AQUINAS ON NATURE, HYPOSTASIS, AND THE METAPHYSICS OF THE INCARNATION RICHARD CROSS Oriel College, University of Oxford Oxford, England A CCORDING TO Christian orthodoxy, Jesus Christ is one person-the second person of the Trinity-who has both divine and human natures. As the Council of Chalcedon (451) puts the matter, the two natures are united in one person. The claim that the two natures are united in one person is contrasted, in the creed of the Council, with something like the claim that the two natures are mixed together into one new nature. Thus the creed clearly presupposes some kind of distinction between the senses of "person" and "nature." 1 I think that it is fairly clear that the distinction that the Council of Chalcedon presupposes must be something like the distinction between an individual, on the one hand, and its kind-nature and non-essential properties on the other. The position would then be that the second person of the Trinity began to instantiate some kindnature (viz., human nature) which he did not previously instantiate, without this entailing that the person ceased being divine. The human nature, on this view, would be a non-essential property-or a non-essential kind-nature-of the second person of the Trinity. As Thomas Morris points out, this will mean that the orthodox Christian 1 "We teach the confession of ... one and the same Christ, Son, Lord, only-begotten, acknowledged in two natures which undergo no confusion, no change, no division, no separation. At no point was the difference in natures taken away through the union, but rather the property of both natures is preserved and comes together into a single person and a single subsistent being": thus the creed of the Council of Chalcedon, in Decrees of the Ecumenical Councils, ed. Norman J. Tanner (London: Sheed and Ward; Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press, 1990), 1:86. I have used Tanner's translation, making slight alterations in the punctuation. 171 172 RICHARD CROSS will reject the view that every nature [i.e., kind-nature] is an essential property of every individual who exists in that nature. 2 Since the second person of the Trinity did not cease being divine, the Chalcedonian account will also entail acceptance of the possibility of some individual having more than one kind-nature. But, as Morris again points out, this does not seem to be necessarily inconsistent-it might be the case that, for some sets of kind-natures, such a state of affairs is indeed possible. 3 In this paper, I want to look in some detail at Aquinas's account of the distinction between person and nature. In so doing, I hope to get a fairly clear grasp of Aquinas's account(s) of the . metaphysics of the incarnation. I shall argue that the accounts which Aquinas gives of the metaphysics of the incarnation other than in De Unione Verbi Incarnati fail to be coherent and that the somewhat different account in De Unione Verbi 2 Thomas V. Morris, The Logic of God Incarnate (Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press, 1986), 41. 3 Morris, 40. It is worth noting that this interpretation of Chalcedon is not found unanimously in the literature. For example, Bernard Lonergan claims: "The distinction between persons and nature [in the decree of Chalcedon] is added to state what is one and the same and what are not one and the same. The person is one and the same; the natures are not one and the same. While later developments put persons and natures in many further contexts, the context of Chalcedon needs no more than heuristic concepts" (Bernard Lonergan, "The Origins of Christian Realism," in A Second Collection, ed. William F. J. Ryan and Bernard J. Tyrrell [London: Darton, Longman and Todd, 1974], 259: my italics). Kenneth Surin makes a similar point: "The 'classical' christological formulations function-'negatively'-as 'meta-linguistic' or 'grammatical' principles, and not as ontological 'descriptions' of the 'mind' or 'will' of Christ" (review of Morris in Theology 90 (1987]: 55). By way of external support for the interpretation suggested here, however, I would cite a recent attempt to show that Cyril of Alexandria-whose work was of great importance for the formulation of the Chalcedonian creed-operated with a set of logical and ontological tools, derived from Aristotle's Categories and Porphyry's I sagoge, which allowed him to formulate a christological model based upon the distinction between subject, on the one hand, and essence and property on the other (see Ruth M. Siddals, "Logic and Christology in Cyril of Alexandria," Journal of Theological Studies, n.s., 38 (1987]: 341-367; also R. A. Norris, "Christological Models in Cyril of Alexandria," in Studia Patristica 13, Texte und Untersuchungen, 116 [Berlin: Akademie Verlag, 197 5], 225-68). For the importance of Cyril for Chalcedon, see A. Grillmeier, Christ in Christian Tradition, vol. 1, trans. John Bowden, 2nd ed. (London and Oxford: Mowbray, 1975), 544-549; also R. V. Sellers, The Council ofChalcedon (London: SPCK, 1953), 207-28. It is, of course, my claim that something like this distinction can be found in Chalcedon, too. AQUINAS ON NATURE, HYPOSTASIS AND METAPHYSICS 173 Incarnati achieves coherence at the expense of explanatory power. 4 While I shall be criticizing Aquinas's christology, my main purpose is to provide an accurate summary of Aquinas's position, and to trace the way in which his position changes through the different accounts he offers. It may be felt that it is wrong to concentrate merely on the philosophical aspects of Aquinas's account of a doctrine that must ultimately remain a theological mystery. But Aquinas sets high philosophical standards both in his discussions of metaphysics and in his analyses of Christian doctrine: in the very first question of the Summa Theologiae, he expressly notes that arguments directed against the faith are not merely false but demonstrably false. By calling them "demonstrably false,'' Aquinas means that they can be refuted philosophically. The context makes this clear: the opponent Thomas has in mind at this point in the discussion is one who does not believe the truth of any position which can be derived merely from revelation. 5 Of course, Aquinas's theological program is consistent with the claim that some doctrine might turn out to be a mystery, or ineffable. This claim allows that our philosophical categories are not sufficient to deal with the requirements of theology: the descriptions which we give of Christian doctrines may all turn out to be mere analogies for the real thing. But Aquinas's claim that arguments against the faith can be refuted philosophically entails that our descriptions of some theological doctrine, even if they are all analogies, must themselves be philosophically coherent. If 4 I refer to the following works of Aquinas: the Sentences commentary(= Sent.); the Quodlibetal Questions (= Quodl.); the disputed question De Unione Verbi Incarnati (= De Un. Verb. !near.); Summa Theologiae (= STh); Compendium Theologiae (= Comp. Theol.); De Ente et Essentia (= De Ente). I use the following editions: Scriptum super Libras Sententiarum, ed. P. Mandonnet and M. F. Moos, 4 vols. (Paris: Lethielleux, 19294 7); Quaestiones Quodlibetales, ed. R. M. Spiazzi (Turin and Rome: Marietti, 1949); Quaestiones Disputatae, ed. R. M. Spiazzi et al., 2 vols. (Turin and Rome: Marietti, 1949); Summa Theologiae, ed. Petrus Caramello, 3 vols. (Turin and Rome: Marietti, 1952-56); Opuscula Theologica, ed. R. A. Verardo, R. M. Spiazzi, and M. Calcaterra, 2 vols. (Turin and Rome: Marietti, 1954); De Ente et Essentia, ed. M.-D. Roland-Gosselin, Bibliotheque Thomiste, 8 (Kain, Belgium: Revue des Sciences Philosophiques et Theologiques, 1926). 5 STh I, q. 1, a. 8 (1:7a-b). 174 RICHARD CROSS they are not, it is difficult to see how the arguments of the opponent Thomas mentions can really be refuted by philosophywhich, as I have noted, is the claim he makes. In this paper, I shall argue that Aquinas's account of the metaphysics of the incarnation fails to be coherent, and that it therefore fails to meet the requirements of his own theological program. In my conclusion, I shall suggest some ways in which we might modify some of Aquinas's metaphysical presuppositions to allow him to give a philosophically coherent account of the incarnation. I. DISTINCTIONS BETWEEN SUPPOSITUM AND NATURE What is important about persons, for Aquinas, is that a person will necessarily be an (onto )logical subject: the kind of thing that has attributes. In this sense, the term "person" is equivalent to a number of other terms, two of which I shall need for this article: "hypostasis" and "suppositum." Aquinas restricts the use of the term "person" to the set of logical subjects that are rational.6 But he does not rely on the rationality of persons to draw his distinction between person and nature: it is not rationality which makes something an ontological subject. To avoid confusion, I shall use the more general term "suppositum" instead of the term "person"-since, in the relevant sense, these two terms are equivalent, and since the term "person," in much modern usage, tends to emphasize the status of persons as psychological, not ontological, subjects. As far as I can tell, Aquinas has two quite distinct ways of drawing a distinction between suppositum and nature in his christological discussions. (1) The first runs as follows: "Person" signifies something different from "nature." For "nature" signifies "the essence of a species, which the definition signifies." 7 ••• It happens that in some subsisting things we find something which does not pertain to the nature of the species, viz., accidents and individuating principles. This is most apparent in those things which are composed of matter and form. Therefore, in such things nature and sup- 6 7 See, for example, STh III, q. 2, a. 2 (3:13a) and STh III, q. 2, a. 3 (3:14a). Aristotle, Physics 2.l (193a30-31). AQUINAS ON NATURE, HYPOSTASIS AND METAPHYSICS 175 positum are really distinct, not as two things totally separate [from each other], but since the nature of the species is itself included in the suppositum and certain other things are added which are beyond the nature of the species. Whence, a suppositum is signified as a whole, having a nature as a formal part, perfective of it." One or two surprising facts emerge from this account. One is that a suppositum is not some subject underlying a nature. It is not quite like Locke's substance. Rather, the suppositum is a whole which includes a set of parts. These parts, however, do not all exist on the same kind of ontological level. They fit together in a rather complicated way. (Thus, it would be quite wrong to saddle Aquinas with any kind of mereological bundle theory of particulars.) Aquinas, in fact, mentions three types of part included in a suppositum: the nature, the individuating features, and the accidents. "Nature" is clearly here to be taken as something like kindnature. It is not a particular thing, but just a way of talking about the kind of thing some suppositum is. Talk of a nature, on this account, is thus talk about, roughly speaking, an abstract part. Nature, according to Aquinas, is what is susceptible of definition: thus, we can meaningfully talk of the intension of suchand-such a nature. The second thing included in the suppositum is its individuating feature. For Aquinas, the kind-nature of a material substance is individuated by matter-with-dimensions. The kind-nature of an immaterial substance is self-individuating. 9 • Persona aliud significat quam natura. Natura enim significat "essentiam speciei, quam significat definitio." . . . Contingit autem in quibusdam rebus subsistentibus inveniri aliquid quod non pertinet ad rationem speciei, scilicet accidentia et principia individuantia: sicut maxime apparel in his quae sunt ex materia et forma composita. Et ideo in talibus etiam secundum rem differt natura et suppositum, non quasi omnino separata: sed quia in supposito includitur ipsa natura speciei, et superadduntur quaedam alia quae sunt praeter rationem speciei. Unde suppositum significatur ut totum, habens naturam sicut partem formalem et perfectivam sui (STh III, q. 2, a. 2 [3:12b-13a]). Aquinas gives similar accounts in STh I, q. 3, a. 3 (1:16a-b); III Sent., d. 5, q. 1, a. 3, par. 57-62 (3:196-197); Quodl. IX, q. 2, a. 1 [2] (178b-180b); De Un. Verb. /near. 1 (2:421a425b). 9 On the question of individuation, see for example De Ente c. 2 (pp. 6-23); STh I, q. 50, a. 2 (1:253a-254b); STh I, q. 75, a. 7 (1:356a-357b). The clearest account of Aquinas on individuation is found in Anthony Kenny, Aquinas, Past Masters (Oxford: Oxford 176 RICHARD CROSS The third thing included in a suppositum is its accidents. Accidents are the features that a thing has contingently. Granted this description of accidents, and granted the account of Chalcedonian orthodoxy given above, we might expect Aquinas to argue that the human nature is an accident of the second person of the Trinity. But Aquinas would regard such an account as highly problematic. I shall return below to the question of why Aquinas rejects the view that the union could be accidental. In the passage just quoted, Aquinas does not claim that the various parts are parts of the suppositum, but rather that they are included in a suppositum. Nevertheless, Aquinas does not name any other parts; so we must conclude that the suppositum for him will not be anything over and above these parts. The unity of the suppositum is guaranteed just in virtue of the peculiar types of entity that its parts are. Its parts are not in themselves supposita; they are types of entity that will naturally unite with each other to produce just one suppositum. I think that a fairly clear and workable distinction between suppositum and nature emerges on this account. But it does not accord easily with Aquinas's account of the hypostatic union. The reason is that, according to Aquinas, human nature is necessarily individuated by matter-and matter, of course, cannot be an essential part of the immaterial divine suppositum. 10 Thus, as Aquinas realizes, he cannot use the account just given to explicate the mechanics of the hypostatic union. (2) Aquinas therefore presents a second account of the distinction between suppositum and nature: Not every individual in the genus of substance--even in rational nature-counts as a person, but only that which exists in itself, and not that which exists in some other more perfect thing. . . . Therefore, University Press, 1980), 43-45. For a fuller account, with bibliography, see Joseph Owens, "Thomas Aquinas," in Individuation in Scholasticism: The Later Middle Ages and the Counter-Reformation, 1150-1650, ed. Jorge J. E. Gracia, SUNY Series in Philosophy (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1994), 173-194. Owens importantly brings out senses in which both form and esse can be said to have a role in individuation. 10 STh I, q. 3, a. 2 (1 :15b). AQUINAS ON NATURE, HYPOSTASIS AND METAPHYSICS 177 although [Christ's] human nature is a certain individual in the genus of substance, it does not have proper personality, because it does not exist separately in itself, but rather in some more perfect thing-viz., the person of the Word. 11 In this passage a nature is a particular individuated substance. What distinguishes a suppositum from a nature is just a negative condition: that of failing to be assumed by some more perfect suppositum. 12 On this account, "nature" is used to refer to some entity which includes matter (i.e., the part of the entity responsible for individuation): it is thus a part of the nature which is responsible for individuation. u Presumably, then, for a non-assumed nature, the individual nature and its suppositum will be identical (a negation is not a thing which a non-assumed nature could have); whereas in the case of the hypostatic union, the individual nature will be a (non-essential) part of the suppositum. It will be something like a concrete part of a suppositum. I will assess the results of this second distinction in a moment. 11 Non quodlibet individuum in genere substantiae, etiam in rationali natura, habet rationem personae: sed solum illud quod per se existit, non autem illud quod existit in alio perfectiori. ... Licet igitur humana natura sit individuum quoddam in genere substantiae, quia tamen non per se separatim existit, sed in quoddam perfectiori, scilicet in persona Dei Verbi, consequens est quod non habeat personalitatem propriam (STh III, q. 2, a. 2, ad 3 [3:13b]). See also STh I, q. 29, a. 1, ad 2 (1:156a);similar accounts are given in I Sent., d. 25, q. 1, a. 1, ad 7 (1:605); III Sent., d. 5, q. 2, a. 1, ad 2, par. 76 (3:200); Quodl. IX, q. 2, a. 1 [2] (179b); De Un. Verb. !near. 2 (2:425b-428a). 12 I think we can be fairly sure that what distinguishes a suppositum from a nature in this account is just a negative condition: i.e., that Aquinas does not mean that some nature will be a suppositum only if it has some further entity added to it. My reason is that Aquinas always seems to speak of the non-assumption of some complete nature as a necessary and sufficient condition for its being a suppositum: see STh I, q. 29, a. 1, ad 2 (1:156a); STh I, q. 29, a. 2 (1:156a-157b); STh III, q. 2, a. 2, ad 2 and ad 3 (3:13b); STh III, q. 4, a. 2, ad 2 (3:33a). For a review of the debates on Thomas's view of the distinction between individuated nature and person, see 0. Schweizer, Person und Hypostatische Union bei Thomas van Aquin, Studia Friburgensia, N.F., 16 (Freiburg, Switzerland: Universitatsverlag, 1957), 6-10, 15-17, 23-53. Schweizer himself holds that what distinguishes person from individuated nature is just the negative condition of non-assumption (Schweizer, 114-17). 13 On the claim that the second person of the Trinity assumed an individuated human nature, see STh III, q. 4, a. 2, ad 1 (3:33a); STh III, q. 4, a. 4 (3:34a-34b); III, q. 6, a. 4 (3:44a-44b). 178 RICHARD CROSS Of course, the context makes it quite dear that the salient feature distinguishing these two accounts, as far as Aquinas is concerned, is that the two accounts serve two different purposes. The first distinction shows that the union of two natures, divine and human, if it is to be a union at all, must be a union in a suppositum-where a union in suppositum is contrasted with a union in nature. Aquinas considers three types of union in nature: (I) some artificial nature which is constituted by a layout of parts, where each part retains its own nature and numerical identity; (2) a mixture of two (or more) elements resulting in some third type of substance; (3) a union of two incomplete things which together constitute a whole of some particular type (e.g.: the union of soul and body in a human being). 14 Aquinas rejects all of these accounts as irrelevant to the incarnation. (I) This type of union is only accidental: and Church doctrine excludes an accidental union in Christ. Secondly, this type of union. does not result in a genuine unity at all. Thirdly, the resulting form is artificial, not natural: and thus it could not count as one nature in any case. (2) This type of union is impossible since the divine nature is totally immutable, and thus could not mix with a human nature to produce some composite type of thing. Secondly, if per impossibile the two could unite to produce some composite thing, this composite thing would count neither as human nor as divine: hence, we could not talk of a divine person being human-which is required for the incarnation. Thirdly, the two natures are too dissimilar for any such mixing to occur. One of them would be completely obliterated. (3) This type of union is not analogous to the incarnation, since both divine and human natures count as complete types: not incomplete parts of some further nature. Secondly, the divine and human natures cannot be constitutive, as quantitative parts, of some quantitative whole, since the divine nature is incorporeal. Neither could they constitute some whole as matter and form, since the divine nature cannot be the form of a body. Thirdly, on 14 STh III, q. 2, a. 1 (3:1 la-b). AQUINAS ON NATURE, HYPOSTASIS AND METAPHYSICS 179 this account the whole nature of which the divine and human natures are parts would also be some third type of nature-and Christ would be neither divine nor human, but some other type of thing. 15 In Summa Theologiae III, q. 2, a. 2, quoted above, Aquinas argues that any unmixed natures, if they are to be united to each other in any way at all, must be united in a suppositum, on the grounds that unmixed parts are necessarily parts of a suppositum. By "unmixed natures," I mean natures that are not united in any of the three .ways rejected in Summa Theologiae III, q. 2, a. 1. Roughly, we might claim that an unmixed nature is one that does not fall under the intension of any other nature. The second distinction between nature and suppositum, on the other hand, is supposed to explain why Christ's human nature fails to be a suppositum. And this is an issue just because, in the case of the hypostatic union, a human nature is individuated by a part of itself (and not by an essential part of its suppositum). I shall refer to a nature individuated by a part of itself as a self-individuated nature. It is here that the problem arises. The aim of the first distinction between "nature" and "suppositum" which Aquinas proposes is to show that Christ's human nature must be united to his divine nature in his suppositum. It does this by listing the kinds of parts that a suppositum can have. But, oddly, not included in this list is exactly the type of part that Christ's human nature turns out to be: i.e., a non-essential self-individuated naturewhich is some kind of concrete part. So we cannot conclude, on the basis of the discussion in Summa Theologiae III, q.2, a. 2, that it is possible for a self-individuated nature to be a part of a suppositum (as opposed to being the whole suppositum). In other words, we cannot show that a self-individuated nature can be part of a suppositum unless we can show how a self-individuated nature can be part of a suppositum. Furthermore, the account in Summa Theologiae III, q. 2, a. 2, seems to mean that a suppositum will standardly be identical with an individuated 15 STh III, q. 2, a. 1 (3:11a-b). 180 RICHARD CROSS nature. 16 In addition, then, to showing that a suppositum can have concrete parts, Aquinas will have to show how a concrete self-individuated nature can be such a concrete part of some suppositum. In fact, however, Aquinas elsewhere does attempt to show how an individuated nature could be part of a suppositum. He does this by means of an account in terms of the unity of Christ's esse. II. EssE, HYPOSTASIS, AND THE INCARNATION (1) In Summa Theologiae III, q. 2, a. 2, ad 3, Aquinas spells out his second account of the distinction between nature and suppositum by means of the example of a concrete part existing in a concrete whole-viz., in a suppositum. Aquinas argues as follows: The hand of Socrates, although it is a certain individual, is not however a person, because it does not exist in itself, but in some more perfect thing, viz., in its whole." He later uses this example to explain not only the distinction between nature and suppositum but also to explain how the human nature can be united in the divine suppositum. Roughly, Aquinas claims that the human nature is united in the suppositum rather as a concrete part exists in a whole suppositum. In the Summa Theologiae, Aquinas spells out his account in terms of his metaphysic of esse (i.e., being, or existence). He begins with a distinction between the esse that pertains to a suppositum and the esse that pertains to a nature: Esse pertains to hypostasis and to nature: to a hypostasis as to that which has esse; and to a nature as to that by which something has esse; for nature is signified through the mode of form, which is called a being from the fact that something exists by it. 1• 16 On this, see Alfred J. Freddoso, "Human Nature, Potency and the Incarnation," Faith and Philosophy 3 (1986): 46-48. 17 Manus Socratis, quamvis sit quoddam individuum, non est tamen persona: quia non per se existit, sed in quoddam perfectiori, scilicet in suo toto (STh III, q. 2, a. 2, ad 3 [3:13b]). '" Esse ... pertinet ad hypostasim et ad naturam: ad hypostasim quidem sicut ad id quod habet esse; ad naturam autem ad id quo aliquid habet esse; natura enim significatur per mod um formae, quae dicitur ens ex eo quod ea aliquid est (STh Ill, q. 17, a. 2 [3:11 lb]). AQUINAS ON NATURE, HYPOSTASIS AND METAPHYSICS 181 The point of this distinction is that only supposita may be said to exist. A nature exists just in so far as some suppositum instantiates it. Hence the nature is that in virtue of which the suppositum is of a particular kind. (This is another way, of course, of claiming that a nature is a formal part of a suppositum.) Peter Geach distinguishes three possible usages of the verb esse, "to be" (for convenience, Geach gives negative propositions): A. There is no such thing as Cerberus; Cerberus does not exist, is not real. B. There is no such thing as a dragon; dragons do not exist. C. Joseph is not and Simeon is not. 19 The first usage is of no concern to us in this context. The second and third of these two usages correspond to the distinction that Aquinas makes in Summa Theologiae III, q. 17, a. 2. Geach explains the differences between B propositions and C propositions as follows: [In B propositions, the term "dragon"] is not ... used as a name, as a subject of predication, but as a logical predicate .... The importance of B propositions is that the question whether there is a so-and-so, what Aquinas calls the question an est? has to be answered with an affirmative or negative B proposition. Aquinas realized the logical peculiarity of B propositions: that the B proposition "an F exists" does not attribute actuality to an F, but F -ness to something or other.' 0 In the case of C propositions, Geach suggests: It would be quite absurd to say that Jacob in uttering these words was not talking about Joseph and Simeon but about the use of their names. Of course he was talking about his sons; he was expressing a fear that something had happened to them, that they were dead. We here have a sense of "is" or "exists" that seems to me to be certainly a genuine predicate of individuals .... The fact that in ... B propositions the verb "exist" or "be" is not such a genuine predicate tells us nothing about C propositions. 21 19 Peter Geach, "Form and Existence," in Aquinas. A Collection of Critical Essays, ed. Anthony Kenny, Modern Studies in Philosophy (London and Melbourne: Macmillan, 1969), 43. 20 Geach, 44-45, with reference to STh I, q. 48, a. 2, ad 2 (1:245a). 21 Geach, 46-47. 182 RICHARD CROSS C propositions express what is going on when we attribute esse to a suppositum; B propositions express what is going on when we attribute esse to a nature. Since, however, something which exists will necessarily be a thing of some type, it will necessarily be the case that the esse attributed to a suppositum corresponds on a one-to-one basis with the esse attributed to an essential nature. Thus, we could say of some suppositum that it exists and that, necessarily, it is a thing of some identifiable kind (i.e., that, necessarily, it belongs to some natural kind). Aquinas refers to the esse attributed to a suppositum as "personal esse,'' "substantial esse," and "esse simpliciter." 22 It would be tempting to claim that, in the case of B propositions. which pick out the esse which a thing has in virtue of its essential nature, there are no real grounds for distinguishing B propositions from C propositions. This would mean, in terms of the discussion in Summa Theologiae III, q. 17, a. 2, that the esse of the suppositum and the esse of its essential nature are just one and the same: the suppositum exists just in virtue of its being a suppositum of a particular kind. On this account, we could simply dispense with C propositions altogether, at least as logically perspicuous ways of talking about things. But this is not quite how Aquinas construes the matter. He makes a distinction-for all beings except for God-between the esse (i.e., the esse expressed by C propositions) and nature. Geach puts the basic reason for the distinction as follows: If x is F and y is F, then in respect of F -ness x and y are so far alike; the F-ness of x will indeed be a different individualized form from the F ness of y, but they will be, as F-nesses, alike. But when x is and y also is, the esse of x and the esse of y are in general different as such. 23 22 For "substantial esse," see III Sent., d. 6, q. 2, a. 2, par. 81 (3:239). The remaining terms occur in all the accounts I discuss. 23 Geach, 49, with reference to STh I, q. 3, a. 5 (1:18b). The literature on the distinction between essence and esse is extensive. See the articles by J. Wippel, "Aquinas's Route to the Real Distinction: A Note on De Ente et Essentia, c. 4," The Thomist 43 (1979): 279-95, reprinted, together with a reply to criticisms by Joseph Owens, as "Essence and Existence in the De Ente, ch. 4,'' in John F. Wippel, Metaphysical Themes in Thomas Aquinas (Washington, D. C.: Catholic University of America), 107-32, and "Essence and Existence in other Writings,'' in Metaphysical Themes in Thomas Aquinas, 133-61, together with the works cited in the notes of these articles. The argument for the AQUINAS ON NATURE, HYPOSTASIS AND METAPHYSICS 183 Thus far, in Summa Theologiae III, q. 17, a. 2, Aquinas has examined the esse that the suppositum has in virtue of its formal part, together with the corresponding personal esse of the suppositum. In the rest of q. 17, a. 2, Aquinas spells out the esse that a suppositum will have in virtue of its other parts. He does not mention matter, because in his metaphysic matter does not contribute existence to the suppositum. Matter is wholly potential, and is actualized only in virtue of being united to some form. The other part of the suppositum mentioned in Summa Theologiae III, q. 2, a. 2, is its accidents. In q. 17, a. 2, Aquinas argues that a suppositum receives further esse in virtue of its accidental forms: If there is some form or nature which does not pertain to the personal esse of a subsisting hypostasis, that esse [viz., the esse which the suppositum has in virtue of its accidental forms] is not said to be of the person simply, but secundum quid [i.e., according to some form or another]: just as being white [esse album] is the esse of Socrates, not in so far as he is Socrates, but in so far as he is white. And nothing prevents this type of esse being multiplied in one hypostasis or person: there is one esse by which Socrates is white, and another by which he is musical. 24 The point is that a suppositum is all sorts of things in virtue of its accidental forms: Socrates, for example, is musical, and is white, in virtue of his accidental forms. One way of putting this is by claiming that Socrates instantiates these different accidental forms. Another way of putting this is by claiming that accidental esse can be multiplied in one suppositum. The type of esse at issue, of course, is that exemplified in Geach 's B propositions, real distinction between essence and esse in Aquinas which I gave above is labeled the "genus" argument by Wippel, following Leo Sweeney (see "Essence and Existence in other Writings," 134-39, where Wippel gives a complete list of the places in Aquinas's work where the argument can be found). For a discussion of Geach's way of putting the argument, see Anthony Kenny, The Heritage of Wisdom: Essays in the History of Philosophy (Oxford: Blackwell, 1987), 24-28. 24 Si aliqua forma vel natura est quae non pertineat ad esse personale hypostasis subsistentis, illud esse non dicitur esse illius personae simpliciter, sed secundum quid: sicut esse album est esse Socratis, non inquantum est Socrates, sed inquantum est albus. Et huiusmodi esse nihil prohibet multiplicari in una hypostasi vel persona: aliud enim est esse quo Socrates est albus, et quo Socrates est musicus (STh III, q. 17, a. 2 [3:111b)). 184 RICHARD CROSS where B propositions pick out the esse had by a thing in virtue of its accidents. Aquinas calls this esse "esse secundum quid": the (many) esses that a suppositum has in virtue of (secundum) its accidental forms. In the hypostatic union, however, the human nature is not an accident of the Word. It is worth exploring a bit more deeply why Aquinas rejects the view that the human nature could be an accident of the divine person. Basically, his account of the relation between substance and accident means that it is impossible for the divine person to be the subject of any accidental forms. He argues for this in three ways. (1) On a standard Aristotelian account of the relation between substance and accident, we can claim that the accident actualizes some potentiality in the substance: for some substance x and some accidental form F, x is F if and only if F -ness actualizes x 's potentiality to be F. But on the standard Thomist account of God, God is pure act, not admixed with any potentiality. Hence God cannot have any potentiality to be F, and thus cannot be a subject of accidents. (2) God's essence is just to exist (esse), and according to Boethius 25 nothing can be added to what is just esse. Hence accidents cannot be added to God. (3) Substance is logically prior to accident. But God is logically prior to everything. Hence, he cannot include accidents. 26 Clearly, there is no reason for us to accept these arguments. If we reject either Aquinas's account of the relation between substance and accident, or his account of the divine nature, or both, then we might be able to provide a coherent account of the hypostatic union by arguing that the human nature is something like a non-essential property of the divine person. But my interest here is simply with the internal coherence of Aquinas's strictly christological arguments: hence I would regard arguments (1) to (3) as sufficient to block the possibility of Aquinas's giving an account of Christ's human nature as an accidental property of the second person of the Trinity. Hence, I would regard them as 25 Boethius, Quomodo Substantiae [De Hebdomadibus], in The Theological Tractates: The Consolation of Philosophy, ed. H. F. Stewart, E. K. Rand, and S. J. Tester, Loeb Classical Library, 74 (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press; London: Heinemann, 1978), 40. 26 STh I, q. 3, a. 6 (1:19a). AQUINAS ON NATURE, HYPOSTASIS AND METAPHYSICS 185 sufficient to rule out, for Aquinas, the possibility of the second person of the Trinity receiving accidental esse from his human nature. Oddly, in his discussion of the hypostatic union, Aquinas does not develop his rejection of the multiplication of accidental esse in just this way. The reasons for this are partly historical. In his Sentences, Peter Lombard posited three possible accounts of the hypostatic union. According to one of these, the human nature is united to the second person of the Trinity by being the vesture (habitus) of that person. 21 This account aims to avoid the possibility that the divine person could be a human being essentially. Aquinas labels the union posited in this account "accidental." 28 As Aquinas reads this account, it is just a version of the Nestorian heresy, according to which the incarnation is to be understood as the divine person dwelling in a human person. Hence, Aquinas reasons, we must reject the opinion that the union between the second person of the Trinity and his human nature is accidental. And it is for just this reason that he disallows talk of new accidental esse in the divine person in the discussion in Summa Theologiae III, q. 17, a. 2. But we might guess also that Aquinas would reject the accidental union view on the grounds that the only possible category into which the human nature could fit would indeed be that of vesture: we could see this simply by running through the remaining eight accidental categories and noting their unsuitability. (I leave this task for the reader: I think it is quite clear, for example, that the human nature could count as neither a quality nor quantity of the second person of the Trinity.) Granted that the accidental categories are exhaustive of the types of accidental predicates that can be attributed to subjects, then it will follow that, if the human nature is an accident of the second person of the Trinity, it will be the vesture of the second person of the Trinity. And I think that we could fairly claim that this would indeed be a version of the Nestorian heresy. The union between 27 Peter Lombard, Sentences 3.6.4, nn. 1-3, Spicilegium Bonaventurianum, 4-5, 3rd ed. (Grottaferrata: Editiones Collegii S. Bonaventurae ad Claras Aquas, 1971-81), 2:55. 2 • STh III, q. 2, a. 6 (3:18a). 186 RICHARD CROSS a person and his vesture is a fairly loose kind of union: not at all the sort of thing that the Fathers of Chalcedon had in mind. If the human nature is not an accident of the Word, Aquinas reasons that the Word cannot receive any further esse secundum quid from the human nature. What about the personal esse of the suppositum corresponding to the esse which it receives from its essential nature? In Summa Theologiae III, q. 17, a. 2, Aquinas claims that, necessarily, one suppositum can have only one personal esse. And he clearly supposes that, in the hypostatic union, the divine suppositum receives no esse from the human nature. 29 Aquinas's reason is that the only natures which can give esse to supposita are essential natures or accidental natures. But it makes no sense to speak of a thing having more than one essential nature; and Aquinas will not allow that the human nature is an accident. So: the divine person receives neither esse simpliciter nor esse secundum quid from the human nature. In fact, part of Aquinas's talk about esse is just another way of claiming that certain predicates can be attributed to some subject. So Aquinas's discussion of Christ's esse thus far amounts to the rejection of the two following claims: (I) the human nature is the essential kind-nature of the second person of the Trinity; (2) the human nature is an accident of the second person of the Trinity. I think it is perfectly clear that (1) would not make any sense at all, and certainly could not count as an explanation of the hypostatic union. And I have tried to indicate the grounds upon which Aquinas would reject (2). Clearly, since Aquinas is committed to the endeavor of remaining faithful to Chalcedonian orthodoxy, he will have to propose a third way in which a suppositum can instantiate a nature. He does this by analyzing his conception of personal esse a bit more closely. This esse is the esse which corresponds on a one-to-one basis with the esse that the suppositum has in virtue of its essential nature. This personal esse is analyzable as the esse of the concrete parts of the suppositum. For example, Aquinas 29 STh III, q. 17, a. 2 (3:lllb-112a). AQUINAS ON NATURE, HYPOSTASIS AND METAPHYSICS 187 talks of the esse of heads, bodies, and souls, as parts of a (human) suppositum, such that they together compose just one personal esse: Having a head [esse capitatum], being bodily [esse corporeum] and being animate [esse animatum]all pertain to the one person of Socrates; and therefore from all of these there is made just one esse in Socrates.Jo Aquinas uses the analogy of a suppositum and its concrete parts to spell out the metaphysics of the incarnation. The concrete parts that Aquinas mentions in this context are a person's hands, feet, and eyes. Socrates's hand, for example, will be a concrete part of the suppositum Socrates. This is what Aquinas means when he claims that the parts pertain to a person's one esse; or that they are parts of a person. Aquinas goes on to argue in a way which makes it clear that a concrete part like a hand can be individuated independently of the suppositum of which it is a part: If it should happen that, after the constitution of the person of Socrates, there should come to Socrates hands, or feet, or eyes (as happens in someone born blind), there would not from these accrue to Socrates another esse, but only a relation to this sort of thing, since he would be said to be [esse] not only in virtue of those things which he already had, but also according to those things which came to him later.J1 On this account, we could claim that Socrates has a hand-or predicate "is-handed" of him-not in virtue of any new esse attributed to the suppositum, but simply in virtue of a new relation between the suppositum and some concrete part. Aquinas labels the type of unity spoken of in this passage "personal unity"; and he expressly contrasts it with accidental unity. In an accidental unity-unlike a personal unity-we can talk of Jo Esse ... capitatum, et esse corporeum, et esse animatum, totum pertinet ad unam personam Socratis: et ideo ex omnibus his non fit nisi unum esse in Socrate (STh III, q. 17, a. 2 [3:112a]). JI Si contingeret quod, post constitutionem personae Socratis, advenirent Socrati manus vel pedes vel oculi, sicut accidit in caeco nato, ex his non accresceret Socrati aliud esse, sed solum relatio quaedam ad huiusmodi: quia scilicet diceretur esse non solum secundum ea quae prius habebat, sed etiam secundum ea quae postmodum sibi adveniunt (STh III, q. 17, a. 2 [3:112a]). 188 RICHARD CROSS as many additional esses as there are additional accidental forms. This contrast makes it look as if Aquinas would hold that, when we predicate "is-handed" of Socrates, we are in effect just predicating of Socrates one of his essential parts. Thus, we would not be ascribing to Socrates any further nature or property not included in his kind-nature. This is presumably what Aquinas means when he claims that Socrates receives no new esse when his previously lacking hand is grafted onto him. 32 It is worth pausing here to tighten the account up a bit. A hand, after all, is very different from a head: a head is certainly essential for being human, but I am not at all sure that I should want to say that a hand is. And Aquinas seems to deny that a hand is an essential part of a suppositum when he claims-in the last-quoted passage-that the suppositum is complete even without the hand. As he puts it, the suppositum has (all?) its constituent parts prior to the missing hand's being grafted on. In fact, the evidence here is fairly ambiguous: and it is not impossible that Aquinas changes his mind. In the ninth Quodlibet (Easter 1258, and therefore fourteen years earlier than the third part of the Summa Theologiae), 33 Aquinas is quite clear that a hand falls under the intension of human nature. He expressly refers to hands, feet, and bones as parts of human nature. 34 He also claims that hands are concrete parts of a suppositum: Parts of substances, even though they belong to the nature of subsistent things, do not themselves subsist, however, but exist in another. Whence the above-mentioned terms [viz., "hypostasis,""person," "sup32 Aquinas is not denying that the nature of such a concrete part has the kind of esse that is properly attributed to a nature: i.e., the esse in virtue of which some suppositum is F: "All those things which do not subsist in themselves, but in another and with another-whether they are accidents or substantial forms or any kind of part---do not have esse such that they themselves are. But esse is attributed to them in another way, i.e., as that by which something is" (Omnia vero quae non per se subsistunt, sed in alio et cum alio, sive sint accidentia sive formae substantiales aut quaelibet partes, non habent esse ita ut ipsa vere sint, sed attribuitur eis esse alio modo, idest ut quo aliquid est) (Quodl. IX, q. 2, a. 2 [3] (181a); affirmed also in STh III, q. 17, a. 2 [3:111b]). 33 See James A. Weisheipl, Friar Thomas d'Aquino: His Life, Thought, and Works (Oxford: Blackwell, 197 5), 36 7. 34 Quodl. IX, q. 2, a. 1 [2] (179b). AQUINAS ON NATURE, HYPOSTASIS AND METAPHYSICS 189 positum," "thing of a nature"] are not said of the parts of substances: for we do not say that this hand is a hypostasis, or a person, or a suppositum, or a thing of a nature.Js I think that it is fairly clear that "substance," in the first sentence, is being used to refer to a subsistent thing-viz., a suppositumand that Aquinas's claim is that a hand is a (concrete) part of that suppositum. Now, Aquinas does not think here that a hand is an accidental part of a human suppositum. Rather, as just noted, he refers to hands as parts of human nature: and thus, presumably, the explanation of why a concrete thing like a hand is part of a suppositum is that it is part of the intension of that suppositum's kind-nature. On the other hand, as I have just noted, Aquinas seems to hold in the Summa Theologiae that a human suppositum is complete without a hand: and this would prima facie be evidence that he now rejects the assertion that a hand can count as a part of human nature. The claim that having a hand is not essential to a human suppositum is just the same as the claim that having a hand is not part of the intension of human nature. As we shall see, the claim that a hand is not part of the intension of human nature raises some problems. Particularly, Aquinas consistently denies that a concrete part like a hand is an accident of anything; but, on the other hand, he also denies that it is essential to a human being. In his metaphysic, there is a further possible class into which attributes can fall: it could be a property following necessarily from the essential principles of its subject. This refers to attributes which we would probably label "essential": the kind of attribute that a thing of such-and-such a type cannot fail to have. 36 For Aquinas, however, they do not count as essential since they are not defining properties: parts of the definition of a thing. And since Aquinas, like Aristotle, identifies "nature" or "essence" with "definition," it follows ex hypothesi that nonJs Partes vero substantiarum quamvis sint de natura subsistentium, non tamen per se subsistunt, sed in alio sunt. Unde etiam praedicta nomina de partibus substantiarum non dicuntur: non enim dicimus quod haec manus sit hypostasis vel persona, vel suppositum, vel res naturae (Quodl. IX, q. 2, a. 1 [2] [179b]). 36 See, e.g., STh I, q. 3, a. 4 (1:17a) 190 RICHARD CROSS defining but necessary properties are not essential properties (in this sense). This is not much help in trying to sort out the status of a hand for Aquinas. Necessary but non-essential attributes are the kind of attributes which a thing cannot be without: and so they cannot be much like hands, which (according to Aquinas's later account) a thing can be without. On the other hand, if having a hand does not fall under the intension of human nature, it is difficult to'see why the advent of a handfails to give some new esse to the suppositum. Aquinas uses the analogy of a concrete whole and some of its concrete parts to explain the metaphysics of the incarnation. I shall argue that much the same problem dogs the accounts Aquinas gives of the hypostatic union (with the exception of his account in De Unione Verbi Incarnati, which I consider below) as is troublesome for his discussion of the unity of a concrete whole. The unity of a concrete whole (whatsoever that might entail) is called personal unity; and personal unity gives us a further model for construing part-whole relations such that the relevant whole is the suppositum, i.e., it gives us a further type of relation between a suppositum and its parts. Furthermore, the relation is one of concrete whole (suppositum) to concrete partwhich is just the type of relation that Aquinas requires for his understanding of the hypostatic union. Granted this, it is perhaps no surprise to learn that Aquinas uses this concrete wholeconcrete part model as an analog for the how of the hypostatic union: Since the human nature is united to the Son of God hypostatically or personally ... and not accidentally, it follows that no new personal esse comes to him in virtue of the human nature, but only a new relation of the preexisting personal esse to the human nature, such that the person can now be said to subsist not only according to the divine nature but also according to the human."' 37 Cum humana natura coniungatur Filio Dei hypostatice vel personaliter ... et non accidentaliter, consequens est quod secundum humanam naturam non adveniat sibi novum esse personale, sed solum nova habitudo esse personalis praeexistentis ad naturam humanum: ut scilicet persona iam dicatur subsistere, non solum secundum naturam divinam, sed etiam humanam (STh III, q. 17, a. 2 [3:112a])· AQUINAS ON NATURE, HYPOSTASIS AND METAPHYSICS 191 Some of the limitations of Aquinas's account can be made fairly clear. I argued above that, if having a hand does not fall under the intension of human nature, it is difficult to see why the advent of a handfails to give some new esse to the suppositum. And this is the same as claiming that, if the hand fails to give new esse to the suppositum, then having a hand will be an essential attribute of the suppositum. (Aquinas wants to deny-at least in the Summa Theologiae-both that the hand gives new esse to the suppositum and that having a hand is an essential attribute of a human suppositum.) Analogously, it seems difficult to see both that the assumed human nature fails to give new esse to the second person of the Trinity and that the assumed human nature fails to be an essential attribute of the divine person. In fact, just as Aquinas is unclear about the essential or nonessential status of a human hand, so too he is equivocal about the essential or non-essential status of the assumed human nature vis-a-vis the second person of the Trinity. Although Aquinas is always clear that he wants to reject a union of divine and human into one nature (i.e., some third type of thing), he sometimes uses language which suggests that his understanding of the hypostatic union fails to keep the two natures sufficiently distinct. For example, in the Sentences commentary (1252-56)38 Aquinas claims that the divine and human natures are constitutive parts--or at least very like constitutive parts--of the second person of the Trinity. 39 In the same article, Aquinas uses the example of the advent of a hand to a human being as an explanation of how the incarnation took place. 40 Similarly, in the ninth Quodlibet, Aquinas argues that the divine and human natures in Christ are integral parts of the suppositum. 41 On Aquinas's standard account of integral parts, an integral part is a concrete constitutive part, 42 though he occaFor this date, see Weisheipl, 358-59. III Sent., d. 6, q. 2, a. 2, par. 82 (3:239). 40 III Sent., d. 6, q. 2, a. 2, ad 1, par. 84 (3:239); note that here Aquinas is silent about the claim that a human person lacking a hand is a complete human being-a claim which, as we have seen, he makes explicit in the Summa Theologiae. 41 Quodl. IX, q. 2, a. 2 (3] (181a). 42 See, e.g., III Sent., d 33, q. 3, a. 1, sol. 1, par. 268 (3:1073). 38 39 192 RICHARD CROSS sionally distinguishes two senses of integral part: (1) concrete constitutive parts; (2) parts of the kind-nature of the whole. 43 The relevant contrast which Aquinas makes in the Quodlibet is between integral parts and accidental parts; and it is clear from his account of integral parts that he construes such parts standardly as essential parts of a suppositum. If integral parts are concrete, non-accidental parts, Aquinas's claim that the divine and human natures in Christ are integral parts of the suppositum· will amount to the claim that some entity will count as a concrete part of a suppositum if and only if, considered abstractly, that part is a part of the intension of the kind-nature of the suppositum. Applied to the hypostatic union, this would be a version of the monophysite heresy. On the other hand, much of what Aquinas says in both the Sentences commentary and in the Quodlibet is inconsistent with the position I have just outlined. For example, even though Aquinas defends the claim in the Sentences commentary that the divine and human natures are constitutive parts of the divine suppositum, he carefully rejects the claim that the divine suppositum is in any sense composed by the conjunction of concrete parts. 44 Furthermore, in the Quodlibet Aquinas argues that the human nature is not a constitutive part of the divine suppositum (thus rejecting the claim he made in the Sentences commentary).45In the Quodlibet, Aquinas also claims that the divine suppositum is complete prior to the assumption of the human nature. 46 This is contrary to the claim that the human nature is an integral part of the suppositum-at least as I have understood this claim. In the Sentences commentary, Aquinas carefully rejects the monophysite claim that the incarnation could be a union in (one) nature, using much the same arguments as those I outlined above from the Summa Theologiae.41 In the Summa Theologiae, Aquinas's account of unity in See, e.g., IV Sent., d. 16, q. 1, a. 1, sol. 3, par. 41 (4:774-75). III Sent., d 6, q. 2, a. 3, par. 95 (3:241-42). 45 Quodl. IX, q. 2, a. 1 [2] ad 1 and ad 2 (180a-b). 46 Quodl. IX, q. 2, a. 1 [2] ad 1 (180a). 47 III Sent., d. 5, q. 1, a. 2, par. 41-51 (3:191-94). 43 44 AQUINAS ON NATURE, HYPOSTASIS AND METAPHYSICS 193 Christ-in terms of Christ's one esse-avoids most of the difficulties and ambiguities found in the one-esse accounts of both the Sentences commentary and the Quodlibet. But it does so at a price. The one-esse account defended in the Summa Theologiae has lost all three of the possible conceptual underpinnings found variously in the Sentences account and the Quodlibet account, and discussed above: (1) that a hand is an essential part of a human suppositum, and that Christ's human nature is analogous to a hand; (2) that a person without a hand is incomplete, and that the second person of the 'Irinity without his human nature is like a person without a hand; (3) that the human nature in Christ is an integral part of the divine suppositum. Any one of these claims would be sufficient, of course, to commit Aquinas either to a version of the monophysite heresy, or-granted elsewhere a clear rejection of this heresy-to some degree of incoherence. So Aquinas has good reason to drop them. The one-esse account in the Summa Theologiae is an attenuated version of the earlier positions, clearly aiming to avoid some of the monophysite tendencies of the earlier versions. Despite Aquinas's commitment, in the Summa Theologiae, to the claims that having a hand is not part of the intension of human nature, and that a human person lacking a hand will still count as a complete person, Aquinas still regards the advent of a hand to a human person who previously lacked a hand as a good one for the hypostatic union. And there are some obvious reasons for this. As Aquinas understands hands in the Summa Theologiae, a hand is a non-essential concrete part of a human person. The account thus far enables us to formulate three theses about the relation between a concrete whole and its nonessential concrete parts which will explain why the analogy of a non-essential concrete part is a good one for the hypostatic union. (1) A non-essential concrete part can be (is?) individuated independently of its suppositum. (2) A concrete whole subsists with respect to (i.e., having a relation to) its concrete parts. (3) A concrete whole does not receive any additional esse from its concrete parts. 194 RICHARD CROSS And the relation between the assumed human nature and the second person of the Trinity is in all significant respects just like this. The problem, for the Summa Theologiae account, is in justifying the second and third theses about the relation between a concrete whole and some non-essential (viz., non-necessary) concrete part: i.e., how can we justify the claims that a concrete whole subsists as having a relation to some non-necessary concrete part, and that a concrete whole does not receive any new esse from a non-necessary concrete part? In the Summa Theologiae account, it is here that Aquinas's account encounters difficulties in the metaphysics involved, which difficulties seem to produce some degree of philosophical incoherence. If a concrete part is non-necessary (viz., accidental), then Aquinas ought to allow that it contributes esse to the concrete whole (the suppositum) of which it is a part. This is a problem for the Summa Theologiae account in a way in which it is not a problem for the accounts of the Sentences commentary and the ninth Quodlibet. In these latter two accounts, Aquinas implies that a hand is an essential part. His problem in these two accounts, then, is in justifying the claim that the example of an essential concrete part is a good one for the hypostatic union, since it looks as if, according to Aquinas, some concrete part fails to contribute esse to its suppositum just if the concrete part is an essential part of its suppositum. In fact, in Summa Theologiae III, q. 2, a. 6, ad 2, Aquinas suggests a new image to underpin his account of a concrete nonessential part and its concrete whole-and thereby to underpin his one-esse account of the hypostatic union. He argues as follows: That which comes after complete esse comes accidentally, unless it is brought into communion with that complete esse.4" This image of "communion in shall call it "sharing in esse"-does not occur in the earlier accounts, and clearly repre48 Illud quod advenit post esse completum, accidentaliter advenit, nisi trahatur in communionem illius esse completi (STh III, q. 2, a. 6, ad 2 [3:19a]) AQUINAS ON NATURE, HYPOSTASIS AND METAPHYSICS 195 sents Aquinas's attempt to clarify his account in a way which will avoid both monophysitism and a merely accidental union. We can now add a fourth thesis to the description of the relation between a concrete non-essential part and its concrete whole: (4) A concrete non-essential part shares in the personal esse of its sup- positum. This fourth thesis looks as though it will explain the problematic second and third theses-and I take it that it is certainly consistent with them. (Thus, I take it that the account in Summa Theologiae III, q. 2, a. 6, ad 2, is consistent with that in q. 17, a. 2.) But this thesis cannot in fact do very much properly explanatory work. Aquinas does not spell out what exactly "sharing in esse" might mean. The term "communio"-which I have translated as "sharing"-does not have a technical sense in Aquinas's writings. In his discussions of christology, Aquinas uses the word in two other senses: (1) the three divine persons have communion in one nature; 49 (2) each of the two natures in Christ acts with the communion of the other. 50 Neither of these has much in common with the use of the term in the phrase "sharing in esse." Since in the above quotation Aquinas contrasts the type of parts which qualify for sharing in the esse of a suppositum with accidental parts, we might imagine that the kind of parts that qualify for sharing in the esse of a suppositum are essential parts. But Aquinas clearly wants some non-essential parts to share in the personal esse of the suppositum too. Effectively, an old problem reappears in a new guise: just why do some non-essential parts share in personal esse, while others (e.g., predicamental accidents) do not? More specifically, Aquinas fails to spell out what he means by claiming that some non-essential parts--e.g., hands-fail to be accidents. STh III, q. 3, a. 6 (3:28b). STh III, q. 19, a. 1, ad 5 (3:12lb). Here are some of the non-christological ways in which Aquinas uses the term: (1) "communio politica" (i.e., political association): see STh I-II, q. 90, a. 2 (1:41lb); (2) the "communion" of household life: see STh I-II, q. 105, a. 4 (1:510b); (3) the ban on "communion" (i.e., any form of contact) between Christian and non-Christian: see STh II-II, q. 10, a. 9 (2:59b-60a); (4) communion in the eucharist (as in modern English usage): see STh III, q. 80, a. 6 (3:494b). 49 50 196 RICHARD CROSS In Summa Theologiae III, q. 2, a. 6, ad 2, Aquinas spells out what types of entities can share esse by means of another example. At the resurrection of the body, the soul reassumes its body. The body begins to share in the esse of the soul: it does not give any new esse to the soul. The reason is that the body is animated (has "vital esse") from the soul.51 This example clearly avoids some of the problems of the hand analogy. But if the body/soul analogy is taken seriously, it makes the case in favor of Aquinas's monophysitism look rather strong. Body and soul are two constituent parts of a human person, 52 and they are a human person's essential parts. 53 If, on the other hand, the union of body and soul is not to be taken as an analogy for the hypostatic union,54 then the use of the body/soul union as an example of sharing in esse does not help us understand at all how Christ's human nature can share in the esse of the divine suppositum. It looks as though the claim that some individual shares in the esse of another, or (equivalently) that one individual communicates its esse to another, is not a claim whose meaning is transparent. I have attempted to show that the elucidations that we can attempt all turn out to have unorthodox consequences. If we grant the four theses proposed for the nature of the union between a concrete part and its concrete whole, we can summarize the account of the relation between the human nature and the divine suppositum in the Summa Theologiae as follows: (1 ') The assumed human nature is individuated independently of its suppositum (viz., the divine suppositum). (2 ') The divine suppositum subsists in relation to its concrete human nature. STh III, q. 2, a. 6, ad 2 (3:19a-b). STh III, q. 2, a. 5, obj. 2 and ad 2 (3:16a-b). 53 STh I, q. 75, a. 4 (1:353b). 54 As, according to STh III, q. 2, a. 1, it should not be: the union of body and soul is here taken as paradigmatic of the third type of union in nature (viz., the union of two imperfect things into one complete and perfect thing [3:11b])-a type of union which would, as Aquinas realizes, have monophysite consequences. 51 52 AQUINAS ON NATURE, HYPOSTASIS AND METAPHYSICS 197 (3 ')The divine suppositum does not receive any additional esse from its concrete human nature. (4 ')The concrete human nature shares in the personal esse of the divine suppositum. ss Theses (4) and (4') yield a third way in which a suppositum can instantiate a nature; and Geach 's B propositions will be true just if they correspond to one of these ways. Here is the complete list of the ways in which a suppositum can instantiate a nature: (i) A suppositum can instantiate its essential nature (i.e., its essential kind-nature). (ii) A suppositum can instantiate some accidental nature (i.e., a property or non-essential attribute). (iii) A suppositum can instantiate some nature which, as individuated, shares in the personal esse of the suppositum. (In the earlier Sentences commentary and Quodlibet accounts, Aquinas affirms merely the narrower claim, [iii'] A suppositum can instantiate some essential part of its essential nature [i.e., some part of the intension of its essential nature], in place of [iii].) The position which Aquinas defends in the Summa Theologiae is very difficult to understand. Affirming (4) and (iii) in place of (iii') weakens the charge of monophysitism: but it also lessens any possible explanatory value of Aquinas's analogy. As I have indicated, we would expect the concrete whole-concrete part analogy to rely on the fact that a concrete part is essential to its concrete whole and hence on the fact that a suppositum can instantiate some essential property of its essential nature. On this model, the concrete essential part shares in the personal esse of the suppositum just if its essence is also a part of the intension of an essential kind-nature. And this would only be the case, of course, if the human nature and the divine nature were in some sense parts of the intension of some third type of nature: i.e., if the union of divine and human in Jesus were in fact a union in ss The accounts in the Sentences commentary and in the Quodlibet include (l ') to (3 '), but not (4'). 198 RICHARD CROSS nature. And this would be a version of the monophysite heresy, which Aquinas in all three accounts elsewhere rejects, for reasons given above. 56 III. EssE, HYPOSTASIS, AND THE INCARNATION (2) Spelling out just what the nature of the hypostatic union is clearly caused Aquinas even more trouble than I have suggested thus far. About the same time as he was writing the opening few questions of the third part of the Summa Theologiae-though before he had reached question seventeen-Aquinas proposed a totally different solution. In the disputed question De Unione Verbi Incarnati 51 he denies that the best analogy for the hypostatic union is that of a concrete part and its whole: The human nature in Christ ... exists in another, i.e., the hypostasis of the Word: not like an accident in a subject, or properly like a part in a whole, but by an ineffable assumption. 58 56 Interestingly, Duns Scotus found just this problem in Aquinas's account as well. Scotus rejected Aquinas's concrete whole-concrete part analogy on the grounds that, in the relevant sense, the human nature fails to be a part of the divine suppositum: the human nature does not fall under the intension of the essential nature of the suppositum: "A part coming to a whole does not give esse to the whole, but rather receives [esse], since it is perfected by the form of the whole .... But the human nature united to the Word is not informed by the Word, but remains simply distinct [from the Word]" (Pars adveniens toti, non dat esse toti, sed recipit, quia perficitur a forma totius .... sed natura humana unita Verbo non informatur a Verbo, sed manet simpliciter distincta) (Duns Scotus, Ordinatio 3.6.1 [Assisi: Biblioteca Communale], MS 13 7, fol. 14 7vb]; see Opera Omnia, Wadding-Vives edition [Paris: Vives, 1891-95, 14:310a). "The existence of a foot is not different from the existence by which I exist. It is rather only some partial existence in that by which I exist. But the opposite holds here [i.e., in the union of the Word and the his assumed nature]" (Existentia pedis non est alia ab ilia qua existo; sed tantum est aliqua existentia partialis in ilia qua existo. Sed oppositum est hie) (Ordinatio 3.6.1, MS 137, fol. 147vb; see Wadding-Vives edition, 14:310b-311a). It is perhaps not surprising that for Scotus the closest analogy for the hypostatic union is that of the relation between an accident and its subject (Ordinatio 3.1.1, n. 3, MS 137, fol. 139v; see Wadding-Vives edition, 14:9a). 57 The date of this disputed question is spring 1272. Aquinas left Paris shortly after 25 April, 1272, and, according to Weisheipl, Aquinas could have completed no more than "the first two or three questions of the tertia pars before leaving Paris" (Weisheipl, 307). 58 Humana natura in Christo ... existit in alio id est in hypostasi Verbi Dei (non quidem sicut accidens in subiecto, neque proprie sicut pars in toto, sed per ineffabilem assumptionem) (De Un. Verb. /near. 2 [2:427b]). AQUINAS ON NATURE, HYPOSTASIS AND METAPHYSICS 199 As this quotation might suggest, the De Unione account is rather more agnostic than Aquinas's other accounts. Having rejected the concrete part analogy, Aquinas does not replace it with any further explanation. There is, however, an important consequence of the rejection of the concrete part analogy, of which Aquinas is cognizant. If it is not the case that the concrete whole-concrete part union is a good analogy for the hypostatic union, then a one-esse account cannot be used to explain Christ's unity-or if it is used, it will have to be given a rather different explanation from that offered in the Sentences commentary, the Quodlibet, and the Summa Theologiae. In fact, in De Unione Aquinas drops the one-esse account of Christ's unity. 59 Most of Aquinas's strictly metaphysical presuppositions are shared among the various accounts. Thus, Aquinas still holds that a suppositum is what properly speaking has esse, and that natures-essential and accidental-have esse just in the sense that some suppositum instantiates them. But he now argues that, since the divine suppositum instantiates human nature, it must be the case that the divine person receives some esse from the human nature. This esse is not accidental: but neither is it the esse simpliciter of the suppositum. Christ ... has one esse simpliciter in virtue of the one eternal esse of the eternal suppositum. But there is also another esse of this suppositum, not in so far as he is eternal, but in so far as he is made man temporal- 59 For other discussions of Aquinas's accounts of the esse to be attributed to Christ, see: Franz Pelster, "La Quaestio Disputata de Saint Thomas 'De Unione Verbi Incarnati,'" Archives de Philosophie 3 (1926): 342-89; Paul Bayerschmidt, Die Seinsund Formmetaphysik des Heinrich von Gent, Beitrage zur Geschichte der Philosophie und Theologie des Mittelalters, 36/3-4 (Miinster-in-W.: Aschendorff, 1941), 43-67; H. M. Diepen, "L'existence humaine du Christ," Revue Thomiste 58 (1958): 197-213; A. Patfoort, L'unite d'etre dans le Christ d'apres s. Thomas (Tournai: Desclee, 1964); Etienne Gilson, "L'esse du Verbe incarne selon saint Thomas d'Aquin," Archives d'Histoire Doctrinale et Litteraire du Moyen Age 35 (1968): 23-37; Weisheipl, 307-13; Francis Ruello, La Christologie de Thomas d'Aquin, Theologie historique, 76 (Paris: Beauchesne, 1987), 115-19, 317-20, 352-55, 391; Edouard-Henri Weber, Le Christ selon saint Thomas d'Aquin, Collection "Jesus et Jesus Christ," 35 (Paris: Desclee, 1988), 229235. 200 RICHARD CROSS ly. This esse-even if it is not accidental esse (since "man" is not predicated accidentally of the Son of God ... )-is not however the principal esse of its suppositum, but secondary [esse].60 Here, Aquinas has dropped the claim that the human nature does not contribute esse to the suppositum: and the reason for this is presumably that he no longer admits the relevance of the concrete whole-concrete part analogy, which is sufficient to explain why the human nature-which is united to the divine suppositum-fails to contribute esse to the divine suppositum. The esse which, according to the De Unione account, the human nature contributes to the suppositum is labeled "secondary esse": it is the secondary esse of the suppositum, and is contrasted with the principal esse of the suppositum, which the suppositum has in virtue of its essential nature. By way of observation on this account, I have two offerings. (1) The account has no explanatory value (unlike the one-esse account in the Sentences commentary and the Quodlibet, and to an extent in the Summa Theologiae as well). It offers no explanation of how a concrete nature, individuated separately from its suppositum, can be united to the suppositum, and serves merely to reiterate the claim that the human nature is united to the suppositum in some way or another-Le., that the suppositum is human, albeit as the result of some unspecified type of union. (2) On the other hand, by remaining fairly agnostic, it clearly avoids the undesirable consequence of the one-esse account: i.e., either monophysitism or a tendency towards incoherence. For this reason, it is a preferable account. It does not violate Aquinas's basic methodological claim that good metaphysics will be wholly consistent with the Christian faith: and it achieves this by frank acknowledgment that the doctrine of the hypostatic union exceeds the possibilities of any philosophical explanation. 6° Christus ... habet unum esse simpliciter propter unum esse aeternum aeterni suppositi. Est autem et aliud esse huius suppositi, non in quantum est aeternum, sed in quantum est temporaliter homo factum. Quod esse, etsi non sit esse accidentale--quia homo non praedicatur accidentaliter de Filio Dei ... -non tamen est esse principale sui suppositi, sed secundarium (De Un. Verb. /near. 4 [2:432b]). AQUINAS ON NATURE, HYPOSTASIS AND METAPHYSICS 201 If Weisheipl is right about the relative dates of the Summa Theologiae and De Unione (see note 5 7 above), Aquinas will have been committed to two quite different accounts of the incarnation in the spring of 1272: one found in De Unione, and the other in Summa Theologiae III, q. 2, a. 6, ad 2. And I have argued that this latter account is consistent with the slightly later account in Summa Theologiae III, q. 17, a. 2. So his flirtation with the De Unione account must have been remarkably brief: perhaps its non-explanatory nature did not appeal. (As we might expect, Aquinas's last account, a brief summary in the Compendium Theologiae, adopts a fairly attenuated one-esse account.) 61 IV. CONCLUSION Perhaps the most striking philosophical lesson to be learnt from all this is that Aristotle's list of accidental categories is by no means a complete list: there are (all sorts of) other non-essential properties which could be added to the list. And human 61 As Christopher Hughes points out, with reference to Comp. Theol. 211, "the treatment of the Incarnation in the Compendium theologiae appears to stress the mysterious and ineffable nature of the union more strongly than the treatment in either of the Summas, or in the disputed question 'De unione verbi incarnati'" (On a Complex Theory of a Simple God, Cornell Studies in the Philosophy of Religion [Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press, 1989], 243 n. 6). The Compendium Theologiae is a one-esse account, though it denies the relevance of the hand example, and claims instead that the human nature is most like an accident. But this is not as much of a shift from the earlier accounts as it looks. In the Compendium Theologiae, Aquinas has a rather different account of accidents from that of the earlier texts; and the new account makes an accident look fairly like the essential parts of the earlier discussions: "An accident is taken into the personality of the subject" (Accidens autem trahitur ad personalitatem subiecti) (Comp. Theo!. 211, par. 413 [1:97a-b]). On the other hand, while expressly denying that the divine person is in any sense composed from parts (one of which would be human nature: see Comp. Theol. 211, par. 412 [1:97a]), Aquinas defends the one esse account by noting: "If therefore we consider Christ himself as a certain integral suppositum of two natures, then there will be just one esse in him, just as there is one suppositum" (Si ergo consideremus ipsum Christum ut quoddam integrum suppositum duarum naturarum, eius erit unum tantum esse, sicut et unum suppositum) (Comp. Theol. 212, par. 418 [1:98a]). This bases the one-esse account on the supposition that the incarnate person can be thought of as if he is a whole composed of two parts (one of which would be human nature, the other divine nature). 202 RICHARD CROSS kind-nature will be one of these, if Christian orthodoxy is right. But Aquinas's account of the hypostatic union also teaches us that we go wrong if we take Aristotelian talk of accidents "actualizing the potentiality of their subjects" too literally. The claim that it is possible for God to instantiate human nature does not imply that God has some non-actualized potentiality, some intrinsic lack of actuality and perfection. If Aquinas had seen his way to these two conclusions, he could have made a straightforward claim that the human nature could be accidental to the Son of God-and thus have contributed new accidental esse to the Son of God. This would have enabled him to avoid all sorts of theologically damaging claims about unity of esse in Christ. The De Unione account comes closest to the account that I am suggesting. It sensibly distinguishes three possible ways in which a nature can contribute esse to a suppositum: (1) as its essential kind-nature (contributing esse simpliciter); (2) as an Aristotelian accident (contributing esse secundum quid); (3) as a non-necessary nature that is not one of the Aristotelian accidents (contributing secondary esse). And it is of course the third of these which is relevant for the hypostatic union. But, granted the view some of Aquinas's other presuppositions-particularly that the assumed human nature is individuated independently of the divine person-the De Unione account is less explanatory even than the fairly attenuated one-esse account of the Summa Theologiae. 62 62 I am most grateful to Richard Schniertshauer for reading an earlier version of this paper and making a number of helpful suggestions. BALTHASAR AND ECKHART: THEOLOGICAL PRINCIPLES AND CATHOLICITY CYRIL O'REGAN Yale University New Haven, Connecticut Or pleas'd to wound, and yet afraid to strike, Just hint a Fault, and hesitate Dislike; Alike reserv'd to blame or to commend, A tim'rous Foe and a suspitious Friend 1 T HE TENDENCY to avoid exclusion is a mark of the thought of Hans Urs von Balthasar. It represents an identifying habit, an incorrigible feature of style and sensibility. His texts in which theologians, philosophers, poets, dramatists, and saints are christianly praised give testimony to a catholicity that barely brooks limits. Not only in true Gospel fashion are a multitude invited to the eschatological banquet, they constitute the vast medium of tradition, in which Maximus the Confessor rubs shoulders with Plato, in the company of Claudel, Calderon, and Therese of Lisieux. At different times Balthasar thinks of the tradition as one huge symphony in which notes sound only to be transcended and as a conversation between particular perspectives on the great mystery of redemption, no one of which is final and which meet only in the infinity of their object. The decision for plurality and variety in the tradition certainly validates difference and counts against its reduction. 2 Yet at the same time tradition, precisely as a matter of variety, exhibits a measure of coherence or concordance that pro1 These couplets are from Alexander Pope's poem Atticus. See Minor Poems, ed. Norman Ault, completed by John Butt (London: Methuen & Co. Ltd.; New Haven: Yale University Press, 1954), p. 143. 2 See, for example, The Theology of Karl Barth, trans. Edward T. Oakes, S.J. (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1992), pp. 39, 187, 251. 203 204 CYRIL O'REGAN hibits difference from becoming truly excessive. It is this prohibition of excessive difference in Balthasar's reading of tradition that I would like to examine here. I take as my case study of Balthasar's rhetoric of reading his conflicted response to Meister Eckhart, about whose inclusion in the Christian tradition Balthasar expresses no doubts, yet whose theological message is such as to cause anxiety. We shall occupy ourselves in this paper with the way in which Eckhart's nonnegotiable inclusion within the tradition serves to repress the account of those features that present a fundamental challenge, that represent difference that would make the Christian field radically heterogeneous. In the first two sections, focusing mainly on the fifth volume of The Glory of the Lord (=GL),3 I shall offer outlines of both the positive and negative contributions Eckhart is deemed to have made to the theological tradition. Though I do not wish to give the impression of Scholastic pro and contra, Balthasar's positive remarks being imbricated with the negative and vice versa, it will be suggested that the elements adduced in both cases constitute mirror images of each other. Balthasar takes a bifocal, though not stereoscopic, view of a group of five elements: aesthetic disposition, the sameness of Being and God, the whylessness of the divine, Gelassenheit, and Gottesgeburt. This group is in effect read twice, once in a way that affirms and confirms Eckhart's unproblematic inclusion in the tradition (section 1), and again in a way that, in the light of basic Christian principles, raises serious questions about such inclusion (section 2). In a final section the question is raised whether the conflict in interpretation suggests a deeper underlying conflict between Balthasarian commitment to Catholic theological principles and catholicity. I. BALTHASAR'S AFFIRMATIVE RENDERING OF ECKHART On the surface there is little reservation about the approbation Eckhart receives in the fifth volume of The Glory of the 3 The Glory of the Lord: A Theological Aesthetics, vol. S, The Realm of Metaphysics in the Modern Age, trans. Oliver Davies, Andrew Louth, Brian McNeil, C.R.V., John Saward, and Rowan Williams, ed. Brian McNeil, C.R.V. and John Riches (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1991). BALTHASAR AND ECKHART 205 Lord. If the depths of Balthasar 's analyses of the medievals in his volumes on metaphysics (vols. 4 & 5) never reach the level of his account of Anselm and Bonaventure in volume two, it would be caviling to suggest that his intention at the start of volume five is anything other than the continuance of the praise of Thomas that completed volume four. Thus, even if Balthasar eventually turns out to be something of a "suspitious friend," to use Pope's locution, the charge of disingenuousness can be ruled out from the beginning. How we are to talk of an interpretation that seems to take back with one hand what it gives with the other, we can leave until later. What is important to get on the table at the moment is the religious and theological content in Eckhart that earns Balthasar's praise. Balthasar seems to espy a five-fold contribution made by Eckhart to Christian thought. Basic to Eckhart's inclusion at Balthasar's Christian banquet is his status as an aesthetic theologian. Though it helps the assignation of "aesthetic" to a Christian system if beauty is an express category of thought, this is not a requirement. On the basis of Balthasar's systematic outline of theological aesthetics in the first volume of The Glory of the Lord, "aesthetic" can appropriately be applied to a modality of religious thought provided it satisfy the following conditions: (1) there is a fundamental aisthesis or perception of divine presence more primitive than dogmatic formulation and religious apologetics; (2) the perception of presence involves the whole person and has the character of response, even surrender; and (3) presence is compelling because it is at once radiant and formed, where the former gives it its power, the latter its comprehensibility. 4 Balthasar's attitude with respect to Eckhart in volume five is that these criteria are sufficiently satisfied for him, provisionally at least, to stake a claim for Eckhart's not being a radical iconoclast, a raging lover of the 4 I intend these conditions to represent a digest of Balthasar's reflections in The Glory of the Lord, vol. 1, where he offers his most coherent and detailed account of what he means by "aesthetics" in general, "theological aesthetics" in particular. See The Glory of the Lord: A Theological Aesthetics, vol. 1, Seeing the Form, trans. Erasmo LeivaMerikakis, ed. Joseph Fessio, S. J., and John Riches (San Francisco: Ignatius Press; New York: Crossroad, 1982). In this volume Balthasar's influences are many. Nevertheless, 206 CYRIL 0 'REGAN formless. This is not to say that Balthasar is comfortable with the level of apophasis in Eckhart, or that he believes it should go unchecked. Yet he does understand that the Christian tradition in general, the Catholic tradition in particular, is a scene of tension between kataphatic and apophatic demands in which it is difficult always to strike the correct balance. Eckhart is not eccentric in showing some signs of overemphasizing the apophatic, but then he is in a long tradition that includes such exemplary ecclesial figures as Pseudo-Dionysius and John of the Cross (GL 1: 125). As long as the apophatic emphasis does not become so radical as to break free altogether from the kataphatic anchor provided by revelation, and especially by the consummate revelation of Jesus Christ, the stress is bearable and helps toward correction of overemphasis in the other direction by reminding Christians that the comprehensibility of God is to be seen against the backdrop of the ever-greater incomprehensibility. s More specific than the affirmation of Eckhart as aesthetic theologian is the validation of Eckhart's experience of the fundamental sameness of God and Being (GL 5:30). This experience discourages hyperbolic apophatic formulas such as God is beyond Being or God is nothing, particularly as these formulas tend toward hypostatization. Though he suggests that this experience is authentically Christian, the indissolubility of ontophany and theophany was one of the truly important lessons of Balthasar's review of ancient metaphysics in volume four, where metaphysics functioned as a term broad enough to include classical myth and philosophy. The assertion of the christianness of Eckhart's identification of God and Being is predicated on the Balthasar's free borrowing from Bonaventure, Thomas, and Albert indicates that medieval aesthetics, with its dual emphasis on radiance and form, is at the forefront. Radiance or splendor suggests the transcendent power that is the condition of form even as it appears in form, just as form is what makes available to cognition what is more than form. Needless to say, given Balthasar's aesthetic emphasis, such cognition ought not to be considered as discursive in the strict sense. 5 This relation of incomprehensibility-comprehensibility reflects Balthasar's often stated support for the Lateran Council's version of analogy-similarity (similitudo) is always subtended by an ever-greater dissimilarity (dissimilitudo). BALTHASAR AND ECKHART 207 relation of analogy between Christianity and the classical mythical and philosophical traditions, where Christianity is understood to represent their completion and supersession. From Balthasar's point of view the Eckhartian experience, which is consistent with the Thomistic experience, shows its superiority to Scotus's essentialist metaphysics, where Being, abstract and formal (GL 5:12-13) and univocal (GL 5:21), is specified by God and creature alike. Not only is Scotus summarily dismissed in the way few medieval figures are in Balthasar, 6 the dismissal smacks of rank stereotyping once typical of Catholic infighting between Dominicans and Franciscans. Plausibly, however, the dismissal is overdetermined, with Balthasar taking into account Heidegger's influential critique of metaphysics,7 which found one of its earliest and most emblematic targets in Scotus. 6 An emblem of Scotus's banishment is provided by Balthasar's reading of Gerard Manley Hopkins in volume three. In the face of the erosion of glory, both cosmic and transcendent, in modernity, Hopkins is regarded as offering an exemplary Christian antidote. Despite Hopkins's express assertion, however, that his cosmic and christological vision is fundamentally Scotist, hardly a mention of this is found in the approximately one hundred pages Balthasar devotes to exegesis of the Victorian poet. 7 While the influence of Heidegger is most conspicuous in volume five, which concerns metaphysics in the modern age, it extends also over the preceding English volume treating of metaphysics in the classical period. The unity of Balthasar's reflection on metaphysics is best captured in the German edition, which does not mark off the treatment of classical and modern metaphysics by volume. For Balthasar's treatment of metaphysics in the classical period, see The Glory of the Lord: A Theological Aesthetics, vol. 4, The Realm of Metaphysics in Antiquity, trans. Brian McNeil, C.R.V., Andrew Louth, John Saward, Rowan Williams, and Oliver Davies, ed. John Riches (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1989). Nevertheless, however influential Heidegger's reading of the history of metaphysics is for Balthasar, it is contested at every point. As volume four makes clear, the Platonic tradition abjured by Heidegger is regarded highly by Balthasar. For Balthasar, this tradition is the scene of the preservation of mystery rather than its overcoming. Moreover, while with Heidegger Balthasar thinks of modernity as problematic, he is prepared to exonerate significant numbers of philosophers, including Heidegger, theologians, and writers from modernity's constitutive deformation, that is, the eclipse of glory. Again, the medieval philosophical and theological tradition, so consistently and summarily dismissed by Heidegger, is regarded by Balthasar not only as relatively benign, but also in general as a source of philosophical, theological, and aesthetic opportunity. Nevertheless, Balthasar does make some concessions to Heidegger regarding Scholasticism in general and Scotus in particular. In some of its forms, it is conceded, Scholasticism does involve the eclipse of glory, just as Scotus 's formalist metaphysics loses touch with what is both most aesthetic and concrete in the medieval metaphysical tradition. 208 CYRIL O'REGAN Whatever the fairness regarding Scotus, Balthasar's general point is an important one: Christian theology can be unfaithful as well as faithful to the classical interlacing of ontophany and theophany that it not only retrieves and redeems but also elevates into a norm. Eckhart successfully passes, then, a normative test other theologians fail. The logical limits of Balthasar's approval, however, should be noted, since the order of explanation is different from the order of description. Approval of Eckhart's identification of ontophany and theophany need not imply validation of Eckhart's actual formula of Esse est Deus, which represents his conversion of Thomas's Deus est Esse. 8 Eckhart's trope of the "whylessness of God" (GL 5:31-34) is also affirmed. For Balthasar, in this trope is displayed, as perhaps nowhere else, Eckhart's fidelity to biblical witness. Eckhart's God renders "the infinite free 'I' of the God of Israel," the one who announces "I am who am" (45).9 Ingredient in the trope is an embargo against finitizing and instrumentalizing God. If Balthasar pictures an Eckhart who is not absolutely aiconic, here he feels called on to praise the kind of non-radical iconoclasm typical of the Bible and the protection afforded the sovereign freedom of God (GL 5:31, also 214-215). The warrants for Balthasar's approval are not rendered in volume five and await the volumes on the Old and New Covenant (vols. 6-7). Here he charts the full context from which affirmation of a sovereignly free God, neither subject to the immanentization of language (e.g., GL 6:54; 7:15-16), nor constrained by means-ends 8 Balthasar is demonstrably aware of Eckhart's inversion of key Thomistic tropes like Deus est Esse. While inversion is not absent from Eckhart's German texts, it is clearest in the Latin texts where actual Thomistic formulae are rearranged. The locus classicus for inversion of Thomas's famous identification of God and Being (STh I, q. 13) is the Prologue to the Opus Tripartitum. For a convenient translation of these prologues, see Parisian Questions and Prologues, trans. Armand A. Maurer (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies, 1974), pp. 77-108, esp. 85-93. For a good discussion of Eckhart's inversion, see Frank Tobin, Meister Eckhart: Thought and Language (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1986), pp. 38-42. 9 The Exodus formula of ego sum qui sum was a favorite of Thomas's (STh I, q. 13, also q. 2) as it was of Eckhart's. It is central to Eckhart's Parisian Questions, the Prologues to the Opus Tripartitum, and his interpretation of Exodus. See Parisian Questions and Prologues, pp. 50, 86-87, 107-113, respectively. BALTHASAR AND ECKHART 209 relations specified in the final analysis by the human subject (e.g., GL 6:317), emerges and is confirmed. The biblical volumes in the Glory of the Lord do not depart in any way from the kind of avowal Balthasar made in his great study of Barth. Rather they supply the evidential norm for judging the fidelity of theological constructions. That theological constructions can and do swerve from the biblical norm is clear, as far as Balthasar is concerned, in the propositionalist tendency in neo-Scholastic thought and certain trends in Christian Neoplatonism. For instance, while Christian.Neoplatonism hardly shows a predilection in the direction of valorizing language and the concept, The Glory of the Lord does worry about its tendency to undermine the freedom of God by conceiving of the God-world relation as being necessary in some way (GL 4:287-288). The fruitfulness of the trope of whylessness in the Christian tradition is, for Balthasar, an additional virtue. Pivotal in the pre-Reformation German mystical tradition (GL 5:65), in the shape of Angelus Silesius it can be said to outlast the tearing of the Christian fabric (GL 5:31-32). And given the relation of Heidegger to Eckhart, mediated through Silesius, that Balthasar takes for granted in volume five, it can even be said that something of this trope survives in the post-Christian thought of Heidegger who conceives of the mission (Sendung) of Being as ohne Warum (GL 5:441).10 This brings us to Eckhart's fourth major positive theological contribution. Gelassenheit in Eckhart (GL 5:36-39), Balthasar insists, most authentically describes the normative Christian disposition to reality. The very opposite of the libido dominandi exposed by Augustine as being at the heart of the self, and the very opposite of the titanic posture so rampant in modernity, Gelassenheit is not so much indifference to reality as diffidence, the "letting be" of reality calling for response, the rendering of oneself as the ' 0 Balthasar's treatment of Heidegger in volume five (429-451) makes it clear that at his best the "later" Heidegger is in line with the whyless emphasis of Eckhart and Silesius. For the same reason, Heidegger is in line with the biblical tradition. Balthasar is convinced, however, that this thrust in Heidegger exists in tension with an anthropological tendency that carries over from the earlier existential problematic of Being and Time. 210 CYRIL O'REGAN space for the perception and acceptance of reality as gift. Like other Eckhart commentators, 11 Balthasar understands that Gelassenheit should not be confused with Stoic apatheia (GL 5:36-38), even though Eckhart frequently invokes the authority of Stoic authors like Cicero. Balthasar is perfectly clear about the discrimen. Eckhart thus completely transforms Indian/Greek/Arab apatheia. It is the opposite of a technique for preserving oneself from sorrow; it is not a question of pain or pleasure but a total gift of oneself to eternal love. (GL 5:37-38} Gelassenheit, however, is not without classical prototypes. Trading on the close relationship between Greek tragedy and Christianity argued for in volume four (101-104), Balthasar maintains that Greek tragedy's enjoining of waiting in patience (hypomene), in its coincidence of passion and passivity, proves a model for specifically Christian Gelassenheit. Interestingly, in making this connection Balthasar at once validates Simone Weil 's sense of the connection between the tragic and Christian posture of exposure and their difference. 12 Acknowledging that Eckhart does in fact typically make a distinction between Gelassenheit and love, Balthasar argues that this distinction should not be taken at face value (GL 5:36-37). While Balthasar does not make available his rationale, his general acceptance of the distinction between agape and eros (GL 5:220), and his general reservations about eros (GL 5:263, 284 ff.), make it likely that he understands Eckhart's discrimination to be that between Gelassenheit and eros and not that between Gelassenheit and agape. Accordingly, agape can be regarded as being in good standing. 13 Moreover, a particular reading of the history of 11 See, for example, Reiner Schilrmann, Meister Eckhart, Mystic and Philosopher: Translations with Commentary (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1978), pp. 1617, 76-77, 170. 12 Simone Weil, Waiting on God, trans. Emma Craufurd (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1952). 13 Yet as Balthasar makes clear throughout volume five of The Glory of the Lord, particularly in his treatment of Renaissance N eoplatonism, his criticisms of eros are restricted. While eros sometimes shows a tendency toward a will-to-power, rightly appropriat- BALTHASAR AND ECKHART 211 effects of Eckhart's thought, its link with the thought of Suso, Ruysbroeck, and Tauler in particular (GL 2:37, 52-77), reinforce the rhetoric on behalf of the presence of agape in Eckhart. The point seems to be that if love functions conspicuously in orthodox mystical theologians rightfully regarded as belonging to the Eckhartian line, then at the very least it must be regarded as latent in Eckhart. Balthasar even goes so far as to suggest that Christ is seen by Eckhart as the mediator of this love, love moreover that is not without passion and agony (GL 5:37). Balthasar's attempt at hermeneutic generosity is at its most strained here. Eckhart's express denial of the connection between Gelassenheit and love is an embarrassment, and the historical argument made in the interest of Eckhart's Christian crebetween dentials is obviously a two-edged sword. The Eckhart and later mystical writers influenced-though not determined-by him can also warrant thinking of this later tradition as corrective and supplemental. Indeed, as we shall see later on, when he withdraws the cloak of absolute hermeneutic generosity with which he tends to clothe Eckhart here, Balthasar can take advantage of this second, more negative reading of the relation between anterior and posterior. For if .Balthasar wants to insist in the section on Eckhart that Suso and Tauler add nothing to their master, he also acknowledges that they recall the passion more frequently and penetratingly than he (GL 5:37). In addition, he is convinced that Ruysbroeck's more consistent trinitarianism provides a safer haven for Christian love (GL 5:70). In volume five Balthasar is rightly emphatic about the connection between Gelassenheit and Eckhart's image theology, particularly the Gottesgeburt, the trinitarian birth in the highest part of the soul: "The doctrine of Gelassenheit attains its Christian completion in a Trinitarian context" (GL 5:39). Openness is openness to and receives its completion in the trinied and put in context by grace, eras has its own legitimacy as the enactment of human freedom in response to the divine call. The two kinds of love are not to be construed as in principle antithetical in the manner of Anders Nygren. Interestingly, Balthasar does not interpret Karl Barth to be supporting anything like Nygren's distinction. See The Theology of Karl Barth, p. 116 212 CYRIL O'REGAN tarian birth, conceived as grace in the form of the self-communication of divine persons, a self-communication of the Son, but also of the Spirit (GL 5:38). Balthasar both recognizes and approves of Eckhart's choice of Mary as the prototype of the letting-be that makes the trinitarian birth possible. He writes: The Marian womb receivesthe seed of the Father, and since the Father is eternally, at every moment, begetting the Son, the eternal procession of the Son takes place in the pure medium of receptivity.(GL 5:39) The Gottesgeburt also comes in for discussion in Theo-Drama 2, 14 where Eckhart's rendition is said to represent the culmination of a history of the cipher (310). Even allowing for Balthasar's tendency toward nervous inclusion by means of excessive praise, this superlative is especially notable since Eckhart is said to complete a trajectory having its origin in Maximus the Confessor (302), an icon in the Balthasarian universe and a critical measure of theological health. 15 Though Balthasar provides no clue as to how Eckhart improves on Maxim us, rhetorically the association is good for Eckhart, effectively disbarring the suspicion that Eckhart's use transgresses the grammar of faith. Only insinuated, Balthasar's point in Theo-Drama is still at best quite formal. He does, however, offer something like a sketch of a ruled use in volume one of The Glory of the Lord. Importantly, the doctrinal locus of the Gottesgeburt is sanctification, and not the doctrine of God or some confusion between the two. Focusing his account, as Eckhart did, on the metaphors of virginity (599-600) and fertility (364, 539, 599-600), Balthasar insists, as he does in volume five, on the Marian context of Gottesgeburt. Within the ambit of a doctrine of sanctification what is crucial about Mary is her role 14 Theo-Drama: Theological Dramatic Theory, vol. 2, The Dramatis Personae: Man in God, trans. Graham Harrison (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1990), pp. 302-310. 15 This is the explicit theme of Liturgie Cosmique: Maxime le Confesseur (Paris: Aubier, 1947). The fact that Maximus is not promiscuously cited in The Glory of the Lord, arguably, indicates not so much Maximus's lack of theological purchase as the thorough assimilation of his christocentrism and trinitarian horizon. By contrast, in Theodramatik there is consistent invocation of Maximus. In Theodramatik 211 and Theodramatik 3, it is not only Maximus's christological sensibility that is functioning as a norm, but Maximus's actual christological elaboration. BALTHASAR AND ECKHART 213 as prototype. It is faith as receptive to the Word, and her fertility as bearing the Word in faith, that is relevant for our following at a distance. What is not relevant for us, because not possible in the order of imitation, is Mary's ontological status as theotokos, the immediate doctrinal site of which is that of Christ and/or redemption but which bears a relationship to a doctrine of God. The Marian constraint upon the Gottesgeburt, then, involves prohibiting the literalization of the metaphors of virginity and fertility in that transcendent dimension of human being, such that it becomes the womb of the Word and ontologically commensurate with it. On the basis of Balthasar's positive remarks in volume five we are entitled to view Eckhart as standing within this Marian tradition. To say that this is somewhat ironical is a huge understatement, for on the surface, at least, it would seem that the normative account stipulated in volume one is necessitated precisely because of Christian thinkers like Eckhart taking the Gottesgeburt out of the order of sanctification and homologizing the fertility of the virgin self with nothing less than the theotokos, understood metaphysically rather than physically. II. BALTHASAR'S NEGATIVE RENDERING OF ECKHART The assertion of multiple positives obviously neither prohibits serious qualification, nor rules out a balancing list of negatives. Histories of philosophical and religious thought typically adopt some version of "on the one hand-on the other" formula. What Balthasar tends to do, however, goes beyond this commonplace interpretive practice. He seems in fact to withdraw credits given to Eckhart at the same time that he deposits them. The list of debits turns out to be a function of the list of credits that provides the raison d'etre of Eckhart's inclusion in the history of christianly friendly metaphysics, indeed their mirror image. Here we will deal with Balthasar's withdrawals point by point, leaving until section three further reflection as to what this means for Balthasar's interpretation of Eckhart and his style of interpretation in general. We begin with the problematization of Eckhart's aesthetic stature. It is evident from his book on Maximus and his early reflec- 214 CYRIL O'REGAN tions on truth, 16 as well as from The Glory of the Lord, which comes a generation later, that Balthasar is thoroughly exercised by the legitimacy and limits of Christian apophaticism. Consistently proposed is a distinction between biblical mystery and the mystery of speculative or negative theology (e.g., GL 7:265-272). 17 He recognizes the danger in Christian Neoplatonism for apophaticism to be cut loose from its proper revelational-ultimately christological-moorings, and so unloosed God will come to be regarded not only as other than the one who answers the question of proper name by the odd name of ehyeh asher ehyer (Exodus 3:14), but also as other than the most ultimate of realities, the Trinity (GL 1:44; 5:228). Suspects in the Christian Neoplatonic field are named, only for charges to be subsequently withdrawn. In Balthasar's Maximus text, Pseudo-Dionysius is regarded as guilty of a christianly forgetful apophasis that borrows too heavily from Proclus, a position that seems to be sanctioned by the first volume of The Glory of the Lord (196). But in volume two all such reservations are dropped. 18 Pseudo-Dionysius is depicted as the most aesthetic of all Christian theologians, with "aesthetic" carrying all the positive evaluative freight referred to above. And counterintuitively, 16 See Liturgie Cosmique, pp. 45-47, 52-60; also Phenomenologie de la verite, trans. R. Givard (Paris: Beauchesne, 1952). 17 See Balthasar's essay, "Bibel und negative Theologie,'' in Sein und Nichts in der abenliindischen Mystik, ed. Walter Strolz (Freiburg: Herder, 1984), pp. 13-33. In maintaining the distinction in principle, Balthasar wishes to offer as generous an interpretation as possible of the negative theology tradition. There is also a wide-ranging discussion of the place of negative theology vis-a-vis biblical theology in Theologik 2: Wahrheit Gottes (Einsiedeln: Johannes Verlag, 1985), pp. 80-116. Balthasar is clear that the appropriate kind of negativity for Christianity is that mediated through the biblically rendered God who approaches in the Old Covenant and becomes consummately present in the New. It is not simply transcendence to which the Church in a biblically"wrought world responds, but rather the dialectic of transcendence and immanence. Certain kinds of negative theology, for example, non-Christian Eastern varieties, fail to meet the biblical test, and historically speaking not every ingestion of Neoplatonism into Christianity is christianly fruitful, though on the whole Balthasar finds himself to be fairly sanguine about the historical outcome. 18 Liturgie Cosmique, pp. 17, 45, 48; also The Glory of the Lord: A Theological Aesthetics, vol. 2, Studies in Theological Styles: Clerical Styles, trans. Andrew Louth, Francis McDonagh, and Brian McNeil, C.R.V., ed. John Riches (San Francisco: Ignatius Press; New York: Crossroad, 1984), pp. 144-210. BALTHASAR AND ECKHART 215 not only is apophasis not as wild as some commentators and critics of Pseudo-Dionysius have thought, but Pseudo-Dionysius also has a centripetal revelational force that is in line with scripture and the christocentrism of the best of patristic thought (GL 2:142, 172).19 Similar vacillation attends Balthasar's reading of Eckhart. If in his most extensive treatment of Eckhart in volume five Balthasar signals an Eckhart of limited apophasis, in volume one Eckhart is placed among the apophatic radicals who privilege darkness over light, beyond being over being, and assert that the former is the truly primal ground of all else thereby relegating the God of revelation and even the Trinity to the secondary status of manifesting the immanifest one (196). Theo-Drama 2 seems to support this latter position when it expresses considerable discomfort with the designation of God as nothing (255), a designation typical of Eckhart. 20 By doing so, of course, a more historically real Eckhart emerges, a theologian who constitutes a challenge to the tradition that prioritizes revelation, whether direct or indirect, but a theologian also with whom theologians of Balthasarian-like convictions can enter into disputation and accuse of forgetfulness. One thing is certain, however. Eckhart cannot seek the sanctuary of Thomas (TD 2:274) or Maximus, in both of whom apophaticism is vitally alive but constrained, albeit constrained in different ways; in Thomas 's case by the analogy of Being, and in the case of Maximus by Christ as the center of all analogy of Being. 21 In his discussion of Thomas at the end of The Glory of the Lord, volume four (393-412), Balthasar calls attention to a war19 Similar reservations expressed in the Maximus text about Eriugena are also withdrawn in The Glory of the Lord. See vol. 4, pp. 345, 350-351. Interestingly, in vol. 7 the earlier accusation of the non-christocentric nature of the thought of Pseudo-Dionysius is revived. See The Glory of the Lord: A Theological Aesthetics, vol. 7, Theology: The New Covenant, trans. Brian McNeil, C.R.V., ed. John Riches (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1989), p. 273. ' 0 The radical divine ascription of nothing is more typical of Eckhart's German sermons, yet it can also be found in Eckhart's Latin works with which Balthasar seems to be more engaged. For a good example of its use in a Latin text, see Parisian Questions and Prologues, p. 51. 21 Liturgie Cosmique, p. 58. 216 CYRIL O'REGAN rying corollary of Eckhartian apophasis, that is, the way in which predicating goodness of God is undermined (397).22 Balthasar has available to him a number of texts, the most famous being a sermon from the period of the Parisian Questions where Eckhart, arguing against Thomas, asserts that goodness is as predicable of God as blackness is of the sun. 23 Balthasar's issue with Eckhart's view is not that of antinomianism; it is rather the purely theological issue of the concept of God. What is existentially at stake is clarified only later (GL 5:22), when Balthasar comes to discuss the modern fragmenting of the kalokagathon, particularly in the case of Heidegger, Eckhart's most famous twentieth-century lionizer. Separating goodness from God, qua presence, leaves a space open for a demonic substitution for the Christian God (GL 5:59). The refusal of the attribution of goodness to God, it is implied, is essentially the refusal of the transcendentals, whose function in Albert, Bonaventure, and Thomas Balthasar takes to be Christianly normative (GL 4:372 ff.). The other side of the Eckhartian refusal is the prioritizing of oneness, which seems to be placed beyond the bounds of predication, either categorical or transcendental. 24 The tendency to prioritize oneness has the consequence of placing Eckhart's status as an aesthetic theologian in real jeopardy, for 22 Numerous examples can be found throughout Eckhart's German sermons. See, for example, sermons 54, 63, 67, in Sermons and Treatises, trans. and ed. Maurice O'Connell Walshe, 3 vols. (London: Watkins, reprint: Dorset, England: Element Books, 1987). These sermons correspond to numbers 12, 40, and 9 in the Kohlhammer edition of Eckhart's works edited by Josef Quint (Die deutschen und lateinischen Werke [Stuttgart: Kohlhammer, 1936-]). See Sermons and Treatises, 2:71-72, 118, 149-150. 23 See German sermon 17. 24 Here Balthasar notes a tendency observed by other commentators on Eckhart. Maurer, for instance, in his introduction to Parisian Questions and Prologues underscores the tendency towards assertion of the primacy of unity (p. 32). Maurer's identification of the nub of the problem as the dominance of the Proclean element in Eckhart's Neoplatonism bears a close resemblance to Balthasar's general anxiety with respect to the Proclean dimension of Christian Neoplatonic thought. Though Balthasar does not directly accuse Eckhart of a repristination of Proclus, this is the general thrust of his reading. In his Maximus book, Proclus is regarded as the great danger for Christian thought, one to which Pseudo-Dionysius and Eriugena-both masters of Eckhart-succumb. In The Glory of the Lord, vols. 2 and 4, Proclus still remains a danger for Christian thought, even if Pseudo-Dionysius and Eriugena can prove their Christian credentials. BALTHASAR AND ECKHART 217 such a divine ceases to have shape and form (GL 1:196). But there is perhaps an even more ultimate danger, one diagnosed in Gregory of Nyssa, that is, that God may be refined so out of existence that one can no longer talk about presence, and apophaticism blends with a kind of sophisticated agnosticism. If Thomas is up to the first aesthetic challenge in insisting that God is known in species, he is up to the second in construing relations between God and world to be effective and intimate. Analogia entis, for Balthasar, is not simply an epistemological requirement, it is at once a metaphysical and a theological necessity. On the very same pages in volume five that praise Eckhart for his insight into the intimate relation of God and Being, Balthasar argues that the way in which this is conceived establishes a system of identity with invidious theological consequences (42-43). The consequence that gets most emphasis is the ontological devaluation of the world precisely as different from God. The radical divinization of Being both evacuates and elevates. Balthasar cites the famous passage from German sermon 40 that played a role in Eckhart's condemnation: "All creatures are pure nothing .... All creatures have no being, for their being consists in the presence of God" (GL 5:42).25 It is with some justice, then, that Eckhart can be seen minimally as a significant figure in the pantheistic trend within Christianity, and plausibly even its source (13-14, 45). Though Balthasar is extremely careful to distinguish Eckhart from Scotus, always in favor of the former (GL 1:13), the identity orientation of Eckhart's thought, which subsequently has quite a different trajectory (GL 4:397-399), itself is destined to issue in a kind of essentialism. The lack of commitment to the distinction between essence and existence, the loss of "the Thomistic mediation of the non-subsistent actus essendi," cannot but prove harmful to the status of the concrete world of particulars that Thomas philosophically and christianly sought to defend (GL 5:31). In his overall questioning of the way in which Eckhart understands the sameness of God and Being, Balthasar appears to be 25 See also German sermons 57, 68, 69, in Sermons and Treatises, 2:89, 160, 168. These sermons correspond to sermons 12, 11, and 68 in Quint's edition of the Deutsche Werke. 218 CYRIL 0 'REGAN rejecting the Eckhartian move of converting Thomas's Deus est Esse into Esse est Deus and the dismantling of analogy that this involves. That the decision for Thomas's formula is crucial for Balthasar is underscored when he insists on the prerogatives of the theological difference between God as summum esse and finite being as secondary esse over Heidegger's ontological difference regarded as the critical alternative (GL 5:472). At the same time, of course, analogy is affirmed (GL 5:447). There are good reasons to believe that Balthasar has the Opus Tripartitum in mind. This text is, of course, the locus classicus of the Esse est Deus formula, That Balthasar's textual concern seems to be the Latin texts in which Eckhart self-consciously takes issue with his master is further evidenced when he highlights the related thought of the ordering of being to knowing that distinguishes the Parisian Questions (43-44). In that text, he writes: "The quaestio whether in God Being and Intellect (intelligere) are identical, is first of all answered by Eckhart in the affirmative, in keeping with the tradition, but then he explains that the actus secundus is nobler than the actus primus." Balthasar proceeds to quote Eckhart to the effect that "God does not know because He is, but He is because He knows; knowledge is the foundation ifundamentum) of His being" (GL 5:43). Once again Eckhart is engaging a key element of Thomas 's doctrine of God only to subvert it. Balthasar finds himself no more happy with this subversion than the previous one, and clearly takes sides with Thomas. This decision too can be said to lead to either a fundamental decision between identity or analogy or be predicated on it. For, as Balthasar reads him, Eckhart's prioritizing of intelligere over esse subserves his identity program (GL 5:43-44). By contrast, Thomas's assertion of the final prerogative of esse over intelligere in Summa theologiae, I, q. 14 guarantees both real difference and real relationship. Read in the context of Eckhart's relationship to Thomas, the aim of Eckhart's support of intelligere would be to subvert the analogical field and the particular kind of discontinuity and continuity it allows. At the core of Eckhart's subversion is his willingness to grant merely intentional being to creatures in the mind of God. Beyond their status as intenda creatures are devoid of ontological status, or correlatively pos- BALTHASAR AND ECKHART 219 sess only meontological status. Moreover, as it operates in Eckhartian discourse in concert with esse,26 the apparent equivocist form of intelligere obscures its depth logic, which is that of identity. Assertion of the prerogatives of intelligere dictates not only that if esse is predicated of the world it is denied of God, it also suggests that if esse is predicated of God, then it is to be denied of the world. But this rule of absolute incommensur.ability between the divine as divine and the non-divine as nondivine ultimately clears the way for the view that the relative non-divine obscures what it really is, and what really is. And what really is is intelligere as dynamic divine Being that is not the property of the transcendent beyond, but a divine milieu inclusive of the terms "God" and "human being," terms it turns out that do not name substantial entities, but rather point to polarities of event. It is this concern about the identity implications of Eckhart's preference for intelligere that seems to prompt Balthasar's general acceptance of Eckhart as a plausible origin for modern Geistphilosophien, which for him always has an identity physiognomy. One can construct, he believes, a plausible genealogy from Eckhart to Hegel via Cusanus (GL 5:45). Balthasar is convinced in the case of both Eckhartian inversions of Thomas that analogia entis is compromised. In this he agrees with Ebeling. 27 And on the basis of the Parisian Questions and the Prologues to the Opus Tripartitum, where Eckhart most directly engages Thomas, he also agrees with Fabro and Otto in judging Eckhart's thought to drift in a monist direction. 28 The drift for him is certainly not such, as with Otto, that Eckhart becomes the occidental Sankara. Nor is the drift such that he would think it justifies Fabro's rendering of Eckhart as a 26 While in Parisian Questions the association of Deus and intelligere seems to involve the denial of the association of Deus and esse prominent in the Prologues to the Opus Tripartitum, Eckhart commentators have not taken this to imply a substantive dissociation of esse and intelligere. See Vladimir Lossky, Theologie negative et connaissance de Dieu chez MaUre Eckhart (Paris: Vrin, 1960), pp. 217-220. 27 See Heinrich Ebeling, Meister Eckharts Mystik (Stuttgart, 1941), p. 204. 2• Cornelio Fabro, Participation et causalite selon Saint Thomas d'Aquin (Louvain: Presses Universitaires de Louvain, 1961), pp. 551-609; also Rudolph Otto, Mysticism East and West: A Comparative Analysis of the Nature of Mysticism, trans. Bertha L. Bracey and Richenda Payne (New York: Macmillan, 1970). 220 CYRIL 0 'REGAN Parmenidean monist, despite the assistance supplied Fabro in this respect by Eckhart as he points back at his own philosophical precursors. 29 Given Eckhart's Neoplatonic heritage, most commentators would be prepared to say that this drift does not rule out analogy altogether. In fact, the position that Eckhart's denial of analogy lexically extends only as far as the analogy of proportion and not the analogy of attribution corresponds well with Balthasar's at once positive and negative reading of Eckhart on analogy. 30 Moreover, support for the analogy of attribution not only would not necessarily rule out an identity program, but could in fact encourage it. If being spoken of in many ways (:pollachos legetai) is always emphatically referred to the first term (alla pros en), 31 which in the Christian context is God, then, there is not, as Thomas recognized, protection against the imperialist claims of the prime analogate. Certainly, in forms of Neoplatonism untempered by the biblical doctrine of creation, the real tends not only to get defined by, but exhausted by "the really real," with the result that the finite, as the not really real, is not. In advocating the nullity of the posterior term, Eckhart suggests that he belongs to this radical N eoplatonic tradition in which identity metaphysics proceeds by way of difference presupposed and then annulled. We will treat somewhat more sketchily Balthasar's withdrawal of support for the remaining three elements of Eckhartian espousal that initially are taken as markers of positive contribution. Expressive of the biblical view of God's transcendence with respect to language, thought, and ritual and his untrammeled freedom, the Eckhartian trope of the whylessness of God represents a highpoint of theological and doxological response to God as the mystery that grants a reality that can be received appropriately only as grace. There are, however, two kinds of danger to which the Eckhartian rendition is exposed. On the one hand, as Balthasar in his defense of theology against Heideggerian crit29 See Parisian Questions and Prologues, pp. 94-95. ° For this point, see Schiirmann, Meister Eckhart, p. 172; Lossky, Theologie negative, 3 pp. 286-320. 31 See Aristotle, Metaphysics, 1028a. BALTHASAR AND ECKHART 221 icisms in volume five of The Glory of the Lord makes clear, whylessness may be associated with sheer contingency (444), a road traveled by Heidegger, a sometime champion of Eckhart. On the other, as suggested in volume four and elsewhere, whylessness may be understood to be consonant with some kind of conceptual or ontological need, whereby manifestation becomes definitional of the divine. Again, Balthasar does not so much accuse as insinuate. The insinuation in the latter case takes the form of hemming Eckhart in by means of Neoplatonic precursors and Idealist successors who are deemed to have this problem. The Glory of the Lord shows time and again Balthasar's awareness that not all varieties of Neoplatonism are christianly healthy (GL 4:238-241; 5:43-45, 214). If Plotinian Neoplatonism can be regarded as benign (GL 4:280ff.), the Proclean strain cannot. In its parsing of the relationship between immanifest and the manifest, or the unparticipated and participated, 32 it introduces a logic of necessity invidious to the biblical freedom of God normative for Christianity (GL 2: 158). A similar logic of necessity characterizes German Idealism, where creation is said to complete God (GL 5:302, 319-321).33 If such is the case, the axiom of the self-sufficiency of God that served as the linchpin of the classical tradition, and receives something like a summation in 32 At various points throughout The Glory of the Lord, Balthasar invokes the Proclean formula of "participation in the unparticipatable" in order to show that the Christian view is qualitatively different. In volume two (188), for instance, he wishes to underscore the extent to which Pseudo-Dionysius 's adoption of the formula (here amethektos metaxoumena) overcomes the suggestion of immanence that is contained in Proclus 's use of the formula in The Elements of Theology. Using a slightly different version of the formula (amethektos metexetai), he makes essentially the same point in volume six. See The Glory of the Lord: A Theological Aesthetics, vol. 6, Theology: The Old Covenant (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1991), p. 10. This time, however, Pseudo-Dionysius is no longer called to mind. Balthasar is obviously convinced that Christianity is capable of adapting and constraining any valuable item of pagan wisdom. Thus his use of the Proclean formula for non-Proclean purposes is a good example of spolatio Aegyptiorum. 33 See also Theo-Drama, vol. 2, pp. 205, 256-257, 261, where he criticizes Hegel for thinking that God must go out of the Trinity to complete himself. For a good account of the relationship between Balthasar and Hegel on this point, see James Naduvilekut; Christus der Heilsweg: Soteria als Theodrama im Werk Hans Urs von Balthasars (St. Ottilien: EOS Verlag Erzabtai, 1987), pp. 160-172. 222 CYRIL O'REGAN Thomas, is undercut. 34 Lack or need indicate that if one considers God as love, then this love is erotic. Poros haunts the now relativized penia of divine love. 35 While Balthasar believes that the whylessness of God is reconcilable with divine love, indeed must be reconcilable, if the divine is to correspond to the biblical reliability of God, it is so only if love is interpreted as agape. The erotic interpretation of love introduces a why into God, in which otherness is invested in only insofar as God becomes more himself. God is no longer pleroma, but the process or movement towards realization, the filling of lack, that is, plerosis. At its best, Eckhartian whylessness is just the opposite of this; it is the joyous, unaccountable fertility of giving and expenditure. But it is caught in Eckhart, Balthasar thinks, betwixt and between sheer irrationality and a rationality as instrumental as it is restricted. In his account of the movement of the Eckhartian line in mystical theology Balthasar affirms its increasingly horizontal and practical focus, as well as the way in which it gets christologically anchored. Ruysbroeck, Suso, and Tauler represent not so much speculative subtractions from Eckhart as Christian additions. As we saw earlier, Balthasar does not claim that the values ascribable to Eckhart's successors are in a zero state in him. His position is simply that the level of their existence is such that it calls for improvement. Eckhartian Gelassenheit defines rather than stands as an exception to the rule. Eckhart's successors are more successful than he in seeing how, as a state, Gelassenheit is incorporable into the Church with the consequence that the community context of its operation and practical focus is more to 34 It is clear from Theo-Drama, for instance, that while Balthasar is anxious to open reinvestigation concerning the way in which we construe the relation of God to suffering, and thus the way in which God is to be affected by the world, he does not wish to undermine divine self-sufficiency, nor the attendant classical views of divine immutability and impassibility. He does suggest, however, that the forms in which these ideas have been expressed may have to be rethought and more nearly adapted to biblical witness, and particularly the consummate witness of the cross. 35 Balthasar tries to counter the view that lack is somehow an ingredient of divine love throughout his work. This is especially the case in Theo-Drama and Mysterium Paschale. See especially, Theo-Drama, vol. 2, pp. 49, 256-257. See also Mysterium Paschale: The Mystery of Easter, trans. Aidan Nichols, O.P. (Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1990), pp. 29-34. BALTHASAR AND ECKHART 223 the fore. Rightly understood, Gelassenheit is the ground of action, even apostolic action, not its substitute (GL 5:291). A further lack in the Eckhartian construal may be implied in Balthasar's praise of the dramatic figuration of Gelassenheit in Eckhart's successors. In their more Augustinianly rendered universe Gelassenheit has to be wrested not from the darkness of the created but from the compelling darkness of the sinful self. For Eckhart, as is well known, darkness is applied to the "not" of the materiality, temporality, and multiplicity of the created order, a "not" more passive, less aggressive than sin. Any and all problems regarding Gelassenheit, however, in Balthasar's view, finally devolve from lack of appropriate christological focus. This point is made in a number of different places in The Glory of the Lord, volume five, and repeated in Theo-Drama 2. Without christological orientation, Gelassenheit is bereft of aim. While such erring would not particularly disturb either committed Christian critics of institutional religion and theological orthodoxy, who sometimes appeal to Eckhart, or Eckhart's postmodern, post-Christian celebrators, 36 it manifestly disturbs Balthasar. Gelassenheit, even in its most episodic form, is detachment for, not from. It is the ground and possibly the enactment of a form of attentiveness toward reality not ordinarily present, but not demanding superhuman strength or genius. This is even more the case if Gelassenheit is understood nonepisodically as a disposition toward reality that is constant, that at once is an ingredient in a life and the power that shapes the story of a life. Ultimately this means that Gelassenheit is a form of imitatio Christi wherein the self models itself on the way Christ offered himself to the Father and whose story took the shape of this offer. In affirming the christological focus of Eckhart's successors Balthasar, interestingly, recalls Maximus, 37 and when he insists on their christological improvement on Pseudo-Dionysius in particular (GL 5:78), he effectively is setting 36 An obvious example of the former is the creation spirituality group led by Matthew Fox that finds in Eckhart a source for spiritual and theological renewal. Postmodern celebrators of Eckhart would obviously include Schtirmann and John Caputo. 37 Liturgie Cosmique, pp. 150-170. 224 CYRIL O'REGAN up an analogy between Maximus's improvement of PseudoDionysius, which was one of the main drifts of the Maximus book, and Eckhart's successors' improvement on him. But he is also indicating something like a normative rendering of Gelassenheit. Maximus is in a privileged position to provide such a normative rendering, since he represents one of the most satisfactory translations in the Christian tradition of its scriptural, specifically Johannine expression (GL 7:323). For John describes a Christ who not only utters the words "thy will be done," Gn 6:38) but whose life and death are also testimony and, as such, also utterance . .And it is John's Gospel that also sets this surrender in the ample theological context in which the Father's sending and the Son's obedience are seen as moments of divine love. 38 We come to Balthasar's fifth and final querying of the Eckhartian contribution. Instead of directly condemning Eckhart for transgressing the grammar of image theology and for actually literalizing the metaphors of virginity and fertility associated with the Gottesgeburt, Balthasar simply stipulates the undesirability of transgression and explicates the consequences of literalizing. If there is a charge on the table against Eckhart, it has to be regarded as conditional. As with anyone else, Eckhart is to be condemned if he undermines the incommensurability of the divine and the human and if the literalization of metaphors of virginity and fertility has the consequence of thinking of the Gottesgeburt in the transcendental dimension of self as being on the level of Mary's bearing Christ. Of course, this irenic strategy is especially effective, since it will be unlikely, if not impossible, for anyone with the slightest acquaintance with Eckhart's texts not to concede that Eckhart breaks the rule of incommensurability and literalizes in a quite extraordinary way. Indeed, if anything Eckhart's German and Latin sermons make it clear that our gynecological capacity may very well surpass that of Mary as theotokos. For if she gives birth to the incarnate Son of God, 38 This Johannine trope becomes central to Balthasar's constructive theological work. It is particularly central to his profound christological reflection of Theodramatik 211 and Theodramatik 3. BALTHASAR AND ECKHART 225 each self, as constituted by the spark in the soul beyond the order of creation and time, gives birth to the eternal Son. Not alone, then, does Eckhart move his image theology out of the ordinance of sanctification, but out of the ordinance of christology, and resituates it at the level of the doctrine of God. And the claims are truly astounding, as Balthasar well recognizes. At one level, the challenge presented by Eckhart is his particular view of uncreated grace (GL 5:39). Balthasar, certainly, is persuaded that assertion of the self as the site of an intratrinitarian process from which it emerges divinized, and even announcements that it too is engendered as the Word, as the Son, need not conflict with the tradition. For the conflict not to arise, however, one has to recognize that Eckhart was primarily a giver of sermons, not a philosopher, and not even a systematic theologian. Without generous allowance for metaphor and hyberbole, Eckhart has to be regarded as going decisively beyond not only the divinization tradition in the West, fundamentally specified by Augustine, but also the more radical Eastern Christian tradition, with which through Eriugena he is in contact. Certainly, he goes beyond Maximus, who provides a classic rendering of the symbol of the Gottesgeburt, and who insists, no less than Augustine does, on the createdness of image, and on sonship being both christologically mediated and thus the adoptive mode of sonship. In Eckhart's exemplarist christology, Christ is only our elder brother who points the way beyond the shackles of temporality and createdness to our common eternity with the Trinity (GL 5:554). The last thing Christ is in Eckhart is the site of the difference between the divine and the human, even while he is the overcoming of a distance that separates. III. THE AGON OF THEOLOGICAL NORMS AND CATHOLICITY Since my primary interest here is Balthasar's rhetoric of interpretation, the adequacy of Balthasar's interpretation of Eckhart need not be assessed in any detail. Still, it would be hermeneutically irresponsible not to say something about the relative merits of the two sides of Balthasar's conflicted reading. While there is 226 CYRIL O'REGAN no reason to doubt the sincerity of Balthasar's appreciation of Eckhart's contribution to the tradition of aesthetic Christian thought, yet the fact that every element of this contribution is effectively contested in the very pages where we find the positive estimate, at first sight, seems to indicate that the latter is more basic. Certainly, it seriously undermines the case that can be made on behalf of Eckhart's inclusion as an important Christian and spiritual resource. Yet it turns out that the positive and the negative are not on the same level and that Balthasar's argument with Eckhart only functions in the context of a prior acknowledgment that Eckhart is part of the great Christian conversation. In this regard the function of the more positive appraisal is to establish the intramural horizon of critique. Placed safely beyond the possibility of extrusion from the tradition, or excommunication from the company of theologians with orthodox credentials, questions can be raised as to whether Eckhart's thought as a whole reflects, in the way the thought of orthodox Western and Eastern theologians and mystics do, inalienable Christian beliefs without detriment to theological perceptiveness and insight. A very definite ceiling is, therefore, set on criticizability. With regard to the first three areas of contestation, it seems that Thomas is in effect Eckhart's main interlocutor. Two points are important. First, it is clear that as measured by Thomas the radically apophatic thrust in Eckhart, his explicit inversion of basic Thomistic formulae, and the particular slants possibly implied in Eckhart's rendition of the whylessness of the divine are to be regarded as temptations. At the same time, however, these temptations are not fully rendered. Second, at no point in volume five does Balthasar explicitly integrate his first three objections to Eckhart or argue that they are integrated in Eckhart, though there are plenty of hints regarding both. With respect to the first point, for example, Balthasar supplies a mere notice of the extensivity and intensivity of the apophatic language rampant in Eckhart's German and Latin sermons, and present even in his exegesis. Taking a cross-section of a narrow band of Eckhart's German sermons, one comes across the fol- BALTHASAR AND ECKHART 227 lowing statements made about God: God is without name, even I (S49); is hidden (S53); is darkness and unknown (S53); is beyond goodness and truth (SS4); is nothing (SS4); beyond God (S56); is formless (S65); beyond being (S67).39 The situation is hardly different in the Latin sermons. Tobin has pointed to the currency of such epithets "innominabilis," "ineffabilis," "innarrabilis," "incomprehensibilis." 40 Whatever its intent, the effect of this radically Dionysian language in both German and Latin sermons is to challenge the theistic and biblical God, the one who is revealed, and point to the divine that is beyond God, the Godhead who is wesen ane wesen, the equivalent of the Hyperousias Thearchia of the Divine Names. 41 Arguably, its effect is even to go beyond Pseudo-Dionysius, if one agrees that in the Divine Names the Trinity is coextensive with the superessential Godhead. 42 Balthasar definitely gestures towards the radicality of Eckhart's apophatic challenge, but not rendering it, together with the surrounding positive corona, enables him to mitigate the challenge and to avoid the emergence of an either-or decision. With regard to the issue of integration, while it is clear that the support of analogy is a major issue in the reservations expressed concerning Eckhart's inversion of Thomas, Balthasar suggests rather than demonstrates how analogy, or its failure, relates to Eckhart's apophaticism or divine whylessness. The 39 Sermon numbers are taken from Sermons and Ireatises, vol. 2. These sermon numbers correspond to 77, 23, 23, 12, 6, and 9 respectively. See pp. 38-39, 67, 71-72, 74, 7981, 134, 149-150. 40 See Tobin, Meister Eckhart, p. 66. 41 The locution wesen ane wesen, or in modern German, wesen ohne wesen, was the German mystical tradition's way of translating the hyper-ousias of the hieratic Dionysian tradition. 42 Whether or not the superessential Godhead transcends the Trinity remains a disputed issue in Dionysian studies. While many scholars often fall into opposing camps, some are not persuaded that Pseudo-Dionysius has a unified position. In this context the issue gets reduced to the issue of the drift of different texts, with a text such as the Divine Names seeming to support the orthodox position in a way that the Mystical Theology, arguably, does not. 228 CYRIL O'REGAN texts of Eckhart, certainly, permit the argument to be made that the undergirding issue is that of analogy. At a number of points in Eckhart, apophaticism is brought into relation with an ontotheology of esse. In Parisian Questions and Eckhart's commentary on Exodus in particular-a text also read by Balthasar-Thomas's famed connection of the ego sum qui sum of Exodus with his construct of esse is deconstructed. In the former text Eckhart remarks that ego sum qui sum should not be taken to mean that God reveals who he is; rather the name indicates that God hides himself in a dark night. 43 And_given the conversion of Thomas's Deus est Esse formula, Eckhart can argue straightforwardly that if esse and God are the same, then esse, as immanifest, has nothing in common with manifestation or revelation, which accordingly belongs to an antithetical order.44 Again, in the commentary on Exodus esse is discussed in the context of an elucidation of negative names and their superiority and is paired with the Tetragrammaton, which name, Eckhart confesses, is conceptually odd since it is hidden, secret, and inexpressible. In this context, esse is the nameless name, i.e., the nomen innominabile applying only to the divine. 45 But its applying only to the divine does not mean that the extension of esse is exhausted by a discrete entity, God, as distinct from other entities, creatures. Rather esse covers all being insofar as it is divine. As the nameless name, it is also the name of all things, i.e., the nomen omnium. This text repeats a move in operation in Parisian Questions. In both cases radical apophaticism insures the collapse of analogy. Arguably, the brevity of Balthasar's discussion prohibits the kind of rendering that would bring out connections between Eckhartian themes that would allow the systematic swerve of this view from more traditional construal to become transparent. Still, read against the background of his interpretation of a sim- 43 See Parisian Questions and Prologues, p. 50. Questions and Prologues, p. 48. 45 Parisian Questions and Prologues, pp. 107-113. 44 Parisian THEOLOGICAL PRINCIPLES AND CATHOLICITY 229 larly situated mystical theologian, Pseudo-Dionysius, and even on its own terms, there is evidence that Balthasar is involved in repressing a systematic difference between a radical theological figure and the more mainline tradition, or, at a minimum, refusing to have it loudly announced and fully articulated. In any event, Balthasar does a considerably better job of making explicit the connection between the Eckhartian trope of ohne warum and the ontotheology of esse. Eckhart's refusal to mark the relation between the divine and non-divine as one of epistemological and ontological reliability goes hand in hand with a refusal to construe God in Thomist terms as summum esse. Certainly, Balthasar might have been more explicit about linking divine whylessness and a disagreement with Thomas 's understanding of esse with a disagreement about analogy, though this relation is probably implied. 46 In summary, then, even if there is some measure of repression in Balthasar's account, the Auseinandersetzung of Eckhart with Thomas that expresses itself throughout the first three points does finally seem to be a dispute about analogy, its nature and limits, in which Balthasar takes the side of Thomas. Yet Balthasar's taking sides with Thomas is more than a little muted by the fact that he does not bring out into the open the level of integration in Eckhart's position and the systematic nature of its swerve from a canonic theological model. Whatever role Thomistic analogy plays as the rule of Eckhartian metaphysical reflection turns out to be limited, since banishment of Eckhart beyond the pale of tradition is not a possibility. One might say that Thomas functions as a kind of ontotheological measure not only for diagnosing but also for correcting deficiencies in Eckhart's thought, thereby stabilizing it and making Eckhart a more mainline member of the Christian tradition and more fully serviceable within the ecclesial community. This raises the interesting question whether Thomas will continue to play the role of measure with regard to the final two 46 For an argument for the close connection of the problematics of esse and analogy in Eckhart, see Schiirmann, Meister Eckhart, p. 191 230 CYRIL O'REGAN Eckhartian topoi and again what kind of role a theological measure as such plays. There seems an evident change of concern in Balthasar's treatment of the last two points. As he begins to worry about Eckhart's rendition of Gelassenheit and Gottesgeburt Balthasar's concern seems less that in both cases there is some infraction, implied or on the surface, with regard to analogy. Rather the issue is primariJy christological. Specifically, Balthasar is concerned that both tropes are, at the very least, christologically underdetermined. Balthasar's objections are clear enough. The pattern of existence intended by Eckhart in Gelassenheit does not find its measure in Christ, and the exemplarist tendency displayed in the symbol of the Gottesgeburt proximally undermines differences between Christ's would-be followers and Christ himself, and ultimately undermines differences between would-be followers of Christ and the intratrinitarian Word. Again Balthasar does not delve into the extent and depth of Eckhart's christological subversion. In particular, he neither examines the extent of Eckhart's neglect of dogmatic christological language, 47 nor Eckhart's subversion of such language when he uses the traditional deification formula of Christ becoming human in order for the human to become divine. 48 Now while the christological turn does not imply that analogy ceases to be an issue-this is particularly the case with respect to the Gottesgeburt-all suggestion of Eckhart's dispute with Thomas disappears, and with it any confidence that Thomas continues to be the measure when the main issues cease to be those of religious epistemology and the doctrines of God and creation. If there is another theological measure for Balthasar, then, it is likely that this theological measure has to be looked for elsewhere. Meister Eckhart, p. 157. See, for example, sermons 47 and 75 in Sermons and Treatises, 2:27-28, 207. These correspond to sermon 46 in Quint's edition and to sermon 75 in that by Franz Pfeiffer, res pee ti vely. 47 For this point, see Schiirmann, 48 BALTHASAR AND ECKHART 231 The nearest thing to a clue is perhaps provided by Balthasar's mentioning of Maximus in the context of a discussion about the history of the Gottesgeburt. When at the end of volume one Balthasar formulates his requirements for standard Christian usage of the Gottesgeburt, he could be talking about Maximus. For in the Ambigua Maximus brings a whole patristic tradition of such talk, beginning at least as far back as Clement and Origen, to conclusion. 49 Despite Balthasar's positive suggestion that it is Eckhart who completes Maximus, the norm by which Gottesgeburt renditions are to be judged, it turns out, is Maximan, rather than Eckhartian. Eckhart himself, therefore, is judged by a norm he does not provide. Even more generally, however, from his book on Maximus, it is clear that Balthasar regards Maximus as offering a mystical and ascetical theology, extraordinary in its balance and sobriety and christological specification. The goal of asceticism and the mystical life in general is not one of mystical or contemplative flight, but rather of imi-. tation of Christ. This imitation means that one's life is to be rendered christiform, ultimately cruciform, but this cannot be done unless there is a surrender of will to the Father after the pattern of Christ's surrender. One surrenders not to or toward the formless divine but within the matrix of the relation of Christ to the Father. One's path is thereby an accountable path, however mysterious it is. One does not get lost in the desert of the superessential God, become pathless in the One to whom and from whom there is no path, but moves safely within the precincts defined by the self-giving and receiving of the trinitarian persons. The surrender of the self, illustrated by Maximus, expresses the Christian sense that the Gottesgeburt is event only as narrative, indeed is the condition of the possibility of narrative. Maxim us 's recognition that as Christ is first in the order of knowledge, the Trinity is first in the order of explanation, dictates the Christian parameters of the mystical life that is short49 This point is made by Schiirmann (Meister Eckhart, pp. 24-26) and supplements the point that Balthasar made in Theo-Drama, vol. 2, p. 302. Schiirmann's supplement is consistent with the general view of Maximus elaborated by Balthasar in Liturgie Cosmique, where Maximus is regarded as completing and correcting the whole patristic tradition of divinization. 232 CYRIL 0 'REGAN changed outside the context of christological optics and trinitarian foundation. Of course, it should be said that, for Balthasar, trinitarian foundation is much more event and act than the static hypokeimenon or supposit underlying beings.so For Balthasar, Maximus is not an exemplary christological theologian simply because his optics are christological. He is so because he also shows the way by demonstrating how in practice a Chalcedonian allegiance founds rather than restricts a mystical theology. In The Glory of the Lord, volume five, Balthasar does not invoke the norm of a Chalcedonian base for mystical theology that earlier in his Maximus book he had invoked against the Neoplatonic mystical tradition that preceded him.s1 Judged against this norm Eckhart's thought would not only have seemed to be christologically underdetermined, but christologically problematic. Nevertheless, even in the event of a successful case for a christology quotient in Eckhart, there would still be the problem of what Eckhart does with the ancient mystical formula respecting the incarnation: God became human in order for the human to become divine. For Eckhart, whose interpretive manifold is here supplied by the Neoplatonic exitus-reditus schema, the descending and ascending movements are perfectly symmetrical. The humanity assumed by the Word is such that it presents no obstacle against conceiving it as becoming divine,s 2 or revealing itself as divine. Chalcedon is evoked, but only onesidedly. The event of the Word in Mary, and in us, reveals that humanity and divinity are without division and separation. Lacking, however, is the correlative Chalcedonian stress on the preservation of the essential distinction between humanity and divinity. But, then, Eckhart shows no interest in preserving, as 50 One of the major insights Balthasar gleaned from the work of Barth was to conceive of God as act or event rather than in static terms. See The Theology of Karl Barth, pp. 63, 162-163. Balthasar tries to carry this over into his major constructive work. As is clear from his criticisms of Heidegger in The Glory of the Lord, vol. 5, in particular, however, Balthasar does not tolerate any and all versions of event. ·11 See Liturgie Cosmique, pp. 150-170. 52 A number of Eckhart's German sermons are particularly important here. See especially, sermon 47, in Sermons and Treatises, 2:27-28. This sermon is 46 in Quint's Kohlhammer edition. BALTHASAR AND ECKHART 233 Chalcedonian christologists do, the becoming of Christ. The term "humanity" does not designate a nature with limited possibilities and extraordinary fragility due to its createdness. 53 Rather "humanity" as such is uncreated and the event of the Word ultimately occurs on a level beyond the flesh. Eckhart, therefore, effectively redescribes the logos sarkos as the logos asarkos. In addition, the incarnation is not unique in any fundamental way. This humanity is a general property, no more particular to a Conrad or Henry-to avail of Eckhart's nominal choices-than a Mary or Jesus of Nazareth. And since the event is essentially beyond any time frame, an essential contemporaneity exists. Thus the decreation of the event of the incarnation is matched by a correlative dehistoricization. By insisting on the unmixedness of humanity and divinity in the hypostatic union, Maximus goes some way toward protecting mystical theology against claims of apotheosis. By indicating that the incarnation is not built into the order of things, and thus mysterious, Maximus goes some way towards underscoring its unrepeatability and historicity. While there are other possible versions of a Chalcedonian Christology, as Balthasar indicates clearly in his great essay on Anselm in volume two, 54 Maximus's rendition proves sufficient to diagnose and counter a christological frame like Eckhart's. As was the case with the first three points, Balthasar neither renders Eckhart's positions on Gelassenheit and Gottesgeburt with sufficient clarity for them to be subject to a fundamental critique, nor shows how their respective insufficiencies integrate into a christological deficiency that could only be taken as the kind of challenge that must be met. Like Thomas, Maximus functions as a measure for diagnosis and rehabilitation. The mission of diagnosis, however, is definitely not that of search and destroy. Eckhart is to be kept intact for rehabilitation, even if this means that as judged by the Maximan measure he fails the 53 For this trend in Eckhart's thought, see sermons 70 and 75 in Sermons and Treatises, 2:176-177, 207. 54 See The Glory of the Lord, 2:211-259. 234 CYRIL O'REGAN test only to be allowed to pass anyway. We will return to this point once again at the conclusion of the essay. That Maximus functions as Balthasar's christological measure need not necessarily imply that Thomas is regarded as an unsatisfactory resource. What is compliment to Maximus is not insult to Thomas. Yet there are some indications that Thomas is not regarded as a full-blown theological, that is, trinitarian and christological, resource in the way Maximus is, or for that matter Anselm and Bonaventure. Discussion of these other theologians invariably brings these matters to the surface; discussion of Thomas by and large does not. Since Balthasar's account of metaphysics in volumes four and five is not intended to be a straightforward historical account, it is not incumbent on him to outline the relationship of Eckhart's view on Gelassenheit and the Gottesgeburt to Thomas 's view of love with which Gelassenheit is in actual negotiation and Thomas's view of the trinitarian character of the mystical life and the role of Christ. Nevertheless, as with the issues of apophaticism and analogy, it is Thomas 's views that provide the proximate background of Eckhart's more radical proposals. What amounts to a virtual historical acknowledgment in the case of the former in volume five, therefore, seems to suggest a particular reading of Thomas as primarily, if not exclusively, a metaphysical and not at all a spiritual theologian. With regard to the reading of the Summa, for instance, the logic of this reading is such as effectively to cut off the thematic of De Deo Uno from the De Deo Triuno, even more importantly the doctrines of God and creation from the subsequent theological anthropology and christological material from which answers to Eckhart's provocation might be supplied. Certainly, it is outside the context of De Deo Uno that Thomas elaborates his views about deification, where deification is construed as nothing less than sharing in the trinitarian life, under the conditions of finitude and createdness, and where the energy and ambiance of deification is divine love. Moreover, as the third part of the Summa makes clear, Thomas has going for him his own version of a Chalcedonian christology that at once BALTHASAR AND ECKHART 235 makes possible participation in the divine life, and yet keeps intact the uniqueness of Christ and his role as the indispensable mediator. 55 Thomas 's neutralization in the case of Gelassenheit and the Gottesgeburt provokes the interesting question about the relationship in volume five between the misgivings regarding the analogy of being and the christological misgivings. Specifically, do the misgivings about analogy and Christology function as two coordinate but ultimately different types of misgiving? What Balthasar writes about Eckhart makes it difficult to answer the question. While the concern for the status of analogy and christological determination seem polymorphous enough, in practice these concerns tend to get distributed over specific Eckhartian determinations and symbols. Nevertheless, in the context of Balthasar's opus as a whole, it is clear that one can say that (a) all theological concerns are in some way or other concerns of analogy, and (b) all theological concerns are in some way or other christological concerns. For instance, problems with Eckhartian Gottesgeburt can easily be seen to be a function of a lack of respect for analogy that protects against identifying the divine and the human. Similarly, problems with apophaticism are ultimately solved theologically by appeal to the form of Christ. But this still leaves the question of superordination-subordination. Granted that all concerns with a thinker like Eckhart could be thought of either as problems of analogy or as problems of Christology, what is determinative in the last instance? Balthasar's answer to this question is fairly decisive, as his operative theological practice illustrates. It is the latter. This has the consequence that if one were forced to choose between Thomas and Maximus-though the choice is not a realistic one, given Balthasar's view of the tradition--0ne would choose the latter because of the presumptively greater christological determinass The only place where this seems partially recognized by Balthasar is Theo-Drama, vol. 3, where Balthasar discusses Thomas's treatment of the consciousness of Christ in Summa Theologiae III, qq. 10-12. See Theo-Drama: Theological Dramatic Theory, vol. 3, Dramatis Personae: Persons in Christ, trans. Graham Harrison (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1992), p. 174. 236 CYRIL O'REGAN tion. Balthasar's reading of the Confessor demonstrates that he believes that Maximus, in contradistinction to his non-Christian and Christian Neoplatonic predecessors alike, has grasped the meaning of the analogy that serves as the bulwark against identity programs within the Neoplatonic Christian tradition. But analogy receives its ultimate anchor in Christ. Balthasar fails to suggest that Thomas has similar advantages, though arguably with Przywara Thomism is on its way toward the recognition. Christ is the true analogia entis, a position that Balthasar early on gleaned from his reading of Maximus and confirmed in his encounter with Barth. 56 This is the center from which the whole theological enterprise radiates, even if, with certain limitations, a non-christologically specified analogy of being can continue to play some role in apologetics. It is, then, the more nearly Maximan criterion, which is at the center of Balthasar's own constructive proposal in his great trilogy, that in effect sets a more stringent criterion of inclusion than the analogy of being. This is exacerbated when it is realized that it is in Christ, particularly in the cross and resurrection, that reality, brought to the ultimate point of contradiction and nonidentity, is embraced, yet in such a way as not to reduce difference to identity. An authentic theological aesthetics, therefore, invariably surpasses itself in a theodramatics of the dialogical play of freedom between the divine and the human. This in principle leaves theological or mystical work that is not Christ-centered at best competing for "aesthetic theology" status, the bad side of Balthasar's contrast of "aesthetic theology" with "theological aesthetic." The former is not yet what a Christian view is or ought to be, but is capable of recontextualization and reconfiguration. Perhaps, it is this capability that facilitates Balthasar's consistent practice of reading generously Christian thinkers who would be found on the "aesthetic theology" side of 56 On this point Balthasar announces his full agreement with Barth in his The Theology of Karl Barth, pp. 326-363. For a particularly explicit statement, seep. 55. And, just as with Maximus, Balthasar is approving of the Chalcedonian thrust of Barth's thought, even down to its dyothelite development (pp. 115-116). As a matter of historical fact this development is only completed, of course, by Maximus. BALTHASAR AND ECKHART 237 the "aesthetic theology"/"theological aesthetic" divide. In Eckhart's case this would mean that deficiencies in analogy are virtually compensated for by being corrected in Thomas, and lack of christological focus, and error of christological and trinitarian substance, are compensated for by being corrected in Maxim us. Of course, this can be interpreted in two different ways. One could view Balthasar as presuming that the tradition corrects for its own anomalous formations. Alternatively, one might read him as discouraging anomaly by imputing theological virtues regarding analogy and christological formation to a Christian thinker diagnosed as being deficient in these dimensions. Needless to say, not every mode of Christian thought is rehabilitatable. For instance, non-aesthetic, propositionalist treatments of Christianity would not be granted the same kind of generous reading; their claims or overclaims are not redeemable. In Balthasar's scheme of things the advantage is given to aesthetic Christian modes of thought such as Neoplatonism, N eoplatonism in particular. At one point or other Balthasar is able to point out analogy and/or christological deficits in PseudoDionysius, Eriugena, Cusanus, as well as Eckhart. Nevertheless, their aesthetic thought encourages Balthasar not so much to drop the criteria that would force a discrimen between these and more orthodox forms of thought, as to consider that these thinkers in fact realize an analogy and christology minimum. Indeed, in the case of Pseudo-Dionysius in volume two we are asked to believe counterintuitively that Pseudo-Dionysius realizes a christological maximum, an idea denied in Balthasar's text on Maximus, for there Pseudo-Dionysius was regarded as Maxim us 's foil. Interpretation then seems to be a scene of imputation and donation of forgiveness by which the tradition is given amplitude and abundance. Yet the self-evident dismantling of accusations made by Balthasar himself with respect to Eckhart and other Christian thinkers in the Neoplatonic tradition has a price. Eckhart, the apophaticist, disanalogist, the christologically underdetermined Christian thinker, is granted entrance into the tradition. He adds to the variety of the Christian tradition and joins the other symptomatically prob- 238 CYRIL 0 'REGAN lematic cases of Pseudo-Dionysius, Eriugena, and Cusanus, but arguably at the price of his own measures of analogy and Christology operative throughout The Glory of the Lord and the authority of those theologians who exemplify these measures. 57 Perhaps as an enduring sign of his disaffection with manual theology, Balthasar is resolutely anti-monolithic in his view of tradition. If the Catholic tradition is deep, it is also broad. Most certainly, it is not constituted by a narrow band of creedal confession. Yet neither is it reducible to the thought of one thinker, as was the tendency in the first decades of the century. As Balthasar writes in his book on Barth: ... even an Aquinas is only one Doctor of the Church among others. Even if he is the greatest of the cathedrals, there are still others built in different styles from the Gothic. 58 Indeed, given Balthasar's numerous full-length studies on theologians, saints, and literary figures, and in particular his determined attempt in his analyses of clerical and lay styles in The Glory of the Lord, volumes two and three (and five) to present a truly pluriform tradition, it can be said that the Catholic tradition has more than ·a few and, arguably, a considerable number of able representatives. Thus, as "and" functions in the theological domain as an approximate marker of the difference between the Catholic and the Protestant traditions, insofar as locutions like nature and grace, free will and grace are sayable within Catholic theological grammar, "and" is also a marker of the formation of a tradition where one contribution can be laid alongside another, tradition being the sum of such historical deposits. Yet, however pluralist Balthasar's conception of tradition is, it is not altogether without hierarchy; just as however decentered the tradition is by style and emphasis, it is not radically decentered or disseminative in the postmodern sense of the term. The promiscuity of "and" is structurally resisted by the "either-or" of 57 Balthasar Jays down these measures in the first, "foundational" volume of The Glory of the Lord. 58 The Theology of Karl Barth, p. 261. BALTHASAR AND ECKHART 239 theological measures found in general theological principles and embodied more deeply in some Christian thinkers (and believers and doers) than others. If the result in the case of Eckhart and others is a conflicted response, it is not because there is no resolution, but rather because of its complexity. That irenicism wins out over the critical exercise of theological measures does not mean that these measures and their critical potential are fully neutralized. Pope's divagations on hesitant judgment in the epigraph brilliantly capture the symptoms that articulate this recoil from facile praise without ringing endorsement, faults hinted at without being fully explored, criticism as a kind of selfconsuming artifact. Balthasar's practice, however, differs from that portrayed by Pope in one profoundly important respect: there is in it nothing of conscious contrivance. What becomes manifest is not an animus toward Eckhart incompletely hidden, but rather the hermeneutic counterpull to the pull of inclusion that is more comprehensive and deep. While Balthasar, as we have seen, is prepared to exclude, exclusion is invariably reluctant, particularly so in the case of Christian N eoplatonic thinkers who satisfy the aesthetic hunger of modernity. Thinning the Catholic ranks of Eckhart and other Christian Neoplatonists, then, not only removes a resource to meet a modern need, but more importantly leaves the Catholic tradition less rich, less textured, and less polyphonic. And for Balthasar to be less polyphonic is to be less "catholic." It is catholicity, then, that dictates inclusion of difference and, at the same time encourages the tendency toward domesticating any difference that might be divisive, any difference that would strike an unresolved discordant note jangling within the symphony of truth. THOMISTIC PRIDE AND LIBERAL VICE 1 PAUL J. WEITHMAN University of Notre Dame Notre Dame, Indiana L IBERALISM IS often portrayed, and sometimes portrays itself, as a moral and political view that rejects the claims of tradition. Thus liberals characteristically claim that the traditional standing of a social arrangement contributes little or nothing to its political legitimacy. Whether an arrangement is legitimate depends upon whether or not those who currently live under it can understand and accept its rationale. Members of each generation must be able to examine arrangements as if they themselves were signatories of the social contract; the justification of regimes must, as it were, be susceptible of renewal in every age and to every citizen. Jefferson gave this view its most extreme expression when he claimed that each generation has the right to begin its nation's political life anew, and that national constitutions should be rewritten every two decades. 2 Liberals often seem no kinder to intellectual than to political traditions. As they think political life can periodically begin anew, so they sometimes seem to think that political and moral philosophy can begin anew. Hobbes famously castigated the obscurities of scholasticism and argued that political philosophy could achieve firm footing only if the rubble of the past were swept away. 3 Liberal contract theorists have followed Hobbes's lead, developing political theories that rely not at all upon classi1 Thanks to Alasdair Macintyre, David O'Connor, Michael Pakaluk, David Solomon, Eleonore Stump, and Allen Wood for helpful comments on earlier drafts. This paper is dedicated to the memory of my teacher and friend, Prof. Judith Shklar. 2 See Jefferson's famous letter to Madison of September 6, 1789 (The Portable Jefferson, ed. Merrill D. Peterson [New York: Viking, 1977], 444ff.), as well as his lesser known missive to Samuel Kercheval of July 12, 1816 (ibid., SS2ff.). 3 See Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, ed. C. B. MacPherson (New York: Penguin Books, 1985), 72 7, for an especially pungent expression of a view that runs throughout the Leviathan. 241 242 PAUL J. WEITHMAN cal and medieval moral philosophy. To take but one example of this neglect of the past, the ethical writings of scholasticism are dominated by richly detailed analyses of the virtues and vices, yet liberal writers roundly ignore these discussions. Liberals have been quick to defend their suspicions of the thought and politics of the past, but critics of liberalism have been equally quick to seize upon them. Champions of virtue ethics have been among the most vocal critics of liberalism in recent years, arguing that liberals court philosophical peril by neglecting the insights of earlier moral theories. Edmund Burke, the eighteenth-century opponent of liberalism, had an additional complaint. Burke discerned an arrogance in the liberal rejection of intellectual and political tradition. It was mere pride, Burke thought, to suppose that politics and political theory could be made transparent to the reason of every individual in the way that liberals sometimes claim. 4 Burke's allegation that the liberal rejection of tradition reflects pride is ironic, for pride is a central element of one of the traditions of moral thought that liberals seem determined to reject. During a lengthy period of philosophy's history, pride was thought to be a motive of all wrong action. The biblical book of Sirach says that pride is the beginning of all evil 5 and a long line of medieval moralists labored to explain how this might be so. Yet the tradition of moral thought that accorded pride so central a role now suffers from neglect at the hands of many philosophers. And pride itself is a vice that many philosophers now consider unworthy of attention. Most fail to consider it seriously as a motive for any wrong action at all. I have three aims in this paper. One is to examine pride's neglect more closely. I shall argue that pride suffers this neglect because of its centrality to a religiously based tradition of moral thought that many philosophers no longer accept. The alleged connection between pride and religion is, I shall argue, suggestive. It suggests what an account of pride would have to include 4 See Edmund Burke, Reflections on the Revolution in France, in Selected Works, ed. Edward John Payne (Oxford: Clarendon, 1883), 102. 5 Sirach 10:15. THOMISTIC PRIDE AND LIBERAL VICE 243 if contemporary philosophers are to find it useful. My second aim is to recover one medieval analysis of pride, that of Thomas Aquinas, and to show that Aquinas provides a much richer account of pride than the conception that contemporary philosophers reject. Finally, I want to show the usefulness of Aquinas's account as an account of the motive to do wrong. In doing so, I shall focus on acts that liberals, at least Kantian liberals, are committed to condemning as failures. I shall argue that the concept of pride proves more useful in explaining those actions than do the Kantian accounts which reject it. I One reason for pride's neglect is that many philosophers concur with Thomas Nagel in thinking partiality to one's own inclinations, interests, and commitments is the primary motive of immoral action. 6 It follows from this view that a systematic analysis of immoral motivation must first come to grips with partiality. Pride, if it plays any role in this analysis, will be a derivative notion because pride will appear as but one of its manifestations. And it may seem an uninteresting one when compared with the greed, intolerance, and hedonism on which philosophers have lavished so much attention. Partiality seems so important because other religiously based moral considerations have been eclipsed. Indeed, contemporary philosophers quite consciously neglect pride out of a concern to sever the connection between religion on the one hand and moral and political philosophy on the other. To see this, recall that humility is among the most important virtues of the Christian life. That virtue is accorded such centrality because it is thought to reflect the proper attitude toward God, whom Christians are enjoined to love with their whole hearts. Pride, it might be thought, is the vice opposed to humility, a vice which consists in failure to maintain the proper attitude toward divine greatness. To the extent that philosophers once regarded pride as an impor6 For one statement of Nagel's view, see his "Moral Conflict and Political Legitimacy," Philosophy and Public Affairs 16 (1987): 215. 244 PAUL J. WEITHMAN tant source of immoral motivation, its importance was derived from the religious importance of the virtue it opposed. If pride seemed important only because humility was deemed essential, then humility's decline in importance as a virtue explains the decline of pride's importance as a vice. 7 If philosophers no longer think that maintaining a proper attitude toward God is the central component of living well, then they will accord pride far less attention in their analyses of immoral motivation. Discussion of pride and its connection with immoral action is, for example, notably absent from Martha Nussbaum's work. This is because maintaining a proper attitude to the God of biblical religion is not important to her Aristotelianism. Humility does not appear on her list of the virtues, for she regards it as a "competitor" of the magnanimity she favors. 8 Elsewhere, Nussbaum maintains that rebellion against a divinely imposed moral law is not an important component of human moral experience as Aristotelians describe it. 9 The claims that humility is not an important virtue and that prideful rebellion does not figure in the experience of one's own immorality explain why discussion of pride has no place in Nussbaum's rich analysis. Judith Shklar's denial that pride and humility are important ethical concepts is quite explicit. Her argument for that claim and her attempt to distance political theory from biblical religion are equally so. Shklar notes that Judaism and Christianity take pride to be the worst of sins because it is essentially a "rejection of God.'" 0 Political theorists within those traditions-most notably Augustine-accordingly took it as fundamental to their accounts of the moral education government should provide. 7 I am indebted to Michael Pakaluk for this way of formulating the point. Nussbaum, "Non-Relative Virtues: An Aristotelian Approach," in Peter A. French et al., eds., Ethical Theory: Character and Virtue, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, vol. 13 (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1988), 38. 9 Martha Nussbaum, "Recoiling from Reason," The New York Review of Books 36 (1989): 40. "Recoiling from Reason" is Nussbaum's review of Alasdair Maclntyre's Whose Justice? Which Rationality? (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1988). 10 Judith Shklar, Ordinary Vices (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1984), 8 Martha 241. THOMISTIC PRIDE AND LIBERAL VICE 245 Augustine, for example, argued that the primary purpose of political authority should be to chasten pride and foster humility.11 This thesis about the proper aims of political authority is, Shklar argues, opposed to the liberalism she endorses. Liberals, Shklar states, should not see government as an instrument for fostering humility or any other virtue; government can at best hope to restrain the vices in their grosser manifestations. The vices with whose expression Shklar thinks liberals should be concerned are those she, following Montaigne, dubs "ordinary"-hypocrisy, snobbery, treachery, misanthropy, and cruelty. Shklar focuses on these vices, rather than on pride and the other deadly sins of medieval Christianity, because she claims that liberal governments should regard the infliction of pain on other human beings as the summum malum. 12 It is the ordinary vices, she argues, that ought to be restrained because it is they that motivate the infliction of pain. Shklar neglects pride expressly because she rejects the moral agenda that Augustine and others thought biblical religion set for political theory. Liberals as different as Nagel, Nussbaum, and Shklar thus reject pride as a concept inadequate to the description, explanation, and evaluation of our most important moral and political experiences. They do so because of the connections they see among the condemnation of pride, the elevation of humility, and the necessity of reverence toward the Judaeo-Christian God. I want to suggest, however, that they neglect the concept of pride because they have an unduly narrow understanding of it. A proper understanding of pride would show that notion to be adequate to the tasks for which Nagel, Nussbaum, and Shklar reject it. Nussbaum and Shklar neglect or reject what might be called See Augustine's Enarrationes in Psalmos 124, 8. Shklar, Ordinary Vices; see also Shklar's "Liberalism of Fear" in Nancy L. Rosenblum, ed. Liberalism and the Moral Life (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1989), 21-38, especially 23. Annette Baier's review of Ordinary Vices is indicative of how far from philosophical view the vice of pride has slipped. Baier says of the book that Machiavelli is its villain. She makes no mention of Augustine, Gregory, Aquinas, or of any other of the theologians who preached against the sin of pride; see Shklar, Ordinary Vices, 240. For Baier's review, see Political Theory 14 (1986): 56-59. 11 12 246 PAUL J. WEITHMAN "the Miltonian conception" of pride, after Milton's Lucifer. 13 The pride Milton attributes to Lucifer is directed against God and includes a "high disdain" for or contempt of God. Second, it is a trait of character of which its possessor is aware and from which he knowingly acts. Third, acting from and sustaining it require great strength of character. Any plausible account of pride must be capable of accommodating these three features. If contemporary philosophers like Nagel, Shklar, and Nussbaum are to find that account useful, however, it cannot be exhausted by the Miltonian conception. A usable account of pride can, I believe, be found in the work of Thomas Aquinas. According to Aquinas, pride can serve as the primary motive for any kind of evil act. Pride is also needed to explain fully evil acts done knowingly, even if it was not the primary motive of those acts. But pride is not exclusively a rebellion against God, in Aquinas's view. Acts of pride need not be motivated by a desire for goods that are God's nor accompanied by contempt for God. The proud person need not exhibit extraordinary strength of character, though she can. She need not be aware that she acts from pride, though she may be. Aquinas's conception of pride is thus a richer and more inclusive one than that described by Milton. It can accommodate the Miltonian paradigm. It can also be useful even to those like Nagel, Shklar, and Nussbaum who do not share Aquinas's and Milton's theological presuppositions and who are little worried about offending God. II Aquinas produced two discussions of pride or superbia, one in the Summa Theologiae and one in the Quaestiones Disputatae de Malo. 14 These discussions, like much of Aquinas's work, are remarkable for their reconciliation of views that seem to conflict 13 For the characteristics of the Miltonian conception, see John Milton, Paradise Lost, Book I, lines 95·112. I have referred to the critical edition edited by Alastair Fowler (London: Longman, 1980). 14 References to both of these works will hereafter be included parenthetically in the text. Throughout I have referred to the Parma edition of Aquinas's Opera Omnia. THOMISTIC PRIDE AND LIBERAL VICE 247 and that are drawn from a diversity of sources. The tradition to which these sources contributed took for granted that pride bore some causal connection to other sins. The nature of the connection, however, was a matter of debate. Thus among the problems with which tradition presented Aquinas was that of whether "pride" names a particular sort of sin that is the efficient cause of others or whether, on the contrary, it names some matter or form common to every sin or to every kind of sin. The earlier-cited passage from the book of Sirach can be interpreted to support the latter view and was taken by many of Aquinas's predecessors to do so. As we shall see, Aquinas does think that there is one sense of the word "pride" that accords with the latter view and therefore with a powerful current of theological tradition. His considered view, however, is that pride is a particular kind of desire, "an appetite for one's own excellentia" (STh II-II, q. 162, a. 2). This desire is, by definition, sinful: Aquinas says that superbia is a desire that exceeds the rule of reason (De Malo, q. 8, a. 2). Pride is therefore a sin of a particular kind. It is, finally, a sin that can stand in a variety of causal or explanatory relations to other sins, sins directed against God and man. Let us see how Aquinas establishes each of these claims. Aquinas thinks that desires are distinguished in kind by the kinds of their objects. The burden of establishing the first claim-that the desire for excellentia differs in kind from other desires-therefore rests on the claim that excellentia is a distinctive kind of object of desire. Obviously this depends upon what Aquinas means by "excellentia," a word usually translated into English as "excellence." To say of someone that she wau.ts her own excellence is to say that she wants to have the property of being excellent or that she wants to excel. Note two conditions on having such a desire. First, the person who wants his own excellence must employ (possibly subjective) standards by which people can be compared or assessed. Sometimes, of course, people compare themselves to others in one or another respect and rely on standards by which people's beauty, intelligence, taste, or ability at chess, for example, are compared and assessed. Second, whatever stan- 248 PAUL J. WEITHMAN ea quae ratione non valent comprehendi, sicut est creatio et modus creandi omnia simul et divisim." A similar interpretation of Albert's position on the creation of matter is offered by Lawrence Dewan, "St. Albert, Creation, and the Philosophers," Laval theologique et philosophique 40 (1984): 295-307; for an account of how Albert's position developed from the earlier commentaries on the Sentences and the Physica to the later commentary on the Metaphysics and the Liber de processu universitatis, see Steven C. Snyder, "Albert the Great: Creation and the Eternity of the World," in Philosophy and the God of Abraham: Essays in Memory of James A. Weisheipl, O.P., ed. R. James Long (Toronto: P.l.M.S., 1991), 191-202. 35 For the date of St. Bonaventure's Commentary on the Sentences, see John Francis Quinn, The Historical Constitution of St. Bonaventure's Philosophy (Toronto: P.l.M.S., 197 3), 91. 292 TIMOTHY B. NOONE Intelligence that separated the latent forms from their material conditions. The third school of philosophers, founded by Plato, advanced a still more sophisticated account of the origin of the universe according to which there were separate Forms, eternally existing matter, and a Maker that introduced the Forms into the matter. Aristotle instituted the fourth school of philosophy whose followers are the Peripatetics. The universe, according to these philosophers, is made but eternal. 36 Immediately, St. Bonaventure confesses his uncertainty about how the Aristotelian doctrine of the universe's origin is to be understood, by openly stating that he is in doubt as to whether Aristotle posited any creation of matter and form. In the succeeding question which deals with whether the world is eternal, he gives his most comprehensive treatment of the Peripatetic philosophy. Recognizing that some more recent authors (moderni) claim that all Aristotle meant by his proofs of eternal motion is that the order of motion was not brought into being through generation or any other natural motion, he officially reserves judgment; but the force of his words indicate that he is more inclined to accept a harsher interpretation, while the words themselves suggest that Bonaventure has read Grosseteste's H exremeron: And this view [i.e., that matter eternally existed under some form] seems more reasonable than its opposite, namely, that matter existed eternally incomplete, bereft of form and divine influence, as some of the philosophers posited. Indeed, this view seems so reasonable that the most excellent of the philosophers, Aristotle, fell into this error, at least as the saints impute it to him, his commentators expound him, and his own words indicate. 17 36 Saint Bonaventure, Commentarius in II librum Sententiarum, tom. 2 of Opera theologica selecta, ed. Patres Collegii S. Bonaventurae, ed. minor (Florentiae ad Claras Aquas: Collegium Sancti Bonaventurae, 1938), d. 1, pars 1, art. 1, q. 1 (II: 10b-11a). ·17 "Et magis rationabile est quam suum oppositum, scilicet quod materia fuerit aeternaliter imperfecta, sine forma et divina influentia, sicut posuerunt quidam philosophorum; et adeo rationabilius, ut etiam ille excellentior inter philosophos, Aristoteles, secundum quod Sancti imponunt, et commentatores exponunt, et verba eius praetendunt, in hunc errorem dilapsus fuerit" (Saint Bonaventure, In II Sent., lib. II, d. 1, pars 1, art. 1, q. 2, resp. [ed. minor, II: !Sb]). ST. THOMAS ON PHILOSOPHERS AND CREATION 293 Yet the most striking feature of Bonaventure's account of philosophers is the manner in which he juxtaposes the doctrine of creation, as he understands it, with the philosophical theory of origins. According to Bonaventure, only two theories regarding the origin of the cosmos are really tenable: first, the theory of the philosophers according to which the world is eternal and the matter of the universe is without ultimate causal origin; second, the Christian doctrine of creation according to which the universe depends entirely for its being on God, is produced ex nihi'lo, and is temporally finite in the past. The third possibility, namely that the world is both produced ex nihilo and eternal, Bonaventure vehemently rejects on the grounds that such a position is inherently contradictory: We must reply that to posit that the world is eternal or eternally produced, while positing likewise that all things have been produced ex nihilo, is altogether opposed to the truth and reason, just as the last reason stated [in the ad oppositum] showed. Indeed, it is so opposed to reason that I do not believe any philosopher, however small his intellectual abilities, took this position. For this involves, in itself, an obvious contradiction. To posit, however, that the world is eternal on the supposition that matter is eternal seems reasonable and understandable ... :'" Returning to the last argument in the ad oppositum, we find the argument to which Bonaventure refers. The argument is an elegant synthesis and restatement of the position of Parisian theologians since the time of William of Auxerre, but is especially indebted to the Quaestiones of Alexander of Hales. Everything that depends entirely for its being on something else is produced by that thing ex nihilo. The world depends entirely for its being '18 "Respondeo: Dicendum quod ponere mundum aeternum esse sive aeternaliter productum, ponendo res omnes ex nihilo productas, omnino est contra veritatem et rationem, sicut ultima ratio probat; et adeo contra rationem, ut nullum philosophorum quantumcumque parvi intellectus crediderim hoc posuisse. Hoc enim implicat in se manifestam contradictionem. -Ponere autem mundum aeternum, praesupposita aeternitate materiae, rationabile videtur et intelligibile ... "(Saint Bonaventure, In II Sent,, d, 1, pars 1, art. 1, q, 2, Resp, [ed, minor, II: lSa]), For the proper interpretation of Bonaventure's position on creation and the eternity of the world, see Stephen Baldner, "SL Bonaventure on the Temporal Beginning of the World," The New Scholasticism 63 (1989): 206-28. 294 TIMOTHY B. NOONE on God. Hence, the world must be produced ex nihilo. If the world is produced ex nihilo, it must either arise out of the nihil as out of matter or out of the nihil as out of a point of origin. The world cannot arise out of nihil as out of matter. Thus the world must arise out of nihil as out of a point of origin. If, however, the world arises out of nihil as out of a point of origin, then the world has being after non-being. Nothing having being after non-being can be eternal. The world, as a created thing, has being after non-being. Therefore, the world, precisely as created ex nihilo, cannot be eternal:'" Before exammmg, then, the texts of St. Thomas's Commentary on the Sentences, we may characterize the tradition that St. Thomas inherited in the following way. There was considerable disagreement among St. Thomas's predecessors about how to interpret the recently received philosophical literature regarding the philosophical theory of universe's origin. Some, led by such figures as Robert Grosseteste and William of Auvergne, thought that the philosophers believed in an eternal universe that arose from several distinct co-eternal principles, one of which was God. Others, such as Philip the Chancellor and Alexander of Hales, doubted that Aristotle ever meant to claim that the world was eternal; rather, he simply adduced proofs that the world could not have arisen out of a process of natural gen" 9 Saint Bonaventure, In II Sent., d. 1, pars 1, art. 1, q. 2 (ed. minor, 15a): " ... impossibile est, quod habet esse post non-esse habere esse aeternum, quoniam hie est implicatio contradictionis; sed mundus habet esse post non-esse; ergo impossibile est esse aeternum. Quod autem habeat esse post non-esse, probatur sic: omne illud quod totaliter habet esse ab aliquo, producitur ab illo ex nihilo; sed mundus totaliter habet esse a Deo; ergo mundus ex nihilo; sed non ex nihilo materialiter; ergo originaliter. Quod autem omne quod totaliter producitur ab aliquo differente per essentiam, habeat esse ex nihilo, patens est. Nam quod totaliter producitur, producitur secundum materiam et formam; sed materia non habet ex quo producatur, quia non ex Deo; manifestum est igitur quod ex nihilo." The term "after" needs to be carefully understood here; "after" does not function as a temporal designator since we are explaining, in part, the very origin of time itself. Bonaventure himself prefers the locution that things are created with time (see Bonaventure, In II Sent., d. 2, p. 1, dub. 2 [ed. minor, 61]). The philosophical force of the expression that there be a logical moment at which we could say that the world is not and with reference to which the world begins to be. The ontological reference of such a logical moment is the divine eternity with respect to which (after which) the world begins. ST. THOMAS ON PHILOSOPHERS AND CREATION 295 eration. Still others, such as Richard Rufus and St. Albert, took up the second more benign interpretation, but emphasized that the philosophers had posited God as the Cause and Source of all things. Yet there is a point of common agreement among all these writers. They are agreed that the philosophers did not posit creation and they are agreed as to why. The philosophers cannot be construed as positing a doctrine of creation because the notion of creation involves the coming to be of something out of nothing, which is universally understood to mean that the created thing must acquire being after non-being; whereas the philosophers' universe is a beginningless universe, a universe wherein things besides the First Principle have always existed. Bearing in mind this understanding of the doctrinal tradition prior to Aquinas, let us turn to his earliest major theological work to see how his doctrine differs from theirs. IV. THOMAS AQUINAS: IN II SENT. (1253) If we turn to the fifth article, question 1 of distinction 1, Book II of Aquinas's Commentary on the Sentences, we find Aquinas raising the same issue St. Bonaventure did in his second question, namely, whether the world is eternal. Thomas's presentation of the philosophers, here, is similar to that of his predecessors; following Moses Maimonides's Guide of the Perplexed, 40 Aquinas arranges the arguments of the philosophers under different headings representing the basis of their various proofs. Even Thomas's answer to the question is not without some anticipation in previous writers: like Bonaventure, Thomas commends Aristotle's opinion among those advanced by philosophers, but rejects all the philosophical opinions on the subject of 40 Moses Maimonides, Guide of the Perplexed, trans. Shlomo Pines (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1963) II, c. 14 (II, 285-89); on Maimonides's position regarding creation, see the two excellent articles of William Dunphy, "Maimonides and Aquinas on Creation: A Critique of Their Historians,'' in Gerson, ed., Graceful Reason, 361-79, and "Maimonides' Not-So-Secret Position on Creation,'' Moses Maimonides and His Time, ed. Eric L. Ormsby, vol. 19 of Studies in Philosophy and the History of Philosophy, ed. Jude P. Dougherty (Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of America Press, 1989), 151-72. 296 TIMOTHY B. NOONE the eternity of the world as false and heretical 41 ; like Albert, Thomas defends the position that belief that the world began is not demonstrable by reason and must be held by faith. 42 Indeed, the originality of St. Thomas's presentation here seems to consist in the clear and straightforward manner in which he contrasts the philosophical views positing the eternity of the world and the theologians claiming that creatio de novo is demonstrable by reason as two extremes to his own view, cast in the role of the mean. Yet Aquinas's way of relating the philosophical account of the origin of the universe to the doctrine in the Sentences is quite original, as is seen in the second of the articles in the same question. The title of the article asks the question whether something can come forth from the First Principle in the manner of creation. After listing five arguments denying, for a variety of reasons, that creation is possible, Aquinas gives his startling response. Creation, he claims, is not only held on faith but demonstrable by reason. Knowing that Aquinas is chary in his the sophisticated and use of the term 'demonstration'-witness well-reasoned arguments on behalf of the eternity and non-eternity of the world that he denies to be demonstrations-we should pay close attention here to why he believes creation to be demonstrable. His reasoning is that the things in the world are akin to items in a genus that imperfectly possess a generic quality, like the way that items that are hot, according to medieval physics, imperfectly and incompletely possess the quality of heat found per se and completely in the element of fire. Similarly, each 41 Thomas Aquinas, Scriptum super libros Sententiarum magistri Petri Lombardi episcopi Parisiensis: Commentum in I I librum, ed. P. Mandonnet and M. F. Moos (Paris: P. Lethielleux, 1929), d. 1, q. 1, a. 5, sol. (II: 33): "Alii dixerunt quod res fuerunt ab aeterno secundum ilium ordinem quo modo sunt; et ista est opinio Aristotelis, et omnium philosophorum sequentium ipsum; et haec opinio inter praedictas probabilior est: tamen omnes sunt falsae et haereticae."; Saint Bonaventure, In II Sent., d. 1, pars 1, art. 1, q. 1 (II: 1 la): "ideo et ipse [sc. Aristoteles) etiam deficit, Iicet minus quam alii." 42 Thomas Aquinas, In II Sent., d. 1, q. 1, a. 5 (ed. Mandonnet-Moos, II: 33): "Tertia positio est dicentium quod omne quod est praeter Deum incepit esse; sed tamen mundum incepisse non potuit demonstrari, sed per revelationem divinam esse habitum et creditum .... Et huic positioni consentio: quia non credo, quod a nobis possit sumi ratio demonstrativa ad hoc ... "; Albertus Magnus, In II Sent., d. 1, B, art. 10, sol. (ed. Borgnet, 27): "Absque dubio nihil probabilius etiam secundum rationem est, quam quod mundus inceperit, sicut dixit Moyses, et hoc fide tenendum." ST. THOMAS ON PHILOSOPHERS AND CREATION 297 and every being in our experience participates, according to the measure of its being, in the act of being (esse) and is thus, in respect of the act of being, something imperfect. Therefore, there must exist a Primal and Perfect Being from which each and every thing arises. But for something to be produced according to the entirety of its being is for something to be created. Thus, all things must arise from the First Principle by way of creation. 43 In short, what Aquinas gives as his demonstration of creation is a brief sketch of the proof for the existence of God eventually to be seen as an alia ratio in the Summa contra gentiles and the quarta via of the Summa theologiae.44 Upon first reading Aquinas's text, one may be inclined to think that St. Thomas has achieved a tremendous economy in both proving the existence of God and the truth of the doctrine of creation in one fell swoop. After some further reflection, however, one may well grow suspicious and question the legitimacy of the whole enterprise. How, after all, can a proof for the existence of God be considered the basis for inferring that the world was created? The answer to this question lies, of course, in what Aquinas understands to be the doctrine of creation, a matter to which he devotes the remainder of the article's solution. According to Aquinas, two points belong to the notion (ratio) of creation. First, creation, unlike any other change, presupposes nothing in the thing created, neither matter nor subject. Second, in the thing created non-being is prior to being, not in the sense that there is any priority of duration, but in the sense that there is a priority of nature; if the created thing were left to its own devices, so to speak, it would cease to be. In light of these two features of creation, one may say that the created order comes to be out of nothing (ex nihilo) in two ways. The negative, nihil, denies that the ordinary notion of subject applies; in other Thomas Aquinas, In II Sent., d. 1, q. 1, a. 2 (ed. Mandonnet-Moos, II: 18). See Thomas Aquinas, Liber de veritate catholicaefidei contra errores infidelium seu 'Summa contra gentiles,' ed. Celsai Pera, D. Petro Marc, and D. Petro Caramello (Turin; Rome: Marietti, 1961), lib. I, cap. 13 (20: para. 114); Summa theologiae, ed. Inst. stud. med. Ottaviensis (Ottawa: Commissio Piana, 1948), I, q. 2, a. 3, resp. (14b). 43 44 298 TIMOTHY B. NOONE words, created things come to be out of nothing in that they come to be out of no pre-existing subject. In another way, ex nihilo signifies that the ordination of created things to nothing remains even after they are created, for each created thing more naturally possesses non-being than being, since its being is ab alio whereas non-being belongs to it per se.45 Now what is perhaps most remarkable is the way Aquinas concludes this account of creation. At the beginning of this paragraph, Aquinas had begun quite magisterially in the indicative mood by stating ad rationem creationis pertinent duo; he concludes with the following comments: And if these two points would suffice [su.fficiant] for the notion of creation, then creation can be demonstrated and in this way the philosophers have posited creation. If, however,we should accept [accipiamus] a third point as required for the doctrine of creation, namely that the created thing have being after non-being with respect to duration, in such a way that it can be said to be out of nothing because it is in time after nothing, then creation cannot be demonstrated, nor is it granted by the philosophers; but it is rather supposed by the faith.46 Aquinas has now shifted to the subjunctive mood. Creation is knowable by reason, if the two points or notes that Aquinas just explained are considered sufficient. If, however, one adds the notion, much emphasized by his contemporaries and reaffirmed by the Church at Fourth Lateran Council, that the created thing is of finite temporal duration ex parte ante, then creation is not knowable by reason and philosophy. Clearly, Aquinas's hesitation concerns what one includes in the notion of creation. There can be little doubt, however, that, of the three points mentioned as constituents of the doctrine of creation, the first two are the ones that are essential; they are the ones that Aquinas unwaveringly affirms belong to the very notion of creation. Aquinas, In II Sent., d. 1, q. 1, a. 2 (ed. Mandonnet-Moos, II: 18). et si haec duo sufficiant ad rationem creationis, sic creatio potest demonstrari, et sic philosophi creationem posuerunt. Si autem accipiamus tertium oportere ad rationem creationis, ut scilicet etiam duratione res creata prius non-esse quam esse habeat, ut dicatur esse ex nihilo, quia est tempore post nihil, sic creatio demonstrari non potest, nee a philosophis conceditur, sed per fidem supponitur" (Thomas Aquinas, In II Sent., d. 1, q. 1, a. 2 [ed. Mandonnet-Moos, II: 18]). 45 Thomas 46 " ••• ST. THOMAS ON PHILOSOPHERS AND CREATION 299 Viewed against the historical background sketched earlier, Aquinas's doctrine of creation, as it embraces the two essential notes, is quite unique and novel. The emphasis among earlier theologians, especially Parisian theologians, was that ex nihilo entailed being after non-being; as Bonaventure so aptly stated it, the world came out of nothing as out of a point of origin. Aquinas recasts the doctrine of creation in such a way as to interpret the ex nihilo not to imply the need for finite duration in the past on the part of the creature, but to express the nature of creaturely being: left to themselves created things would resolve into nothing since the source of their actuality and existence is outside themselves. Aquinas's account of the philosophers in the Sentences, on the other hand, does not seem to be that original, as we saw above. Consequently, based on an examination of the historical evidence reviewed here, we must conclude that Aquinas's originality in the matter of the knowability of creation on the part of philosophers relies much more on his own reinterpretation, not to say reformulation, of the doctrine of creation than in any profoundly novel reading of the philosophers. Yet in a sense the conclusion reached is incorrect. For we seem on the verge of missing Aquinas's whole point. Although we might say that Aquinas's claim that the philosophers know creation amounts to a truism once he has redefined, to his own satisfaction, the doctrine of creation, we should ask, if we are really to understand his position, why he is so willing to reformulate the doctrine of creation and why he thinks that the philosophical proofs of the First Principle are tantamount to admissions of the doctrine of creation. The answer to both these questions is given by Aquinas in the texts we have reviewed. The heart of creation is total ontological dependence, not temporal finitude. Aquinas consciously and deliberately brings to bear his doctrine of being in an effort to explain what that dependence means. Likewise, the philosophers posit a First Principle to account for the universe of beings. Whether they realize it or not, they are positing a God, a Being Itself, upon which every other thing depends at each and every moment; they are positing not just a cause, as Richard Rufus thought, but a Creator. What Aquinas seems to be engaged in when he grants philosophers knowledge of ere- 300 TIMOTHY B. NOONE ation is not simply a restatement of the doctrine of creation, but a lectio humilis; he is, in effect, granting to their metaphysical theories of being precisely that notion of being that he himself thought so obvious. What of the questions raised at the beginning of this paper? Does Aquinas's acumen consist in perceiving a doctrine of creation in the philosophical texts unnoticed by his contemporaries? Certainly not; his discovery of creation in the texts of the philosophers is more a function of his revamping and nuancing the notion of creation than in any unique textual interpretation or historical insight. Hence there both is and is not originality in Aquinas's interpretation of the philosophers. There is no originality in that Aquinas seems to know just about as much (or as little) about the philosophers as his contemporaries and attributes to them fundamentally the same doctrines; there is great originality in that Aquinas, blessedly ignorant of the historical genesis of the philosophers' thought, is reading their doctrines in terms of a quite different metaphysical outlook. ENVIRONMENTAL THEOLOGYA REVIEW DISCUSSION* KEVIN W. IRWIN l The Catholic University of America Washington, D.C. UST OVER a decade ago the Norwegian philosopher Arne Naess coined the term deep ecology to encapsulate his challenge that while others have dealt with short-term views of ure and ways of dealing with the ecological crisis, 1 he urged a deeper probing of "why, how and where" educational systems, religious bodies, and societies themselves can deal with environ- * The books under discussion are: Leonardo Boff, Ecologia, Mundializacao, Espiritualidade (Sao Paolo: Editora Atica, 1993), English translation by John Cuming, Ecology and Liberation: A New Paradigm (Maryknoll: Orbis, 1995); Denis Edwards, Jesus the Wisdom of God: An Ecological Theology (Maryknoll: Orbis, 1995); Catharina J. M. Halkes, New Creation: Christian Feminism and the Renewal of the Earth, trans. C. Romanik (Louisville: Westminster/John Knox Press, 1991); Michael J. Himes and Kenneth R. Himes, Fullness of Faith: The Public Significance of Theology (New York/Mahwah: Paulist Press, 1993), especially chapter 5, "Creation and an Environmental Ethic"; Tony Kelly, An Expanding Theology: Faith in a World of Connections (Newtowne: E. J. Dwyer, 1993); Richard N. Fragomeni and John T. Pawlikowski, eds., The Ecological Challenge: Ethical, Liturgical and Spiritual Responses (Collegeville: The Liturgical Press, 1994); Albert J. LaChance and John E. Carroll, eds., Embracing Earth: Catholi.c Approaches to Ecology (Maryknoll: Orbis, 1994); Sean McDonagh, The Greening of the Church (London: G. Chapman; Maryknoll: Orbis, 1990); and Passion for the Earth: The Christian Vocation to Promote Justice, Peace and the Integrity of Creation (London: G. Chapman; Maryknoll: Orbis, 1994). 1 From the outset it is important to clarify terminology and to indicate the meaning of some terms used in this review. In accord with common usage we understand that the term "ecology" (from the Greek oikos, "home") refers to our being at home on the earth, and "ecological crisis" refers to the destruction that has been worked to make the earth/home less inhabitable for a variety of species. "Creation" refers to the whole created world and all living beings as gifts from God the creator. "Environment" refers to the life context in which we live, our habitat as given to us by God and for which we are responsible. 301 302 KEVIN W. IRWIN mental deterioration and devastation.2 That Roman Catholicism has an important contribution to make to this issue 3 is clear from recent magisterial statements as well as from the theological literature under review here. For example, in 1990 John Paul II articulated a number of avenues from within the Catholic tradition that relate to the ecological crisis and the Church's corporate responsibility to face it theologically, spiritually, and practically.4 In 1991 the U.S. bishops issued a more focused document, Renewing the Earth, which was drawn largely from the Church's social teaching tradition. 5 The purpose of this article is to review some recent Roman Catholic theological literature in English (originally or recently translated) on environmental theology and ethics that can be understood as deep ecology from within mainstream Catholic thought. The contention of these authors is that the ecological crisis is a matter of theology, ethics, and values. Not surprisingly, given the comparative infancy of Catholicism's theological contribution to this issue, these works include collections of essays with a variety of approaches of varying quality, monographs that deal with the issue with greater methodological pre2 "Intuition, Intrinsic Value, and Deep Ecology," The Ecologist 14 (Sept./Oct., 1984): 56; also see Devall Bill and George Sessions, Deep Ecology (Layton, Utah: Gibbs Smith, 1985). 3 It is important to note that other Christian faith traditions have offered pertinent and challenging statements on this issue, especially the Orthodox. See, for example, the statement by Patriarch Dimitrios, Orthodoxy and the Ecological Crisis (Geneva: Ecumenical Patriarchate, 1990). 4 See "Peace with God the Creator, Peace with All of Creation," Origins 19 (Dec. 14, 1989): 465-68. This is but one example of John Paul's voice on this issue, which is not univocal. Among other statements, his 1993 Lenten Message is particularly interesting in the way it addresses the devastation caused by "uncontrolled industrial development and the use of technologies which disrupt the balance of nature [that] have caused serious damage to the environment and caused grave disasters." He cites specifically the lack of potable water and the expansion of the desert "to lands which only yesterday were prosperous and fertile." For perspectives on John Paul's writings on the environment, see Daniel Cowdin, "John Paul II and Environmental Concern: Problems and Possibilities," The Living Light 28:1 (Fall, 1991): 44-52 and Peter C. Phan, "Pope John Paul II and the Ecological Crisis," Irish Theological Quarterly 60:4 (1994): 333-38. 5 "An Invitation to Reflection and Action on the Environment in Light of Catholic Social Teaching," Nov. 14, 1991, text in Origins 21(Dec.12, 1991): 425-32. ENVIRONMENTAL THEOLOGY 303 cision and theological substance, and works of a pastoral-theological-spiritual nature that speak to the need for integrating theory, practice, and worldview so that ecology is appreciated as intrinsic to Catholic faith and life as well as theology. That a diversity of approaches to environmental theology and ethics exists in Catholic theological literature today is evident in the comprehensive collection of essays, Embracing Earth. If American ecologist Eugene Odum is correct that ecology is the study of organisms "at home," and as intrinsically interrelated, interconnected, and interdependent, then a chief contribution of this book is the way an ecological theology and vision is espoused as integral and integrating of a number of aspects of Catholic life and theology. The book's early chapters emphasizing the interrelatedness of God, creation, and humanity lead to more thoughtful essays on human productivity (Richard Haas, "A Loaves and Fishes View of Productivity") and "appropriate" technology (Albert Fritsch, "Appropriate Technology and Healing the Earth"). Both articles are thoroughly Catholic in that their world views embrace such seemingly diverse aspects of life as economics, sexual morality, and the Eucharist (Haas), and liturgy, technology, and the world's many nations as intrinsically interconnected (Fritsch). What would have enhanced this latter argument would have been some discussion of the equally compelling Catholic characteristics of the way the liturgy itself uses things that are the result of human ingenuity and technology (for example, church buildings and the eucharistic bread and wine) and of how a broad notion of sacramentality grounds liturgical participation in the seven sacraments. Gratefully, some of these issues surface and are developed in the essay that follows ("Eating the Body of the Lord" by Marc Boucher-Colbert), which stresses the fundamentally communal aspects of farming and liturgical participation-themes that lead to the challenge that "we cannot poison our land and our food [and] remain aloof from agriculture and expect to find a profound ecological meaning in the eucharist" (12 7). The rootedness of the eucharistic species through human productivity from the fruit of the earth is worth recalling in this regard. 304 KEVIN W. IRWIN The breadth of Catholic spiritual traditions and what they can contribute to ecology is indicated in helpful essays on St. Francis (R. Rohr and K. Warner), St. Benedict (T. Kardong), and the Spiritual Exercises of St. Ignatius Loyola (W. Wood). Of these the most "contemplative" (in the sense of offering a way to "see" creation as the Lord's) is from R. Rohr. T. Kardong asserts that more is said indirectly than directly about ecology in the Rule of St. Benedict. The key assertion that harmony of oneself with, not against, the world, however, is a chief characteristic of Benedictinism (164) and deserves fuller treatment; this would complement his helpful statements linking ecology with characteristics of the monastic life: humility, stability, and frugality. An additional exploration into the intrinsic linkage of work, prayer, and the common life--characteristic of a Benedictine vision of life-would be another avenue worth pursuing. 6 Similarly, the contribution on the Spiritual Exercises to this issue seems diminished in the White essay, since it is focused on the cosmic Christ. Further probing of the Ignatian corpus might yield a richer harvest of insight on creation and the environment more generally. Finally, even though Wayne Teasdale's essay is entitled' "Concluding Reflections," his article is a most provocative foray into ways in which the Church might deepen its commitment to this issue in the already established forum of interreligious dialogue (notably through the East-West monastic dialogue) and the Parliament of the World's Religions, specifically the concluding statement from its 1993 meeting entitled Towards a Global Ethic. 1 The Ecological Challenge is a much more focused collection of essays that helpfully fill in areas often neglected in recent literature on the environment. Thus the benefit of D. Bergant's essay on Hosea 2 is that it presents an integral rereading of Genesis in 6 The brief statement from St. Benedict's Rule, chapter 32, that the person chosen by the abbot as cellarer of the monastery should "regard all the utensils and goods of the monastery as sacred vessels of the altar" summarizes the kind of integral vision of life interwoven throughout the entire Rule. 7 In this connection some reference to the helpful statement of Cardinal Joseph Bernardin to that assembly held in Chicago Aug. 28-Sept. 5 1993 would have enhanced this section. ENVIRONMENTAL THEOLOGY 305 which ideas of "stewardship," "dominion," and the unity of all created beings (not just humans alone) are helpfully nuanced. 8 Two particularly important essays of a general nature include that of Thomas Nairn about contemporary Roman Catholic social thought on ecology and that of John Pawlikowski exemplifying the helpful rediscovery of the integration of systematic theology with ethics. This integration serves both theology in general and ecological theology in particular where theology and ethics are partners. The most focused and precise essay from the theology derived from the celebration of the Eucharist concerns "the preparatory rites" (formerly the "offertory") by E. Foley, K. Hughes, and G. Ostdiek. This article succeeds as a careful historical and theological study of the nature of these rites and a helpful critique of the present Roman liturgy. One additional avenue for creative critique of the present rite might have been derived from research into contemporary practices from parts of the Catholic Church that emphasize or have adapted this rite (e.g., Africa) or from other Christian churches, specifically the (American) Lutheran Book of Worship, which (paradoxically) gives greater emphasis on the gifts presented by the sung anthem "Let the Vineyards Be Fruitful." In line with the Pawlikowski essay in The Ecological Challenge on integrating theology and ethics is the keenly insightful and methodologically helpful work Fullness of Faith: The Public Significance of Theology by Michael and Kenneth Himes. The first chapter on "the Public Church and Public Theology" sets the agenda and method for what follows about creation and an environmental ethic (chapter five). A chief aim of "public theology" is to move religious belief away from a narrow concern with personal life to serve the church's mission to the wider realm of society and social existence. The distinctive contribution of Catholicism to public theology and policy according to the authors is to make "explicit the theological component of social ethics so that believers can understand and test 8 Most notable in this connection is the ground-breaking study by Robert Murray, The Cosmic Covenant: Biblical Themes of Justice, Peace and the Integrity of Creation, Heythrop Monograph Series, 7 (London: Sheed and Ward, 1992). 306 KEVIN W. IRWIN the coherence of their religious beliefs with their public policy decisions" (23). The chapter of Fullness of Faith on "Creation and an Environmental Ethic" is true to the authors' intent to raise questions and demonstrate the interrelationship of theology and ethics. Here they support the move away from viewing creation through "instrumental rationality" toward retrieving the biblical view of "relational anthropology." To regard all creatures as "thou" forms the basis for the theological themes of "companionship," "a sacramental vision" of the world, "an ethic rooted in sacramentality," "constructing an environmental ethic," "ecology, justice and economic development," "sustainable development,'' and "the right attitude [for] seeing the world" (124). Hence a theologically inspired vision of creation and the world can "revision all beings as united in their creatureliness, given to one another as companions, sacraments of the 'love that loves the sun and other stars' (Dante)." Here a lucid and penetrating analysis is accompanied by a truly sacramental vision of all of life and a requisite ethic about reverencing all of its forms. The brevity of this work (one chapter among seven) is its limitation. One can only hope that the authors draw out more fully in a monograph what they have so successfully undertaken here. The most substantial and thorough contributions to method in environmental theology and ethics under review here are by two Australians, Tony Kelly and Denis Edwards. An Expanding Theology by Tony Kelly is thoroughly researched and documented (almost all are English language sources), clear in intent, scope, and outline. Sometimes rather tersely written, this work is modest in size yet rich in insight about a method for theology that embraces the centrality of environmental issues and that articulates connections from the Catholic theological tradition that can influence the combining of environmental theology and ethics. Kelly ascribes the "thinness of the modern theologies of ecology and creation" to a "theological reinvention of the wheel . . . without taking into account ... past achievements" (xii). Kelly relies on a significant number of theological forebears of many stripes (both classical and contemporary). He also willingly admits the strengths and weaknesses of some key Catholic voic- ENVIRONMENTAL THEOLOGY 307 es, Aquinas for example, and invites continued dialogue with such theological mentors about ecology and the environment. For Kelly, a characteristic strength of Roman Catholic theology throughout history has been its ability to reread and rethink its traditional beliefs in the light of contemporary issues, challenges, and pastoral needs. Thus he begins his work by stating that the environmental crisis offers the challenge of remaking and making connections among faith, theology, creation, and ecology-hence the book's subtitle, "faith in a world of connections" and its structure as a "spiral of connections" (213) that include: the import of making connections itself; contemporary contexts for theology; the Logos in the cosmos; working from within the theology of creation itself (as a Catholic hallmark); the human being in the world; the Trinity as center of Christian faith; the eucharistic universe; and the specifically human dimensions of death and love. The breadth and depth of the section on "making connections" bespeaks a firm grasp of the way Catholic theology discloses and betrays a keen sense of the integral and unified understanding of the world, of God's pervasive presence in it, and of the need to articulate these connections for the sake of contemporary theology-especially theological method-and for Catholic life and practice. This section also offers a paradigm of the way Kelly converses with and articulates important insights from contemporary philosophy and (what he terms) "the new science." Kelly is careful and judicious both in making distinctions, for example, of how humanity relates to but is not on the same level as the rest of creation in the cosmos (in section five), and in critiquing popular movements that attempt to engage the ecologically minded, specifically New Age and "pathological holism" (in section two). An invitational stance imbues his treatment of the Word, creation, and human beings wherein he relies on the work of others, articulates his own keen insights, and opens the door for further elaboration by others. Less successful because of brevity, but still most insightful and rich, are the sections on Trinity, eucharist, and death and love. The section on the Trinity is the briefest, but remarkably profound in that here Kelly argues for a relational theology of God that leads toward the cen- 308 KEVIN W. IRWIN tral theological insight that "ultimate reality is relational" and that the relationships within the Trinity image and invite the communion of all creation in the Godhead. 9 Having made other important observations on sacramentality and liturgy earlier on in the book, it is lamentable that the eucharistic section derives more from others' than from Kelly's own thought. Here some fuller explication of sacramentality could help fill out this otherwise significant chapter. Perhaps the most important contribution which Kelly makes here is to invite other theologians to rethink the shape of theological method, the conventional separations among theological disciplines, especially the nature and place of the theology of creation, and to see the environment as an integrating force for Christian theology today. Kelly's aim here is to probe the breadth of theology as seen from an environmental perspective and not to construct a "theology of ecology." Taking up this challenge is made the more challenging and urgent because of the publication of this book. Edwards's book, Jesus the Wisdom of God: An Ecological Theology, consists of three parts: "Jesus of Nazareth as the Wisdom of God"; "The Trinitarian God and Creation"; and "Human Beings in the Community of Creatures. 1110 In some ways it follows up on Kelly's work by explicating the intrinsic relationship between the Catholic theological tradition and (what he terms) "ecological praxis." He is concerned to probe the "profound inner link between an adequate theology and an ecological stance" and argues that "theology is necessarily ecological" (3). From the outset he states that the ecological issue "is not just about flora and fauna, but is also a people ... justice issue" (4). At the same time he will argue that "the truths of Christian faith push us beyond anthropocentrism to an ethics of intrinsic value" (10). A careful balancing of these theological polarities marks 9 Something of the same argument can be gleaned in Fullness of Faith, chapters 3 and 7. ' 0 The table of contents does not indicate the separation between parts two and three nor does it list the title of the third part. Correcting this editorial oversight in any succeeding printings would be helpful. ENVIRONMENTAL THEOLOGY 309 this book; at times, however, their integration could be more forcefully presented. By intention this book is more focused than Kelly's work on theological method in general. Edwards 's work is a straightforward and clear argument from wisdom Christology to an economic theology of the Trinity to the human participation in the community of creatures to ecological praxis. (One detects here the seminal insights of Jiirgen Moltmann.) In Part One, Edwards argues from the wisdom tradition in the Bible, through wisdom Christology to "wisdom ecology." In the process he summarizes (and carefully documents) main points of the retrieval of wisdom Christology in (English-language) theological literature today. His aim is to suggest how proper exegesis of scriptural texts about Christ, notably Jn. 1:1-18 and Col. 1:15-20, indicate the important link between wisdom Christology and a cosmic Christology, where the transformation of the universe is through Jesus, the wisdom of God. In Part Two, Edwards picks up on the Trinitarian theme frequently reflected in the current theological literature on the environment (exemplified in many of the works under review here) and does so in a compelling and substantive way. Here he draws fully and richly from Richard of St. Victor (specifically, the Trinity as mutual love) and Bonaventure (the universe as God's self-expression) to substantiate his central thesis that wisdom Christology leads necessarily to an economic Trinitarian theology that leads to an integral notion of Christian theology, ecology, and praxis. The import of this argument is significant in that through it Edwards gives substance and offers nuances to the now commonplace assertion that the themes of mutuality, relationship, and intimacy among persons that characterize much economic Trinitarian theology can well ground-if not compelthe move toward a view that Trinitarian theology and ecological theology converge. Edwards's discussion of Richard of St. Victor and Bonaventure (chapter four) leads to a significant delineation of "some theses" for an economic theology of the Trinity (chapter five). In Part Three, Edwards moves to a consideration of "human participation in the community of persons" and the relationship 310 KEVIN W. IRWIN among science, theology, and the future of the universe, with important reference to contemporary developments in cosmology (chapter six), and then to the final chapter on ecological praxis. Here he argues for the intrinsic value of all creatures and reverence for all life. In a very important section (termed "ecological sustainability") he urges the necessary commitment "to an ecologically sustainable economic and political system and to a lifestyle congruent with sustainability" (163).11 This section contains a brief but important articulation of the criterion that the discernment between competing interests of different species "is that of the level of consciousness of the creatures involved" (161). With regard to depth and substance, Edwards 's book is an important contribution. It is focused and complete. It also exemplifies what can be undertaken by others who wish to probe the Catholic theological tradition more fully about creation and the environment. The linear progression from scriptures through the arguments of theologians to ethics is exemplary. At the same time the book's clear focus may also be its weakness, that is, it is so Christological and Trinitarian that other theological themes are not explored. For example, while he states at the outset that he "will not be able to deal at all with other aspects of theology, such as the theology of church and the sacraments, which clearly are relevant to an ecological theology" (14), it is surprising and disappointing that these precise aspects of Christian theology are absent from his compelling critique of individualism and the requisite move to a conception of persons-in-mutual-relationship (chapter six). In fact, ecclesiology and theology derived from the celebration of sacraments would provide strong theological arguments to substantiate this counter-cultural thesis. This may be asking for a theological encyclopedia on environmental theology, however, rather than respecting a significant monograph that goes far beyond the limitations of collections of essays. Jesus the Wisdom of God is an important contribution toward a truly 11 One of the few theologians to deal with this issue, often argued (or posited) in ecological circles, is John Cobb, Sustainability: Economics, Ecology and Justice (Maryknoll: Orbis, 1992). Also see, John Cobb and Herman E. Daly, For the Common Good: Redirecting the Economy toward Community, the Environment, and a Sustainable Future (Boston: Beacon Press, 1989). ENVIRONMENTAL THEOLOGY 311 substantial theology and ethics grounded in the theology of creation and reverence for the environment. In ecological literature in general and in theological literature about the environment, feminist voices have been clear, challenging, and compelling. One particularly useful work is New Creation: Christian Feminism and the Renewal of the Earth by Catharina J.M. Halkes (emeritus professor, Catholic University of Nijmegen). Written in part as a response to the World Council of Churches' appeal for a world-wide conciliar process to reconsider the meaning of justice, peace, and the becoming-whole of creation in 1990, Halkes 's book draws on both American and European ecological and feminist thought. In Part One, designed as a prelude to the theological arguments in Part 1\vo, she discusses the relationship of nature and woman from diverse, principally philosophical, points of view. In chapters seven and eight (the beginning of Part 1\vo) she offers a theology of creation that leads to her approach to ecological theology. Her nuanced observations about the nature of God and God's relatedness to creation are worth further reflection. She observes that "the onesided God transcending the world has led to deism ... the overemphasis on God's immanence in the world has led to pantheism ... [where] everything becomes deified" (91). Hence the need for a more nuanced approach which she terms the "sacramentalization" of the world. (Others argue for a panentheism.) Common perspectives on feminist theology and the ecological movement are discussed in chapter nine. Of particular note is the treatment of insights for theological anthropology in chapter ten derived from the convergence of ecological and feminist theology, which discussion is prefaced by reference to George Tavard 's insight that the starting point for Christian anthropology is humankind as it now is, not as it is imaged in the scriptures (128). Thus the transition from exegesis to contemporary theological movements that inform her thought about the need for greater interrelatedness among the earth's species, a deepening sense of community and humankind's "receptivity, and (another insight derived from Tavard) humankind's openness to the sanctifying and fulfilling work of the Holy Spirit (137). 312 KEVIN W. IRWIN The original publication date of 1989 is to be noted since much of the terrain covered here has been traversed more deeply in the meantime by others (some already discussed here) which indicates the maturing going on in theological circles on this issue. What makes this work unique is its reference to a wealth of philosophical sources, classical and contemporary, and its concern to deal with themes from the theology of creation in dialogue with currents in contemporary culture. Leonardo Boff's contribution Ecology and Liberation is comprised of three parts entitled "Ecology: A New Paradigm,'' "From Ecology to Global Consciousness,'' and "From World Consciousness to Mysticism." 12 The key insight throughout is that "ecology has to do with relations, interaction, and dialogue of all living creatures ... among themselves and with all that exists. This includes not only nature (natural ecology) but culture and society (human ecology, social ecology, ... ). From an ecological viewpoint everything that exists, co-exists"(7). Boff engagingly offers insights about a wealth of human experience and new fields of learning to demonstrate his passion for just such an interaction. Without a proper theology of creation in Catholic theology he poignantly asserts that "we tend to exaggerate the importance of the Bible (fundamentalism), inflate the role of the church (ecclesiocentrism), and exaggerate the function of the sacraments (sacramentalism)" (47). Further on he observes that theological thinking must be seen in passionate commitment to social justice, which for him is broader than relations among persons. It concerns the relations among all creatures in and with God. In Part Two Boff links ecology and global consciousness and challenges that consciousness to produce a new and alternative model of society that seeks to project "a participatory, egalitarian, sharing society, one capable of combining imagination and analytical reasoning, technology, and utopia" (91-92). This new model needs to rebuild the social fabric: "work has to be bal12 The book's English title, Ecology and Liberation, is not a translation of Ecologia, Mundializacao, Espiritualidade. The editors would have served the readers better by translating the title more literally because it suggests what the book actually is and does. ENVIRONMENTAL THEOLOGY 313 anced with leisure time, efficiency with gratuitousness, and productivity with playfulness. We need to place a higher value on imagination, utopia, dreams, symbols, poetry and religion" (92). Here Boff is at his finest in terms of insight and challenge. He is also the most "catholic" in the sense that our faith tradition incorporates all of these aspects and integrates them: theology with ethics, liturgy, and aesthetics, the arts with reflective thought. It is also in this section that Boff makes the most poignant criticism of the unjust economic structures of society and the need for an ecological liberation that frees persons, enables them to share resources and to value every living thing as intrinsically interrelated. Part Three begins with the observation and challenge that "to be spiritual means living in accordance with the thrust of life toward and in unison with society and nature ... [and that] in its mature stage, spirituality becomes mysticism" (13 7-38). Regrettably, this last section is the least developed and ultimately the least satisfying. Boff 's references to the scriptural foundations for this kind of spirituality and the (regrettably few) glimpses into the thought of St. Francis of Assisi might have been more fully drawn out and organized in order to make this section the more cogent and compelling. Two books that reflect the Philippine experience with ecological and economic devastation and that provide some of the theoretical underpinnings of the Philippine bishops' conference statement on the environment 13 are from Sean McDonagh, The Greening of the Church and Passion for the Earth. 14 The Greening of the Church is divided into three parts: the first deals with the confluence of ecological and economic oppression in the third world; the second offers an overview of creation in scripture and tradition; the last part contains two appendices, the first of which is "a new decalogue" that results from ecological con13 Entitled "What Is Happening to Our Beautiful Land? A pastoral letter on ecology from the Catholic bishops of the Philippines." 14 A poignant first-person account of the move to an ecologically centered theology, spirituality, and pastoral ministry is Niall 0 'Brien's Revolution from the Heart (Maryknoll: Orbis, 1987). 314 KEVIN W. IRWIN sciousness and the second is the Philippine bishops' statement of 1988. Part One is both engaging and challenging in the way it demonstrates how international economics, specifically, how international debt affects the poor and the earth itself. What could be a dry review of statistical data here becomes involvement with people whose lives are daily diminished because of the debt crisis. Part 1\vo is equally engaging as a survey of the roots of the J udaeo-Christian tradition on the theology of creation (chapters four to seven) and then some particular Roman Catholic voices. Chapter eight reviews spiritual traditions such as the Fathers of the Church, monasticism, Sts. Benedict and Francis, and Celtic spirituality, and chapter nine presents the state of the question in magisterial statements and in issues that need to be revisited, including population. The book is a helpful balance of theological fact and economic reality as well as of Catholic tradition and contemporary voices on the environment. The subtitle of McDonagh's (carefully researched and documented) second book, Passion for the Earth, "The Christian Vocation to Promote Justice, Peace and the Integrity of Creation," is significant, for it summarizes the author's thesis and present work to spread this challenge among his fellow Columban missionaries and to the wider Church. Chapters one to five update and deepen the argument in Part One of The Greening of the Church on the impact of the global economy and international debt on the poor and environmentally disadvantaged. (Particularly acute are his observations on the GATT trade agreement, on the policies of the World Bank, and on "the controlling interests" of transnational corporations.) McDonagh is at his best in these chapters when he translates thorough research and documentation into a language that comparative laypersons can understand. The links with a challenging environmental theology and ethics are clear. Chapter six on "Church response and prophecy" complements the last chapter of The Greening of the Church and updates the review of current Church teaching (e.g., The Catechism of the Catholic Church), as well as providing some indication of statements of episcopal con- ENVIRONMENTAL THEOLOGY 315 ferences 15 and other Christian bodies. McDonagh 's critique here is more compelling than in the first volume, and his suggestions for how Catholicism can contribute to deepening a prophetic stance on this issue are most poignant and pertinent. 16 In discussing "eco-centered ethics and Christian hope" (chapter seven), McDonagh critiques the anthropocentrism of much of Christian ethics and moves to an eco-centered ethic by way of the biblical and classical Christian view of stewardship. In the concluding chapter the author offers a series of suggestions (not all fully thought through or thorough in presentation) that could assist "a pastoral ministry of sustainability." The suggestions on "renewing liturgy and devotions" are polyglot, from adopting the Orthodox custom of having a "feast of creation," to adjusting the present liturgical rites to be more primal and cosmically engaging, to adjusting the mysteries of the rosary and the stations of the cross to critique ecological devastation and offer hopeful images for a prophetic and productive resolution to this crisis. It would seem that the revised liturgy does offer some of what McDonagh argues as desirable. Appropriate catechesis and delineation of a contemporary liturgical theology of the revised rites could enhance the author's legitimate agenda here. A characteristic strength of Roman Catholic theology throughout history has been its ability to reread and rethink its traditional beliefs in the light of contemporary issues, challenges, and pastoral needs. Today the environmental crisis offers such a challenge. The works reviewed here (among others) attest to the deep roots within Catholicism that speak to this issue theologically, spiritually, and pastorally. The maturity of thought expressed in the literature reviewed here augurs well for an even more substantive Catholic contribution to environmental theol15 Additional notable episcopal conference statements on the environment are: from Germany on the future of creation and the future of humanity (1981); from Zaire on development and the environment (1988); from Indonesia on development that respects and develops the environment (1989); from Burundi on the world day of peace (1990); and the concluding statement from the seminar for Brazilian bishops (1992). 16 For example, he laments that in the new catechism "the possibility of a link between liturgy and creation as a way of developing an ecological catechesis is never raised ... [n]or does the present devastation of the natural world figure in the discussion of sacraments" (109). 316 KEVIN W. IRWIN ogy and ethics. It may well be that the desired integration and integral vision of creation expressly called for in some ecological writing may well be supplied by the characteristically Catholic appreciation for the integration of theology, ethics, and the spiritual life. The variety of approaches currently taken on this issue reflects the depth and breadth of Catholicism's resources to deal with the ecological challenges of our day. It is clearly one pivotal source for deep ecology. BOOK REVIEWS Galileo: For Copemicanism and for the Church. By ANNIBALE FANTOLI. Translated by George V. Coyne, S.J. Studi Galileiani Vol. 3. Vatican City: Vatican Observatory Publications, 1994. Distributed by the University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame, Indiana. Pp. xix+ 540. $21.95 (paper). This exhaustive treatment of Galileo and his relationship to the Church was first published in Italian by the Vatican Observatory in 1993 as Vol. 2 of its Studi Galileiani series, bearing the title Galileo: Per il Copemicanesimo e per la Chiesa. So excellent was the study that Father George Coyne, the director of the Vatican Observatory, took it on himself personally to translate the volume into English. Although not a member of the Galileo Commission set up by Pope John Paul II to review the Galileo case, as were Coyne and myself, Fantoli has admirably complemented the work of the Commission and his book surely belongs in the Studi Galileiani collection. A former Jesuit with degrees in mathematics and physics, Fantoli began the book more than twenty-five years ago when he was preparing a course on Galileo at Sophia University in Tokyo. His intention was to show that for Galileo it was never a question of choosing between Copernicanism and the Church, and that the saddest drama of his life was being faced with an injunction that forced him to be for the Church and against Copemicanism. The subtitle of his book proclaims Galileo's true intentions, despite his failure to convince others that this was what his life was all about. A great strength of Fantoli's treatment is its documentation, which abounds in excerpts from Galileo's writings and his correspondence as found in the National Edition of his works and also in citations from new materials that have been uncovered by the Galileo Commission. Thanks to Coyne, all of these texts, many of which were hitherto available only in Latin or Italian, can now be easily accessed in English translation. Another strength of Fantoli's work is that he has kept abreast of Galileo literature over the years and thus is able to offer scholarly critiques of authors whose works exhibit a bias against the Church. Especially welcome are his careful discussions of the positions of earlier writers such as Giorgio de Santillana, Ludovico Geymonat, and Stillman Drake, as well as those of more recent authors, Mario Biagioli, Maurice Finocchiaro, Pietro Redondi, William R. Shea, and Richard S. Westfall. The book is a tour de force and there is little to criticize in it. Unfortunately, however, a typesetting error at its very beginning might create 317 318 BOOK REVIEWS the wrong impression and throw off prospective readers. About six lines of text were omitted at the bottom of page 9. To remedy this the following words should be inserted between the end of page 9 and the beginning of page 10: confused with the Sun) which had heen worked out by Philolaus (about 475 B.C.) within the context of the Pythagorean school.9 In a further modification of this theory the central fire as well as the hypothesis of an anti-earth were done away with, which left the earth at the center of the universe. To offset this addition, the last six lines on the bottom of page 10 should be deleted, for these lines are repeated at the top of page 11. Otherwise, with this change, the exposition reads correctly. The remaining typographical errors are few and in no case do they affect the sense. After a brief introduction in which he presents the astronomical concepts necessary for understanding the details of the Copernican debate, Fantoli divides his treatment into seven chapters. The first two of these are devoted to Galileo's early life and teaching at the Universities of Pisa and Padua, his perfection of the telescope, and the beginnings of the controversies about the earth's motion that were provoked by his telescopic discoveries, The next three chapters then take up the scriptural arguments in detail, Galileo's battle with the Jesuits over the comets of 1618 and his The Assayer of 1623, and his resumption of the Copernican program with the publication of his Dialogue of 1632. The eighth chapter is devoted to the storm that broke loose after that publication, culminating in the trial and condemnation of 1633, and the ninth chapter, to the "Galileo Affair" as this extends from the trial's end to the present. The work concludes with an extensive bibliography and an index of names. Some specific comments may now serve to provide a more complete picture of Fantoli's volume. Most studies of Galileo begin right off with his discoveries with the telescope, their authors apparently unaware of the fact that these were not made until Galileo was already 45 years of age. Fantoli's opening chapter remedies this defect by giving a full account of Galileo's intellectual formation, including his early contacts with the Jesuits and his use of lectures given at the Collegio Romano on logic and natural philosophy. He also takes note of the De motu Galileo composed at Pisa, and how this foreshadowed much of his later work. Unfortunately he does not follow this up with a discussion of the expe1iments on motion that Galileo performed at Padua shortly before perfecting the telescope. By 1609 Galileo had in effect established his "new science" of motion, which he was not to bring to print qntil 1638, after his condemnation by the Inquisition. But it is important to observe that he knew much about the laws of motion before he embarked on his Copernican crusade, and most of this knowledge resulted from the use of notes on the Posterior Analytics he had appropriated from the Jesuits (on this, see my Logic of Discovery and Proof [Kluwer, 1992]). How much Galileo knew but did not tell of the new physics is surely part of the background required to make sense of his later claims and activities. BOOK REVIEWS 319 Undoubtedly Fantoli abbreviated his treatment of the early period to make room for the telescopic discoveries and the long series of controversies in which Galileo became embroiled as a result. The first series, which culminated in Copernicus's De revolutwnibusbeing placed on the Index "until corrected" and Galileo's being served the famous injunction of 1616, is the focus of Fantoli's second and third chapters. Of note here are his treatments of Galileo's Letter to the Grand Duchess Chri.stina,of Cardinal Bellarmine's key letter to Foscarini and Galileo, and of the injunction itself. With regard to the first Fantoli is perhaps too favorable to Galileo, defending the latter's views on Scripture and science, and particularly his statements that science should take precedence over exegesis not only when it had demonstrated its results but even when there was the possibility of their being demonstrated in the future. Fantoli also agrees with Galileo that it is the burden of theologians, before condemning any scientific result, to show that proofs alleged in the support of that result are not conclusively demonstrated. Obviously Fantoli takes little account of Galileo's clever but ill-fated use of rhetoric in the Letter. This aspect has been carefully analyzed by my colleague at Catholic University, Jean Dietz Moss, first in her "Galileo's Letter to Chri.stina: Some Rhetorical Considerations," Renai.ssanceQuarterly 36 (1983): 547-576, and then more fully in her Novelties in the Heavens: Rhetoric and Science in the CopernicanControversy(Chicago, 1993). Much emphasis has been placed by Catholic apologists on Bellarmine's letter of April 12, 1615, addressed to the Carmelite Paolo Foscarini and Galileo and calling for a "true demonstration" that the sun is at the center of the universe and that the earth moves before setting out to reinterpret texts of Scripture that hold the contrary. Fantoli cautions against making too much of this demand, particularly in view of Bellarmine's going on to state: "I will not believe that there is such a demonstration, until it is shown me," and then adding that he is extremely doubtful that one will ever be given. Making use of Richard Blackwell's recent studies of Bellarmine and Foscarini, Fantoli argues that Bellarmine had personally gone far beyond the Council of Trent in thinking that every word of Scripture is divinely inspired, and thus that its teachings about the Sun's motion are matters of faith that can never be overturned, regardless of how much science might progress in the future (p. 178) These views, as Fantoli sees them, were informed by a mind-set that Bellarmine had acquired during his long polemic with the Protestants in defense of the Catholic faith, and this disposed him to be fearful of any new ideas that might upset the Church's philosophical-theological synthesis, a synthesis he had been called upon constantly to uphold. On the matter of the injunction of 1616, this is the important document, dated 26 February of that year, that contains admonitions to Galileo: first, that he relinquish altogether the opinion that the sun is at the center of the world and the earth moves, and second, that he is not "to hold, teach, or defend it in any way whatsoever, verbally or in writing." It is this document 320 BOOK REVIEWS that formed the basis for the Trial of 1633. Two problems have exercised historians with regard to it, namely: (1) how the words enclosed in quotes came to be in the document, and (2) what precisely was their juridical force. The work of the Galileo Commission has turned up new documents that provide answers to both these questions, and they are given full consideration by Fantoli. In his view the words quoted were not in the actual minutes of the Holy Office, which have only recently been uncovered, but were inserted there in a second document prepared by the over-zealous Commissary of the Holy Office, Michelangelo Segizzi. The second document was the one preserved in the Galileo file of the Holy Office through the centuries, and despite its use in the Trial it had no juridical force whatever (pp. 200-206). Fantoli's fourth chapter focuses on Galileo's dispute with the Jesuit astronomer and mathematician Orazio Grassi over the nature of comets. Grassi has been poorly treated and much maligned by historians in the past, and Fantoli sets the record straight on his competence in treating comets the way he did. Grassi was well informed on recent work in astronomy, including Kepler's publications, he was superior to Galileo in the field of optics, and he did catch Mario Guiducci, Galileo's foil in attacking him, in overt contradictions on the subjects of parallax and the comets' being an optical illusion. Fantoli also gives a detailed analysis of Galileo's final answer, The Assayer, which is commonly regarded as a masterpiece of polemical literature. It has been singled out by many historians of science as his best exposition of a scientific methodology, essentially on the basis of its statement that the book of nature "is written in the language of mathematics." Galileo's intention here, Fantoli argues, was not to make a mathematical claim about the nature of physical reality, but simply to emphasize the difference between the subjectivity of poetical literature and the objectivity of reasoning about nature that is based on quantitative techniques (p. 268). The Trial of 1633 was precipitated, of course, by the publication in 1632 of Galileo's Dialogue on the Two Chief World Systems, which Fantoli treats in Chapter 5, and then the Trial itself, which he covers in Chapter 6. In many ways these two chapters are the heart of Fantoli's book. He can only be commended for the impartial way in which he evaluates the records and the intrigues of all parties involved in censoring the draft of the book, in evaluating it after it was published and Pope Urban VIII had turned it and its author over to the Inquisition, and finally in analyzing all the documents now available for assessing the legal process that ensued. Here we only mention two of Fantoli's conclusions that are illustrative of his balanced treatment. The first relates to his judgment about the validity of Galileo's crowning argument for the earth's motion, the ebb and flow of the tides, which provoked Urban's anger and was probably the proximate cause of his condemnation, and the second about the Church's having taken the action against him that it did, seeing that he had failed to offer conclusive proof of the earth's motion. BOOK REVIEWS 321 Much ink has been spilled over whether or not Galileo had offered a conclusive proof of the earth's motion in the Dialogue. Many think that he himself thought he had given such a proof, and some, that he actually had. Stillman Drake has argued against both positions, maintaining that Galileo was convinced that such a proof was forever beyond human reach. Fantoli's judgment is partially in agreement with Drake's but more nuanced. He holds that Galileo was under no illusion of having offered a "definitive proof' that the earth moves and was particularly well aware of the limitations in his argument from the tides. On the other hand, he was firmly convinced that one day a scientific proof would be offered, and that this would show Copernicanism to be the true system of the world. His intent in the Dialogue, therefore, was to show that the totality of arguments he had offered, even though not constituting apodictic proof, was sufficient to tip the balance from a position of equal probability for the two systems, the Aristotelian-Ptolemaic and the Copernican, to a position clearly favoring the latter (p. 365). This agrees substantially with my own analysis based on Galileo's knowledge of logic as presented in Galileo's logic of Discovery and Proof, pp. 214-216 and 226-233. On the second point, Fantoli opposes the efforts of Catholic apologists such as Walter Brandmi.iller to use Galileo's failure to offer conclusive proof of the earth's motion in the Dialogue to justify, or at least to excuse, the position taken by the Church in 1633. In Fantoli's view the totality of the arguments offered in the Dialogue were entirely probative against the Ptolemaic system, and so, considering the physical limitations of the Tychonian system, the Copernican hypothesis was really the only alternative left. Fantoli further observes that the question of conclusive proof never entered into the deliberations at the trial in 1633, and that even in 1616 the qualifiers who condemned Copernicanism never did, nor were they in a position to, weigh the scientific evidence in its support. In the final analysis, then, Fantoli agrees with Galileo's position as argued in the Letter to Christina that the Church should not condemn scientific propositions that one day might be shown to be true and, a fortiori, those that enjoy a high probability of being so. It is interesting to note that, in presenting the final results of the work of the Galileo Commission to the Pontifical Academy of Sciences on October 31, 1992, Pope John Paul II affirmed that position, stating that the very purpose of the Academy was to advise him, considering the current state of science, not only of matters that can be regarded as acquired truths but also of those that enjoy such a degree of probability that it would be imprudent or unreasonable not to take them into account. Fantoli's concluding chapter is a somewhat grim account of the aftermath of the trial and the many missteps taken by the Church throughout the centuries until Galileo was finally "rehabilitated" in our own day. There are few bright spots in that history. Dominicans can rejoice that one of the heroes was Father Benedetto Olivieri, an ex-Master of the Order and then Commissary of 322 BOOK REVIEWS the Holy Office, who in the early 1800s recognized that empirical demonstrations of the earth's motion had finally been given and convinced Pope Pius VII to revoke the longstanding decree against Copernicanism. Unfortunately his greatest opponent turned out to be another Dominican, Father Filippo Anfossi, Master of the Sacred Palace at the time, who had views similar to those voiced by Cardinal Bellarmine in 1615 (pp. 473-475). The story is told in great detail by Walter Brandmiiller and Johannes Griepl, Copemico, Galilei e la Chiesa: Fine delta controversia (1820), gli atti del Sant'Uffizio, Vatican City 1992-summarized in my notice in The Catholic Historical Review 80 (1994): 380-83. It is ironic, of course, that the battle was fought out by two Thomists, the one a progressive and the other a traditionalist, but it is indeed fortunate that it was the progressive Thomist who won out in the end. WILLIAM A. WALLACE, O.P. The Catholic Universityof America Washington, D.C. Love Your Enemies: Discipleship, Pacifism and Just War Theory. By LISA SOWLE CAHILL. Minneapolis, Minn.: Fortress Press, 1994. Pp. xii + 252. $17.00 (paper). Lisa Cahill's Love Your Enemies: Discipleship, Pacifism and Just War Theory provides an excellent introduction to questions of peace-making and war-making in the history of Western Christianity. Cahill canvasses the standard sources for her history: the generally pacifist period of the New Testament and the early church (chapters two and three); the emergence of the just war tradition with Augustine and Aquinas (chapters four and five); just war, crusade, and pacifist responses during the Reformation period (chapters six through eight); and just war and pacifist responses in the twentieth-century American debate (chapters nine and ten). Love Your Enemies is relatively comprehensive, even-handed, and well-written. Beyond its general competence, Love Your Enemies provides rich theological fare, situating questions on war and peace in the context of Christian discipleship as a whole. One result of using discipleship as the organizing motif is that pacifism gets an unusually sympathetic and fair hearing. Cahill serves as an excellent reporter on these contentious questions. While often intimating her sympathies, she consistently avoids taking decisive positions or closing avenues of exploration. The title of her final chapter-the "Fragility of the Gospel"-reflects this approach. In this chapter Cahill emphasizes that Christian communities must continuously challenge themselves and their society to live out the gospel of peace (239-44). BOOK REVIEWS 323 What does it mean to live as a follower of Jesus today (ix)? This is Cahill's central question. To this end she asks two further questions. First, what is the way of discipleship established by Jesus with regard to doing violence? Second, to what extent can Christians hope to apply this ethic of discipleship to the wider civil society (40)? These questions arise in a variety of forms throughout the book. For instance, Cahill elegantly shows how a Christian's eschatological commitments (i.e., beliefs about the extent to which God's peaceful rule can be established by a community of believers and/or the extent to which this can be realized in "the world") can affect her response to the possibility of doing violence. While setting as one's task the attempt to find a way to combine Christian discipleship with public responsibility has many strengths, it is not without possible pitfalls. Typically, "Christian responsibility" is contrasted with "the evangelical imperative of non-violence" (see 55-56). But this notion of "responsibility" often begs the central question-i.e., for the Christian, can the most "responsible" stance be anything but what Cahill proclaims to be the evangelical stance of non-violence? While Cahill does acknowledge the strength of the argument by advocates of "responsibility" (i.e., those set up the non-violent stance in opposition to the faithful following of Jesus), she does not explicitly endorse their move. From her self-professed Catholic context, Cahill strives fo harmonize a neo-Thomist understanding of natural law-that there is "an objective moral order, knowable by reason, that yields universal moral laws by which all human persons and communities should abide" (3)-with a more particularistic gospel ethic of discipleship to Jesus, a way of life that cannot be expected of those who are not disciples. While love Your Enemies is generally comprehensive, I see two significant omissions. First, in the chapter "War in God's Name," one senses that Cahill's (understandable) abhorrence of all crusade-like movements makes her reluctant to explain them in more than cursory fashion. When she turns to the recent debate, she neglects to discuss crusades at all. To be fair to Cahill, she is not attempting to address general attitudes in contemporary American culture, but some acknowledgment and explanation of the continued prevalence of the crusade ideal in our culture would have been helpful. One only has to think of the drill sergeant in Kubrick's Full Metal Jacket-said by many veterans to be the most realistic film depicting the Vietnam War-or read the training manuals of American military and paramilitary groups to realize that theological justifications remain central for the crusade ideal in America today. Second, love Your Enemies lacks any extended discussion of liberation theology or contemporary theories of revolution. Though her passing references to liberation theology are sympathetic (she even defends it against the charge of it having a "crusade mentality" [122]), it never receives serious attention. This is unfo11unate for such an excellent introduction, because liberation theology in particular has challenged the very terms of the tradition- 324 BOOK REVIEWS al debates about pacifism and just war theory, as well as conventional notions of what constitutes "violence." This book has much to recommend it. Besides its clear and accessible introduction to the issues of pacifism and just war theory, it signals a movement (which we can hope will further flower) to give theological questions concerning pacifism and just war theory a more central place. There has been a recent movement within Catholicism-yea, from the Vatican itself-to approach the just war tradition from a broadly evangelical (i.e., gospel) perspective, and Cahill's work analyzes this movement in insightful ways. Towards this end, Cahill contrasts "obediential" pacifism (H.R. Niebuhr, Yoder, Hauerwas) with "empathetic" pacifism (Rauschenbusch, Merton, Dorothy Day). Though the distinction is not entirely convincing, her efforts to display a plurality of pacifist orientations is helpful and illuminating. Love your Enemies can be highly recommended for undergraduate courses on issues of war and peace, and as background reading for graduate seminars. From my own experience, I can attest that it works very well with undergraduates, providing a comprehensive and comprehensible context for a wide variety of primary materials on these questions. Also, each chapter concludes with helpful summaries, and there are both author and subject indexes. In conclusion, Love your Enemies is a work in the spirit of the NCCB's 1983 letter, The Challenge of Peace, in that both strive to wrestle seriously with and find complementary roles for just war theory and pacifism. Is Cahill more successful than The Challenge of Peace in showing their complementarity? Cahill's primary move is to make a category distinction, to claim that just war theory and pacifism are like apples and oranges. Whereas just war theory is a theory of statecraft, pacifism is a form of life requiring discipleship (235). Is this convincing? It seems to me that Cahill has not adequately made a case for thinking that Christian just war theory can be sustained as merely a theory. I would argue that its faithful application requires a set of practices, wisdom, and a form of life as demanding and disciplined-or nearly so-as does pacifism. Thus I would argue that this is precisely why it is doubtful whether contemporary political leaders are capable of applying just war criteria, at least applying them in a way faithful to the best of the classical Christian tradition. Whether or not Cahill has been more successful than The Challenge of Peace in giving complementary characterizations of just war and pacifism, whether or not Cahill has supplied convincing answers to her many questions, she has succeeded in both the vital task of asking the right questions, and has surveyed the key theological categories necessary for working out a Christian ethic of discipleship. Cahill's book is a sign that some theological ethicists are presently fulfilling their vocation-to be both theological and ethical. JOHN BERKMAN Sacred Heart University Fairfield, Connecticut BOOK REVIEWS 325 Recapitulations: Essays in Philosophy. By THOMAS PRUFER. Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of America Press, 1993. Pp. 112. $34.95 (cloth). Re-reading and pondering this little volume, it is hard not to remember John Milton's commendation of a good book as "the precious life-blood of a master-spirit, embalmed and treasured up on purpose to a life beyond life." This is, indeed, the distillation of a life's intense reflection on the central issues of philosophy, parceled out misleadingly in a collection of essaysmisleadingly, because (as the preface asserts) the collection is not a heap. It is not a heap or agglomeration, despite the essays having been published over a period of thirty years, partly because the author gathered them together, organized, and revised them before his untimely death, and partly because they are unified by the pervasiveness and centrality of the careful reflection on the inflections that philosophers have effected in the sense of the word "being" and the word "nature." Indeed, it might have been entitled Nature and Being or Physis kai Einai. The essays are arranged chronologically, from ancients to modems. In tracking their philosophical themes, the author is constantly and perceptively attentive to the form of the language in which thought comes to expression: to the form (and genre) of the texts and to the ways in which language is troped into philosophical uses. So the first essay is on "The Dramatic Form of Plato's Phaedo," and deals with the way the dialogue's narrative framework interacts with the dramatic discussion. And the last essay deals with the relation between structure and story in Waugh's Brideshead Revisited ("The Death of Charm and the Advent of Grace"). In between these are eleven essays on Oedipus and the Poetics, Aristotle, solitude and creation, nature in Epicurus and Hobbes, Augustine's Confessions, comparisons of Aristotle, Aquinas, and Leo Strauss, and studies of Hume, Husserl, and Heidegger. Most of them are brief: dense because condensed, shipped to essentials. They demand attentive reading, but they repay it. Three philosophers are foci or axes: Aristotle, Aquinas, and Heidegger. Aristotle serves as a foil, a reference point for the inflections that-in particular-Aquinas and Heidegger bring to the senses of "nature" and "being." In addition, Husserl serves as a foil for Heidegger, so that each illuminates the other. For Aristotle, although separate being-the noesis noeseos-is primary being, it is necessary that it not be the only sense of "being." It is necessary that "being" mean being in common to many and being in common with many. Separate being is part of the whole of what is. But, for Aquinas, although it is true that God is not the only sense of "being," it is meaningful 326 BOOK REVIEWS (though false) to say that "being" means not God and others but God alone. God cannot not be, but for creatures-even necessary creatures, those with no intrinsic potentiality not to be-their being is a gift, an act ofliberality and generosity by God. That means that God's necessity is utterly different from the necessity of necessary creatures, which not only can be annihilated but which form a whole with all other creatures, which are complemented and completed by other created beings. A greater whole is formed by what complements, but as Aquinas wrote: "Created good added to uncreated good does not result in something greater." Moreover, God's necessary nature, unlike that of the necessary nature of separate being, is not opposed to, does not exclude, the freedom to create. Nor is that freedom to create (or not to create) an indeterminacy or arbitrariness in God's nature. God does not act in order to gain what He lacks or does not have, but as willing to communicate what He has. As Prufer summarizes: For Aquinas the superahundant and therefore necessary and self-sufficient goodness of God is His freedom, ... freedom that is free-of-and-for whether or not there be many others, freedom that is free.to be generous because, being self-sufficient, it need not be generous. One of the most interesting essays reflects on this understanding of God and creation from the point of view of hiddenness and manifestness (fundamental terms for Heidegger, of course). God is a deus absconditus, but His hiddenness is manifested, while if God were to choose that creatures not be, hiddenness would be all there is. Being would be God alone in, so to speak, solitude. (Think of the light which is the first of creation, and which makes manifest the dark, that is, not created.) With creation, not only is hiddenness manifested (as hiddenness) but creatures are totally manifested to God, if hidden from each other and indeed from themselves. This last aspect is taken up in Prufer's reflections on Augustine's Confessionsand Augustine's attempt to bring himself-his life, his being-in recollection from hiddenness to manifestness. These chapters on solitude and creation and on Augustine are intellectually delightful and informative examples of the way in which Prufer brings classical themes to insightful expression in the language of Husserl and Heidegger. Prufer moves with deceptive ease from the grammar of Aristotle and Aquinas to that of Husserl and Heidegger without ever becoming the captive of any of those grammars. He has thought with them long enough to be able to appropriate them for his own. The longest chapter in the book deals with Husserl, Heidegger, and Aquinas, who clearly are, along with Aristotle, the major formative influences on Prufer's own thought. There Heidegger is charged with fundamental misinterpretations of Plato, of Husserl, and of the nature of creation. Of Plato, because Heidegger reduces Plato to the theme of eidos or form, and seems blind to the otherness, the sameness, and difference of the forms and of their BOOK REVIEWS 327 unity, which is not that of a one kind. In a Scholium to the book, Prufer shows that Gadamer's analyses of Plato are incompatible with Heidegger's reduced "Plato." Husserl is misinterpreted by Heidegger because the latter reduces Husserl's phenomenology to the reflexive objectification of subjectivity, to the analysis of intentional acts and their objects. But the deepest theme of Husserl's thought is the flow of so-called inner time consciousness, the unity of presencing and absencing in the primary showing together with its absenced presence in retention and its protentional absence. This unity is not the unity of (intentional) act-and-object, not an act intending an object, but the primal distention of (to use Heidegger's language) the "presencing/absencing of the presence/absence of that-which-ispresent/absent." That which is present is different from its presence (or absence), but the latter tends to be occluded, forgotten, or, if the presencing of presence uncovers it, it is reduced to a that-which-is-present. Husserl in distinguishing the primal presencing from the act-object structure of intentionality distinguishes it from that which is present to consciousness. Prufer acknowledges that Husserl did not always succeed in freeing his thought from inappropriate language, but then neither did Heidegger ever cease to struggle to find the appropriate modus significandi for the res significata he wished to make the theme of thought. And finally Heidegger misinterprets the theme of creation in medieval thought by reducing it to making or production, and thereby reduces the difference between essence and existence to the issue of making "ideas" real, of adding existence to them. Creation is thus understood by Heidegger not only as production ex possibili instead of ex nihilo, but essence is interpreted as a variant of the eternal eidos of Greek thought. Heidegger acknowledged that in medieval thought creation was said to be different from making, but he argued that the philosophical categories in which beings were analyzed subverted that claim. There are illuminating clarifications of a number of Heidegger's fundamental terms (e.g. Lichtung) and of an analogy between Sein and Seiende for Heidegger and esse (not ens) commune and ens for Aquinas. I said above that Aristotle and Aquinas, Husserl and Heidegger are the major interlocutors in these essays. Indeed, few contemporary philosophers-and, if I am not mistaken, no philosophers from the analytic or AngloAmerican tradition-other than these are discussed or even mentioned (except in a few footnotes). There are two exceptions to that: one, already mentioned, is the brief discussion of Gadamer's studies of Plato and Aristotle in the context of some critical remarks on Heidegger's reading of these classical figures. The other exception is perhaps more important: it is Leo Strauss. Indeed, the central chapter (the seventh of thirteen) juxtaposes thi1teen quotations, 328 BOOK REVIEWS mostly from Strauss and Aquinas, and then thirteen interpretive theses of Prufer, on something that concerned Strauss, namely, the incompatibility between philosophy and taking creation to be true. Three other themes of Strauss's work are mentioned: the relation between esoteric and exoteric readings of texts, the senses of "political philosophy," and the quarrel of ancums et modemes. While these three are not discussed explicitly, anyone who knows Strauss's writings will not be unaware of the shadow of his ideas in the background of many of these essays. For example, I mentioned that the middle chapter deals with Strauss, who taught many to attend to the structure of texts written by careful thinkers in seeking to read them as the author intended them to be read by some, at least, of his readers. It may seem excessive or amusing to remark such facts. Yet consider that the last page of the text of this book calls attention to just such a structure in Waugh's Brideshead Revisited: "It is time to speak of Julia .... " is at the center; it is the beginning of the seventh of thirteen chapters; it is preceded and followed by an almost equal number of pages. At the center is the turn from Sebastian to Julia. But more to keep in mind, or in the back of one's mind, in reading the other essays are the other two Straussian themes mentioned, namely, the quarrel of ancients and modems and the importance of political philosophy bien entendu. The Preface, which is described as "both too long and too short" (it is three pages) is supplemented or complemented by summaries added to several of the chapters. One must also note the additions of numbers of scholia and addenda, as returns to or retrievals of the themes. An index, at least of proper names, would have helped a great deal in tracing the discussion of Prufer's central themes through the book. The foregoing examples of Prufer's reflections and clarifications are indicative of the centrality of the philosophical issues dealt with in the essays, but, without long quotation, they cannot give a sense of the precision and terseness which characterizes his analyses. These essays are not commentaries on texts, but dialogues with the authors of texts about the res significata. They show Prufer to have been an incisive, thoughtful, careful reader and thinker on the deepest and most important metaphysical issues. Or, if "metaphysics" has critical overtones for readers of Heidegger, let us simply say they show him to be a thinker. FREDERICK University of Notre Dame Notre Dame, Indiana J. CROSSON BOOK REVIEWS 329 ]oumeybread for the Shadowlands: The Readings for the Rites of the Catechumenate, RC/A. By PAMELA E. JACKSON. Collegeville, Minn.: The Liturgical Press, 1993. Pp. 171. $12.95 (paper). The purpose of this book is to promote interior conversion of adult catechumens by means of its meditative and complex interpretation of the readings for the last, pre-baptismal stages of the Rite of Christian Initiation for Adults. The author anticipates that the baptized and unbaptized alike, together comprising "the Elect," will come from unbelief to belief by the process of hearing the Word, recognizing and abhorring their sinfulness, rejecting Satan, trusting Jesus, and entering his church. The author expects that, if read slowly and carefully, the book will move its readers closer to understanding and living the biblical story as their own, so that they may become viatores leaving the darkness of the present world and entering the light of the kingdom of heaven (p. 171). Jackson intends the book to be "a source-book for meditation," based on some of the possible combinations specified for each of the final rites of the catechumenate. Its genre is liturgical theology, and it claims as its patrimony the early Christian exegesis of the Bible. Indeed, ]oumeybread is an eloquent expression of one aspect of the Christian life, and of one type of Christian spirituality: the soul poised between the claims of the world and the Deceiver (e.g., pp. 58-59) and Christ, pictured in one passage as the Captain of Salvation spoken of by the Church: To those engulfed in death's black nothingness they cry: "Come to Him whose bright obedience reaches out to encircle you with the infinite hues of His divine compassion! Let Him Hold you in that rainbow of His arms .... " (p. 41) In eight chapters Jackson comments on the proper readings for the rites of the catechumenate: Acceptance in the order of Catechumens, Election (Years A, B, and C), the Three Scrutinies, Presentation of the Creed, Presentation of the Lord's Prayer, and Recitation of the Creed. Her commentary is an unusual one, however. Because it attempts to revive a patristic approach to the Biblical texts, which shows by interpretation the living Word speaking to believers through the inspired Scriptures, the book's style and substance will be unfamiliar to many readers accustomed to the historical-critical or literary approaches to the Scriptures. Jackson aims to have the readers experience not only this more traditional, spiritual reading of the Bible, but also experience the profound existential crisis and decision of those approaching baptism. Therefore, the Scripture passages cease to be an object of study in her treatment; rather, they are read as different lines of the same melody. Harmonized, all the passages specified for the RCIA sound the call to depart from the world with its "service of individualistic self-fulfillment" (p. 67), repent, convert, and be united with Ch1ist. 330 BOOK REVIEWS As the Introduction explains, the book is informed by the catecheses and mystagogies of Cyril of Jerusalem, Ambrose, and John Chrysostom: In my studies of the Fathers I came to share their perception of the Church as living in the world of the Bible in the sense that the Church understands itself in Biblical terms and sees itself as a continuation of the story of God's saving work recorded in the Bible .... (p. 5) The resulting book "is offered simply as one example of what can happen when one gazes into the kaleidoscope of the Word, believing it to be a catalyst for conversion" (p. 6). Thus, Jackson intentionally places the book within the context of the half-century of patristic revival in Roman Catholic theology usually associated with the names of de Lubac, Danielou, Balthasar, and, more recently, Schoenborn. Having its origins in European theology, the revival of patristic studies as a foundation for modern theology is now an American and ecumenical project as well. It has received official validation of a sort in the new Catechism of the Catholic Church, a document abounding in references to patristic authors, and in the recent Vatican instruction on the role of patristic studies in priestly formation. Such a movement reflects the urgency of the classical Christian tradition in crisis, in which various writers and church teachers return to the roots of the tradition. It is striking, then, that many aspects of Jackson's book and its theology bear a marked resemblance to the theology of evangelical Christianity. Surely this is in part due to the character of the RCIA, a rite which in itself seems to require believers' baptism following a clear interior conversion. The book, following the RCIA, assumes that adult catechumens will not have been raised as Christians knowing their place in the story of sin and salvation, and both may well be correct. Yet other aspects of ]ourneybread are evangelical, such as its obvious debt to the thought of C.S. Lewis, its concentration on the importance of the Word instead of the sacraments and sacramentals of initiation, and the lack of mystagogy normal in patristic treatments of initiation. ]ourneybread constructs a dialogue between the iay Faithful and the lay Elect, who accompany each other on the path to conversion and the latters' baptism largely without benefit of clergy. Perhaps due to the influence of C.S. Lewis, or perhaps to that of John Bunyan, ]ourneybread portrays the catechumens at the beginning of Lent as being possessed by a mortal illness (sin and death), and enslaved to the deceiver (p. 51). Given the "inseparability of the rite and faith experience," "what the catechumen must learn is a relationship with God" (p. 23); abandoning the "horrifying [internal] blackness" (pp. 111, 113) they must join the Faithful against the Deceiver as they begin a pilgrimage toward adoption as Sons of God (pp. 144-145). This portrait owes much for its dramatization of the progress of the embattled Christian soul to Bunyan and to Lewis, from whom the term "shadowlands" derives. The latter term appears twice as a synonym for the "land of unlikeness." On p. 119 it connotes both spiritual blindness and life outside BOOK REVIEWS 331 full membership in the church, and in the last sentence of the book (p. 171) it signifies, apparently, the present dispensation: "the shadowlands of the catechumenate have prepared [the initiates] well for the shadowlands of the Church, where the kingdom is always here, and always just out of sight." For Lewis, the term derived ultimately from the Platonic view that the present world is merely a shadow of the Ideal realm, but as a Christian metaphor it stood for the darkness of a world ruled by Satan, and betrayed the persistent dualism that fueled Lewis's pessimism (cf. That Hideous Strength) and disturbed his Catholic friend Tolkien. The other word of the title, "journeybread" (Greek ephodion), has rich associations in early Christian thought and practice, but Jackson interprets it in conjunction primarily with the battle preceding baptism. Jackson uses it to mean the Gospel (p. 21) or the verbal announcement of a Christian's adoptive relation to the Father. For instance, at the Presentation of the Lord's Prayer, on the verge of the Paschal Vigil, the Elect again receive the journey bread: What a mystery, they think: here, so close to the destination of their pilgrimage, the All-Powerful One they sought so long shows Himself to them simply as Father; the final Word He gives them as journey bread is that He has always loved them, been with them, cared for them, leading them every step as they sought after Him, even though they didn't know it or appreciate it. (p. 144) The term ephodion (Latin viaticum), however, in the early Christian tradition had a much wider meaning than the Word of scripture. What had signified "a day's provisions" came in the church's lexicon to mean prayer and baptism (Basil), Eucharistic communion (Gregory of Nyssa, Nicaea, Canon 13), almsgiving (Cyprian), or the entire collection of Christian practices (1 Clement). But Jackson's connotation of the term "journeybread," is actually closer to the post-Tridentine understanding of viaticum as provision for the dying (which definition ironically echoes the pagan viaticum as "Charon's wages"). In these two instances, and throughout the book, Jackson adapts her patristic sources to the evangelical mood in Christianity. The Biblical interpretation on which she founds the dramatic narrative of the pilgrimage of the Elect in Lent to their reception of the Lord's prayer is a spiritual exegesis not unlike that of the fathers, but its emphasis on combat and sin conforms more to the apocalyptic strain in early Christianity than it does either to the catechetical writings or to monastic spiritual theology. ]ourneybread is a powerful echo of some patristic conceptions of Christian initiation. An account like Jackson's is perhaps one way of convincingly staging the Christian drama. In that case, the main recourse of the Christian is the departure from the enemy world and identification with a transcendent victor. This is the vision that enlivens Jackson's book; it has more in common with the Apocalypse than with the comprehensive synthesis of Origen, Gregory of Nyssa, or Augustine, each of whom successfully incorporated ear- 332 BOOK REVIEWS lier Christian dualism into a balanced, theological whole. As a protreptic device, Jackson's book may be, in a certain way, part of a collective movement that may form a prolegomenon for a new synthesis-informed by the patristic authors but written as a vademecum for contemporary inquiry. ROBIN DARLING YOUNG The Catholic Universityof America Washington, D.C. Ministry: Lay Ministry in the Roman Catlwlic Church, Its History and Theology. By KENAN B. OSBORNE, 0.F.M. (New York: Paulist Press, 1993). Pp. 722. $29.95 (paper). In his Lay Ministry, Fr. Kenan Osborne, O.F.M., sustains his effort to introduce a program of reform in ecclesial self-understanding inaugurated in his earlier Priestlwod: A History of the Ordained Ministry in the Roman Catlwlic Church (New York: Paulist Press, 1988). The project undertaken in this second installment aims primarily to undermine those traditional patterns of distinguishing klerikos/laikos and ordained/non-ordained that locate "lay ministry" at a lower latitude on the ontological map, and in this way to clear a path for a more adequate understanding of the place of the laity in the ministry of the Church. Of the 609 pages of text, 548 are dedicated to genealogical analysis of the transmission of Christian understanding of ministry. The author's narrative might be condensed as follows. The first millennium was a period marred by theological definitions of ministry and order derived from the terms of debate that emerged in the conflict between temporal and spiritual rulers. Necessary for successful participation in this cultural debate was the embrace of a hierarchical view of reality, a view destined to obscure the truth about the distinctively egalitarian Christian form of life in common (48-332). The second millennium is interpreted as a period of the gradual reemergence of a vision and practice of evangelical life that had been surrendered to alien philosophical and religious doctrines. The primary historical moments in this recovery, treated in three successive chapters, include the late medieval vita evangelica movements (333-90), the Protestant Reformation (391-463), and the French and American Revolutions (464-517). The Second Vatican Council, where it treats of lay ministry, consolidated these post-medieval insights gained into the Christian religion and the nature of man (518-95) and advanced the conclusion: Equality of discipleship is primary in the Christian religion and differences in ministerial function serve only to promote this fundamental good. Osborne is aware that this basic line of thought was that taken by the Reformers and found inadequate by the Council of Trent. But Osborne does BOOK REVIEWS 333 not present his position as an instance of theological dissent. Rather, he argues that the magisterium acting in the Second Vatican Council teaches that there exists no meaningful sense in which "lay ministry" can be understood as subordinate (ontologically) to "ordained ministry" in the sacramental life of the Church. This review will focus on this latter aspect of Osborne's argument which, while limited in scope, appears to be the more original and important element of the book. Osborne himself provides a further narrowing of scope with his selection of two key sources upon which he relies: Lumen Gentium and the 1983 Code of Canon Law. In his interpretation of Lumen Gentium, Osborne argues that the rejection of the preparatory documents signaled the majority bishops' desire to distance themselves from a "hierarchical approach" and move toward "a new form of ecclesiology" (516). This new form is rooted in the primacy of Jesus, and it is He (and not the Church) who is the sole lumen gentium, from which it follows immediately that there can be only one form of "gospel discipleship" (530). "All Church ministry, whether ordained or non-ordained, is relativized by the identical christological base" (528), Jesus, who transcends the distinction between clerical and lay (558). Osborne argues further that Lumen Gentium supports this position in its identification of the Church as "the people of God," "christifidelis," and "priesthood of all believers" (530-40). On the basis of this recovery of the "foundational and most sacred level of discipleship" (541), at which level the distinction between ordained and nonordained "makes no difference" (39), Osborne maintains (in accord with what he takes to be the teaching of the magisterium) that Christians share in the tria munera of Christ in a manner "COMMON and EQUAL to ALL" (542). His case is further supported, Osborne believes, by the shift in language that occurs between Canon 107 in the 1917 Code-which speaks of a divinely instituted distinction between clergy and laity-and Canon 207 in the 1983 Code, which refers to a divinely instituted distinction between "sacred ministers" and "other Christian faithful," which groups are only juridically distinguished as clergy and laity. Osborne finds here not only a sign of reluctance to specify (in law) the divinely ordained characteristics proper to clergy and laity (the characteristics of which are in part bound up with changing pastoral circumstances), but proceeds further to argue that this new canon cancels "any effort to turn this typological description (of the clergy/lay distinction) into an ontological one" (45). To reinforce these points, Osborne argues that this position is confirmed in the New Testament and the concept of "gospel discipleship" contained therein. While "gospel discipleship" remains a somewhat underdeveloped concept given its centrality for Osborne's work, it is clear enough that this concept includes an immediacy to the person of Jesus, mediated through encounter with the "enscriptured word," prior to the ministerial structures of the Church (112, 463), and a mystical dimension that "goes far beyond offi- 334 BOOK REVIEWS cial church documents ... , systematic theology, ... and liturgical celebration" (329), and as such "is first and foremost a lived reality, not a cogitated reality" (330). In light of these criteria, Osborne maintains that the distinction between clergy and lay "is in many ways devoid of a gospel foundation" and is without christological basis (39). Further, "gospel discipleship" is opposed to "a theologically based view of ordo" (509), the latter which intrudes upon the purity of the former from Greco-Roman politics, philosophy, and culture (114-62, esp. 159-62). The statement "that there is an ontological difference in the ordained priesthood, episcopal and presbyteral, is a questionable statement at best" (576); elsewhere, Osborne concludes: '"Ontological difference' appears to be no longer a viable theological approach to determine the difference between klerikos/laikos"(581). While he affirms "that the sacrament of orders confers a character" is a defined teaching, he denies that the what of this character is defined (567). It is not Osborne's goal in the present book to determine the whatness of sacramental character in orders. It is his aim, however, to deny that speech about sacramental character signifies an ontological change in the one upon whom the sacrament of orders is conferred (569, 576, 581). Osborne prefers to limit the signification of the difference between clergy and lay to one of "degree." What this amounts to in Osborne's mind is unclear in his text; it would appear, however, to run into an explicit contradiction with the text upon whose authority he relies, at that point where lumen Gentium at nn. 10 and 27 speaks of the "essential difference" between laity and clergy and of a hierarchical understanding of the Church that this entails. For his part, Osborne simply rests his argument on the sentences from lumen Gentium cited above and attributes any possible contradiction here to that internal to the Council document. Finally, these arguments are linked with the wider findings of Osborne's historical exploration into the "meaning, function, ministry, and role of the presbyter and bishop over the centmies," which investigation yields the conclusion that "there is no permanent element or dimension in the ordained priest, whether presbyteral or episcopal, which through the centuries has remained constant" (569). According to Osborne, any speech about sacramental character merely begs the question concerning the permanent element in these ministries in the absence of an "immutable definition" of orders that can survive historical analysis of the Christian tradition. What are the rules that govern whether a particular definition qualifies? That the power to consecrate bread and wine, as an example, might so qualify is ruled out in part because it fails to appear in the most primitive extant ordination ritual. Yet Osborne does not rely solely upon "conservative" appeals to antiquity. In the end, the possibility that a power of action proper to the ordained alone might be found in a historical survey of Christian tradition is ruled out a priori by the positions established in Osborne's reading BOOK REVIEWS 335 of Lumen Gentium. For example: The power to act in persona Christi capitis fails to qualify as a definition of the whatness of sacramental character, not on historical grounds, but rather because, on Osborne's account, the authoritative teaching of Vatican II (in continuity with the New Testament) denies that there can exist any power of action proper to the ordained with its affirmation that all powers of action in Christ and his tria munera are shared by the "baptized-eucharistic Christian" (570). It should be made clear that Osborne does not intend to threaten differences in the way ordained and non-ordained ministers function in the Church. He holds, for example, that his position can sustain the beliefs that only the hierarchy teaches with ultimate authority, exists as "the duly appointed and official leaders in the Church," and possesses a priestly ministry that is eucharistically and penitentially effective (553). Yet a fundamental problem with the book remains, one that might be described as a misapplication of his concern to affirm the universal call to holiness for all members of the Church. Osborne appears to think that there exists some intrinsic connection between an ontological interpretation of sacramental character (in holy orders) and a pernicious clericalism in the life of the Church, one that impedes an evangelical understanding of lay ministry. The scholastic tradition makes clear, however, that the sacramental character effected in holy orders establishes a pre-eminence, not in the order of grace or holiness, but in the order of instrumentality: the ordained priest possesses a power to act in such a way that the saving action of Christ upon the cross is made present in the Eucharist. Yet viewed from another perspective, according to the order of holiness or theological virtue, greater pre-eminence belongs to the Eucharistic act of participating in Christ's sacrifice of love and obedience to the Father than to the priestly act of the ordained that makes Christ's sacrifice present to those assembled. Osborne acknowledges that the difference between lay and ordained members of the Church functions "empirically" in the life of the Church, but commits himself to a position that denies that the action of the priest might be said really to effect (as an instrumental cause), in the time and place of those gathered to celebrate the Eucharist, what his actions signify. In his promotion of an interpretation of Christian ministry shorn of ontological realism, Osborne severs the link between the community that is the Church and the Lord Jesus Christ capitis ecclesia who acts visibly in her midst. Not surprisingly, Osborne leaves unexplored in this work the sacrament of Confirmation and its conferral of a spiritual character equipping the adult Christian for indispensable forms of public ministry in the Church. GARY M. CULPEPPER ProvidenceCollege Providence,Rhode Island 336 BOOK REVIEWS The De-Moralization of Society: From Victorian Virtues to Modern Values. By GERTRUDE HiMMELFARB. New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1995. Pp. 314. $24 (paper). If there were a Society for the Prevention of Cruelty to Words, its members would undoubtedly be protesting the unfair treatment that has been meted out to that much-abused adjective, "Victorian." (Meanwhile, the Sub-Committee on False Claims and Deceptive Practices would be casting a cold eye on the broken promises of "Romantic," but that is a story for another day.) Except in the phrases "Victorian literature" and (sometimes) "Victorian architecture," "Victorian" has largely degenerated into a shorthand for a certain combination of priggishness and prudery. My dictionary duly notes in its first definition that the word pertains to the reign of Queen Victoria (1837-1901). But its second definition is more to the point: "Exhibiting qualities, as moral severity or hypocrisy, middle-class stuffiness, and pompous conservatism" that are "usually associated" with that period. In fact, an inventory of what is usually meant by "Victorian" would include just about every sin currently enrolled on the Index of political incorrectness. The Victorians, we are told, were guilty of being patriarchal, imperialistic, sexist, elitist, racist, classist, and Eurocentric. They were also grossly materialistic and, sin of sins, sexually repressed. For many years, the eminent historian Gertrude Himmelfarb has been providing an antidote to these distorting prejudices. In two classic studies about poverty in the Victorian period, she has shown that the popular image of Dickensian squalor-epitomized by the figure of young Oliver Twist in the workhouse-must be supplemented by the countless reform movements that proliferated in Victorian England and that did so much to relieve the condition of the poor and the working class. In this new collection of essays, The De-Moralization of Society, Professor Himmelfarb continues to correct our understanding of the many received ideas that have accumulated around the word "Victorian." Consider the piano leg. If there is a single image that crystallizes the popular conception of Victorian prudery and sexual squeamishness, it is the image of piano legs decorously swathed in pantaloons. How refreshing to learn from Professor Himmelfarb that those piano legs-like such other "Victorian" kinks as home libraries in which male authors were rigorously segregated from female authors-were generally "the invention of satirists, foisted by the English on gullible Americans and perpetuated by unwary historians." (The covered piano legs, for example, originated with a traveler to America who reported seeing a piano in a girls' school sporting "modest little trousers with frills at the bottom" [15].) BOOK REVIEWS 337 Again and again in these essays, Professor Himmelfarb invites us to peek behind a stereotype or cliche or presupposition. Most of us think that we have a pretty good idea of what feminism is. But in her thoughtful essay "Feminism, Victorian Style," Professor Himmelfarb shows that the real history is more complicated, and more various, than we might have appreciated. Given the common stereotype of patriarchal Victorian society, it may seem odd to say that feminism is itself a Victorian phenomenon. Yet the word-and the smorgasbord of movements, principles, and sentiments that the word names-is of Victorian provenance. Most contemporary readers will be surprised, too, to discover the positions that many eminent female Victorians took on women's issues. For example, when the movement to give women the vote gained momentum, there seemed to be as many women opposing female suffrage as there were supporting it. The feminist Millicent Fawcett campaigned tirelessly to secure the vote for women; but those opposing it included such luminaries as George Eliot, Charlotte Bronte, Mrs. Gaskell, Elizabeth Barrett Browning, Christina Rossetti, Margaret Oliphant, Florence Nightingale, and even the socialist Beatrice Webb (99-101). There was a similar diversity on the controversial question of birth control. Detailing this diversity, Professor Himmelfarb observes that "One is reminded once again that Victorian feminists were not all of a kind and did not all subscribe to the same 'program'" (123). Or consider that hearty myth that the guiding ethos of Victorian life was "ruthlessly materialistic, acquisitive, and self-centered," not to say cruel, exploitative, and unfeeling (143). Professor Himmelfarb is not Pollyanna. She readily acknowledges the sometimes vicious inequities that marred Victorian life. And she several times pauses to note that "no-one ... is proposing to revive Victorianism" (252). But she also shows that "Humanitarianism became, in effect, a surrogate religion" for the Victorians (14 7). Indeed, whatever else it was, the Victorian age was an age of reformers and do-gooders of all varieties, some of whom actually managed to do considerable good. "In addition to societies for the promotion of piety and virtue," Professor Himmelfarb notes, "others were established for the relief of the poor and infirm-for destitute orphans and abandoned children, aged widows and penitent prostitutes, the deaf, dumb, blind, and otherwise incapacitated" (6). By the mid-nineteenth century, there were legislative reforms to limit working hours, to improve sanitation and the condition of prisons, to establish public education, and to extend the legal rights of women. This reforming impulse had many beneficent social consequences. In her lengthy epilogue, "A De-Moralized Society," Professor Himmelfarb cites studies showing that the number of indictable criminal offenses declined by nearly half during the Victorian age, from 480 per 100,000 in 1857 to 250 in 1901. It was not until after the Second World War that things really started to change for the worse. In the last three decades, the change has been cataclysmic. By 1981 the number of indictable offense per 100,000 had risen to 338 BOOK REVIEWS 5,600. By 1991, the number was 10,000 (221-27). Then there is that other powerful index of social pathology, the rate of illegitimacy. At the tum of the nineteenth century, the illegitimacy rate was just over five percent. It crept up to seven percent by 1845, but then declined to less than four percent by the tum of this century. It remained fairly stable until the late 1950s. Then it skyrocketed. In both the United States and Britain, the illegitimacy rate increased sixfold between 1960 and 1991. Professor Himmelfarb introduces such comparative statistics not because she prefers Victorian answers to contemporary social and moral problems, but because she recognizes that many of the problems the Victorians faced continue to plague us. Her discussion of the New Poor Law, introduced in 1834, is a case in point. Like most debates over welfare policy, it was deeply controversial. The basic intent of the law was to circumscribe the right to public relief. It did this by stigmatizing the able-bodied poor, requiring them to live in sexually segregated workhouses in order to obtain relief. Dickens indelibly, if not quite accurately, fixed the horrors of workhouse life a few years later in Oliver Twist. Opposition to the law was fierce. Benjamin Disraeli, for example, wrote that "I consider that this Act has disi;raced the country more than any other upon record." Professor Himmelfarb is quick to note that "by the standards of the present day, the New Poor Law was grudging and harsh" (141). But she also points out that it was not the simple punitive measure it has often been portrayed as. It arose partly from the conviction that habitual dependency on relief was demoralizing, especially to those who were able to work. Thus it is that the debate over the New Poor Law has a contemporary relevance. Today, Professor Himmelfarb writes, "the very word 'stigma' has become odious, whether applied to dependency, illegitimacy, addiction, or anything else. Yet stigmas are the corollaries of values. If work, independence, responsibility, respectability are valued, then their converse must be devalued, seen as disreputable. The Victorians, taking values seriously, also took seriously the need for social sanctions" (142). Taking values seriously: that is the leitmotif that echoes throughout these essays, binding them together into a continuous narrative. Not that the term "values" is unproblematic. On the contrary. Professor's subtitle-"From Victorian Virtues to Modern Values"-hints at the change that she explores in her prologue and touches on repeatedly throughout The De-Moralization of Society. The central Victorian vi1tues of thrift, self-reliance, hard work, and dutifulness were not the classical virtues of wisdom, justice, temperance, and courage; nor were they the traditional Christian virtues of faith, hope, and charity. Neve1theless, they were "vi1tues" in the sense that they were regarded as objective moral standards that pertained to everyone even if everyone did not live up to them. Today, we are much more apt to speak of "values" than of "virtues." But the words are not synonyms. As Professor Himmelfarb points out, the term BOOK REVIEWS 339 "values," which did not come into vogue until the end of the nineteenth century, "brought with it the assumptions that all moral ideas are subjective and relative, that they are mere customs and conventions, that they have a purely instrumental, utilitarian purpose, and that they are peculiar to specific individuals and societies" (11). It is perhaps this above all that separates us from the moral universe of the Victorians. We all know the ways in which our world is freer and less stratified than the world of the Victorians. We must be grateful to Professor Himmelfarb for so vividly recalling us to the moral and spiritual resources we have lost. ROGER KIMBALL The New Criterion New York, New York