creator within the three traditions. Within Judaism, once again, he focuses upon Maimonides and finds the decisive point which determines the Rabbi's reasoning "against accepting what Aristotle was said to have taught regarding the origins of the universe" to have been the philosopher's contention that "the world exists in virtue of necessity, that no nature changes at all, and that the customary course of events cannot be modified with recourse to anything" (28). According to Burrell," ... what offends him about such a contention is that 'it destroys the Law in its principle, necessarily gives the lie to every miracle, and reduces to inanity all the hopes and threats that the Law held out ... "' (28). Furthermore, in Burrell's view, from the theological presumption that God is a free originator of everything, Maimonides is led to draw the philosophical conclusion that it must be the very nature of God to exist. Consequently, Maimonides's use " ... of Avicenna's distinction between essence and existence offers a way of parsing the claim that 'His existence is necessary always' ... as but another way of saying that it 'has no cause for its existence'" (30). Within Aquinas Burrell finds a completion of "the grammar of divinity" (31), in particular regarding the way existence and essence are to be understood in God and creatures; and to make the position of Aquinas regarding the relation of essence and existence clearer he explains this against the background of lbn Sina's teaching on the matter. BOOK REVIEWS 491 All this having been done, Burrell begins to make the notion of creation more precise by relating the created order to the Creator-first regarding the notions of act, possibility, and necessity; and then by characterizing the relation within the context of the three traditions. Within this latter context Burrell finds certain central facts to be present. Within Judaism this is the covenant; within Christianity it is the Word made Flesh; and within Islam, as represented by such thinkers as al-Ghazali and the Asharites, it is the omnipotence of God. After finishing the above analysis, the author turns to an examination of the structure of the religious narratives of the traditions in order to focus attention both upon how each respectively understands God's action within creation and the free action of creatures in relation.to God. Within each tradition Burrell finds some difficulty grappling with what he calls "the zerosum impasse" of created freedom-as-autonomy in the face of an omnipotent freely originating God. Within Islam he notes this difficulty in particular within the Mutazilite school between the Qadarites and the Asharites-the former accepting and the latter rejecting the notion "that rational creatures are the originators of their actions by a power created by God" (76-83). Within Judaism he again turns to Maimonides, whose views on these matters he finds heavily developed in reaction to the aforementioned Islamic debates (84). Finally, within Christianity Burrell refers to Augustine's notion of freedom; and he considers this notion both as it is understood by Scotus (88-94) and "as it has been employed by Aquinas to 'make explicit' what Aristotle left in umbrage: the inner dynamics of voluntary human action" (87). In Chapter 7, Burrell turns to what he calls "explicit philosophical reflection" regarding the relations between divine and human free agency within each of the three traditions which are the focus of his study (95). In so doing, he intentionally "gravitates toward Aquinas as the most credible spokesman for any of the traditions" for several reasons: 1) he intends to "focus on the philosophical tools needed to explicate the unique relations obtaining between existents who are creatures and their creating source"; 2) "Thomas incorporated into his synthesis the results of three centuries of prior labor by Muslim and Jewish thinkers on the very issues which confronted him"; and 3) "because of his metaphysical acumen, perhaps also a function of his prior tutelage, he was able to transform the inherited Hellenic schemes in such a way as to exploit the implications of creation ex nihilo and so create a specifically 'Christian philosophy' that would also prove of considerable use to Jew or Muslim alike" (95-96). Interestingly, the main "philosophical tool" for which Burrell appears primarily to tum to Aquinas seems to be a rather decidedly theological one-namely, Aquinas's faith conviction that human beings need an infused knowledge (such as that of the Trinity) in order to have the correct idea of creation. With this tool in hand, Burrell notes that, even though Aquinas's faith dependence is distinctively Christain, nonethe- 492 BOOK REVIEWS less, all three traditions share the same conclusion that " ... God produced creatures not because he needed them, nor because of any other extrinsic reason, but on account of His own goodness." Then he concludes this Chapter by considering four issues which he finds to be relevant to his treatmentnamely: "l) causality: primary and secondary, the cause of being and causes of manners of being; 2) eternity and time as a corollary of creator/creature; 3) the efficacity of providence with respect to a world subject to failure; 4) the relative merits of a metaphysics which privileges the possible or the actual to explicate this unique relation" (96). Chapters 8 and 9 deal with "the pattern of love (or friendship) as an analogy for the interaction involved" between God and created, voluntary agents (96). Chapter 8 considers this interaction against the background of the notions of sin and redemption and of the distinctive ways in which each of the three traditions understands these ideas; and, once again, Burrell stresses: the Jewish tendency to interpret these notions in relation to "the covenant with Abraham and Torah with Moses" (143); the Christian inclination to interpret these same ideas against the background of "the person and actions of Jesus" (146); and the Muslim propensity to view these same issues in relation to the "Warning and Guidance" of the Qur'an (150). In Chapter 9, he notes that, despite their differences, within each of the three traditions, there is an analogous, threefold pattern of elaboration utilized by each tradition in its discourse about the relation of the Free Creator to His free creationnamely, "source, word, and community" (161-171); and he concludes, with Aquinas: "It is the trinitarian structure of God's saving action which can serve as an operative pattern to correct the principal tendencies to self-destruction endemic to each of the three traditions which we have been considering" (183). In my opinion, both generally and specifically, Burrell's treatment of his chosen topic is an excellent piece of scholarship-one which could not be matched by many thinkers today. First of all, the topic which he is examining is not an easy one, even from the perspective of one tradition and one area of expertise. Burrell, however, is able to move back and forth between philosophy and theology not only within his own tradition, but he displays an exceptional grasp of the problem from the perspective of other theological traditions as well-even to the point that he recognizes the difficulty of talking about the kalam as theology (196, note 8), which is a subtle problem of which few scholars tend to be aware. Secondly, the topic which Burrell examines is one of major philosophical and theological import which, in all its parts, demands both tremendous linguistic and historiographical skills to articulate. Yet, despite these complexities, Burrell is able not only to formulate the issue under consideration with clarity, succinctness, and precision but also, utilizing these same intellectual skills, to achieve all the goals which he has established for himself. BOOK REVIEWS 493 There are, however, a couple of areas in the work where I find it difficult to understand the author's point. For example, I think it would have been helpful for Burrell to explain more precisely within his text what he means by Christian philosophy. The more I study this notion the more I become convinced this is simply an analogous concept for a particular way of doing theology-namely, of using the habit of philosophical argumentation within the context of theological investigation. Burrell, however, seems to think that Christian philosophy is something other than the theological use of the habit of philosophical argumentation (for instance, that it is a "logical system"see 55); but when he gives instances of Aquinas's application of Christian philosophy (for example, 21) what is formal in Aquinas's activity seems to be the habit of theological reasoning illuminating that of philosophical reasoning. Certainly, however, against the background of Burrell's overall purpose, these issues are of minor import and do not detract from the metaphysical beauty of Burrell's scholarship-which, as I have already noted, is difficult to match. PETER A. REDPATH St. John's University Staten Island, New York Theology and Narrative: Selected Essays. By HANS W FREI. Edited by George Hunsinger and William C. Placher. New York: Oxford University Press, 1993. Pp. 274. $35.00 (cloth). To review a collection of ten essays, with introduction and afterword by the editors, poses several challenges. One temptation is to attempt the impossible: to give an adequate reading of each of the essays as well as an assessment of the work of the editors as to their choice of materials and their comments upon them. One risks writing a dozen reviews rather than one. Another temptation is to offer either a synthetic view of the collection, thereby imposing a unity which may not be entirely warranted by the essays themselves, or a highly selective view according to a single theme which the reviewer takes as most important or interesting. Theology and Narrative demands a following of ancient advice: pecca fortiter. The reader can be exceedingly grateful for the fine "Introduction" by William Placher, and the brief but clear introductions to each essay. In his usual lucid and flowing style, he offers us much more than a mere chronological precis of the essays. His remarks offer an albeit brief but thorough synthetic and critical view of the work of Hans Frei. In fact, I would suggest, his introduction is itself an excellent "book review." By contrast, the "Afterword" by George Hunsinger is principally focussed outside this col- 494 BOOK REVIEWS lection. He takes the first essay of the collection, "Remarks in Connection with a Theological Proposal," as the light by which to interpret "the principal work by which he [Frei] is known to us not as an intellectual historian or as a commentator on the theology of others but as a theologian himself' (235). That work, The Identity of Jesus Chri-st, is the subject of a careful analysis for its "polemic," "method," and "content." Hunsinger applies the same grid to The Eclipse of Biblical Narrative (chiefly in the footnotes), and in sketchy form to the other posthumous collection of writings by Frei, Types of Chmtian Theology. Hunsinger is at his best in laying out the argument of Identity. There is little doubt that to understand Frei one must grasp and evaluate the theological positions from which he takes his distance, the methods by which he makes their problems his own, and the deep principles which guide his solutions, at least as evidenced in the Christology he proposes, and by implication in the rest of the doctrinal areas of Christian thought. The excursus in footnote thirteen on the relation of meaning and truth in the gospel narratives, and the relation of faith and history that it presupposes, deserves a careful reading. To clarify the argument of Identity is no small job, and Hunsinger offers many felicitous insights. However, whether one can do so without integrating the historical work of Eclipse, the initial stance found in Frei's doctoral dissertation, and the admittedly fragmentary but nonetheless definite position taken in Types I doubt. That is not to ask of a short afterword more than it can possibly do, but to suggest that a fuller work is much hoped for. After a brief biography of Frei, the "Introduction" by Placher confines itself somewhat more to the essays presented in the volume. It does so, however, by offering the reader two helpful sections on the background to Frei's work in the authors Erich Auerbach and Gilbert Ryle. Despite their brevity these sections are valuable aids to the reader unfamiliar with the literary and philosophical theory upon which Frei is dependent. As Placher himself notes, H. Richard Niebuhr is a third essential component of the background, and the essay by Frei himself, the last in the collection, is a welcome statement of his appreciation and understanding of at least part of Niebuhr's work. As Placher suggests, Frei's important movement away from an emphasis on the formal characteristics of biblical realistic narrative as normative to an appreciation of its function as the rules of discourse within the common life of the Church both locates a shift which frees his theological work from an unnecessary constraint but, needless to say, opens it into an area of complexity which he was yet to engage fully. In addition, Placher notes that a fundamental question for Frei's project is whether it resolves itself into a form of deconstruction (one might add, in another direction, into the kind of fundamentalist reading of the biblical text he was so careful to avoid). How can such a collection be best read? The introduction, I have suggested, is truly introductory, and while the afterword takes the reader far BOOK REVIEWS 495 afield it does so with ultimately helpful materials. The essays of Frei are themselves arranged roughly historically, with only one very early essay (the sixth, on Barth) placed later in the collection, obviously to be a companion with the essay in which Frei reconsiders Schleiermacher and a possible rapprochement between him and Barth. They could be simply read in the order presented. But, as Hunsinger shows well with his use of the other early essay "Remarks in Connection with a Theological Proposal" to clarify the argument of Identity, there is much to be said for reading both early essays first. If nothing else, they pose a clarity and freshness which becomes increasingly rare as Frei contends with, in Hunsinger's words, "the concrete and complex embeddedness in the matrix of the whole, with all the subtle interrelations and contrasts which that embeddedness seemed to entail" (236). It might be well, before proposing a scheme for reading, to name briefly that complex whole. Simply put, it was a conviction that matters of method and matters of doctrine are inextricable. There is no settling the difficulties of clear doctrinal exposition, appropriate development, and pastoral application without attention to the content and claims of doctrine itself, and vice versa of course. This is most evident in Frei's chosen test case of the doctrine of the person and work of Christ, in which decisions as to the appropriate use of general theories of human nature and interpretation of the Scriptures, as well as the tradition of reading and applying them, are ingredients. This is not strange. In the acts of God in Christ which constitute human salvation the what and how are coincident. There are those who might argue that this is not the statement of the Scriptures or the formula of the early tradition, or that even if it is, it need not be held normative. Frei would not agree, and labored at length to unravel the threads of argument and presupposition, of historical and contemporary reasons which account for the divergence of opinion. His deepest convictions may not have been easily visible, and Hunsinger is correct to observe that the few written works which remain are themselves as complex as the problems Frei engages and his appreciation of their subtleties. Frei quite evidently tried very carefully to understand alternative perspectives and claims, and hence I am somewhat hesitant about Hunsinger's use of the title "Polemic" to name Frei's relation to and presentation of the last three centuries of Western Christian theology. If doctrine and method are inextricable, so is the effort of taking account of the ruling discourse while proposing an alternative conversation. Essential to that conversation is testing the grammar of two basic Christian claims: Jesus is Lord; Jesus is risen. With these matters in mind, let me briefly review the contents of Theology and Narrative. One can profitably begin by reading the short piece "Of the Resurrection of Christ." With a very clear focus and in a very brief space, Frei employs for us his basic analysis and critique of current views and presents his own basic position (see especially 205). The reader familiar with Frei's work will find many hints of his more technical writings, and the reader unfamiliar will 496 BOOK REVIEWS undoubtedly discover a multitude of questions to be answered by further reading. Of particular importance here, I think, is the function of the piece as a commentary on a confession of faith. Though his life's work was within the university context, there can be little doubt of the deep faith which shines through the texts. I would recommend also reading the other two essays that were contributed by Frei to the same commentary on the Thirty-Nine Articles of the Church of England and that make passing mention of a very early entry in A Handbook of Christian Theology published in 1958 on the subject of natural and revealed religion which is valuable for its succinct observations. Next, an early short essay, "Karl Barth: Theologian," will introduce the reader to all the preoccupations of Frei's later work, as well as signal his indebtedness to the work of Barth in general. His wonderment about the success or failure of Barth's theology (174-75) occasions remarks about the central task of theology, and about its ironic character, which provide a glimpse of Frei's own motivation and style. Following these two short essays taken as the ouverture to what follows, one might profitably read the "Remarks in Connection with a Theological Proposal." The editors rightfully note that this early essay announces all of the themes of Frei's career: the distinction between explanation and description, and a decided preference for the latter, across a number of academic disciplines; the plea for modest, nonspeculative interpretive devices in expounding scripture; the nontheological modes of conceptual analysis used to elucidate the logic and content of dogmatic theology; the distrust of apologetic strategies that dissolve into the worst fonns of relativism; the insistence on the particularity of the synoptic gospel narratives and the figure of Jesus as they depict him (26-7), It ends with a succinct statement of the coincidence of meaning and truth, as Frei finds it to be given in the account of Jesus' life, death, and resurrection. He admits that "the question of the transition from the aesthetic, nonapologetic understanding to the truth claim_.__historical,metaphysical, and existential" must be addressed, but he takes his place alongside Anselm, Calvin, and Barth, offering the following remark about the story of Jesus as given in the gospels: "Understanding it aesthetically often entails the factual affirmation and existential commitment that it appears to demand as part of its own storied pattern" (44). To understand this remark, the reader must labor through "Theological Reflections on the Accounts of Jesus' Death and Resurrection," an earlier version of the argument presented in The Identity of Jesus Christ. Here, the reader unfamiliar with Frei might wish to read parts one to four of Hunsinger's "Afterword" before, or in conjuction with, a reading of this rather dense piece of writing. In sum, Frei argues that the unique identity of Jesus as clarified by the use of formal elements of identity description requires both a notion of identity and a reading of the New Testament which "quests for the historical Jesus" inevitably cannot sustain. In a somewhat ironic remark he offers the following summation: "I believe further that this descriptive availability, identity, and continuity (of Jesus) represents not a transformation of BOOK REVIEWS 497 Jesus into a myth but the demythologization of the savior myth in the person of Jesus" (75). And put in other words: " ... there is a kind of logic in a Christian's faith that forces him to say that disbelief in the resurrection of Jesus is rationally impossible" (87). Four other essays in the collection will aid the reader to discover more clearly the hermeneutical problems involved in the sort of Christology which Frei has proposed. "Theology and the Interpretation of Narrative" has an important discussion of the meaning of the "literal sense." This is furthered in the essay previously published and much discussed, ''The 'Literal Reading' of Biblical Narrative in the Christian Tradition: Does it Stretch or Will it Break?" which contains remarks on recent literary criticism, particularly deconstructionism, and on phenomenological hermeneutics. Of particular note are the concluding pages (l 43ff) in which one can detect a movement away from the formal characteristics of realistic narrative (and Frei's association with New Criticism) towards a notion of the literal sense in connection with communal discourse (and Frei's association with the work of George Lindbeck). "Conflicts in Interpretation" continues this trend, and the short piece in response to Carl Henry is valuable for its somewhat blunt but clear remarks on a whole range of issues that the three other more technical essays discuss. Finally, there are the two late works, on the convergence of Barth and Schleiermacher as reconstructed by Frei, and on H. Richard Niebuhr. Both are instances of the kind of generous, even if critical, reading Frei could offer, and of the continual reassessment he was engaged in throughout his life. While both selections offer remarks on historical figures, hermeneutical issues, and philosophical matters, I would like to highlight the glimpse of a discussion of the Trinity in the first (82ff.) and the remarks on Christian ethics in the second. Pervading both are hints of the same topic which engaged him in his doctoral dissertation, how to speak about revelation in Christian thought and life. Another "review" of this collection might take as itg theme the importance of its contents for many contemporary theological discussions. Most obviously, anyone interested in questions about ways of reading the Bible, about the presuppositions of recent efforts to search for the historical Jesus, about the use of literary theory in conjunction with Christology, and about hermeneutical questions generally will find them placed in a large historical and theological context. Those wishing to explore the implications of Frei's work for all forms of theological construction, and for theological education as well, will find this volume a distinct convenience. There now lacks only an edition of Frei's doctoral disseration to make available the resources for a broad discussion of the shape and significance of his work. Such a comprehensive study would be not only of historical interest, but might be able to lay out more clearly the lines of possibility in which Frei's work, in conjunction with that of George Lindbeck, can be properly said to be an inspiration for other 498 BOOK REVIEWS generations of theologians across denominational lines. Both Placher and Hunsinger at the end of their essays choose quotations from within Frei's own writings to give a synoptic portrait of the man and his work. Placher chooses a remark about Niebuhr's sense of vocation as a theologian (20), and Hunsinger one about knowledge of that seemingly elusive reality, a person's identity (257). However one might come away from this challenging collection of essays, further confused or more enlightened, more in agreement or disagreement, I think every reader will recognize the coincidence of intellectual perspicuity and generosity with passionate faith. GEORGE P. SCHNER, S.J. Regis College, Toronto School of Theology Toronto, Ontario, Canada Reasoned Faith. Edited by ELEONORE STUMP. Ithaca, University Press, 1993. Pp. x + 364. N.Y.: Cornell As the editor remarks in her "Introduction," it is not so long ago that the analytical philosophy of religion consisted very largely of discussions of the meaningfulness of religious language, and of arguments about the existence of God. Nowadays it is more adventurous, ranging over such topics as creation, providence, and God's responsibility for sin. According to Robert Merrihew Adams, the statement "truth is subjectivity," though one of the most famous, is also one of the most misunderstood in Kierkegaard's writings. He argues that, taken in context within the Concluding Unscientifu: Postscript, the statement is by no means incompatible with the objective truth of religious belief. From the point of view of the Postscript, a member of an idolatrous community who prays to her God with "the entire passion of the infinite" has more of the truth than one who prays in a false spirit from within Christendom; but this implies that the latter does have some truth. Whatever the deficiencies in her faith, she is clearly admitted to be in possession of the true concept of God objectively speaking (223). Adams maintains, quite rightly in the reviewer's opinion, that the Postscript is excessively pessimistic about the integration of the ideals of subjectivity and objectivity, of passionate commitment on the one side and rational assessment of evidence on the other, in religious faith (21). A useful distinction is made by Scott MacDonald between "occurrent" and "dispositional" belief; this seems to resolve some of the more puzzling paradoxes about the relation of the more cognitive and propositional side of faith to other aspects which may be thought essential to it. The demons alluded to by St. James (2:19) might believe dispositionally that their highest fulfillment BOOK REVIEWS 499 was to be found in obeying the divine will, and so performing acts of charity and service to other creatures. But to avoid the inconvenience of acting in such a way, they could think of God occurrently as just a powerful being who makes burdensome demands (55). For MacDonald, the cognitive component of faith has only two elements, belief that certain propositions are true, and belief that the kind of response of the will which is also essential to faith may be grounded on these (56). "We can make sense of Christian faith if we think of it simply as belief that Christianity is true plus an appropriate volitional response to that truth" (69). Against mainline Christian accounts like those of Augustine and Aquinas, he sees no good reason to suppose that one cannot have faith in propositions for which one has conclusive proof, but only in those for which one's justification is relatively weak. He provides interesting grounds for contradiction of a view which has been expounded by both Robert Adams and John Hick, that only such uncertainty can ground the trust which is essential to the relationship which human beings ought to have to God (59). "My ability to love and trust my wife, to commit myself without reservation to her well-being and to the goals and purposes we have chosen as definitive of our common life seem in no way dependent on my being uncertain about what she is like or what she will do" (60). On the question of how faith ought to be related to the demands of reason, Robert Audi remarks that, up to the middle 1970s, it was usual to assess the rational requirements of faith in evidentialist terms; but this is no longer so. (The reviewer believes that the older assumption was quite correct, and that the new-fangled notion that there might be a rationality to faith which is somehow of a non-evidentialist sort is largely sophistry and illusion. But this is by no means to impugn the interest of this article as a whole.) Audi suggests that a rational faith, if it were "volitional" rather than "doxastic," might result in one's praying in the hope of being heard by God, even without confident belief that this will happen. "Even if there should be neither cogent arguments for God's existence nor experiential grounds adequate to warrant unqualifiedly believing that God exists, rational faith is possible" (89). This kind of faith would have some cognitive constraints; it would be incompatible, for instance, with a definite belief that God did not exist (78). Peter van lnwagen brings new light to the overworked topic of how Jews and Christians are to understand the Biblical accounts of creation, against the background of modern scientific knowledge of the origins of the universe and of humanity. He distinguishes two extreme positions, which he labels "genesiac literalism" and "saganism," and repudiates both of them. He suggests that what Genesis is right about-that it is not the case that there are many gods whose wills may be in conflict with one another; or that kings but not ordinary folk bear the divine image; or that it is proper to worship heavenly bodies-is of fundamental importance to all human beings everywhere, and that what it is wrong about is not of such importance (104). Furthermore, until an age of high sophistication, truths relating to such matters as sin and 500 BOOK REVIEWS moral knowledge can be communicated to human beings only in the form of concrete stories (106). No doubt eventually the Holy Spirit could have produced an "abstract" Genesis without factual error (the reviewer is inclined to say that She has done so, or at least is in the course of doing so, by means of the corrective supplied by modem palaeontology); but it is difficult to see in what respect it would have been an improvement on the "concrete, suggestive, effective" document that we have. And what would have been the point? "Only this: that a few saganists in our own time would have had to find some other excuse to reject the Word of God than its disagreement with the fossil record" (108). The article ends with some salutary reminders that many eminent authorities are now unhappy with Darwin's account of the causal mechanisms underlying evolution on purely scientific grounds (127). A curious meditation on the beginning of Genesis, from rather a different point of view, is provided by Harry G. Frankfurt. This reviewer can only make sense of it as a kind ofjeu d'esprit; it is certainly fascinating and thought-provoking as such. The first two verses (we are told) inform us that before the first creative act-the making of light-there were already three entities, the earth, the deep, and the spirit of God. In other words, there is no question of a "creation out of nothing" (130). It even looks as though God becomes God, as opposed to merely "the spirit of God," by imposing form on "the earth" and "the deep," and so making them describable in terms of intelligible speech (132). "This first creative act both transforms a dark world into a lighted one and transforms the spirit of God into God" (134). God realizes and defines God by imposing order on chaos, and indeed needs humanity to accept the imposed order, for the completion not merely of the creation of the world, but of the divine being itself (140). Of what is as a whole an extraordinarily rich collection, William Alston's paper seems to the reviewer to be among the finest. Plainly the terms we use of God are derived from our discourse about creatures, particularly human beings. However, God is so different from creatures that it seems impossible for the terms to be used in quite the same sense in the two cases. But if that is so, just how is one to articulate the difference? Among the many historical solutions to the problem, that of Thomas Aquinas stands out for its depth, complexity, and subtlety (145). Yet it seems irretrievably flawed. The trouble is, according to Alston, that Aquinas "has disavowed any attempt to be specific about what knowing or willing come to in the divine case, except that they constitute a 'higher mode' of the sort of thing we have in human knowing or willing.... By his own admission he is in no position to spell out the respects of similarity and dissimilarity between divine and human causal agency, willing, and so on" (173). Aquinas's teaching on the subject seems to derive from his doctrine of the divine simplicity-that there is no real distinction between the divine being and any of the divine attributes. This doctrine, as Alston sees it, has to be rejected (178). (The reviewer considers that at least "understanding" and "will" have to be understood in the same sense BOOK REVIEWS 501 as between God and creatures. Human understanding is in very restricted potency [to put the matter in Aristotelian terms] what divine understanding is in infinite act; human will is extremely narrow in extent and power, while whatever happens in the cosmos-with qualifications where free created agents are concerned-is due to the divine will. The doctrine of God's simplicity should be retained, if at all, only so far as it is consistent with the account just summarized.) A claim that is quite common among theists, that the primary object of religious faith is "not the final and most profound reality," which is somehow behind, above, or beneath it, is investigated by George Mavrodes. He discusses two versions of the claim, in the work of Paul Tillich and John Hick, and concludes that, seductive as it may seem, it is viable in neither form. Such "Gods above the Gods ... may, on the one hand, be construed in a way which makes them irrelevant to religious life and experience. Kicked upstairs, they can thenceforth largely be ignored. On the other hand, they may be construed in ways that make them religiously attractive. In that case, they are likely to be assimilated by some allegedly lower gods that belong to the particular religions" (203). In another important paper, Richard Swinburne raises the question of how God is related to time, and defends what he calls the "simple, naive, initial answer ... that God is everlasting" (204). The most well-publicized alternative, that God is as it were present to all events, even when to us they are past or future, he rejects as incoherent. His own account, he insists, does not have the inconvenient consequence often attributed to it, of making God a prisoner of time; since "the unwelcome features of time--the increases of events that cannot be changed, the cosmic clock ticking away as they happen, the uncertainty about the future--may indeed invade God's time; but they come by invitation, not by force-and they continue for such periods of time as God chooses that they shall" (221-2). The problem of how divine perfection is to be reconciled with divine freedom is discussed in a pair of papers by William Rowe and Thomas Morris. Rowe asks, How can God be at once free, and unable to do anything which is not for the best? (223) He concludes that God's perfection rather severely limits the scope of divine freedom in creation, and suggests that one might get out of the difficulty either by giving up the libertarian idea of freedom as applied to God, or by maintaining that God might be better than God actually happens to be (233). Morris approaches the problem from a somewhat different angle, contrasting the conception of God as "ultimate in causation" to that of God as "ultimate in value" (234). "How could a perfectly wise, good, and powerful being," he asks, "choose to create anything less than a perfect world?" (235) In opposition to Rowe, he argues that, since the very idea of "the best of all possible worlds" is incoherent, God cannot be faulted for failing to create such a thing (244). "What is hope," demands William Mann, "that it should be in the com- 502 BOOK REVIEWS pany of faith and love?" (251). Some passages in Luther's commentary on Romans tacitly imply an indictment of hope. As Luther sees it, if one is in the highest rank of the elect, one will have an unalloyed desire to conform to the will of God, which entails desiring to be damned if that is what God wishes (256). However, Aquinas seems right in arguing that charity, as a state of friendship with God, presupposes hope. "I cannot enter into a relationship of amicitia with you as long as I despair of the possibility, deeming myself unworthy of obtaining the good that the relationship would bestow" (279). (It should be mentioned in passing that Mann's paper is a regular feast from a purely literary point of view.) Peter Abelard's views on the atonement are commended, in the teeth of contemporary fashion, by Philip Quinn. As he says, Abelard's critics object to his so-called "exemplarism" on the ground not that it is utterly wide of the mark, but that it is insufficient as an exhaustive account (282). In one famous text, Abelard is often taken to be saying that our redemption consists in the love Christ manifests by suffering for us; and some of his translators have rendered the passage accordingly. But, argues Quinn, Abelard's Latin is not necessarily, or even most naturally, to be read in this sense; and comparison with what Abelard writes elsewhere shows that it ought not to be so taken. His meaning appears rather to be that our redemption consists in the love wrought in us by Christ's passion (289). In one place, Abelard actually defends a straight penal substitution theory (290). Bernard's claim, that Abelard's views amounted to Pelagianism, is quite unjust; it can only appear plausible if one takes some of his more extreme statements in isolation, and then exaggerates them (292). Marilyn Adams's paper on hell makes the case for universalism with a splendid compound of moral passion and rigorous argument. She takes particular exception to the views of William Craig, who espouses the traditionally standard view that a very substantial proportiop of human beings are to suffer eternal damnation. Adams reminds us of all the "traumas, impairments, disasters and hardships" which people have to struggle against in this life; for example, the physical and sexual abuse endured from childhood onwards by youths in the gangland of South Central Los Angeles. "I do not find it credible that all such antemortem situations contain grace sufficient for faith in and cooperation with God (Christ) were it not for the creature's incompatibilist free refusal" (319). Adams admits that her own universalism is supported by only a selection of the texts relevant to the subject in the New Testament; but reasonably urges that the same applies to the views of her opponents. Some serious people, as she says, reject universalism on the grounds that it is apt to lead to religious and moral indifference. But she finds in her own pastoral experience "that the disproportionate threat of hell . . . produces despair that masquerades as skepticism, rebellion, and unbelief' (325). The final contribution, by the editor, assesses Aquinas's treatment of the BOOK REVIEWS 503 sufferings of Job, which she finds instructively different from the sort of account which would come naturally to people of our own time. We are apt to wonder how a good God could possibly permit the many and frightful evils which infest the world. Aquinas, however, believed that all human beings are afflicted with "a terminal cancer of soul," for which pain and suffering are the divinely-appointed remedies (340). If we are not cured, we will lose for ever the ultimate bliss of communion with God. At this rate we are to expect that the best people are precisely those who are liable to suffer the most (342). Aquinas would agree with Pope Gregory, who says that it is frequently difficult to understand the ways of providence, but never more so than "when things go ill with good people and well with bad people" (343). Stump concludes that what Aquinas's interpretation of Job, and his overall account of evil, has to show us is "that our approach to the problem of evil is a consequence of our attitude towards much larger issues, such as the nature of human happiness and the goal of human life" (356). The reader will have inferred that this is a remarkable volume. None of the contributions is to be sneezed at, and some are very impressive indeed. HUGO MEYNELL University of Calgary Calgary, Alberta, Canada Christ the 'Name' of God: Thomas Aquinas on Naming Christ. By HENK J. M. SCHOOT. Nijmegen: Peeters Leuven, 1993. Pp. 231 (Paper). The hiddenness of God in Christ and "the relation between the Word Incarnate and human words for this Word" animate this study of Aquinas's christological epistemology; it is a study of Aquinas's understanding of "the mystery of Christ, and [of] human ways of signifying him" (1). And because "all human understanding and signification fails [sic] to reach Christ as he is," Schoot believes that all christological knowledge is primarily negative and heavily reliant on analogy (1). He applies to the names of Christ what another author (Mark Jordan) has applied to the divine names: "the surest approach to the divine is by the scrutiny of linguistic failure" (153). The structure of the book reflects these insights. In the first chapter the author stresses the negative character of christological language by reflecting upon Aquinas's use of mysterium in christology. The second chapter is an analysis of his use of "the concepts of signification, supposition, predication and reduplication," in the context of the most current knowledge of medieval grammar and logic (7). It is here that the author stresses Aquinas's strongly linguistic approach to christology, as well as the distinction between supposition ("standing for") and predication ("sig- 504 BOOK REVIEWS nification"), which will be crucial to his analysis of the hypostatic union in later chapters. In fact, "the whole of christology is built on the distinction between signification and supposition" (55). Schoot believes that Aquinas, following medieval "modist" grammarians, thought that "a fundamental parallel exists between different modes of signification, modes of understanding and modes of being" (43), and hence a linguistic approach is often a decisive entry into questions of theological (and christologiocal) epistemology and metaphysics. In this context, the author examines the distinction Aquinas made between a number of modes of signification. Chapter Three is devoted to Aquinas as a biblical theologian. His use of biblical names of Christ {over ninety in his commentary on Isaiah alone) suggests that "a large part of Aquinas' treatment of the person and life of the Word Incarnate is devoted to a discussion of names" (104), and that the fact that Christ is a mystery "is rooted in (his] being the 'name' of God" (105). Schoot finds that "Aquinas employs the same rules concerning signification examining those names as he does concerning the divine names" (193). Chapter Four applies the key insights of Aquinas's "theory of supposition to the theology of Christ incarnate" (194). Following an analysis of such key concepts as first and second substance, esse, suppositum,singularis,particularis, and individuum, Schoot concludes that The subject-term having both signification and supposition expresses a linguistic unity that Aquinas deems analogous to the unity in Christ. Just like words that have different significations can be one in their supposition for one and the same supposit, Christ can be called one since two natures are united in one person. The mode of signifying Christ is analogous to Christ's mode of being. (194-5) He holds that this distinction between supposition and signification is the "linguistic parallel" to the distinction between being and essence (120), and that since the unity of Christ finally escapes all human signification, it "can only be approached by human supposition" (156). Aquinas's principal concern here is "to safeguard, in all interpretation and construction, the unity of Christ (198), and Schoot demonstrates that "Aquinas' linguistic treatment of the names of Christ and the hypostatic union employs the same basic ideas that are used in his treatment of the divine names: analogous signification, divine simplicity, and mixed relation" (197). Indeed, the theory of the communicatio idiomatum "is for christology what the 'theory' of analogy is for the doctrine about God" (139). The next chapter discusses the esse of Christ, and the importance of Aquinas's affirmation that he est creatura, even though he does not possess a subsistent, personal human act of being. In this densely written and brief chapter, Schoot denies that Aquinas changed his view between the Quaestio DisputataDe Unione Verbi lncamati and the Summa Theologiae.Rather, the author holds that Aquinas always thought that Christ possessed a human esse in the sense of "second substance," that which permits an essence to exist by BOOK REVIEWS 505 itself, but which does "not contribute to the personal being itself' (164). Further, since Christ's human nature is "attached" to the personal esse of the Word by means of a mixed relation, nothing can be "be lacking to the being of Christ's human nature. In fact, whoever objects that a personal human being is lacking in Christ violates the distinction between supposition and signification" (164). The final chapter makes explicit the connection between naming God and naming Christ: "all true naming of God is related to the hypostatic union as its paradigm" (169), and in particular the author shows what he believes to be the connection between the naming of God and the relation between the three types of created knowledge in the soul of Christ. Perhaps the most accessible and theologically rewarding chapter is the first, and it is worthwhile to develop some of its insights. Schoot stresses that Aquinas rarely speaks of mysterium in regard to the Godhead; rather, it is for him the paramount christological term, because it connotes both hiddenness and disclosure, the thing signified and that which signifies. According to Schoot, Aquinas understood Christ's humanity (and his entire human life) to be a mode of signifying God, a mode in which God is at once hidden and disclosed, as in a mysterium. Since the Godhead itself is absolutely pure light in which nothing is hidden, the term does not properly apply to it. One can only properly speak of mystery when the divine light is disclosed through creaturely reality, and the paradigmatic revealing/veiling is the humanity of Christ. The author then develops four modes of revelatory hiddenness that are important for Aquinas, and which may be expressed as follows: the Word is hidden in the articles of faith, in the Old Testament, in the eucharist, and in his human nature. In his consideration of the articles of faith, Schoot again stresses that the formal object of faith (the First Truth) is not a mysterium in itself, but only inasmuch as it is understood by us, only inasmuch as God is revealed to us as the material object of faith. God is revealed to us as a mystery, in a mysterious, and hence hidden, way. The mystery that is Christ is also revealed in the Old Testament in a mysterious way: those things that it refers to literally, "refer mysteriously to the mystery of Christ" (27), and are unlocked by the spiritual senses of scripture. Christ, especially in his passion, is also revealed/hidden in the mystery of the eucharist under the signs of bread and wine: they, too, mysteriously and hence hiddenly reveal him. Thus "mysterium is something hidden with the hiddenness of the propositions of faith and also with the hiddenness of the spiritual signification of Scripture" (28), as well as with the eucharistic species. And all of those modes of hiddenness reflect the primary hiddenness of the Word in his humanity. He ends this treatment with the following analogy, in which the second (italicized) term is the mysterious mode of signifying the res signifzcata: The First Truth is signified by the propositi.on of faith, Christ is signified by the Old Law, the Incarnate Word is signified by his human nature, and the passion of Christ is 506 BOOK REVIEWS signified by bread and wine (39). Schoot sums up the concept of mysterium operative here by saying that it is "something hidden, voiced truly but inadequately, spiritually signified by the Old Testament and now fulfilled in Christ and the sacrament of the eucharist" (38). Despite the meticulous scholarship displayed in this work, students of Aquinas's theological epistemology and christology may well be struck by what seem to be gratuitous harmonizations between theology and christology (the parallel between the analogy of being and the communicationem idiomatum, making the hypostatic union paradigmatic in the naming of God), the overwhelming weight given to the signification/supposition distinction, and the seeming reduction of the principles of christology to linguistic rules. In addition, the complex and often turgid style serves to obfuscate certain important questions, such as Aquinas's understanding of Christ's esse. Is Aquinas being forced into a theological mold that he himself would not recognize? EDWARD L. KRASEVAC, 0.P Dominican School of Philosophy and Theology Berkeley, California An Introduction to the History of Exegesis, vol. III: St. Augustine. By BERTRAND DE MARGERIE, S.J. Petersham, Mass.: St. Bede's Publications, 1993. Pp. xi+ 169 (paper). Unfortunately, today many scholars and general readers neglect the work of the Fathers of the Church. One often hears that the writings of the Fathers have become less relevant or less important because there has been so much progress in Scripture studies and because the Fathers did not really try to find out what the inspired writer meant to say-for they relied on allegory. St. Augustine's exegesis poses a particular difficulty in terms of its reliance on allegory. Augustine was strongly influenced by the allegorical exegesis of bishop Ambrose and recounts in his Confession.5(VI, iv, 6) how he used to hear Ambrose teaching in his sermons, as though he were most diligently teaching a rule: "The letter kills, but the spirit gives life." Father de Margerie admits that Augustine did indeed suffer from "excessive allegorism" (126), but he insists that this is no reason to give up entirely on Augustine. Instead, with keen scholarly analysis he shows that, in spite of some defects, Augustine did in fact give us some really fine work in Scripture study. Father de Margerie stresses that according to Augustine the purpose of all Scripture is to teach love: " ... the plenitude and the end of the Law and of BOOK REVIEWS 507 all the sacred Scriptures is the love ... of a Being which is to be enjoyed and of a being that can share that enjoyment with us" (20; from De Doctrina Christiana, I, xxv, 39). This love is taught even at the beginning of Scripture: " ... on a subjective level, Moses wrote for the love of all men" (30). But how could this be? "It seems to us nowadays that Augustine failed to perceive adequately the progressive nature of the disclosure of religious truths by the God who revealed them" (30). Father de Margerie responds to this objection by pointing out that given the belief that Moses had been given a transient, "face to face vision of the Divine being ... and that this experience was granted him precisely in favor of the universal Church," it makes sense to assume that "the prophet and maker of the old Law received knowledge, during this vision and through divine revelation, of how future interpretation of the Law he was issuing-like that which Jesus was to issuewould extend even to enemies the love of one's neighbor" (31). Augustine was led to this view in the light of the varied interpretations being proposed in his own time for Genesis (48). Father de Margerie admits that "Augustine himself limits the scope of his theory concerning the plurality of literal meaning to a few rather exceptional verses of scripture" (65). Augustine believed, however, that Moses had received most remarkable gifts: I cannot think that Moses Your most faithful servant was given by you lesser gifts than I should have wished and longed to have for myself if I had been born at the same time as he .... I should have wished that you would grant me such a skill in writing, such an art for the construction of what I had to say, that those ... who can grasp so much [how God creates] would find fully contained in the few words of your servant whatever truths they had arrived at in their own thinking; and if in the light of truth some other man saw some further meaning, then that too would be discoverable in those same words of mine. (50; from Confessions XII, xxvi, 36) Furthermore, "Augustine acknowledges in De Genesi ad litteram that Moses beheld God face to face, and in the Confesswnsthat the biblical law-giver had a foreknowledge of the interpretations readers would draw from what he wrote in Genesis 1:1" (52-53). This was needed, Augustine thinks, so that Moses could actually intend all the interpretations that others would later find in his words. Today there is much discussion of the possible plural literal sense. The Second Vatican Council, in Dei verbum §12, had an opportunity to affirm or deny this plural literal sense, but intentionally passed it by. Yet the same Council in Lumen gentium §55 nonetheless used the very same principle in speaking of Gen. 3:15 and Is. 7:14: ''These primeval documents, as they are read in the Church and understood in the light of later and full revelation, gradually bring before us the figure of the Mother of the Redeemer." In other words, the Holy Spirit, the chief author, surely could have more in mind than what the human author saw. Vatican II refrains from asserting that the author did or did not see in these texts all that the Church now sees. Father de 508 BOOK REVIEWS Margerie tells us that Augustine surely held that Genesis contains such a plural sense, with the added affirmation that Moses, whom Augustine considers to be the author of the Pentateuch, thanks to a transient beatific vision, personally foresaw and intended all the interpretations that would later be given. In keeping with his careful and cautious approach, near the end of the book Father de Margerie admits the limitations of Augustine, limitations which Augustine himself often perceived. "First, Augustine's strictly exegetical works are rather limited .... His sustained commentaries are few, those which have reached us concern Genesis, Job, the Letters to the Galatians and part of that to the Romans, the Gospel, and the First Letter of John" (126). Secondly, Augustine had only a slight knowledge of Biblical Greek. He usually worked from the Latin Bible. He seldom referred systematically to the Greek. Further, he had "but a smattering of Hebrew, acquired indirectly through his familiarity with Punic" (126). Finally-a very large admission"he, along with nearly all the Fathers, failed to analyze adequately the literal meaning of numerous texts he sought to interpret" (126). In spite of such limitations, Augustine and the other Fathers do provide us with many insights into sound doctrine. This is especially useful since so many of the errors of today, advertised as new, are merely ancient mistakes rejected centuries ago by the Fathers. Therefore we are all indebted to Father de Margerie for helping to call us back to what is so very good in the Fathers. Father de Margerie has rendered a singular service to scholarship in his first two volumes of study of Patristic exegesis. The present volume, the third, is a worthy successor to the first two. WILLIAM G. MOST Notre Dame Institute Alexandria, Virginia The Primacy of Love: An Introduction to the Ethics of Thomas Aquinas. By PAUL J. WADELL, C.P. Mahwah, N.J.: Paulist Press, 1992. Pp. 162. $11.95. Friends of God: Virtues and Gifts in Aquinas. By PAUL J. WADELL, C.P. American University Studies, Series VII: Theology and Religion, vol. 76. New York: Peter Lang, 1991. Pp. x + 148. Drawing from the virtue-ethics orientation of his earlier work, Friendship and the Moral Life (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1990), Paul Wadell has written two books that seek to accomplish two distinctly different BOOK REVIEWS 509 objectives: to produce a work that can serve as a general introduction to Thomas Aquinas's teaching about ethics, and to produce a monograph that urges a different approach to the interpretation of Thomas's ethical teaching. But both books share a common interest of Wadell's: showing that Thomas's ethics is an ethics of genuine affection. Whether he is judged to have reached the two objectives is a question that is likely to be answered differently by moralists, depending upon the issues and approaches that shape their own understanding of Thomistic moral theology. At the very least, Wadell has produced two well-crafted books that are trend-setting works in a long and promising career, works whose approach is surely to become familiar as more and more writers emphasize virtue ethics with regard to the moral teaching of Aquinas. And at most, Wadell has shown himself to be both a fine teacher of Thomas's ethical thought and an incisive scholar in identifying the subterranean movements of the Common Doctor's thought. I shall consider The Primacy of Love first, which, although it appeared second, is a good intelligible backdrop for presenting the more sophisticated and important argument of Friends of God. Waddell's introduction to Thomas's ethics is not really a synopsis of the Secunda pars of the Summa theologiae, though the lion's share of the material he employs is from there, and in something of its original order. It is rather a sympathetic, almost affectionate, portrait of Thomas's ethical teaching. The book does not introduce the reader to the technicalities of Thomas's thought, or to the bewildering debates surrounding the practical syllogism and natural law that have characterized the secondary literature in the second half of this century. Wadell-and others, I imagine-would consider this a strength of the book, since its goal is to encourage readers to go to Thomas's texts themselves. The introductory chapter quickly presents Thomas's life, relying upon Weisheipl and Pieper, notes briefly the outline and nature of the Summa theologiae, and most importantly addresses something that characterizes Wadell's whole perspective on Thomas's moral teaching: the intimate, indeed inseparable, link between his moral and spiritual teaching (17-21). Using the life-stance Thomas shows us in his famous non ni.si te, domine experience ("Nothing else but you, Lord") as an intelligible entrance-point into his whole reason for writing the Summa theologiae, Wadell reins in his reader of Thomas's moral teaching away from the mechanical "nut-and-bolts" to which we are otherwise accustomed, and rather directs that reader to consider Thomas's rationale for the whole project: ''Thomas wrote the Summa because he loved God, and like all great lovers he believed he had something fabulous to share" (19). Proceeding loosely according to the order of the Prima secundae, Wadell investigates the nature of human happiness, noting how Thomas's investigation leads him to assert that only God is humanity's happiness (Wadell never really engages Thomas's heavy emphasis upon the cognitional element of 510 BOOK REVIEWS human happiness). He then quickly imports some of the treatment of charity (from I-II, 65, and II-II, 23) into the discussion, noting how Thomas terms charity as a "kind of friendship with God" (63-78). Returning to the original order of the Prima secundae, Wadell bypasses the account of morality (I-II, 18-21), and very ably addresses the human emotions-an element of Thomas's teaching rarely mentioned in the literature, even by Thomistic moralists. The virtues are treated next, along with the Gifts, and then finally he concludes, emphasizing that love, and especially the love of God, is the "cornerstone of Thomistic ethics" (145). Veteran readers of Thomas's ethics, particularly of the Secunda pars of the Summa theologiae, might wonder how an introduction to Thomas's ethics can afford not to treat of any number of important topics: the constitution of human acts, the treatment of morality, law, or even grace. Likewise, the emphasis upon charity would seem to call for the other two theological virtues, faith and hope. And the desire to highlight love of God results in little treatment being given to what concrete items-the defining objects of the various virtues and vices-aid or endanger the moral agent in seeking God. But Wadell's goal of providing his reader with an attractive introduction to Thomas's ethics does not commit him to addressing all the various and difficult issues that continue to confound even professional readers of Aquinas. And he has served his reader well by instructing that person, and reminding us, that Thomas's ethics is surely radically incomplete if it is considered without reference to the role of the emotions relative to the virtues and the gifts, or, even more importantly, if considered without reference to the love of God that arguably gives shape to Thomas's theological ethics, and surely grounded his own moral life. This theological emphasis continues in Friends of God, a more sustained account of Thomas's teaching. Here Wadell is concerned to demonstrate the following thesis: Thomas's moral teaching in the Summa theologiae, particularly that of the Prima secundae, must be read under the rubric of charity if his treatment of the passions, the virtues, and the Gifts, is to be understood fully. Starting, accordingly, with a consideration of charity, Wadell notes how Thomas appropriated Aristotle's teaching on friendship in the Nicomachean Ethics, yet how he in moral theology bases the primary instance of "friendship" upon the primary relationship that exists between God and human persons. Wadell again emphasizes how human happiness is to be found in union with God, but again does this with almost no reference to the intellective formality of that union-I shall return to this later. Turning to consider the role of the passions in the moral life, Wadell argues that the passion of love is primary, and, further, that our learning to love things in the right way is essential to our happiness. And learning to love God is, of course, learning to love what is most important, bar none. To do all this well we need the virtues, which are dispositions of the various passions, BOOK REVIEWS 511 and, Wadell notes, which are all to be informed by charity if a truly integrated moral life is to be achieved. A discussion of charity as the "form" of the virtues naturally follows, and in it Wadell points out how, for Thomas, charity in many ways becomes the standard of goodness for all the virtues it informs. The Gifts of the Holy Spirit enter the discussion at this point, though, Wadell insists, not as an appendage. As Wadell sees them, the Gifts are, once charity is granted its proper role as ultimate defining source of virtues, genuine, efficacious means of loving God, and through them, of attaining to human happiness (127-133). Seen in this light, the Gifts form a truly integral part ofThomas's moral theology. The book comes to a close at this point, without a final summation, but Wadell's thesis has been so clearly defined throughout the book that the reader is at every tum referring the current treatment to the book's larger aims. About the strength of the book a few comments are in order. Methodologically, the book does not in any serious way engage some of the disputes concerning charity (e.g., with Lombard) and the Gifts (e.g., with William of Auxerre) that quite likely shaped some ofThomas's treatment, and no sustained account is given to the trends that Thomas's treatment of charity underwent in the course of his writing career. The lacunae present in The Primacy of Love are found here, too. Thus no treatment is given to Thomas's teaching on law, though a prime candidate for "reading the text under the rubric of charity" would obviously and fruitfully have been Thomas's account of the New Law-and the Old Law's "forward glance" to the New Law could have been excitingly illuminated by employing this reading. Wadell's not having addressed the ultimately intellectual basis of Thomas's treatment of human happiness results, I worry, in an emotivism that threatens to undercut what it is in human nature that makes us really interesting to God: our likeness to him tlirough intellect. This absence of intellect in the book leaves Wadell without access to any number of texts and tools that could actually give his point greater cogency: qq. 19-24 (on God), q. 59 (on angels), qq. 82-83 (on humans) in the Prima pars, as well as any number of questions in the de actibu.shumani.ssection of the Prima secundae (qq. 6-21), all ground "love" in the will, which is in turn grounded in intellect-Wadell prefers texts in the treatment of the passions, which are acts that human beings have in common with the lower animals (1-11, q. 6, prol.). I say this, not to be pedantic, but rather to point out that, for Thomas, the act of charity, being an act of the will, is the fullest sense of the term "love" in the vocabulary of his moral theology. But this love of God lasts, while faith and hope do not, precisely because, in eternal beatitude, "we will become like him, for we see him as he is" (1 Jn 3:2), a seeing that is an unmediated intellectual vision of God himself, whom we become more like, through knowledge. And 512 BOOK REVIEWS knowing God, particularly in eternal blessedness, explains that and why he is so much to he loved. Thomas's intellectualism has a greater role in his moral theology. But Wadell's point is still well-taken. The love of God is operative throughout Thomas's moral instruction in the Summa theologiae, and treatments of his teaching on the passions and the virtues that do not see them as linked in some real way to charity are doomed to incompleteness. Both The Primary of Love and Friends of God are genuine contributions in this regard. I am not sure whether they achieve the golden mean of presenting Thomas's moral teaching "dot-on," hut I am sure that embracing the tenor of these hooks will help us to achieve that mean in due time. MARK JOHNSON Saint Joseph's College Rensselaer, Indiana English Reformations: Religion, Politics, and Society under the Tudors. By CHRISTOPHER HAIGH. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993. Pp. 300. $19.95 (paper). Church Papists: Catholicism, Conformity and ConfessionalPolemic in Early Modem England. By ALEXANDRA WALSHAM. The Royal Historical Society Studies in History, vol. 68. Woodbridge: Boydell Press, 1993. Pp. xiii + 142. $53.00 (cloth). The revision of the history of the English Reformation continues at great pace in these two recent hooks. The first, by Christopher Haigh, is one-volume account of the English Reformation that clearly attempts to replace A. G. Dickens's masterful The English Reformation. which has held the field since 1964. Haigh admirably succeeds in this attempt. His style is very readable, forceful, and compelling-reminiscent of Hilaire Belloc's headlong historical narrative, hut without Belloc's confessional loyalties (Haigh is not a Catholic) or oversimplification. This is not a facile account of a complicated Reformation. Haigh knows what the complications are and does not hesitate to discuss them. The hook gets its name from the author's thesis that the English Reformation was the result of political accidents and coincidences, lurching along to an Elizabethan "Settlement," which succeeded only because Henry VIII died eight months too late, because Mary Tudor died too soon, or because Elizabeth lived too long. In other words, the English Reformation did not have to happen; it was not inevitable; it could have been (and was) BOOK REVIEWS 513 reversed any number of times. Grand, long-term causes and patterns (e.g. the popularity of Lollardy, the corruption of the Church) are dismissed as the hindsight of propagandists. In fact, the Reformation happened largely because the people involved did not know that it was happening; they had not read A. G. Dickens on the subject. There are excellent critiques of church warden accounts and will preambles, similar to the critiques offered by Duffy in his recent Stripping of the Altars (Yale, 1992), and caution is urged in seeing in this evidence too much enthusiastic Protestantism. People may have stopped mentioning the saints and the Virgin in their wills, not necessarily because they were convinced Protestants, but more probably because it had become illegal to mention such things. Characters such as Colet, who have long been viewed as being incipient Protestants, are given a more convincing reading by Haigh: "Colet was not a proto-Protestant, disgusted with the ecclesiastical structure and the sacramental system; he was a high clericalist, anxious to maintain the privileges of priests by raising their prestige." Chesterton said this years ago, of course, in his comment that Chaucer (who was resurrected as a hero by the Reformers) did not criticize monks because he wanted to destroy monasticism; he only wanted to improve the monks. The book is not without its shortcomings. Haigh overstates the de-construction of the Reformation. While it is true that there were lurches and reactions and reversals, there was also a continuum which appeared with each separate Reformation, which can be traced to a previous one, be it Henrician or Edwardian. When Edward came to power, the monasteries, convents, friaries, religious orders, shrines, and chantries were gone. When Mary came to power, much of the artwork was gone and people had become wary of giving money towards prayers for the dead-not because they stopped believing in prayers for the dead, but because they were afraid another government would simply confiscate the money. This meant a change in attitude, in practise. Conservative bishops only slowed the process, and eventually lost. When Elizabeth came to power, there was already a liturgy and body of legislation which had previously been enacted and needed only to be put back in place. Each Reformation may have been separate and piecemeal, but each one depended on and built on what had gone before. But what was the Reformation in England? On this Haigh is somewhat confusing. On one page he seems to insist that politics was primary: It was politics which made the difference, politics which provided the dynamic of change, politics which made English Reformations instead of the Reformation in England. . . . English Reformations were about changing minds as well as changing laws, but it was the changing laws which made the changing of so many minds possible. (p. 20) So far so good, but on p. 14 he has said something which sounds contradictory: "What made English people Protestant-some English people Protestant-was not the three political Reformations, but the parallel evan- 514 BOOK REVIEWS gelical Reformation." The confusion, however, is more apparent than real and stems more from the confusing nature of the English Reformation itself. Was it a puritan evangelical revolt, a political change of power, a mere ecclesiastical break with Rome? It could not be all three. Haigh claims that the people carried on despite the politicians and the new theologians. They clung to some rituals and some beliefs despite the preaching of the godly. And what had changed at the end of the day for the typical Englishman, Haigh claims, was not very much. "Some reformations," he concludes. The radical Reformation of Cranmer and Latimer did not succeed at all. Some people went into recusancy, while most conformed reluctantly to the established Church. There was not much difference between them. For the majority and for Haigh, Catholicism had simply slipped a little. He sees continuity, not in theological content so much as in the majority who rejected the negative aspects of Reformation and struggled on. Haigh does not discuss the relative merits or demerits of conformity. Unlike Duffy, he does not care if the people conformed or not; but he does care that the story of how the Reformation happened has been told inaccurately for too long. Protestantism was not thick on the ground before the Reformation, nor was Catholicism unpopular or little-practised, nor was Protestantism welcomed. In fact, it seems rather to have been more widely opposed; if it had been up to the people, there would not have been an English Reformation. All this has become evident from the same evidence which made A. G. Dickens so famous. There is possibly a little too much looking-over-the-shoulder at the great Dickens, but then Haigh is looking at centuries of inaccurate British history. He has made sure that the history of the English Reformation will not be told so inaccurately again. Alexandra Walsham's book takes the question of conformity head-on. She contends that many, if not the majority, of conforming churchgoers in Elizabeth's reign were theologically or instinctively Roman Catholic, and were caught between the rock of conversion and the hard place of bankruptcy, social ostracism, or even death. She then provides a very helpful summary of the debate which raged between the government (which was amazingly minimalistic in its enforcement of conformity) and its more enthusiastic parsons, as well as the debate within Roman Catholicism itself. While this would be sufficient for a useful book, Walsham moralizes about conformity and decides that it was the best way to go. John Fisher and Thomas More are thus necessarily viewed as extremists who mistakenly went too far. (Haigh, incidentally, agrees that Fisher could have accomplished much more by dissembling and staying on in Rochester to prevent the radical Hilsey from his place.) There are many problems with this position. It presumes, first of all, that the religion did not change, or did not change that much. If it did change substantially, as the Romans believed, then conformi- BOOK REVIEWS 515 ty may not be looked on so benignly. But even more cogently, the politics and theology of resistance are overlooked. While it should be admitted that the majority will follow the path of least resistance, in this case, survival, and that some compensation should be made for their weakness (as early popes did with the apostates under the various Roman persecutions), this should not be held up as the ideal. To canonize weakness is to go too far. Martyrs exist not to elicit sympathy from the populace so much as to define the religion. A religion which conforms as a matter of principle is no religion at all. Despite their flaws, these two books mark a refreshing improvement in the way the history of the English Reformation is being told. JOHN VIDMAR, 0.P Dominican House of Studies Washington, DC