SACRA DOCTRINA AND THE THEOLOGY OF DISCLOSURE BRIAN J. SHANLEY, 0.P. The Catholic University of America Washington, D.C. A S IMPLIED by the title, Robert Sokolowski's recent Eucharistic Presence: A Study in the Theology of Disclosure has a dual purpose: it is both a theological reflection on the Eucharist and "an example of the kind of thinking that can be called a theology of disclosure." 1 What is innovative about Sokolowski's project is that it represents an attempt "to discuss a type of theological thinking that draws on philosophical resources provided by phenomenology." 2 Sokolowski argues persuasively that Husserlian phenomenology, hitherto underutilized as a theological tool (in contrast with Heideggerian phenomenology), provides peculiarly powerful resources for both engaging and transcending the problematic engendered by modernity's psychologistic disparagement of appearances. Through a phenomenological recovery of the dimensions of disclosure latent in manifestation or appearance, it is possible to articulate a kind of theological thinking wherein the display of Christian thingshow they come to light-is explicitly thematized as revelatory and disclosive of the divine. Sokolowski's rehabilitation of appearances is not only an attempt to chart a postmodern ' Robert Sokolowski, Eucharistic Presence: A Study in the Theology of Disclosure (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1994), 17 3 (hereafter cited asEP). 2 EP, 1. 163 164 BRIAN J. SHANLEY, O.P. approach for theology, it is also a self-conscious attempt to retrieve a premodern, patristic style of theology. 3 It is precisely this double project of both engaging the postmodern problematic and retrieving a premodern kind of theology that makes Sokolowski's work pregnant and provocative. The purpose of this essay is to push Sokolowski 's project in the direction of a retrieval of a style of premodern theology that he unfortunately overlooks: Thomas Aquinas's sacra doctrina. In Sokolowski 's reading of the history of theology, the medieval period marks the ascendancy of what he characterizes as speculative-ontological theology, in distinction from the theology of disclosure. I intend to show, however, that what Sokolowski understands by the theology of disclosure is at the heart of what Aquinas understands by sacra doctrina secundum revelationem divinam. Herein lies a certain irony: what Sokolowski (along with most others) overlooks in Aquinas, he also reveals in his articulation of the theology of disclosure. Hence Sokolowski's theology of disclosure can function as a hermeneutical tool to retrieve a proper understanding of Aquinas's sacra doctrina in a way that both enhances and contemporizes the latter. In order to establish this claim, I will begin with an exposition of Sokolowski's general account of the theology of disclosure, emphasizing how it differs from more traditional styles of theology and how it represents a strategic response to the problematic of modernity. Then I will highlight certain fundamental themes in the theology of disclosure that will be helpful in the retrieval of sacra doctrina. In the second section, I will show how Aquinas's understanding of sacra doctrina secundum revelationem divinam is an exercise in the theology of disclosure and how that is reflected in the very structure of the Summa Theologiae. In the final section, I will offer some concluding remarks regarding why this dimension of Aquinas's thought has been obscured and why it needs to. be retrieved. ·1 "The Fathers, in their Neoplatonic style, accepted the display of Christian things as part of the subject of their theology. Emanation, splendor, presence, concealment, and imaging were spontaneously accepted and vividly described. It is this aspect of Christian reflection that the theology of manifestation is to recover, but in a manner appropriate to our day and age and with recognition of the contributions of both speculative and positive theology" (EP, 10). · SACRA DOCTRINA, THEOLOGY OF DISCLOSURE 165 I A) Sokolowski's General Account "One of the central forms of thinking used in phenomenology is the activity of making distinctions .... [it] is a much more strategic part of philosophy than is usually recognized. " 4 Sokolowski accordingly begins his exposition of the theology of disclosure 5 by characterizing it as an "intermediate form of reflective thought" 6 distinct from the traditional forms of faith seeking rational understanding exemplified in positive and speculative theology. Drawing primarily upon history, positive theology aims (1) to show "how the articles of faith are found and developed in Scripture and Tradition" and (2) "to formulate the truths of revelation in contemporary terms." 7 Drawing primarily on philosophy and presupposing the findings of positive theology, speculative theology aims "to provide an ordered and comprehensive understanding of these truths [of faith], using distinctions, definitions, causal explanations, and analogies. " 8 Speculative theology targets the realities or "things" that have come to light through Christian revelation: God; his nature, attributes, and activities; the cosmos; the human being, etc. 9 In its analysis of Christian realities, speculative theology manifests an "ontological" concern to define things and to articulate their intelligible connections. This is the form of theology developed 4 EP, 197-98. See also Sokolowski's essay on "Making Distinctions" in his Pictures, Quotations, and Distinctions (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1992), 55- 91. 5 Sokolowski acknowledges that the term "theology of disclosure" is not entirely satisfactory, but argues that it works better than any alternative candidates like "theology of manifestation" or "phenomenological theology." See the discussion of terminology in EP, 173-74. 6 EP, 5. 7 EP, 5-6. The text goes on: "Biblical studies are the primary part of positive theology, but other parts examine the Fathers of the Church, the Papacy, the Councils, the liturgy, and the general history of the Church as it is related to the articles of faith. Positive theology discusses the historical settings in which the truths of faith have been revealed, confirmed, and transmitted; it tries to shed light on these truths by discussing the historical contexts in which they have been presented to us, and it also tries to formulate them again in terms appropriate to our own context." 8 EP, 6. 9 See the description of speculative theology in EP, 6. 166 BRIAN J. SHANLEY, O.P. and displayed most fully in the Scholasticism of the Middle Ages (and a fortiori in the theology of Thomas Aquinas). Sokolowski distinguishes the theology of disclosure from the two traditional forms as follows: There is room for another form of reflective theological thinking. This third form, which I will call the theology of disclosure, would have the task of describing how the Christian things taught by the Church and studied by speculative theology come to light. ... While historical theology examines facts, the theology of disclosure examines structures of disclosure; it describes the forms of manifestation proper to Christian things. It tries to describe how Christian things must display themselves, in keeping with what they are, and how they must distinguish themselves from things that resemble them and with which they may be confused. Thus, the theoIOgy of disclosure differs from speculative theology because it examines the manifestation of Christian things and not, primarily, their nature, definition, and causes; and it differs from positive theology because it is concerned with the essential structures of disclosure, which would hold in all times and places, and not with matters of historical fact. Although it differs from these two theologies, it is obviously closely related to them and does not contradict anything they establish as true. 10 To connect the theology of disclosure with manifestation and appearance is to confront immediately the deeply entrenched modern tendency to disparage appearances by reducing them to inner-subjective states of consciousness (ideas) that are split off from some unknown and unknowable outer-objective way that things "really" are. This divorce of "mere" appearance from the "real" display of being is one of the main targets of phenomenology's philosophical therapy. Phenomenological thought attempts to recover the connection between appearance and being ingredient in the Greek understanding of eidos. 11 This retrieval is gained not 10 EP, 7-8. This rather abstract discussion of the theology of disclosure provides only the barest sense of the actual reality. The only adequate way to grasp the nature of the theology of disclosure is to consider its exemplification in Sokolowski's treatment of the Eucharist. 11 "Appearance, manifestation, disclosure were appreciated in antiquity; the very term eidos, which was central to the thought of Plato and Aristotle, implies presentation. Eidos primarily means the 'look' or 'view' that things present to us. In modernity, the eidos of a thing, instead of being a disclosure, becomes merely the subjective impact the thing makes on us or the idea that we ourselves fabricate of an unknown thing. The eidos SACRA DOCTRINA, THEOLOGY OF DISCLOSURE 167 by making an end-run around modernity back to a naive premodern posture, but rather by directly confronting the question of appearance as "the metaphysical problem of modernity." 12 Phenomenology does not attempt to refute the modern problematic, however, since such a refutation would necessarily fail insofar as it accepts the psychologistic starting point of an isolated subjectivity in search of reassurance regarding a common world behind the veil of ideas; to begin with the egocentric predicament is to become locked inside a mental cabinet from which there is no escape. Instead, "Husserl helps us to see that the mind is 'outside' from the start and that the world presents itself to man." 13 Sokolowski 's phenomenological strategy is to expose the "problem of the real world" and its constitutive doctrine of "ideas" as a pseudo-problem arising out of a misunderstanding of the status of our speech "about things insofar as they are experienced and spoken about: that is, insofar as they present themselves to us or are intended by us in the various modes achieved'" 4 in (1) pre-philosophical world-directed discourse about things, features, and relationships and (2) our subsequent ontological reflection on them. Reflection on things as experienced in the various modes of intentionality-for example, as present or absent; as pictured, quoted, or remembered-is properly phenomenological. Now one way in which things can be intended is as merely supposed or proposed by a speaker to some hearer through the use of words; when something is intended by someone as presented by another in speech, then it becomes an idea, or a concept, or a proposition, or a meaning. The basic modern error is to reduce this way of intending things, this way of being in the world and allowing things to present themselves to us, to a pseudo-realm of private mental representations. The of classical philosophy is replaced by the 'idea' of modernity" (EP, 183). Sokolowski notes that eidos originally had an ambiguous meaning: "The word means the substantial form of things (a principle of ontology) and also the appearance, the 'look' of things (a factor in phenomenology). One of the benefits we can draw from modernity is a sharper distinction between these two forms of reflective thought" (EP, 193). 12 EP, 184. '·' EP, 182. 14 EP, 191 (emphasis in the original). 168 BRIAN J. SHANLEY, O.P. thing as presented to us in speech is substantialized into an internal entity that is other than the thing itself and so a dubious intermediary between the ego and the "real world." The modern doctrine of ideas is the result of a profound misunderstanding of intentionality: ideas are the postulates of philosophical confusion, not the givens of experience. 15 Once the modern epistemological predicament is exposed and dissolved, the way is open to reconnect being and appearance through an analysis of the multifarious ways in which things manifest themselves to us and become meaningful to us. Phenomenology helps us to recover the truth that the way things are presented to us is part of their being. Of particular importance to the theology of disclosure is a recovery of an appreciation for the way in which things become manifest and meaningful for us as presented by another, particularly in speech. When something is presented to us by another in speech, a new dimension of the world can be disclosed. Speech does not have as its aim the introduction of private mental entities into consciousness, but the disclosure of a new presentational dimension of being. The words of another can alter how we take the world and how we in turn present the world to others. It is the task of the theology of disclosure to show how the world takes on a new presentational dimension when the speaker is divine. B) Fundamental Themes There are numerous themes opened up by the theology of disclosure, but they all presuppose the central issue of disclosure: the new perspective on the world that is introduced in Christianity. It is a perspective opened up not by philosophical reflection, but rather by divine revelation and Sacred Scripture. 16 The key to this new perspective lies in what Sokolowski calls the 15 EP, 190-93. For a fuller exposition of this topic, see Sokolowski 's "Exorcizing Concepts" in Pictures, Quotations, and Distinctions, 17 3-85. 16 "The Christian understanding of the world as having been created by God was not reached through the exercise of mere natural intelligence. It was disclosed through biblical revelation. Biblical revelation does more than give us new information: it provides an entirely new perspective on the world, on the divine, and on ourselves. It engages new forms of intentionality, new modes of presentation, and new distinctions" (EP, 138). SACRA DOCTRINA, THEOLOGY OF DISCLOSURE 169 Christian distinction between the world and God that is disclosed by the doctrine of creation ex nihilo. 11 God is disclosed in Christian belief as being perfectly self-sufficient such that creation is an act of sheer generosity that introduces no increase of being or goodness into the divine nature. 18 That God has originated a universe of beings is an obvious fact, but the sheer givenness of the world takes on a new light when it is considered as profiled against the possibility that it might not have been at all except for the generosity of God. The God who is the Creator need not create in order to be God. God could have been all that there is, alone, without suffering diminution in being, or loneliness. Sokolowski notes that in order to appreciate the originality of the Christian distinction, it is helpful to contrast it with the natural understanding of the world and the divine that is ingredient in "pagan" (i.e., classical Greek and Roman) thought. In pagan thought the divine is understood to be only a part-albeit the necessary, permanent, most powerful, and hence best part-of a more encompassing whole that comprises both God and the world; the divine and the nondivine are complementary correlatives within the larger and more fundamental whole. Within the horizon of the pagan perspective, it is both false and meaningless to assert the proposition that God could be all that there is without a world, since to be divine is to be the most important part of the more ultimate whole that necessarily includes both the divine and the non-divine. In the horizon opened up by creation, however, God and the world do not constitute a necessary whole since the transcendence of the Creator means that God is not encompassed by some larger totality. Because the Creator God could meaningfully have been the whole, what originates from creation does not constitute a greater whole that relativizes the divine to a part. 11 Sokolowski's original and fuller exposition of the "Christian distinction" can be found in his The God of Faith and Reason (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1982), 1-52. See also Thomas Prufer, Recapitulations: Essays in Philosophy (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1993), 32-42. 18 For an excellent analysis of the gratuity of creation, see Kenneth L. Schmitz, The Gift: Creation (Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1982). 170 BRIAN J. SHANLEY, O.P. A proper appreciation of the Christian distinction leads to a shift in our fundamental perspective on the whole and it is one of the central tasks of the theology of disclosure to thematize the importance of that shift. Drawing on Husserl's analysis of our fundamental belief about the whole (Urglaube or Urdoxa), Sokolowski highlights the need to recognize how our conscious reflection on specific parts (here individual theological doctrines) presupposes a more basic stance regarding the whole that normally remains unthematized. Biblical revelation and the Christian distinction shatter the natural whole so that we come to see God, ourselves, and the world within a completely new context. The natural whole is now seen as utterly contingent, non-ultimate, and therefore gracious when profiled against the God who is not a part of the whole and who could have been apart from the natural whole in undiminished being. A proper appreciation of this new whole requires radical rethinking of the ways in which such concepts as necessity, contingency, choice, and agency are applied to God and creatures; 19 it also requires a new sense of absence and presence to do justice to the transcendent immanence of God. 20 It must be recalled, however, that all such further precisions depend upon the more basic Christian distinction as opening up the context in which they can be made. The fundamental horizon-opening Christian distinction must therefore be continually recalled and remade as a remedy to our proclivity to lapse back into the horizon of the natural whole: "This Christian distinction is always energetic and always needs to be worked out and worked through, because we have a permanent propensity to take the whole as ultimate and to see the divine as part of the whole." 21 Understanding the Christian distinction is not like the registration of a fact about a particular thing, but rather it is the disclosure of a new dimension, a new formal mode of presentation. As Sokolowski notes, the disclosure of a new dimension is more subtle and strategic than the discovery of a new fact because "a See EP, 42-51. EP, 194-95. 21 EP, 198. 19 20 See SACRA DOCTRINA, THEOLOGY OF DISCLOSURE 171 form of presentation arises for us and consequently the whole world, and everything in it, begins to look different." 22 A central presentational dimension thematized in the theology of disclosure derives from the recognition that the manifestness and intelligibility of the world are not exhausted by the human perspective. Just as the world takes on a new dimension of presentation when intersubjective experience reveals to us that what we experience is also given to other datives of manifestation or centers of awareness, so too the world takes on a new presentational dimension when we realize that there is a divine dative of manifestation. The world takes on a different look when it is seen from the point of view of the Creator: If the intersubjective dimension enhances the identity and being of things, how much more does this divine perspective strengthen them in our eyes? The world and the things in it are now seen as being known and chosen to be by the Creator. We ourselves cannot, of course, adopt the divine point of view, but in faith we can formulate something of what it is, and we can strive to see the world as subject to it. The theology of disclosure strives to bring out the special features of this dimension, this form of presentation, which is one of the constitutive elements in the theological virtues of faith, hope, and charity. Reflection on the act of faith, for example, must take into account how the God we believe in is presented or represented to us, and also how we understand the world and ourselves to be presented to him. 23 As I hope to show in what follows, this articulation of the theology of disclosure is also an articulation of Aquinas's understanding of sacra doctrina. II A) Sacra Doctrina Aquinas begins his analysis of sacra doctrina in the Summa Theologiae by describing it as a teaching secundum revelationem divinam. 24 As T. C. O'Brien has demonstrated, this qualification 22 EP, 200. 23 EP, 204. 24 "Dicendum quod necessarium fuit ad humanum salutem esse doctrinam quandam secundum revelationem divinam praeter philosophicas disciplinas, quae ratione humana investigantur" (STh I, q. 1, a. 1). The Summa text cited in this essay is the Ottawa edition of 1941. 172 BRIAN J. SHANLEY, O.P. holds the key to the proper interpretation of Aquinas's understanding of sacra doctrina. 25 The necessity of another body of knowledge in addition to the already established disciplines (praeter philosophicas disciplinas)2 6 follows from the revelation by God that humanity is called to a destiny beyond the ken of natural reason. 27 Following genetically or sequentially from the encounter with God revealing, there arises the need for another teaching or intellectual discipline in conformity with the new dimension of intelligibility disclosed by God. 28 Revelation 25 See T. C. O'Brien, "Sacra doctrina Revisited: The Context of Medieval Education," The Thomist 41 (1977): 475-509. The nature of sacra doctrina is a much-disputed point among Aquinas's interpreters. I cannot enter into the debate in this essay; the interested reader should start with 0 'Brien's piece and follow the references provided in his notes. See especially James A. Weisheipl, "The Meaning of Sacra Doctrina in the Summa theologiae I, q. 1," The Thomist 38 (1974): 49-80; Weisheipl's article is the foil for O'Brien's piece and provides a summary of classical interpretations of sacra doctrina. Since the publication of 0 'Brien's article, two important collections of articles on the theology of St. Thomas have appeared: Albert Patfoort, Saint Thomas d'Aquin, Les clefs d'une theologie (Paris: FAC-editions, 1983), and Yves Congar, Thomas d'Aquin: Sa vision de theologie et de l'Eglise (London: Variorum Reprints, 1984 ). I am convinced that 0 'Brien's reading of the first question remains the most illuminating and the most underappreciated. 26 As O'Brien shows, philosophicas disciplinas refers to the entire corpus of human learning ("Sacra doctrina Revisited," 478-92). 27 The corpus of STh I, q. 1, a. 1 as cited inn. 24 continues: "Primo quidem quia homo ordinatur ad Deum sicut ad quendam finem qui comprehensionem rationis excedit, secundum illud Isaiae LXIV: Oculus non vidit Deus absque te, quae praeparasti diligentibus te. Finem autem oportet esse praecognitum hominibus, qui suas intentiones et actiones debent ordinare in finem. Unde necessarium fuit homini ad salutem quod ei nota fierent quaedam per revelationem divinam, quae rationem humanam excedit. Ad ea etiam quae de Deo ratione humana investigari possunt, necessarium fuit homine instrui revelatione divina. Quia veritas de Deo per rationem investigata, a paucis, et per Iongum temp us, et cum admixtione multorum errorum homini proveniret; a cuius tamen veritatis cognitione dependet tota hominus salus, quae in Deus est. Ut igitur salus hominibus et convenientius et certius proveniat, necessarium fuit quod de divinis per divinam revelationem instruantur. Necessarium igitur fuit praeter philosophicas disciplinas, quae per rationem investigantur, sacram doctrinam per revelationem haberi." '" 0 'Brien notes that the preposition secundum has two interrelated meanings in this context: "The first, immediately linked with the derivation of secundum from sequor, is 'following after,' in time, succession, rank, value. The first meaning of the stated conclusion of art. 1, then, is that there is need for sacra doctrina as a teaching following on divine revelation, genetically or sequentially. The second, extended meaning that secundum has is 'agreeably with,' 'in accord with,' 'according to'; it takes on the idea of conformity or SACRA DOCTRINA, THEOLOGY OF DISCLOSURE 17 3 discloses that the philosophicas disciplinas do not exhaust the intelligibility of the real because the world as manifested to human reason is an incomplete manifestation of the world's meaning to the Creator God. The revelation of a divine dative of manifestation who graciously wills to share the divine dimension necessitates a radical rethinking of the whole. The new horizon or whole explored in sacra doctrina originates in the encounter of God revealing and human believing that is described by Aquinas in his analysis of the theological virtue of faith. Some central points in that analysis bear recollection here. The most significant feature of a theological virtue for Aquinas is that it bears directly upon God as its object. 29 This technical terminology wherein God is described as an "object" must be carefully understood. It is not meant either to reify God as an impersonal thing or to register the banal fact that a theological virtue is somehow "about" God. It is rather meant to express the profound truth that what makes a virtue theological is its origination in an immediate, vital, immanent, and gracious personal union with God. 30 To say that God is the formal object fidelity to a model. The second meaning of the stated conclusion of art. 1, then, is that there is a need for a teaching in keeping with, conformed to divine revelation" ("Sacra doctrina Revisited," 493). O'Brien's analysis of secundum relies on the entry in Charlton T. Lewis and Charles Short, A Latin Dictionary (Oxford, 1969): 1654-55. 29 "Et huiusmodi principia virtutes dicuntur theologicae: tum quia habent Deus pro objecto, inquantum per eas recte ordinamur in Deum; tum quia a solo Deo nobis infunduntur; tum quia sola divina revelatione in sacra Scriptura huiusmodi virtutes traduntur" (STh 1-11, q. 62, a. 1). 30 On the meaning of "object" in the Summa, see O'Brien's appendix 1, "Objects and Virtues," in Faith, volume 31 of the English-Latin edition of the Summa Theologiae, trans. T. C. O'Brien (London: Eyre and Spottiswoode, 1974): 178-85. On the idea of God as the object of the theological virtues, O'Brien writes: "the statement that God himself is the formal objective of the theological virtues is the attempt to articulate the reality of such a union of operation, to state what the mystery of grace is revealed to be. That God is object means that the acts of faith, hope, and love exist and are what they are because God communicates himself as the one to be believed, to be hoped in and to be loved in return. The actuating and perfective function of object with reference to act is elevated to a new level, and is delegated to express the actual graciousness of God. The language of object in this use is meant to describe God's giving of himself. The theological force, so far from being impersonal or from managing God, means that the acts of the theological virtues are pure reciprocity, and are freely given responses to God, lovingly communicating himself to man" (184). 174 BRIAN J. SHANLEY, O.P. of the theological virtues is to affirm the central truth of Aquinas's theological vision and his Summa: by grace we have really become partakers in the divine nature. 31 By grace, the soul and its capacities are given a share in the very life and activities of God such that faith involves our intellect participating in God's own knowledge. 32 Aquinas's realism about grace is reflected in his assertion that the formal object of faith is nothing other than First Truth itself (nihil aliud est quam Veritas prima). 33 Faith is an immediate and grace-filled cleaving to God precisely as the First Truth. Faith first accepts God himself speaking and initiating communication (credere Deo) before it accepts what God reveals (credere Deum). 34 Faith is primarily an assent not to a body of propositional truths, but to Truth itself disclosing itself; 35 revelation is first of all a Revealer revealing and then what is revealed. Of course the believer does assent to a body of truths, a corpus of sacred writings, a Church, because God has chosen a specific historical way to reveal saving Truth. Yet it must always be remembered that the assent to these other truths, the various material objects of faith, presupposes the formal object as 31 "Alia autem est beatitudo naturam hominis excedens, ad quam homo sola divina virtute pervenire potest secundum quandam divinitatis participationem; secundum quod dicitur II Petr. 1,4, quod per Christum facti sumus consortes divinae naturae" STh 1-11, q. 62, a. 1. This article points ahead to the central teaching of the Summa on the reality of grace as a participation in the divine nature, articulated in 1-11, q. 110. 32 "Unde relinquitur quod gratia, sicut est prius virtute, ita habeat subiectum prius potentiae animae; ita scilicet quod sit in essentia animae. Sicut enim per potentiam intellectivam homo participat cognitionem divinam per virtutem fidei; et secundum potentiam voluntatis amorem divinam, per virtutem caritatis; ita etiam per naturam animae participat, secundum quandam similitudinem, naturam divinam, per quandam regenerationem sive recreationem" (STh 1-11, q. 110, a. 4). 33 STh 11-11. q. 1, a. 1. 34 In explaining why the virtue of religion is not a theological virtue, Aquinas asserts that acts of worship do not attain God directly as does faith: "Cui cultus non exhibetur non quasi actus quibus Deus colitur ipsum Deus attigant, sicut cum credimus Deum, credendo attingimus, propter quod supra dictum est [11-11, q. 2, a. 2] quod Deus est fidei obiectum non solum inquantum credimus Deum, sed inquantum credimus Deo" (STh 1111, q. 81, a. 5). 35 "Actus autem credentis non terminatur ad enuntiabile sed ad rem" (STh 11-11, q. 1, a. 2, ad 2). SACRA DOCTRINA, THEOLOGY OF DISCLOSURE 175 providing the authenticating force for the assent. 36 Faith always assents to a truth on the basis of the formal motivation quod est a Deo revelatum or quod est a Deo dictum. 37 If by faith we transcend the human horizon and participate in the divine perspective, 38 such sharing nevertheless remains secundum modum cognoscentis. The fullness and simplicity of divine Truth in se is grasped through a glass darkly, in limited and fragmentary ways. 39 Faith is not yet the fullness of vision towards which it points. 40 Aquinas makes it clear that belief, as an intellectual activity, necessarily involves incompleteness and imperfection. 41 In his analysis of the traditional Augustinian definition of belief as cum assentione cogitare, Aquinas notes that it is of the very nature of belief as a cogitare to involve a kind of restless pondering that is ended by a firm assent based not on intellectual vision, as in scientia, but rather on the concomitant 36 "Dicendum est quod cuiuslibet cognoscitivi habitus obiectum duo habet, scilicet id quod materialiter cognoscitur, quod est sicut materiale obiectum; et id per quod cognoscitur, quod est formalis ratio objecti. Sicut in scientia geometriae materialiter scita sunt conclusiones; formalis vero ratio sciendi sunt media demonstrationis, per quae conclusiones cognoscuntur. Sicut igitur in fide, si consideremus formalem rationem obiecti, nihil est aliud quam veritas prima: non enim fides de qua loquimur assentit alicui nisi quod est a Deo revelatum; unde ipsi veritati divinae fides innituitur tanquam medio" (STh IIII, q. 1, a. 1). 37 Super epistolam ad Romanos lectura, c. IV, lectio 1, n. 327 in Super epistolas s. Pauli lectura, ed. Raphaelis Cai, vol. 1 (Rome: Marietti, 1953). 38 "Unde oportet quod fides, quae virtus ponitur, faciat intellectum hominus adhaerere veritati quae in divina cognitione consistit transcendendo proprii intellectus veritatem" (De Veritate q. 14, a. 8 in Opera omnia, vol. 22 [Rome: 1972]). 39 STh II-II, q. 1, a. 2. 40 "Ad tertium dicendum quod visio patriae erit veritatis primae secundum quod in se est, secundum illud I Joann. 3,2: Scimus quoniam cum apparuerit, similes ei erimus, quoniam videbimus eum sicuti est. Et ideo visio ilia erit non per modum enuntiabilis, sed per modum simplicis intelligentiae. Sed per fidem non apprehendimus veritatem primam sicut in se est" (STh II-II, q. 1, a. 2, ad 3). Faith as the inchoation of the beatitude that will eschatologically consist in vision is a pervasive theme in Aquinas. See II-II, q. 2, a. 3 on the way in which faith is the beginning of our learning about beatitude from God our teacher: "Unde ad hoc quod homo perveniat ad perfectam visionem beatitudinis praeexigitur quod credat Deo tanquam discipulus magistro docenti." 41 "Fides autem in sui ratione habet imperfectionem quae est ex parte subjecti, ut scilicet credens non videat id quod credit" (STh I-II, q. 67, a. 3). See also II-II, q. 2, a. 1 and De Verit. q. 14, a. 1. For a superb analysis of belief, see O'Brien, "Belief: Faith's Act," appendix 4 in Faith, 205-15. 176 BRIAN J. SHANLEY, O.P. activity of the will. 42 The will supplies the firmness and certitude that would otherwise be lacking; the faintness of vision is remedied by the influence of love. This means that belief is an inherently restless intellectual state because the mind naturally seeks clarity and vision and so chafes at being brought to assent on the basis of something extrinsic to itself. The intellect of the believer therefore seeks something more akin to the divine vision of the whole. This intellectual questing is both steadied and prodded by the will: "For when anyone has a ready will to believe, he loves the believed truth and reflects upon it and embraces any supporting arguments that may be found." 43 Fides is inevitably quarens intellectum. Faith demands a sacra doctrina that explores the new intelligibility of reality revealed by Veritas prima, a doctrina that explores the godly view of the whole opened up by faith. The conformity to divine revelation implied by secundum revelationem divinam means more than that sacra doctrina develops in a manner that is logically consistent with what has been revealed. At the deepest level secundum revelationem divinam implies a conformity of perspective, a seeing with God; it is a teaching that strives to display the luminosity and intelligibility that the things believed have in God's own mind. The way in which a new intelligible unity or whole is displayed in sacra doctrina is explained by Aquinas in response to the question of whether or not sacra doctrina is one science. 44 He begins by recalling one of the basic axioms of his thought: acts, powers, virtues, and ways of knowing are specified by their formal objects. 45 The sciences are diversified by the different dimen42 "Dicendum quod intellectus credentis determinatur ad unum non per rationem, sed per voluntatem. Et ideo assensus hie accipitur pro actu intellectus secundum quod a voluntate determinatur ad unum" (STh 11-11, q. 2, a. 1, ad 3). 43 "Cum enim homo habet promptam voluntatem ad credendum, diligit veritatem creditam, et super ea excogitat et amplectitur si quas rationes ad hoc invenire potest" (STh 11-11, q. 2, a. 10). 44 STh I, q. 1, a. 3. 45 "Est enim unitas potentiae et habitus consideranda secundum obiectum, non quidem materialiter sed secundum rationem formalem obiecti; puta homo, asinus et lapis conveniunt in una formali ratione colorati, quod est obiectum visus" (STh I, q. 1, a. 3). For a classic text on the diversification of the sciences, see In Boethii de Trinitate, q. 5, a. 1. SACRA DOCTRINA, THEOLOGY OF DISCLOSURE 177 sions of intelligibility latent in reality; 46 different habits of knowledge correspond to the different dimensions of intelligibility. What specifies and diversifies sacra doctrina as a distinct discipline is the new intelligibility of reality opened up by divine revelation: "Since holy scripture considers things insofar as they have been divinely revealed (as already noted), all things whatsoever that are revealable by God [revelabilia] share in the one formal object of this science. " 47 The term revelabilia here bears the burden of describing the new horizon opened up by divine revelation; it denotes the capacity for reality to be grasped in the light of divine revelation. 48 The formal object of sacra doctrina is the intelligibility of the world as spoken by God. Sacra doctrina is a sharing in God's unified view of the whole as an impressio divinae scientiae. 49 Thus theology is a matter not simply of communicating new information, but rather of articulating an entirely new view of the whole based on the presentational dimension that results from faith's encounter with God revealing. The scope and unity of the new intelligible whole given by divine revelation involves an ordering: "it [sacra doctrina] treats principally of God and then of creatures insofar as they are "Diversa ratio cognoscibilis diversitatem scientiarum inducit" (STh I, q. 1, a. 1, ad 2). "Quia igitur Sacra Scriptura considerat aliqua secundum quod sunt divinitus revelata, secundum quod dictum est, omnia quaecumque sunt divinitus revelabilia, communicant in una formali obiecti huius scientiae. Et ideo comprehenduntur sub sacra doctrina sicut sub scientia una" (STh I, q. 1, a. 3). Aquinas shifts between sacra scriptura and sacra doctrina as if the two were largely synonymous throughout STh I, q. 1. While the terms are not synonymous, they are closely connected; see Per Erik Persson, Sacra Doctrina: Reason and Revelation in Aquinas, trans. Ross MacKenzie (Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 46 47 1970), 86-90. 48 The meaning of the term revelabilia has long been a matter of dispute and a proper understanding of it is the key to grasping the meaning of sacra doctrina: "The term does not stand for the later scholastics' 'virtually revealed,' i.e., deducible from the data of revelation. Nor does it have the meaning given in the fanciful interpretation that it covers truths which, in distinction from the revelata, could possibly be revealed, but need not be because they are accessible to unaided reason. In its context revelabilia means simply the quality, the formal interest, or intelligible value in every subject matter that engages the act of sacra doctrina" (O'Brien, "Sacra Doctrina Revisited," 502-3). 49 "Et similiter ea quae in diversis scientiis philosophicis tractantur, potest sacra doctrina una existens considerare sub una ratione, inquantum scilicet sunt divinitus revelabilia, ut sic sacra doctrina sit velut quadam impressio divinae scientiae, quae est una et simplex omnium" (STh I, q. 1, a. 3, ad 2). 178 BRIAN J. SHANLEY, O.P. related to God as their principle and end." 50 God is the true subject of sacra doctrina and everything else is considered sub ratione Dei vel secundum ordinem ad Deum. 51 Thus nothing lies outside the ken of sacra doctrina because in the great exitusreditus of creation everything has God as its principium vel finem. In contrast with metaphysics, which attains only to a whole wherein God is known mediately as the First Cause,52 sacra doctrina attains a share in God's own knowledge of the whole and thus constitutes a radically new kind of wisdom. 53 In the light of this new wisdom, the conclusions of the philosophicae disciplinae are not annulled, but rather relativized; they are seen now as providing only partial manifestations of the world's full meaning. It belongs to sacra doctrina to bring the partial perspectives into the unified whole disclosed by divine revelation; it is a new binding together of God and the world in the light of God's own perspective on the whole. B) The Structure of the Summa The new presentational whole opened up by divine revelation is displayed and disclosed in the very structure of the Summa so "Dicendum quod sacra doctrina non determinat de Deo et creaturis ex aequo, sed de Deo principaliter, et de creaturis secundum quod referuntur ad Deum, ut ad principium vel finem" (STh I, q. 1, a. 3, ad 1). si "Omnia autem pertractantur in sacra doctrina sub ratione Dei, vel quia sunt ipse Deus, vel quia habet ordinem ad Deum, ut ad principium vel finem. Unde sequitur quod Deus vere sit subiectum huius scientia" (STh I, q. 1, a. 7). 52 On the limited character of the knowledge of God arrived at by metaphysics, see Thomas C. O'Brien, Metaphysics and the Existence of God (Washington, D.C.: The Thomist Press, 1960), especially 124-69. s3 "Dicendum quod haec [sacra] doctrina maxime sapientia est inter omnes sapientias humanas, non quidem in aliquo genere tantum, sed simpliciter. Cum enim sapientis sit ordinare et iudicare, iudicium autem per altiorem causam de inferioribus habeatur; ille sapiens dicitur in unoquoque genere, qui considerat causam altissimam illius generis.... Ille igitur qui considerat simpliciter altissimam causam totius universi, quae Deus est, maxime sapiens dicitur: unde et sapientia dicitur esse divinorum cognitio, ut patet per Augustinum, XII de Trinitate. Sacra autem doctrina propriissime determinat de Deo secundum quod est altissima causa; quia non solum quantum ad illud quod est per creaturas cognoscibile, quod philosophi cognoverunt, ut dicitur Romans 1,19: Quad notum est Dei, manifestum est illis; sed etiam quantum ad id quod notum est sibi soli de seipso, et aliis per revelationem communicatum. Unde sacra doctrina maxime dicitur sapientia" (STh I, q. 1, a. 6). SACRA DOCTRINA, THEOLOGY OF DISCLOSURE 179 theologiae. The ordo disciplinae of the Summa is determined primarily not by the pedagogical requirements of instructing beginners in theology (as indicated in the Prologus), but rather by theology's overriding task of articulating the whole secundum ordinem ad Deum or sub ratio Dei. The ordo disciplinae is dictated by the order that things have in God's own knowledge; the ordo of the Summa is not the construct of human rationalization, but rather the attempt to articulate the way the world is constructed by the creative mind of God.s4 The precise nature of the guiding architectonic plan of the Summa theologiae has been subject to vigorous speculation in the wake of M. D. Chenu's groundbreaking work.ss In a modified version of Chenu 's original proposal to interpret the structure of the Summa in terms of the exitus-reditus motif, M. D. Leroy has argued persuasively that the key to understanding the plan of the Summa as a whole is the classical distinction between theologia and oikonomia. 56 Following the discussion of sacra doctrina in q. 1, the first section of the Prima pars (qq. 2-43) is the theological moment of the Summa, treating de Deo secundum quod in se est, one in essence and three in persons. The remainder 54 "II s'agit d'autre chose, pour S. Thomas, que d'une systematisation rationelle, comme chez Abelard. II s'agit, autant que cela est possible, de s'elever jusqu'a voir Jes choses comme Dieu lui-meme Jes voit: c'est-a-dire toutes relatives a Son mystere necessaire, celui qu'il est lui-meme en Son unite et Sa Trinite. Qu'on parle de !'Incarnation et de la Redemption, de la creation, des anges, de l'homme, des sacrements, Dieu lui-meme est le veritable sujet de tout ce que !'on expose, on s'efforcera de penetrer et de construire ces mysteres a partir de Dieu et vers Lui, tout comme ii Jes a et poses a partir de Soi et vers Soi" (Yves Congar, "Le sens de l'economie salutaire dans la 'theologie' de S. Thomas d' Aquin," in Thomas d'Aquin: Sa vision de theologie et de l'Eglise, 76-77). See also the remarks by M. D. Chenu in Introduction a l'etude de Saint Thomas d'Aquin, deuxieme edition (Montreal: Institut d'Etudes Medievale, 1954), 263-64. 55 Chenu 's original article on this topic was "Le plan de la Somme theologique de saint Thomas," Revue Thomiste 47 (1939): 93-107. The same material appears in his Introduction, 255-76. It is the latter work that sparked renewed scholarly interest in the plan of the Summa. For an overview of the lines of the debate and bibliographical references, see Jean-Pierre Torrell, Initiation asaint Thomas d'Aquin (Fribourg, Switzerland: Editions Universitaires, 1993), 219-28. A valuable overview can also be found in H.-D. Gardeil, "Le plan de la Somme theologique," in Somme theologique: La theologie (Ia., Prologue et Question 1), (Paris: Editions du Cerf, 1968), 171-92. 56 Leroy's proposal comes in the context of a review of Patfoort's Saint Thomas d'Aquin: Les clefs d'une theologie, Revue Thomiste 84 (1984): 298-303. 180 BRIAN J. SHANLEY, O.P. of the Summa considers the oikonomia wherein God is considered as the origin and end of all things, especially rational creatures (secundum quod est principium vel finem earum et specialiter rationalis creaturae).57 It is within the divine economy of the Summa that the exitus-reditus schema is central. The second part of the Prima pars (qq. 44-119) is dominated by the exitus or procession of creation from God, while the secunda and tertia partes treat the reditus of fallen humanity to God through Christ, who is our way of returning to God (via est nobis tendendi in Deum). In the context of this discussion, what is significant about the theologia-oikonomia articulation of the Summa's structure is that it discloses a presentational whole that is reflective of Sokolowski's Christian distinction. The theological moment of the Summa establishes God's absolute independence and transcendence vis-a-vis creation. The treatment of God in se makes it clear that God does not need to be principium or finis of anything ad extra in order to be God. In the midst of this consideration Aquinas makes it clear that the key to understanding the relationship between God and the world lies in understanding the Trinity. In the context of explaining why natural reason cannot arrive at knowledge of the Trinity, Aquinas explains the importance of such knowledge: Knowledge of the divine persons was necessary to us for two reasons. First, in order that we might judge rightly concerning the creation of things. For when we say that God made everything by his Word, we rule out the error of those claiming that God produced things by necessity of nature. And when we affirm that there is a procession of love in God, it is clear God produced creatures not out of any need for creatures nor as a result of any extrinsic cause, but rather out of love for his own goodness .... The second and more important reason is so that we might judge rightly concerning the salvation of humankind, which is accomplished by the Son who became flesh and by the Gifts of the Holy Spirit. 5• 57 The distinction between Deus secundum quod est in se and secundum quod est principium rerum et finis earum is found in the prologue to I, q. 2. 58 "Dicendum quod cognitio divinarum Personarum fuit necessaria nobis dupliciter. Uno modo ad recte sentiendum de creatione rerum. Per hoc enim quod dicimus Deum omnia fecisse Verbo suo, excluditur error ponentium Deum produxisse res ex necessitate SACRA DOCTRINA, THEOLOGY OF DISCLOSURE 181 To judge rightly concerning the creation of things in the light of the Trinity is to understand what Sokolowski means by the Christian distinction in an even deeper sense. Indeed, what Sokolowski intends by the Christian distinction might best be termed the "Trinitarian distinction" in Aquinas. It is the conception of God as Trinity that ultimately distinguishes the Christian view from both pagan and other monotheistic views of the divine. To grasp the Trinitarian distinction is to see that God could have been all that there is and completely happy 59 in the community of Persons that is the Trinity quite apart from creation; creation is an act of pure generosity that adds nothing to God. The procession of creatures ad extra is utterly gratuitous because the processions ad intra of Verbum et Amor, Son and Spirit, constitute the perfect plenitude of divine life. Hence the procession of creatures is a pure gift of love that finds its deepest meaning in its reflection of the very processions of the Trinity. 60 The Trinitarian meaning of the exitus is reflected most significantly in the creation of the human person to reflect the image of the Trinity in a special way by sharing in the divine life through grace and, ultimately, the beatific vision. 61 Just as the exitus of creation from God as principium must be understood in the light of the Trinitarian distinction, so too the way in which God constitutes himself as the finis of creation and especially of the reditus of humankind must be understood in the light of the distinction between the triune God and the world. God's decision to share the divine life with humankind as its finis is as sovereign and free as God's decision to create and still naturae. Per hoc autem quod ponimus in eo processionem amoris, ostenditur quod Deus non propter aliquam indigentiam creaturas produxit, neque propter aliquam causam extrinsecum, sed propter amorem suae bonitatis. Unde et Moyses, postquam dixerat: In principio creavit Deus caelum et terram, subdit: Dixit Deus, Fiat lux, ad manifestationem divini Verbi; et postea dixit: Vidit Deus lucem, quad esset bona, ad ostendendum probationem divini amoris; et similiter aliis operibus. Alio modo, et principalius, ad recte sentiendum de salutate generis humani, quae perficitur per Filium incarnatum et per donum Spiritus Sancti" (STh I, q. 32, a. 1, ad 3). 59 Notice that the treatment of the divine essence (STh I, qq. 2-26) ends with a discussion of God's happiness. 60 See STh I, q. 45, a. 6. 61 See STh I, q. 93. 182 BRIAN J. SHANLEY, O.P. more wonderfully gratuitous. Thus the entire moral horizon outlined in the Secunda pars is transformed by the disclosure that human action is a response to the triune God's generosity in creation, redemption, and ongoing sanctification. The finalization of human action by the gracious gift of God's own life requires new resources for human action, that is, the theological virtues, the infused moral virtues, and the gifts of the Holy Spirit. 62 It is vital to note that sacra doctrina involves a new 'frinitarian way not only of seeing the whole, but also of experiencing the whole. 63 The divine disclosure engages and transforms the entire person. By the gracious indwelling of the 'frinity we attain a new perspective that is not a disinterested speculative shift, but rather a complete reorientation of emotions and experience because the knowledge involved is affective, per modum inclinationis; it is a notitia experimentalis, a verbum spirans amorem. 64 It is knowledge by sympathy, familiarity, affinity, instinct, and assimilation; it is the knowledge of a mind in love. 65 62 Sokolowski has explored this theme in his chapter on "Theological Virtue" in The God of Faith and Reason, 69-87. 63 "Dicendum quod cum iudicium ad sapientem pertineat, secundum duplicem modum iudicandi, dupliciter sapientia accipitur. Contingit enim aliquem iudicare uno modo per modum inclinationis, sicut qui habet habitum virtutis, recte iudicat de his quae sunt secundum virtutem agenda, inquantum ad ilia inclinatur unde et in X Eth. dicitur quod virtuosus est mensura et regula actuum humanorum. Alio modo per mod um cognitionis, sicut aliquis instructus in scientia morali posset iudicare de actibus virtutis, etiam si virtutem non haberet. Primus igitur modus iudicandi de rebus divinis pertinet ad sapientiam quae ponitur donum Spiritus Sancti, secundum illud I Car. 2.15: Spiritualis homo iudicat omnia, etc.; et Dionysius