PERSONAL RECEPTIVITY AND ACT: A THOMISTIC CRITIQUE STEVEN A. LONG Christendom College Front Royal, Virginia I. INTRODUCTION ECENT NEO-THOMISTIC WRITINGS on the nature f the human person have emphasized the metaphysics f spiritual being, and in particular the liberty of spiritual being from the passive potency that characterizes merely physical subsistents. 1 The eminent Thomistic scholar Kenneth Schmitz seems to suggest that receptivity in spiritual being transcends the principles of act and potency altogether. 2 Act and potency would then pertain primarily to subpersonal being. By contrast Norris Clarke infers that creaturely receptivity is defined more by act than by potency.' Thus viewed, receptivity becomes an analogous perfection that is possessed by God-a point made by a variety of authors 4 attempting to unify under one notion creaturely and divine receptivity. 1 See W. Norris Clarke, Person and Being (Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1993). In a different but allied vein, see Kenneth Schmitz, "The First Principle of Personal Becoming," The Review of Metaphysics 47, no. 4 Oune 1994). 1 This is my reading of Schmitz's reflections in "Personal Becoming." .1 See W. Norris Clarke, "Response to Long's Comments," Communio (Spring, 1994)for instance, "But what I, with David Schindler and Hans Urs von Balthasar, am doing is precisely trying to expand the range of the concept, to call attention to the fact that at a certain level of being-the personal-the notion both can and should be detached from the limitations which ordinarily accompany it, so that it can turn into a sign of positive perfection rather than imperfection" (166). 4 See for example "The Person: Philosophy, Theology, and Receptivity" for diverse principled accounts of receptivity, Communio (Spring, 1994). In particular, note the approaches of Norris Clarke, S.J., and David Schindler, who each argue that the recep- 1 2 STEVEN A. LONG In this article I examine the root notion that personal activity transcends the ontological principles of act and potency. I also consider the effort to retain these ontological principles by christening receptivity a pure perfection of act. Both of these views seem to presuppose the inadequacy either of St. Thomas's philosophic anthropology or at least of its traditional interpretation; I shall argue that each implies the abandonment of Thomistic metaphysics. The teaching that act and potency pertain only to lower, subpersonal being and that these principles are utterly inadequate for philosophic analysis of the person contrasts markedly with the doctrine that all subjects of being reflect diverse rationes of subject and act, which as distinct but proportionately identical are bonded in a community of analogy. Likewise, the view of receptivity as pure act seems to imply that the human subject is self-actuating, thus negating the composite character of the human person. Hence the purpose of this essay is in a sense to argue for vindication of the community of analogy in response to arguments that implicitly terminate it within the domain of the sub personal. What is at stake is whether one falls into the very error characteristic of modern philosophy as described by Kenneth Schmitz: "the loss of a more general and more generous metaphysical interiority and the reduction of the residue of interiority to the confines of the human consciousness." 5 Is there a dichotomy between human nature and that of lesser beings, such that the principles of act and potency do not apply to it? Do human spirituality and subjectivity transcend such ontological principles as act and potency which permeate the field of subpersonal being? Should we, as Schmitz's remarks seem to do, distinguish "nonpassive receptivity" from activity and potency? 6 Or should we tivity of the divine Word vis-a-vis the divine nature in Trinitarian theology is bonded in analogical community with creaturely receptivity. Skeptics about this project are represented in the discussion by George Blair, "On Esse and Relation," and by myself, "Divine and Creaturely Receptivity: The Search for a Middle Term." 5 Schmitz, "Personal Becoming," 766. 6 Ibid., 771: "Yet non passive receptivity is as much a mark of the human spirit as is its activity." Schmitz objects to the view that receptivity is "something less than a transcendent value." PERSONAL RECEPTIVITY AND ACT 3 follow Clarke in identifying receptivity as a pure perfection, contrary to the view that receptivity designates potency? 1 I shall first broach this issue in the writing of Kenneth Schmitz, following with a consideration of the ontology of knowledge in relation to receptivity, and of Aquinas's doctrine regarding being and operation. Then I will briefly advert to Norris Clarke's effort at reconciling ontological analysis of the person with contemporary personalist philosophy. II. RECEPTIVITY, IMMATERIALITY, AND INTERIORITY In his recent essay "The First Principle of Personal Becoming," Kenneth Schmitz describes the negation of creaturely subjectivity and interiority characteristic of modern philosophy, which arrogates these traits more or less exclusively to rational consciousness.8 In the course of commenting upon this phenomenon, he endeavors to recover the radically analogous conception of immateriality in Thomistic metaphysics. As he puts it: There is a certain immateriality that is to be found in all things, even physical things. The traditional metaphysicsattributed a nonmateriality to physical things by virtue of their complex constitution, since, in addition to the passive and potential factor within them that was dubbed primary matter, there were the factors of form, finality, and participation in the cosmic web of existence. These nonmaterial factors were held to be the forms of immateriality proper to physical things, but they were also held to be the physical analoguesof the immateriality that was held to be inseparable from the depth and interiority constitutive of every caused being. In sum, the traditional metaphysics held that some kind of immateriality was inseparable from every being by virtue of its being.9 Schmitz relates this realization that being and form entail "some kind of immateriality" to the account that St. Thomas gives of the negative judgment of separation by which one discerns that being, substance, form, and act are not necessarily 7 Clarke, "Response," 167: "I see no convincing reason for including imperfection and limitation as part of the very meaning of the term 'receptivity' or 'receive,' and good reasons for not doing so." 8 See Schmitz, "Personal Becoming," 762-66. 9 Ibid., 766-67. 4 STEVEN A. LONG found with matter and motion, although they may be so. w In this perceptive stress upon the manner in which the actus essendi of any being generically overpasses the limits of material essence, the metaphysical roots of subjectivity are once again discerned. Of course, this immateriality is not the positive immateriality of intrinsically spiritual being: but it is wide enough to provide for the discovery of such being. Were the concept of being essentially determined by materiality and mobility, then the analogous affirmations made of the unmoved mover would be impossible: a material, mobile, mutable being that is immaterial, immobile, and immutable is a contradiction in terms! Being implicitly and actually overpasses the limits of material essence. Being as an analogically intelligible object-"subject in act"-that is intrinsically diversified in different beings does not essentially include potency and matter, although it may be found with them. In other words, there is nothing about the intelligibly analogous object "subject in act" that requires the subject to include potency: matter and potency are accidental to existential act, which is not self-limiting but limited only by its commensuration to a potential principle. Nothing in the intrinsic character of "act" requires that it be commensurated to a finite subject (if it did, proofs for God's existence would be impossible). 10 St. Thomas Aquinas, Opera Omnia: Super Boetium de trinitate (Commissio Leonina: 1992), q. 5, a. 3: "Vtraque autem est de his que sunt separata a materia et motu secundum esse, set diuersimode, secundum quod dupliciter potest esse aliquid a materia et motu separatum secundum esse: uno modo sic quod de ratione ipsius rei que separata dicitur sit quod nullo modo in materia et motu esse possit, sicut Deus et angeli dicuntur a materia et motu separati; alio modo sic quod non sit de ratione eius quod sit in materia et mot•., set possit esse sine materia et motu quamuis quandoque inueniatur in materia et motu, et sic ens et substantia et potentia et actus sunt separata a materia et motu, quia secundum esse a materia et motu non dependent sicut mathematica dependebant, que numquam nisi in materia esse possunt quamuis sine materia sensibili possint intelligi" (speaking ofrevealed theology and philosophic theology). Note also the following lines of ibid., q. 5, a. 4, ad 5: "Ad quintum dicendum, quod ens et substantia dicuntur separata a materia et motu non per hoc quod de ratione ipsorum sit esse sine materia et motu, sicut de ratione asini est sine ratione esse, set per hoc quod de ratione eorum non est esse in materia et motu quamuis quandoque sint in materia et motu, sicut animal abstrait a ratione quamuis aliquod animal sit rationale." PERSONAL RECEPTIVITY AND ACT 5 The ratio entis is intrinsically analogous, and its proportionate unity lies in the diverse but similar proportions of act and subject. Nothing requires this relation to be real and not logical, so it is affirmed (albeit only logically) even of God, ipsum esse subsistens per se. This discernment of the intrinsic analogicity of being highlights the formal intelligibility whereby we distinguish diverse grades of actuality among beings-some forms are more immersed in potency than are others. As the maxim operatio sequitur esse implies, the more immersed in potency is the substantial form the more immersed in potency will be the second act or operation that manifests the nature of a thing. It is at this juncture that Schmitz's analysis seems to backpedal from the rich emphasis upon analogicity that heretofore characterizes his account. The problem is not that he distinguishes-as one ought-the immateriality that characterizes "every being by virtue of its being" from the immateriality that is specific to spiritually subsistent forms. Rather, the difficulty is that he describes the higher acts proper to personal beings in a manner that derogates the imputation of potency to them in relation to their acts. This derogation takes the form of distinguishing the receptivity of personal beings-which is "active"-from the receptivity of subpersonal or merely physical being, whose receptivity is characterized exclusively in terms of passive potency. The context within which the question of receptivity in personal and subpersonal being arises within Schmitz's exposition is that of "communication without loss. 1111 Such communication differs from physical activity, in that the "transfer" of wisdom need not imply the diminishment of it in the one who "transfers" it. Hence: What evidence do we have of communication without loss? A most obvious fact is that which many of us have at hand: it is the evidence of teaching, whether formally in a classroom setting or informally in a conversation among friends. For when we bring someone to understand what we have come to understand, or when they bring us to that point, neither we nor they lose the knowledge communicated. 12 11 12 Schmitz, "Personal Becoming," 770. Ibid. 6 STEVEN A. LONG This point is, as it were, one of the bonafides of the presence of positively immaterial or spiritual being. Note, however, the subtle emphasis upon the "merely physical mode of passivity" in the lines that follow: In this communication we meet another indicator of the human spirit and its proper law. In order to receive the communication we must be properly disposed. We must listen to what is being said or be attentive to the printed page. Gabriel Marcel has remarked upon the need to distinguish the notion of receptivity from that of passivity. In receiving a guest or a gift, the recipient is not simply passive. It makes no sense to say that the host has been mutated. He or she is called to conform to the disposition of a certain gracious activity that transcends any merely physical mode of passivity or activity, though the entire performance contains elements of both. The climate of the Enlightenment is very much with us still, and so the notion of receptivity is not easy to understand in a nonpassive sense. The insistence upon the identification of human dignity with autonomy and choice understood as individual independence makes reception something less than a transcendental value that is compatible with and even ennobling to our humanity. Yet nonpassive receptivity is as much a mark of the human spirit as is its activity, and the laws of such receptivity and activity are the laws that govern scientific understanding, artistic creativity, social civility, moral respect, and religious life." This lengthy quotation reveals philosophical contrapositions whose nature is not immediately clear. We are told that "nonpassive receptivity is as much a mark of the human spirit as is its activity." But precisely what is meant by "nonpassive receptivity"? Does nonpassivity mean activity? If so, then is not a comparison of "nonpassive receptivity" and "activity" simply a comparison of activity and activity? If not, then what is "nonpassive" about receptivity? For is not a potency, pari passu with its actualization, actualized? On the other hand, if receptivity is in some proper and limited sense an instance of passivity, then howsoever much it is a "mark of the human spirit," how is it known save through its appropriate actualization? Granted that human receptivity is irreducible to and "transcends any physical mode of passivity or activity," are we to infer that spiritual receptivity is simply unanalyzable in 13 Ibid., 770-71. PERSONAL RECEPTIVITY AND ACT 7 terms of act and potency merely because it is not a "physical" or "material" receptivity? Or is "physical" perhaps being used here in a way cognate with the Banezian use in the phrase "physical pre-motion" (i.e., does "physical" simply mean "real")? But clearly Schmitz judges the spiritual to be real, so to say that spiritual receptivity transcends "physical" passivity or activity cannot mean that it transcends reality. It appears that Schmitz here construes the spiritual transcendence of the person vis-a-vis lower, subpersonal, physical beings in one of two ways. In the text cited above he suggests that act and potency-as principles garnered in the knowledge of sensible beings-are too crude to serve in the analysis of personal being and operations. He seems also to adduce a third principleneither act nor potency-that is in some sense unique to spiritual beings (for if act and potency do not pertain to personal being, personal being is nonetheless a real principle). In any event it appears that by "nonpassive receptivity" Schmitz does not intend to designate either merely a motio-the act of a thing in potency insofar as it is in potency-or an imperfect act. For motion is predicated analogically both of physical and positively immaterial subjects. In this fashion, even positively immaterial beings are said to "move"-not in space, but from potency to act. Only the type of such motion, and not the generic character of the actualization of potency, differs between subpersonal (physical) and positively immaterial beings. And "imperfect act" lies still in the genus of act, and does not constitute a fundamental shift from analysis in terms of act and potency. Granted, then, that a human being "receives" insight in a mode different from that in which a plant "receives" water, the question is whether in the process of each "actualization" or movement from potency to act we may distinguish potency and act. For even in the most densely symbiotic unity of potency and act, if they remain distinct principles, "nonpassive receptivity" will appear an overgeneral and underdetermined notion; that is, it will appear to refer to the process of receiving as a whole, including its predispositions-a process of actualization in which naturally there is a leavening of act before, during, and after the motio from potency to act. Yet description of any movement 8 STEVEN A. LONG from potency to act can be designated as "nonpassive" in this way. At the level of operation, even the carnivorous insect needs to scramble after, fight, and subdue its prey before actually ingesting it; and actual ingestion precedes the assimilation of nutriment. Motion from potency to act is hardly unique to spiritual creatures. Rather what is unique is the character of the potencies actualized: for the spiritual assimilation to the other as other in knowledge is clearly not a merely physical process. Whereas when we receive food we assimilate it to ourselves, as it were, in knowledge we become the other qua other, transcending the limits of physicality. This is the very nature of objectivity: the cleaving to and identification with that which is the case. A fortiori the communication of truth transcends the nature of merely physical communications. But from this it does not follow that intellective receptivity does not entail a richly intricate symbiosis of act and potency. Let us then take as a given that there are two corollary meanings of "nonpassive receptivity" implicit in Schmitz's analysis. It appears that act and potency are considered inapt to serve in the analysis of personal being and operations, being fit only for the analysis of subpersonal beings; and it also appears that a third principle is being adduced-neither act nor potency-that is contrasted with activity and is in some sense unique to spiritual beings. To assess these points it is helpful to see if the analysis of human knowledge in terms of act and potency can do justice to its object. Ill ONTOLOGICAL ANALYSIS OF HUMAN COGNITION Let us consider receptivity from the vantage point of St. Thomas's ontology of knowledge. As nonpassive receptivity is noted by Schmitz as crucial to "scientific understanding, artistic creativity, social civility, moral respect, and religious life, 1114 it would seem one could not do better than to seek to identify "nonpassive receptivity" within the context of the life of the mind. Indeed, St. Thomas himself writes of the intellect: "Now there 14 Ibid., 771. PERSONAL RECEPTIVITY AND ACT 9 can be no contrariety in the intellective soul. For it receives according to the mode of its being." 15 We must, as Schmitz suggests, in an intellectual context "listen to what is being said or be attentive to the printed page." 16 Clearly, focusing the mind to listen, or being attentive, is an act. If this act is not performed, one will not receive that which another intelligent mind may have to bestow. But when the mind is focused, and one is attentive and listening, what then transpires? Does one already know everything the speaker is communicating? Sometimes this is the case-sometimes we are reminded of something that we not only have considered in the past but that we have in mind even as the speaker communicates it to us. But what transpires when we are told something we did not know before? Take the case of a communication in which the knowledge of the listener is genuinely enhanced. By virtue of what has this enhancement occurred? Has the listener not come actually to know that which before he knew only potentially? Why focus the mind, if not to facilitate an act of knowledge? And even when that which one contemplates is something one has previously known, still with respect to cognizing it once again the mind has moved from potency to act. In Thomas's analysis emphasis is placed upon the actuation of intellective potency as the result of several "active" factors: predispository acts (attentiveness, et al.); the actual form of the thing cognized; and the active principle of the mind-the ontological principle of the agent intellect illumining and abstracting its object, rendering it an actual intelligible inseminating the possible intellect and moving the mind from potency to act. Finally, good intellectual habits-"active potencies"-are important in order quickly and penetratingly to "get the point." Let us consider these elements of act pertaining to the cognitional process more carefully. The role of predispository acts is clear: attending, listening, and so on, are clearly acts. That which is being attended to is an 15 Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae I, q. 75, a. 6: "In anima autem intellectiva non potest esse aliqua contrarietas. Recipit enim secundum modum sui esse." 16 Schmitz, "Personal Becoming," 771. 10 STEVEN A. LONG ontological subject in some aspect or other. It may be that we are attending to a person speaking, or to a physical event, or to the subtleties of an emotional situation. But that to which one attends informs the mind. The "actual character of that which is known" is correctly construed in two ways: in terms of its nature or form, or in terms of its existential act. For instance, one may focus the mind upon what the known thing is, or equally unproblematically consider whether it exists in rerum natura or simply as an object of knowledge. Hence the nature of the dinosaur-outside Jurassic Park-while once to be found in rerum natura, is now found only as an object of knowledge. One may focus the mind upon the mode of a thing's being-does the dinosaur really exist, or does it now exist only cognitionally, solely in intellectual intention? In different ways both the existence of a thing and its nature serve as active principles of our knowledge. For St. Thomas the critically active principle of our knowledge is the agent intellect. The phrase "agent intellect" does not refer to a phenomenologically evident datum. Rather it refers to an ontological principle explicating how the human mind abstracts the nature of a thing from material singularity, how it renders the potentially knowable object to be actually intelligible and uplifted from its immersion in matter. In the absence of such a principle, either individuated natures must somehow convert themselves into universal objects of cognition, or else the principle of human knowledge must be treated as immediately divine (or at least extra and supra human), as in the case of Augustinian illuminationism. While St. Thomas concedes that the agent intellect participates the divine mind, it does so as a secondary cause exercising its own very real causality. 17 Some might consider abstraction an activity that derealizes its subject-a principle of illusion rather than knowledge. But denial of the role of abstraction in knowledge appears unfounded in real evidence. For if all 17 Cf. Aquinas, STh I-II, q. 79, a. 4, ad 5: "cum essentiae animae sit immaterialis, a supremo intellectu creata, nihil prohibet virtutem quae a supremo intellectu participatur, per quam abstrahitur a materia, ab essentia ipsius procedere, sicut et alias eius potentias." PERSONAL RECEPTIVITY AND ACT 11 abstraction is held to deform its object, one's universal criticism of abstraction is itself objectively groundless. Only when the nature of the thing to be known (a nature that in the individual thing is potentially intelligible) is made actually intelligible by abstraction does there ensue a knowable object. This actually knowable object moves the mind from potency to act in respect of the thing known. There are not "two minds"the agent and the possible-but rather two powers of the mind, one abstractive while the other is conceptually apprehensive. 18 The object made actually intelligible through illumination and abstraction moves the possible intellect from potency to act with respect to knowing. 19 Finally, in the act of affirming or denying that the thing conceived is thus and so, the intellect returns to the singular existential subject it has objectivized. Whereas truth is found both in sense knowledge and the apprehension of quiddity, this truth is not self-consciously possessed by the mind until an intellective judgment is made wherein "the intellect can know its own conformity with the intelligible thing, 1120 for then "the thing known is in the knower, which is implied by the word truth. 1121 This judgment reflects the actuality of the thing known in rerum natura, and involves adversion to the phantasm and the senses. 22 Ibid. I, q. 79, a. 4, ad 4. The intelligible species is not that which is known, but the principle whereby it is known: the mind does not simply know impressions made upon it-a suggestion quite familiar to St. Thomas long before Hume--since this would imply the impossibility of science and the view that "seeming" is all that the mind can attain. Cf. ibid. I, q. 85, a. 2. ' 0 Ibid. I, q. 16, a. 2: "lntellectus autem conformitatem sui ad rem intelligibilem cognoscere potest." 21 Ibid. The broader passage states that "Veritas quidem igitur potest esse in sensu, vel in intellectu cognoscente quod quid est, ut in quadam re vera; non autem ut cognitum in cognoscente, quod importat nomen veri; perfectio enim intellectus est verum ut cognitum." 22 Ibid. I, q. 84, a. 7: "Dicendum quod impossibile est intellectum secundum praesentis vitae statum, quo passibili corpori coniungitur, aliquid intelligere in actu, nisi convertendo se ad phantasmata." See also q. 85, a. 1, ad 5: "Dicendum quod intellectus noster et abstrahit species intelligibiles a phantasmatibus, inquantum considerat naturas rerum in universali; et tamen intelligit eas in phantasmatibus, quia non potest intelligere ea quorum species abstrahit, nisi convertendo se ad phantasmata, ut supra dictum est." 18 19 12 STEVEN A. LONG This account of knowledge is simply the application to cognition of the ontological principle that everything that is moved from potency to act is moved by something in act. 23 The fuse of actuality runs from the actus essendi through the substantial form and the essence of the thing; the actual presence of the thing to the senses via its operations; the mind's illumination and abstraction of some objective aspect of the subject actually present via the phantasm (but only potentially intelligible prior to abstraction) 24 rendering the potentially intelligible object to be actually intelligible; the corresponding movement of the possible intellect from potency to act with regard to conceiving the thing known through the actually intelligible object; 25 and then, finally, to the existential synthesis of all the preceding cognitive and subtending acts in a judgment regarding the being of the thing conceived via the abstracted intelligible, a judgment that must advert to the phantasm and the senses. 26 This ontological account of human knowing safeguards two important elements. On the one hand, there is an active element in our knowing: the mind must illumine and disengage some potentially intelligible object and render it to be actually intelligible. 21 Knowing is not entirely passive-it involves not merely 23 See ibid. I, q. 79, a. 3; or I, q. 2, a. 3. 24 Ibid. I, q. 85, a. 1, ad 4: "Dicendum quod phantasmata et illuminantur ab intellectu agente, et iterum ab eis per virtutem intellectus agentis species intelligibiles abstrahuntur. Illuminantur quidem quia sicut pars sensitiva ex coniunctione ad intellectum efficitur virtuosior, ita phantasmata ex virtute intellectus agentis redduntur habilia ut ab eis intentiones intelligibiles abstrahantur. Abstrahit autem intellectus agens species intelligibiles a phantasmatibus, inquantum per virtutem intellectus agentis accipere possumus in nostra consideratione naturas specierum sine individualibus conditionibus, secundum quarum similitudines intellectus possibilis informatur." 25 Ibid. See also I, q. 87, a. 1: "Sed quia connaturale est intellectui nostro secundum statum praesentis vitae, quod ad materialia et sensibilia respiciat, sicut supra dictum est; consequens est ut sic seipsum intelligat intellectus noster, secundum quod fit actu per species a sensibilibus abstractas per lumen intellectus agentis, quod est actus ipsorum intelligibilium, et eis mediantibus intelligit intellectus possibilis." 26 Ibid. I, q. 84, a. 7: "Unde manifestum est quod ad hoc quod intellectus actu intelligat, non solum accipiendo scientiam de novo, sed etiam utendo scientia iam acquisita, requiritur actus imaginationis et ceterarum virtutum. • Also: "Et ideo necesse est ad hoc quod intellectus intelligat suum obiectum proprium, quod convertat se ad phantasmata, ut speculetur naturam universalem in particulari existentem.• 27 Ibid. I, q. 84, a. 6: "Sed quia phantasmata non sufficiunt immutare intellectum possibilem, sed oportet quod fiant intelligibilia actu per intellectum agentem; non potest dici quod sensibilis cognitio sit totalis et perfecta causa intellectualis cognitionis, sed magis quodammodo est materia causae." PERSONAL RECEPTIVITY AND ACT 13 our predispository attentiveness, but abstractive acts of the mind. On the other hand, the agency of the knower is not demiurgically independent of the real. On the contrary, the knower's mind is inseminated and actualized by the real, it is rendered to be actually in conformity with the nature of the thing known. "The knower in act is the known in act. 1128 The mind, which is translucent to the real, must become conformed to the real, must actually become that which potentially it is. If the mind is not to be regarded as entirely self-actualizing with respect to that which it knows, then it must be admitted that the mind is a "measured measure," that it receives a crucial impetus to its own achievement from the part of the actually intelligible nature of the thing known. Yet, were it not for the abstractive (and illuminative) agency of the intellect, this nature would not thus be rendered actually intelligible so as to inseminate our cognition and move us from potentially to actually conceiving it. 29 The Thomistic doctrine of the agent and possible intellect hence preserves and explicates at the ontological level the conjoint activity and passivity evident in our experience. Knowledge involves abstractive acts, certainly; but it also and primarily involves cognition of things through the abstracted intelligible species. If St. Thomas is correct in the proposition that "everything that is received is received according to the mode of the receiver," 30 it is to be expected that the nature of the singular thing should be received intellectually by a rational being, that is, as abstracted and illumined: as actually intelligible. And this requires the application of an active intellectual principle. This actual intelligible actuates the possible intellect, moving it from potential to actual knowledge. Clearly here we are in the presence of a most finely and delicately delineated symbiosis of 28 Ibid. I, q. 87, a. 1, ad 3: "Sicut enim sensus in actu est sensibile propter similitudinem sensibilis, quae est forma sensus in actu; ita intellectus in actu est intellectum in actu propter similitudinem rei intellectae, quae est forma intellectus in actu. Et ideo intellectus humanus, qui fit in actu per speciem rei intellectae, per eandem speciem intelligitur, sicut per formam suam." 29 Ibid. I, q. 79, a. 4. ·'°Ibid. I, q. 84, a. 1: "nam receptum est in recipiente per mod um recipientis." 14 STEVEN A. LONG act and potency. But the principles of act and potency-here as elsewhere in Thomas's theory-are kept distinct. If "nonpassive receptivity" means only that the agent intellect-an active intellective principle-is involved in knowing, this is for the unreconstructed Thomist a noncontroversial proposition. "Nonpassive receptivity" will then only mean that in higher beings both higher potencies and higher acts are to be found. But, understood in this way, both plausible senses of Schmitz's proposition fall apart: act and potency clearly apply to the activity of personal beings (this is precisely how this account of knowing is developed!), and not merely to subpersonal or physical things. And apart from intermediary incomplete or imperfect act 31 there is no principle intermediate to act and potency, but only the motion from potency to act by virtue of something already in act. Any purported transcendence of the mind over act and potency, then, appears illusory from an ontological perspective. What of "active potencies" (i.e., habitus)? Do they not offer some solace? No, because they are not active in the same respect in which they are potencies. In other words, the residual capacitywhich derives from the performance of many good acts of a certain species-to act promptly, joyfully, easily, and well, is active with respect to rendering one more proximate to act, but still in potency with respect to the act itself. Otherwise to have a good habit would mean to be in perpetual act with respect to that which is governed by the habit, which is clearly not the case. The Thomistic analysis of intellective act does not, then, afford evidence for a "nonpassive receptivity" unless this phrase simply refers to the distinctive configuration of act and potency requisite for human knowledge. Indeed, St. Thomas clearly identifies the intellect as a passive power in the wide sense that it needs to be moved from potency to act (but not, it should be 31 Ibid. I, q. 85, a. 3: "Secundo oportet considerare quod intellectus noster de potentia in actum procedit. Omne autem quod procedit de potentia in actum, prius pervenit ad actum incompletum, qui est medius inter potentiam et actum, quam ad actum perfectum. Actus autem perfectus ad quern pervenit intellectus, est scientia completa, per quam distincte et determinate res cognoscuntur. Actus autem incompletus est scientia imperfecta, per quam sciuntur res indistincte sub quadam confusione." PERSONAL RECEPTIVITY AND ACT 15 noted, in the merely physical sense of losing an attribute whether proper or improper). Hence after distinguishing first a sense of passivity that involves the deprivation of natural attributes or inclinations, and then a second sense of passivity that involves alteration or movement wherein anything-whether naturally proper to the thing or not-is lost, St. Thomas writes of a third sense of passivity: Thirdly, in a wide sense a thing is said to be passive, from the very fact that what is in potentiality to something receives that to which it was in potentiality, without being deprived of anything. And accordingly, whatever passes from potentiality to act may be said to be passive, even when it is perfected. It is thus that to understand is to be passive. 32 A few lines down, he writes further: But the human intellect, which is the lowest in the order of intellects and most remote from the perfection of the divine intellect, is in potentiality with regard to things intelligible, and is at first like a clean tablet on which nothing is written, as the Philosopher says in III De anima. This is made clear from the fact that at first we are only in potentiality towards understanding, and afterwards we are made to understand actually. And so it is evident that with us to understand is in a way to be passive, according to the third sense of passion. And consequently the intellect is a passive power:u St. Thomas will allow that there is not simply a division between potency and act; there is also in the power that is actualized an incomplete act: "every power thus proceeding from potentiality to actuality comes first to incomplete act, which is intermediate between potentiality and actuality, before accomplishing 32 Ibid. I, q. 79, a. 2: "Tertio dicitur aliqui pati cornrnuniter ex hoc solo quod id quod est in potentia ad aliquid, recipit illud ad quod erat in potentia, absque hoc quod aliquid abiiciatur. Secundurn quern mod um ornne q uod exit de potentia in acturn po test dici pati, etiarn cum perficitur. Et sic intelligere nostrum est pati." 33 Ibid.: "Intellectus autern hurnanus, qui est infirnus in ordine intellectuurn, et rnaxirne rernotus a perfectione divini intellectus, est in potentia respectu intelligibiliurn, et in principio est 'sicut tabula rasa in qua nihil est scripturn,' ut Philosophus