CREATED RECEPTIVITY AND THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONCRETE KENNETH L. SCHMITZ John Paul II Institute Washington, D.C. G AB RIEL MARCEL gave his phenomenological enquiries the name "Philosophy of the Concrete," 1 and he made no bones about the distance between his philosophy and that of Thomism. 2 Between these philosophies there can be no question of an approchement of tone, nor even of manner, but at most a convergence of truths shared differently. Moreover, there can be no doubt that the two philosophies differ in their relation to experience. Within the broad sense of "Christian experience," Thomas drew upon experientia ( empiria) in the narrower sense in order to derive by way of conceptual abstraction the principles of his philosophy, including those of act and potency. Marcel's relation to experience was more immediate, more deliberate, and more explicit. Yet his philosophy has 1 Actually, he usually referred to "concrete philosophy," and preferred "approaches to the concreti>." See the "Author's Preface to the English Edition" of the Metaphysical Journal (Paris: Gallimard, 1927; London: Rockliff, 1952), viiif. 2 In his "Autobiography" (in The Philosophy of Gabriel Marcel, ed. A. Schilpp and L. E. Hahn [La Salle, Ill.: Open Court, 1984], 3-68) he writes: "the essentially Thomist dogmatism I found in Abott Altermann aroused my unalterable protest. At the time, I made several attempts to understand St. Thomas 's thinking better and to read some of his contemporary disciples. But I am obliged to acknowledge that this effort was not crowned with success, and the most elementary fairness forces me to add that I did not carry it out with the requisite earnestness and tenacity. It was at this time that Charles Du Bos and I had weekly meetings with Jacques Maritain, who took great pains to help us understand Thomist thought better and to appreciate it more. All three of us showed good will, but the result was meager indeed" (30). Nonetheless, he showed a certain reservation in his criticism of St. Thomas without, however, much sympathy. 339 340 KENNETH L. SCHMITZ provided an articulate basis in contemporary experience for many of the ideas that underlie St. Thomas 's thought in a very different way. There may not have been a need in the society and culture of thirteenth-century Europe to make explicit in a methodical, descriptive manner the direct experiential underpinnings of such notions as mystery, fidelity, vocation, and community. They were in the cultural air and had taken institutional form as dogmas, vows, art and architecture, religious orders, and a sense of the transcendent in everyday life in and through the visible presence of the Church. These notions were accessible to lived experience and were given realistic expression in the public speech in a way that they are not in the more secularized contemporary society in which we live and think. With us they have, for the most part, taken refuge in the private sphere. I. INTRODUCING RECEPTIVITY Especially important in Marcel's approach to the concrete are the concepts of availability (disponibilite'), recognition (reconnaitre, reconnaissance) (cf. reconnoiter), and receptivity (recevoir) (cf. accueillir: to welcome). Originating from quite different considerations, receptivity has recently been brought into relation with the thought of St. Thomas, through further philosophical reflection upon his texts and through reflection upon the theology of the Trinity. 3 In an article entitled "The First Principle of Personal Becoming," 4 I had sought to identify the mark of spirit in a thought-world that, for the most part, rejects the metaphysical understanding of the person as spirit. I had pointed to the capacity of the human spirit to "communicate without loss,'' as when we do not unlearn what we have known in teaching it to others. This was meant to indicate the traditional sphere of immanent 3 This is particularly true for David Schindler. See Norris Clarke, Person and Being (Milwaukee: Marquette, 1993); and David Schindler, "Norris Clarke on Person, Being and St. Thomas," Communio 20 (Fall 1993): 580ff. 4 Review ofMetaphysics 47 (June 1994): 757-74. CREATED RECEPTIVITY 341 activity as distinct from transitive (productive) physical action. 5 The correlate of communication without loss is reception without (physical) mutation: receptivity. Both together point to a distinctive mode of existence. I had taken the term receptivity in Marcel's sense and had used the term non-passive receptivity to designate this feature of the human spirit. The critique of my own writing on the person by Mr. Steve Long has brought the issue of the relation between these two philosophies to a head. I might formulate the question thus: Are the principles of act and potency (so central to the metaphysics of St. Thomas) adequate to interpret the contemporary experience of the person? 6 Mr. Long finds the aforesaid notion of receptivity to be in conflict with the thought of St. Thomas, and he charges me with three faults: (1) I am alleged to find the principles of act and potency inadequate to account for the personal mode of being; (2) I make of receptivity a third principle that is neither act nor potency; and (3) the error derives from a tooactive view of the person as causa sui. I am further alleged to have unwittingly accepted the modern divorce between person and nature and the consequent abandonment of analogy. 7 What comes in for trenchant criticism is the double term nonpassive receptivity which I used to describe the way the human 5 Cf. Marcel's notion of "meta-problematical" or "secondary reflection": "The Ontological Mystery," in The Philosophy of Existentialism, 6th ed. (New York: Citadel, 1966), 16, 22; aI\d in more detail, The Mystery of Being, vol. 1: Reflection and Mystery (New York: Press of America, 1984), 77-102. 6 See Steven A. Long, "Personal Receptivity and Act: A Thomistic Critique," The Thomist 61 (1997): 1-31. Mr. Long has rendered a service to all who are interested in the philosophy of the person and in St. Thomas 's thought. With characteristic thoroughness he has amassed an impressive set of texts from the saint's works. His argument deserves careful consideration. As to his critique of my own writing on the person, I can only thank him for pointing up the ambiguities that may well dog not only my style but my thought as well. I should make it clear, however, that, while I have always acknowledged my debt to the great saint, I have also always avoided claiming the honorific "Thomist" for my own thought. Still, I must confess that I experience a certain uneasiness whenever my own thought seems to be in contradiction with the balanced and profound thought of St. Thomas. Now it is just such uneasiness that arises as I read Steve Long's criticism of my own essay on the person, for he clearly finds me delinquent in fidelity to the principles of Thomistic thought, and precisely in regard to the principles of act and potency. 7 Norris Clarke's Aquinas lecture, Person and Being, also comes in for criticism as well as his "Person, Being, and St. Thomas,'' Communio 19 (Winter 1992): 601-18. 342 KENNETH L. SCHMITZ person relates to others, insofar as he or she is a spiritual being. I must confess that the double term is a new term for me, but it is not a new concept. 8 The choice of the adjective non-passive was determined in large part by the context, background, and audience in which I first employed the term. In its original version the essay on personal becoming was read to a meeting of the Metaphysical Society of America whose conference theme was that of "Becoming" in its several senses. I anticipated that the audience would be made up very significantly of American naturalists, pragmatists, and process philosophers. I thought there was a need to disengage the notion of "spirit" from the general view of becoming as process, change, alteration, and mutation, without however losing the sense of the dynamism of spirit. For that reason I spelled out what I meant by non-passive receptivity, stressing the distinctive character of becoming without mutation. The term was meant to be correlative with "communication without loss," which I took to be a clear if initial sign of the spiritual order. The passivity that the term non-passive was meant to reject, then, is precisely material, mutable passivity. I did not reject the quasi-passivity to which Mr. Long refers in quoting St. Thomas. 9 That so-called passivity (potest dici pati) is the very sense of passivity in which there is no loss. 10 The translator renders pati communiter as "passive in a wide sense." That is fair enough, but the condition is better served by understanding it to mean "analogously passive," remembering with the 8 Mr. Long's criticism makes me aware of the term's potential for misunderstanding. His criticism would have been more telling, however, had he taken into consideration both parts of the combined term. Instead he has fastened upon the adjective non-passive to the neglect of the verbal substantive receptivity, and has transferred to the combined term a rejection of all potency. Hence the charge that I have invented a new third principle that is neither act nor potency and have divorced the person from nature as entirely active causa sui. 9 STh I, q. 79, a. 2: "Tertio [modo], dicitur aliqui pati communiter, ex hoc solo quod id quod est in potentia ad aliquid, recipit illud ad quod erat in potentia, absque hoc quod aliquid abiiciatur. Secundum quern modum, omne quod exit de potentia in actum, potest dici pati, etiam cum perficitur. Et sic intelligere nostrum est pati" (emphasis added). 10 Towards the close of the article (see n. 4 above) I do recognize certain forms of loss that afflict an incarnate spirit, such as the loss of memory due to its physical basis and the deliberate spiritual loss entailed in moral evil. But the proper mode of spiritual being is communication without loss. 343 CREATED RECEPTIVITY Fourth Lateran Council that analogy emphasizes the diversity of meanings rather than the identity. 11 Far from departing from St. Thomas on this score, the burden of my essay was to recover precisely that sense of non-deprivation proper to personal becoming and to the order of spiritual being. Belatedly, I must admit that with suitable nuances the term non-privative would have fit my intent better. Still, the sense of "communication without loss" fits well with St. Thomas 's clause, absque hoc quod aliquid abiiciatur. It seems to me that the phrase "communication without loss" is a contemporary metaphysical term for distinguishing the spiritual mode of personal being and immanent activity from the sub-personal modes of physical nature with their alteration and generation. It seems to me, too, that the correlative terms "nonpassive [or better, non-privative] receptivity" and "communication without loss" carry the weight of St. Thomas 's absque . abiiciatur. II. THE NEED FOR A METAPHYSICAL GROUNDING OF PERSONALISM Personalist philosophies are a feature of twentieth-century thought. Many have taken non-traditional form through one or another variant of idealism, 12 or by way of phenomenology. 13 But it seems to me that many forms of personalism in this century are rather "free-floating," using a notion of spirit that would benefit by being situated in the context of a more traditional metaphysics of being. 14 What is more, the absence of such a contemporary resolution favors the modern tendency to reduce personal 11 Denzinger, Enchiridion Symbolorum, no. 806 (32d ed.; Freiburg: Herder, 1963), 262: "quia inter creatorem et creaturam non potest similtudo notari, quin inter eos maior sit dissimilitudo notanda." 12 For example, the philosophy of Josiah Royce or of Ralph Flewelling Tyler. 13 Cf. also Maurice Nedoncelle's existential personalism and the sociological personalism of Emmanuel Mounier. 14 An outstanding exception is the metaphysical personalism of Jacques Maritain, which owes its originating principles to St. Thomas. See, for example, The Person and the Common Good (New York: Scribners, 1947). An interesting use of the metaphysics of St. Thomas and phenomenology is found in Karol Wojtyla, The Acting Person (Dordrecht: Reidel, 197 9). 344 KENNETH L. SCHMITZ modes of being and acting to a dynamic network of physical forces. 15 Thus, for example, there is the tendency among popularizers of the natural sciences to reduce knowing to brain chemistry or to computers. And, what amounts to the same reductionism in reverse, the absence of an adequately contemporary notion of spirit encourages the modern tendency to inflate the notion of physical energy and physical process, so that a vague notion of matter is called upon to explain properly spiritual activities. 16 There is need, then, to recover a properly metaphysical sense of spirit in order to meet the present situation, and it is fitting to ask, given the objection of Mr. Long, whether the principles of act and potency (indispensable to the metaphysics of St. Thomas) are adequate to articulate a contemporary metaphysics of the person. · The last great attempt to restore the concept of spirit to philosophical discourse was made by Hegel with his notion of cosmic self-determination (der absolute Geist). There was, however, no role for potency in the system, since instead of a movement from potency to act the determinate was drawn forth from the indeterminate which already somehow contained its determinations. Without dismissing the thought of this great philosopher, yet without detailing my own particular criticisms here, 17 I may be excused in saying that the attempt failed through its immodesty. Nevertheless, to its credit, it did try to take into account modern developments and to reconcile the being of the ancients with the subjectivity of the moderns. Unfortunately, its widespread rejection 15 Examples are numerous, especially among the materialists, positivists, and natural- ists. 16 I have in mind a work such as that of James K Feiblemann, The Pious Scientist: Nature, God and Man in Religion (New York: Bookman Associates, 1958): "All matter is divine, because it constitutes the world and thus serves the reason for the world; and the higher forms are only its complications .. , . If matter in the old sense is gone, so is the concept of spirit, which lived largely on its opposition to matter .... Matter is far more complex than we had supposed. , . , The old materialism was insufficient, but the new is capacious" (70f.) 17 See "On a Resistant Strain within the Hegelian Dialectic," The Owl of Minerva 25 (Spring 1994): 147-54. The strain is a full-fledged nominalism without which the dialectic will not work. CREATED RECEPTIVITY 345 (along with the present rejection of all "grand narratives") 18 has seemed to discredit further the very notion of spirit itself in many quarters of contemporary philosophy. The roots for this incomprehension lie, however, not simply in the rejection of Hegel's philosophy but in the career of modern thought. Ill. TAKING THE RECENT HISTORY OF BEING INTO ACCOUNT In attempting to recover a metaphysical understanding of spirit it is important to take the modern background into account, given that things have happened in the seven hundred years since St. Thomas re-interpreted Aristotle; not even being itself has stood still. Nor has everything that has happened been a falling away from being. If being is truly universal, then modern developments must have occurred within being and be in some sense connected with the history of being. 19 The more so if Marcel's maxim is true-that being is precisely that which withstands every assault upon it. 20 It is important for those who value the great tradition, and who are acutely aware of the deficiencies in modern thought, to appreciate the great advance in self-understanding that has been 18 See Jean-Franvois Lyotard, The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge (French original, 1979; Minneapolis: University of Minnesota, 1984), 31-41 and passim. 19 Cf. the oft-quoted text from De Potentia Dei q. 7, a. 2, ad 9: "Ad nonum dicendum, quod hoc quod dico esse est inter omnia perfectissimum: quod ex hoc patet quia actus est semper perfectior potentia .... Unde patet quod hoc quod dico esse est actualitas omnium actuum, et propter hoc est perfectio omnium perfectionum. Nee intelligendum est, quod ei quod dico esse, aliquid additur quod sit eo formalius, ipsum determinans, sicut actus potentiam: esse enim quod hujusmodi est, est aliud secundum essentiam ab eo cui additur determinandum. Nihil autem potest addi ad esse quod sit extraneum ab ipso, cum ab eo nihil sit extraneum nisi non ens, quod non potest esse nee forma nee materia. Unde non sic determinatur esse per aliud sicut potentia per actum, sed magis sicut actus per potentiam." 20 "The Ontological Mystery" (1933), in The Philosophy of Existence, 14. In fact, Marcel says that "Being is that which is-or should be-necessary," and "what withstands-or would withstand-an exhaustive analysis bearing upon the data of experience." That "should" and "would" indicates that there is no sure guarantee of the continuing presence of being (bene esse) but that there are grounds for tbe hope that it will survive even the most reductionist onslaught. The "should/would" reminds us that Marcel's thought concentrates not on esse simpliciter so much as upon bene esse in keeping with his emphasis on being as full. 346 KENNETH L. SCHMITZ brought about-as a by-product, so to speak 21 -through an admittedly exaggerated emphasis upon self-identity and selfreference.22 The human person has become more prominent, even as its full spiritual nature has been obscured by the parade of terms used during the modern period to disguise its specificity: mind, ego, self, receptacle of sensory impressions, consciousness, will, Dasein, and subjectivity. Literature has done better. 23 There can be no doubt that modern novels and poems, along with modern psychology, present a heightened portrait of the distinctive character of the human person, sometimes in the darkest colors. At the same time, a metaphysical understanding of the person has been all but lost. Admittedly, many of these presentations still follow from the modern sense of self as wholly self-determining (causa sui). Either they still presuppose the confident assurance of the primacy of the self or they react against the shadow of self that still fascinates more recent critics of modernity. Or yet 21 Or, to speak providentially, by the mysterious process in which God draws truth out of error, good out of evil, and unity out of disunity. We human beings do not seem capable of advancing in a straight line, so that He makes our crooked paths somehow straight and our wanderings reach an often unexpected goal; for hope, as Marcel tells us, consists in lending "credit" to being, whereas despair declares its bankruptcy. Is this not a rational act of faith in the ultimate intelligibility of being without which there would be no philosophy? 22 Jacques Maritain serves as a guide in this. For critical as he was of modern developments, he nonetheless was able to see the positive results as well as the negative. For example, in Religion and Culture (London: Sheed & Ward, 1931), 84£., he writes: "To denounce a fundamental spiritual deviation in a period of culture is not to condemn that period .... During the same [modern] period there is an evolution in human affairs, an expansion of history; there are, conjoined to certain evils, gains and achievements of mankind that have an almost sacred value since they are produced in the order of divine providence; we must acknowledge these attainments and these gains." And, in True Humanism (Freeport, N.Y., 1938), 18f., he writes: "Much progress has thus been made, above all in the world of reflection and self-consciousness, revealing often by lowly means, in science, in art, in poetry, in the very passions and even the vices of man, his proper spirituality. Science has undertaken the conquest of created nature, the human soul has made a universe of its subjectivity, the secular world has been differentiated according to its own proper law, the creature has come to know itself. And such progress taken in itself was entirely normal." 23 Milan Kundera in The Art of the Novel argues that while the philosophers (chiefly Husserl and Heidegger) have underscored the loss of the sense of being (cf. Marcel also), the tradition of the European novel, beginning with Cervantes, has preserved the sense of being. For all that, Kundera's own sense of being seems "unbearably light." CREATED RECEPTIVITY 347 again, they are filled with the reductionist tendencies already mentioned. There can be no doubt that the classical modern period, from the sixteenth to the nineteenth century, from Descartes to Kant, exaggerated the relation of self-reference, and presented a relatively closed sense of subjectivity. This was so, even as I began my own studies fifty years ago, though the criticism was already underway. This primacy of self-reference obscured the role of the other in knowing and willing, turning the other into the pale shadow of the self in the form of ideas (Descartes), sensations (Hume), or phenomena (Kant). Nowadays, the deficiencies of the emphasis upon the self-same are familiar to all who have read contemporary philosophers from Heidegger on. And though it had long been criticized by scholastic philosophers on other grounds, this subjectivist tendency has recently come in for further criticism by postmodern thinkers. Indeed, the current effort seems to be to restore some sense of otherness beyond the horizon of the human subject. 24 Nevertheless, the exaggeration of self-same subjectivity ought not to prevent us from recognizing a genuine increase in the appreciation of the distinctiveness of being human. What is more, even though this modern recognition is distorted, it must be conceded that it does lodge the distinctiveness, if not exactly in the classical differentia (the rationale), at least in the region of consciousness. This modern development has yielded a more intensive appreciation of the (sometimes dangerous) constructive energies of the person, which express themselves in an expansion of freedom of choice and a recognition of a certain dizzying depth of human freedom which is not simply a matter of thought but of life as well. Given the climate of latter-day nominalism and the loss of contact with nature in favor of an urban technical environment, the distinctiveness of the human person has led to a quite general 24 Cf. Emmanuel Levinas, Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority (Pittsburgh: Duquesne, 1969), 212f.; and in a quite different sense the effort of Derrida and others to equate otherness with linguistic heterogeneity, but offering us little more than equivocity and a reduction of meaning to non-meaning. See, for example, Jacques Derrida, "Differance," in Margins of Philosophy (Chicago: University of Chicago, 1982), 3-27. 348 KENNETH L. SCHMITZ sense of divorce between person and nature. The prevalent alternatives seem to be either a materialist reductionism or an antimetaphysical historicism. Both alternatives dismiss the metaphysics of being and its understanding of the spiritual dimension of the person. Moreover, these alternatives are often coupled with a dialectical tendency that turns otherness into conflict. 25 IV. THE RECENT SHIFT TO THE CONCRETE AMONG THOMISTS Reflecting these developments, there has been a rather wideranging shift in the understanding of rationality and the expectation of meaning, and this shift finds its expression in a somewhat different emphasis regarding the task of philosophy. Among contemporary philosophers from a number of traditions-including dialectics, pragmatics, existential analysis, ordinary language analysis, phenomenological description, hermeneutic interpretation, and deconstructive criticism-there has been !ill engagement with the concrete order and a general avoidance of strong systematic claims. It seems to me that this recent approach to the concrete has been fed not so much by the general empirical emphasis of modern science, which considers the instance rather than the singular, as by the recognition of the more historical mode of being and meaning that has engaged modern thought, from Dilthey on, especially in aspects of the social, cultural, and historical disciplines. 26 In philosophy, it seems likely that the shift to the concrete has been in response to the inadequacies in evidential practice and theory that have 25 Echoing Nietzsche's "Homer's Contest,'' Lyotard places speech not in the category of communication but in that of the agon, with the slogan "to speak is to fight,'' softening Nietzsche's "noisy philosophical hammer,'' however, by adding, "in the sense of playing" (Report on Knowledge, 10, nn. 34, 35). A common objection by German Catholic philosophers in the second quarter of this century (Romano Guardini, Gustav Siewerth, Eric Przywara, and others) was that, in the wake of Hegel, difference was turned into dialectical conflict instead of into analogous diversity. 26 Within the broad uniformity of logical reasoning, a different epistemology is more suitable to the properly historical aspect of the human disciplines insofar as they do not attempt to model themselves upon the natural sciences. The reason is that the empirical practice in the natural sciences can be accommodated to, though not identified with, the classical division of terms into universal and particular, in the form of class and member CREATED RECEPTIVITY 349 brought about the rise of phenomenology, not only of the Husserlian variety but of the broader type according to which Marcel might be said to be a phenomenologist of the concrete. 27 Now, it seems to me that the charge that "receptivity" introduces a new principle which is neither act nor potency fails to take account of the shift in the level of philosophical reflection. Receptivity is not to be understood simply at the general and abstract level of act and potency. My argument is that receptivity is a principle of personal being at the concrete level. Far from being a-principle that is neither act nor potency, I mean by it an integral mode constituted of both act and potency. 28 Nor has this trend towards the concrete left recent interpreters of St. Thomas unaffected. Indeed, the shift is observable over the past sixty years, as witnessed by, among others, the works of Aime Forest (1931),29 Cornelio Fabro (1938),30 Joseph de Finance (1938),31 L.-B. Geiger, O.P. (1941),32 Etienne Gilson (1942),33 or law and instance, whereas historicity calls for the recognition that the human person in his or her freedom is more than a particular instance of a law or member of a class, and that concrete meaning is more than an instantiation of a general law or class, just because, as we shall see, the concrete incorporates these abstract divisions within its sense of the singular. 27 I have in mind the circle in Munich around Pfander. See Herbert Spiegelberg, The Phenomenological Movement: A Historical Introduction, Phaenomenlogica, nos. 5-6, 2 vols. (2d ed.; The Hague: Nijhoff, 1969). 28 Mr. Long seems to recognize this when he attributes to me a "symbiosis" of act and potency; but he dismisses the value of such analysis by discounting its results as "merely" symbiotic. In so doing he fails to take into account the transformation of the principles at the concrete level as they are operative in the human person. 29 La structure metaphysique du concret selon S. Thomas d'Aquin (Paris: Vrin, 1931): "Ainsi Ia realite de !'essence n'est veritablement pas independante du rapport qu'elle soutient avec existence" (164). And more succinctly in his summary: "L'etre de !'essence est d'etre relative a !'existence" (376). 30 La nozione metafisica de partecipazione (3d ed.; Turin, 1963). 31 Etre et agir dans la philosophie de saint Thomas (Paris: Beauchesne, 1945). 32 La participation dans la philosophie de St. Thomas (2d ed.; Paris: Vrin, 1953). What I have called the shift to the concrete has come about in association with the retrieval of the modified Platonic elements in St. Thomas's thought. Platonic exemplarism is integrated into existential causality. 33 Le Thomisme (4th ed.; Paris, 1942). A comparison with the earlier editions shows that the shift came gradually. See my Gilson Lecture, What Has Clio to do with Athena? Etienne Gilson: Historian and Philosopher (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies, 1988). 350 KENNETH L. SCHMITZ Thomas Gilby, O.P.,34 the later work of Jacques Maritain (1947),35 and the essays of Josef Pieper. 36 It seems to me, then, that the recent development of existential Thomism finds its tendencies realized in a metaphysics of the concrete singular. Providing one recognizes that this shift to the concrete incorporates the recent history of being, and therefore provides a selective interpretation of St. Thomas, this seems to me to be a legitimate and consequential reading of the saint. There are solid grounds in the study of St. Thomas for such an emphasis, even though the emphasis has been brought about by the modern history of being, providing that the end result stands in continuity with St. Thomas as the source of the development, and providing that continuity does not mean simply the repetition but rather the development of his thought. There can be no doubt, however, that a comparison with St. Thomas 's sense of concretum and its variants discloses a certain difference of weight or emphasis within the term as it is now reflected in the tendencies of the above-mentioned Thomists. For St. Thomas, the primary signification of the term in creatures is composition. 37 Nevertheless, he tells us that the term contains two elements: composition and perfection (i.e., completeness or 34 The Phoenix and the Turtle (London: Longmans Green, 1950; mostly written, however, during the war years). 35 Existence and the Existent (New York: Pantheon, 1948; Doubleday/Image 1957). 36 In Guide to Thomas Aquinas (Notre Dame, Ind., 1987), Pieper introduces a further level of concreteness without obliterating the distinction between philosophy and theology: "If Thomas' theological interpretation of this divine name [He Who Is] is a whole dimension deeper than St. Augustine's interpretation, is Thomas indebted to philosophy (or even to Aristotle)? Or is it the philosophical conception of Being which here profits by the experience of theology? Must we not say that what takes place is a unitary act, or a compound of acts which is no longer separable into its philosophical and theological 'components'? Of course the philosophical element can still be distinguished theoretically from the theological element. But concretely the situation is that a living man, confronted with the Whole of reality-one Thomas Aquinas-as believer and thinker (and experiencer of sense perceptions), as a man reflecting upon his belief and at the same time observing man and the universe with all his powers of natural cognition, asks himself: 'What is all this about?'" (152; emphasis added). The word "separable" should draw attention to the fact that philosophy and theology can be distinguished without being separated in a thinker. Such theoretical distinction is not only possible; it is necessary and provides the charter for the traditional metaphysics of being. 31 I Sent., d. 1, q. 4, a. 2, expositio textus: "concreta [nominal autem significant quid compositum." CREATED RECEPTIVITY 351 subsistence, per se existens). 38 The present shift to the concrete is already signaled by the recognition of the primacy of judgment in the metaphysics of St. Thomas. 39 Indeed, the development is called for by St. Thomas 'sown understanding of act (esse) which is at once both comprehensive and intimate, 40 for it recognizes being in its actuality as the ultimate horizon of all reality, truth, and goodness, and at the same time also recognizes esse as most inward within being, as the intensive excellence of being itself. 41 And it is this paradox of utter comprehensiveness and radical inner presence that calls for an epistemology and a metaphysics that attend to the concrete singular and its tensions. Closely allied with this sensitivity to the singularity of the human person is the modern recognition of the historical mode of being, an awareness that has been fostered in modern life as well as in modern thought. This has prompted essays among recent Thomists regarding the tension between being and history in the attempt to accommodate the properly historical mode of being within a metaphysics of being. 42 And, indeed, there are sources within Thomism for the recognition of the historical mode of being. The intimacy of act (esse) in St. Thomas's thought has drawn interpreters towards the not always explicit concreteness in his Aristotelian vocabulary, a concreteness that does not simply belong to its empirical character. To be sure, the abstract nature of thought is rooted in the human condition, for 38 I Sent., d. 33, q. 1, a. 2: "In concreto autem est duo considerare in rebus creatis: scilicet compositionem, et perfectionem, quia quod significatur concretive significat ut per se existens." 39 Benoit Garceau, Judicium: Vocabulaire, sources, doctrine de saint Thomas d'Aquin (Toronto: PIEM 20, 1968). Despite the earlier controversy over certain insufficiently thought-through expressions in the first edition of Gilson's Vetre et /'essence, the primacy of judgment need not threaten the importance of conceptual knowledge; rather it completes conceptualization. 40 STh I, q. 8, a. 1: "Esse autem est illud quod est magis intimum cuilibet, et quod profundius omnibus inest .... Unde oportet quod Deus sit in omnibus, et intime." 41 Cf. Marcel's insistence on the global character of being and the intimacy of its presence. 42 See for example, M. D. Chenu, O.P., "Creation et Histoite," in St. Thomas Aquinas: 1274-1974. Commemorative Studies, vol. 2 (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies, 1974), 391-99. 352 KENNETH L. SCHMITZ the grandeur and the misery of metaphysics is that it al'\l\'.ayshas to speak in limping syllables of abstraction even as it has always intended-at least for St. Thomas-the most concrete of realities.43 This disproportion takes ultimate form in St. Thomas's own thought as the distinction between our modus significandi and the res significata in our predication to and about God. If the foregoing is true, then the translation of reflection from the general principles of act and potency to the concrete order of integral modes is far from a "mere" shift. Neither need it be an abandonment of those principles. Still, in keeping with the general tendencies of St. Thomas 's thought, the shift to the concrete does call for a further deepening of the sense of act and potency constitutive of all creatures as well as a refinement of the properly personal sense of these terms. But, first, we need to take into account the implications of such a shift to the concrete, for it transforms the nature of the subject of metaphysics and calls for a different epistemology from the familiar one. It is not easy to set forth this difference. V. TOWARDS AN EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE SINGULAR As the natural sciences broke away from philosophy during the late medieval period, the shift began to alter the character of the methodology associated with the study of nature, giving an increasingly mathematical character to what was already an evolving empirical study. 44 But, while this changed the "coloration" of the method, it left the received distribution of 43 STh I, q. 12, a. 4, ad 3: "intellectus creatus per suam naturam natus sit apprehendere formam concretam et esse concretum in abstractione." And in the In Boethium De hebdomadibus 2: "ipsum esse significatur ut abstractum, id quod est ut concretum." Cf. STh I, q. 13, a. 1, ad 2: We apply to God abstract names to indicate his simplicity and concrete names to indicate his subsistence, and so "attribuimus ei [i.e., to God] ... nomina concreta ad significandum subsistentiam et perfectionem ipsius, quamvis utraque nomina [i.e., concrete as well as abstract names] dificiant a modo ipsius." Also STh I, q. 3,a.3,ad 1. 44 Olaf Pedersen, Early Physics and Astronomy (rev. ed.; Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 182-213, remarks that "the history of scholastic mechanics is thus not only an account of how Aristotelian theory was repeated again and again, it is also the history of a critical movement gaining more and more strength until Galileo and the physics of the Renaissance administered its deathblow" (191). And he traces in some CREATED RECEPTIVITY 353 meaning basically intact. That is, while it moved away from the ontological understanding of universal and particular, it kept the generic basis for the distribution of meaning intact. It modified the understanding of universal and particular into that of generality and instance, class and member, and eventually into law and case, where law as repetitive regularity eventually replaced causality in explanatory power. Although the basic distribution of meaning into a modified version of the universal and the particular remained in play, the way meaning was distributed in the natural sciences was modified. The result was to displace natural philosophy as the study that resolved motion into the principles of being (ens mobile) in favor of the natural sciences which took motion itself as the basis of resolution. The unexpected result, only slowly and fitfully realized, indeed only during the past two centuries, was the recognition that there is another, more concrete mode of thought open to philosophy. For as the continuum of meaning which subordinated the particular to the general drew away more and more from traditional philosophy in order to assert its own autonomy in the form, for example, of covering laws, a new possibility for philosophy emerged, the possibility of addressing, not the empirical order of tested knowledge, but the concrete order of being. No doubt, the general turn to history in our own time also favored this recognition of a distinctive mode of thought, since history does not rest easy with the view that its particular figures or events are instantiations of a general law or even of a universal category. 45 detail the separation of motion quo ad causam (dynamics) from motion quoad effectum (kinematics) remarking that "at the beginning of the fourteenth century the emerging nominalist movement in philosophy had attempted to give the problem of motion a new basis" (193). 45 This realization may have contributed to the importance given by some Thomists to the autograph terminology of St. Thomas's In librum Boethii de Trinitate. Quaestiones Quinta et Sexta, ed. P. Wyser (Fribourg, 1948); ed. B. Decker (Leiden, 1955). Stress is laid upon the move of St. Thomas away from the language of degrees of abstraction to recognition of a break between the natural and mathematical modes of thought, on the one hand, and, on the other, the metaphysical, which takes as its proper mode neither abstractio totius nor abstractio formae but separatio. See A. Maurer, The Division and Methods of the Sciences (Toronto: PIMS, 1963). 354 KENNETH L. SCHMITZ It is as though the search for the intelligibility of being has urged metaphysics on towards the singular, an exigency brought about by the history of being itself. But if most personalisms are in need of an adequate metaphysics of being, a Thomism that moves towards the concrete singular needs to think through to a modified epistemology in keeping with that metaphysics. Now, a finite being is more than an individual (ens indivisum) though not thereby a simple unit (ens indivisibile). A concrete finite being is, as Thomas acknowledges, a composite; but we have seen that he also asserted that it is complete. It is this completeness that, it seems to me, is the real terminus and attraction for the shift towards a metaphysics that seeks the intelligibility of the concrete. It is, as we will see, an open completeness. 46 Now, the concrete singular is not the empirical particular, and certainly not an isolated atom. Insofar as it is composite, the singular includes within its constitution all manner of relations to others. So did Leibniz's monads; but the concrete metaphysical singular differs from Leibniz's monads in two very important ways. First, it is not without "windows,'' that is, real relations; indeed it is constituted by its relations to others, including relations of causality and participation. 47 Second, the Leibnizian monad mirrors the whole universe uniquely by way of exemplarity as its exemplans, whereas the metaphysical singular participates in a manifold of causalities. Nevertheless, each being is an ingathering (esse-in) of the principal causal energies, principles, and transcendentals of being as such. Unlike the monad, the singular does not mirror the universe, except insofar as it actualizes the requirements of being. This means that the "' Lest the notion of an open completeness seem too paradoxical for St. Thomas, we may recall his understanding of the human soul as an incomplete substance. STh I, q. 75, a. 2, ad 1: In contrast to a complete substance (pro subsistente completo in natura alicuius speciei), "potest dici [of the human soul] quad hoc aliquid ... quasi subsistens." Also Q. D. de Anima, a. 1, ad 3: "anima humana non est hoc aliquid sicut substantia completiva [or completa]." 47 I have earlier ("Is Liberalism Good Enough?" in Liberalism and the Good, ed. Bruce Douglass et al. [London: Routledge, 1990], 86-104) used the term "constitutive individual," but that remains too much within the orbit of the traditional theory of meaning, and too close to Hegel's concrete universal which operates within that traditional theory. CREATED RECEPTIVITY 355 singular incorporates within itself those requirements without which no created being can be. What are these requirements? Thomas sums them up with the words esse et praeter esse, existence and everything else.48 Praeter: For that reason there should be no fear that the ontological ground of natural law is destroyed, since the requirement of finite being is to have a determinate nature. Nor are the principles of strict demonstration rendered ineffective, since they too are grounded in the causalities that are constitutive of the singular being. Finally, to assert that the inclination of metaphysical reflection terminates, not in the empirical, but ultimately in the singular, does not require a Scotistic intellectual intuition of the singular, but only a recognition of the singular character of being in a judgment that terminates in the actual existence of things. 49 All the principles remain in play. We may well ask, then, what difference does this drive to the concrete singular make? First of all, metaphysics no longer hankers after a systematization of objective knowledge, even as an ideal, but rather attends to the gathering of the principles of being insofar as they terminate in the community of beings. Ens commune is understood principally as the community of beings and not merely as an ens rationis. Language is re-opened to the concrete and reverses the modern penchant which places secondorder language in a position of dominance over first-order 48 ScG II, cc. 52-54. See the remarks of Serge-Thomas Bonino, O.P., in Revue Thomiste 95 (1995): 495 regarding my own emphasis, to the effect that it risks rejecting the "by no means negligible" other aspects of St. Thomas 's thought. It seems to me, however, that the risk must be undertaken to bring out the radically metaphysical character of his thought, especially now that the philosophical viability of the notion of creation is at stake. But an existential reading need not abandon these "by no means negligible" aspects (praeter esse), once the nature and status of essence is secured within its relation to existential act. 49 Maurer, Division and Methods, xxi: "For judgment is primarily pointed to the act of existing of things, whereas simple apprehension has to do rather with their essences or natures. As a result, the subject of metaphysics will have an existential character not found in those of the other two speculative sciences." It may help to distinguish the real as extra-mental (objective), which the natural sciences address, from the real as existential, which is the domain of metaphysics. 356 KENNETH L. SCHMITZ language. 50 Such a metaphysics of the singular becomes more descriptive of actual situations than abstracted from them. It recognizes contingent relations not only as accidental to a substance, but even more as historical developments within concrete beings. The principal difference is this: esse, since it isformalissime in each singular being, since it is the superabundance of act within the limits of the received nature of the singular, thereby opens up from within each being the intelligibility of its singularity ,51 opens to its circumstances and contingencies, in a word, to its history-properly to human history, but in an extended sense to the recognition that all created beings have a "history." Esse, more formal, indeed transformal, and so more actual than anything else in the being, charges the other principles with a kind of hyper-determinacy that realizes itself only in the concrete order of being, in a certain fullness or completeness. 52 VI. FURTHER REFLECTION ON ACT AND POTENCY IN CREATURES The charge that I have introduced a third principle forces the issue, then, of whether act and potency are adequate to provide 50 I have made the distinction between epistemic and noetic discourse in several essays. The former proceeds with a more or less definitive prior demand for what counts as evidence (e.g., only quantified data), for proof (e.g., verification or falsification), and for truth (e.g., what is fruitful for further experimental research), whereas the latter approaches reality with a more open yet not less rigorous expectation of meaning in search of the concrete. See "Metaphysics: Radical, Comprehensive, Determinate Discourse," Review of Metaphysics 39 (June 1986): 675-94. Again, compare Marcel's distinction between primary and secondary reflection, or between problematic and meta-problematic discourse. 51 Cf. de Finance, Etre et agir, 321: "Mais si la forme n'est pas l'actualite la plus profonde de l'etre, la vision des essences ne peut plus combler un esprit dont !'ambition est de posseder l'etre dans ses profondeurs. La connaissance de la realite concrete presente pour moi un double interet: un interet pratique, puisque ce monde reel forme le cadre de ma vie et !'ensemble des moyens qui me serviront a conquerir ma fin;-mais aussi, semble-t-il un interet speculatif. Fondement de l'intelligibilite, se peut-il que !'existence n'ait aucune valeur intelligible? Le concret, dans une metaphysique de l'esse doit-il pas etre la pature par excellence de !'esprit?" The passage brings out the integration of praxis and theoria in the concern for the concrete. 52 Marcel remarks ("The Ontological Mystery," 12): "Providing it is taken in its metaphysical and not its physical sense, the distinction between thefull and the empty seems to me more fundamental than that between the one and the many." CREATED RECEPTIVITY 357 a basic account of personal being. But before that, it raises the issue of whether these principles are universally adequate to account for created being; for if the real composition of act and potency fails to account for the constitution of created personal being, then such a composition cannot lay claim to complete universality in the order of created being. Moreover, we cannot resolve the relation of act and potency within created persons without first determining the character of that relation as it holds for all creatures. It remains, therefore, to probe the precise character of the transformation in the meaning of act and potency that occurs in the shift to the concrete, as it discloses first the general condition of the creature and then that of the created person. A brief, if well-known and no doubt unneeded, reminder of the history of these principles illustrates the radical nature of the transformation in the understanding of act and potency brought about by the recognition of being qua created. The insight into potency (dunamis) had initially come about through Aristotle's reflection upon change and the principles needed to resolve the apparent impasse of the Eleatics. His distinction (already anticipated by Plato) within the unanalyzed notion of non-being between what we might call the simple privative meaning (the absolute negation, ouk on) and the qualified or relative negation (me on) released the notion of qualified non-being to indicate a potential principle in the explanation of change: 53 for the potential is the able-but-not-yet of the subject in accidental change and analogously the able-but-not-yet of primary matter in substantial change. With his sense of creation ex nihilo, St. Thomas interprets the distinction by situating potency within a more radical context of being. 54 53 Metaphysics XII (L), 2, 1069b15-20; also VII (Z), 7-9, 1032a12-1034b19. Cf. the many senses of potency in St. Thomas, V Metaphys., lect. 13. It is characteristic of St. Thomas's project of commenting upon Aristotle that (as far as I can tell) he entirely avoids discussion of the principle of potency in relation to creation, not only in this work but in all of the Aristotelian commentaries. 54 See St. Thomas, XII Metaphys., Parma ed. (1868), lect. 2, 624: "Solvit autem hanc dubitationem antiquorum naturalium philosophorum, qui removebant generationem propter hoc, quod non credebant quod posset aliqui fieri ex non ente, quia ex nihilo fit nihil; nee etiam ex ente, quia sic esset antequam fieret. Hane ergo dubitationem 358 KENNETH L. SCHMITZ With the entry of the doctrine of creation, however, comes a deeper sense of potentiality: for the potential is not potentiality to the reception of form (eidos) on the part of matter (hyle) or subject (hypokeimenon), but the reception of being where there had been none at all (esse absolute seu simpliciter). 5' In this sense, one might say, not without a touch of paradox, that the recognition of creation gives new meaning to the notion of absolute non-being without returning the notion to the dead-end auk on/' God's creative act is so powerful that, after the fact, it throws light even upon absolute non-being, and endows the very contingency of the creature (its always present non-being that constitutes its contingency) with the abundance of the Creator's own gift. And it draws our attention to the fragility and utter gratuity of any and all created existence, so that in a mysterious Philosophus solvit, ostendendo qualiter aliquid fit ex ente et ex non ente; dicens, quod duplex est ens, scilicet ens actu, et ens potentia." I am aware of a certain difference in emphasis between Thomas's account and my own, insofar as mine places an emphasis upon non-being that is absent from St. Thomas's, though the emphasis, I believe, is compatible with his understanding of creation ex nihilo. '' STh I, q. 44, a. 2, ad 1: "Dicendum quod Philosophus in I Phys. (7, c. 9, 190bl) loquitur de fieri particulari, quod est de forma in formam, sive accidentalem sive substantialem; nunc autem loquimur de rebus secundum emanationem earum ab universali principio essendi" (emphasis added). 56 For the insightful texts of St. Anselm on the new sense of "nothing," see M onologium 8-9 (S. Anselmi Opera Omnia, ed. F. S. Schmitt [Stuttgart: Fromann, 1968], vol. 1, pp. 2224; English translation, 2d ed. by J. Hopkins and H. W. Richardson [Toronto: Edwin Mellen, 1975], 15-18). See also my reflection upon these texts in The Gift: Creation (Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1982), 28-34, esp. 32: "The term [de nihilo] denotes after the fact the state of affairs before the endowment. It makes no strict sense to say, before I have received a gift, that I am giftless, as though there is a lack in me in the way that a painting lacks the right colour .... Certainly, before I have received a gift, I am without a gift; I simply do not have one. But I do not lack something due me. And yet, viewed after the fact, after the endowment, the lack of that endowment is more than a simple negation .... We have more here than a simple negation, but we have it only after the fact, not before. The gift is not as such a remedy for some lack, but is rather an unexpected surplus that comes without prior conditions set by the recipient. The element of gratuity indicates that there is no ground in the recipient for this gift, so that the gift is strictly uncalled for. It is not compensation for anything .... Creation is to be understood as the reception of a good not due in any way, so that there cannot be even a [preexistent] subject of that reception. It is absolute reception, there is not something which receives, but rather sheer receiving." Incidentally, this new sense of non-being is also the condition for the modern sense of dialectics; though, because it repudiates a notion of creation, dialectics gives too much to the power of the negative within non-being. CREATED RECEPTIVITY 359 way we draw fresh meaning from the contrast of being with that dark region of absolute non-being. It is as though the very gift of being does not leave the creature's non-being untouched; its very non-being is gifted too. This is not to give some pseudo-positive reality to non-being; quite the opposite, it is to highlight its utter negativity by deepening the sense of contingency. The early Fathers of the Church were conscious of the distinctive character of God's creative act. They insisted that creation ex nihilo is not a motion, neither an alteration nor a generation, because these require a pre-existent subject. Even more, they insisted that creation is not a labor at all,57 and that it is an effortless actuation at the most fundamental level of reality: divine "communication without loss." What, then, has happened to potency? We must look to act, in keeping with its primacy, in order to determine the character of the indeterminacy and otherness that is characteristic of potency. For the Aristotelian understanding of potency posits a pre-existent recipient (ultimately, underived matter) whereas potency to being simultaneously demands that there can be no recipient before the reception itself has been achieved. 58 And so creation ex nihilo is to be understood as the endowment of the capacity to receive being in the very communication in which that actuality is being received. Nature, or properly the essence (essentia), functions as the potential principle that marks the finitude (receptive dependency, radical contingency) of created being and ensures its limited integrity (per essentiam/naturam). A creature, then, is nothing but the relation of dependence upon the proper cause of its being: tantum esse ad Deum. But that "nothing but" is everything for the creature! 5 ' Cf. St. Athanasius, Contra Arianos 2, c. 17, n. 1 (Oxford, 1844), 315f. (PG 26:197), writes, "For God is not wearied by commanding ... but he willed only; and all things subsisted." Also Hyppolytus, Against Noetus, c. 10 (PG 10:818) insists that "the divine will in moving all things is itself without motion." Then, too, St. John Damascene, On the Orthodox Faith 2, c. 29 (PG 94:964) remarks, "He wills all things to come to be and they are made." Cf. Judith 16:17: "You spoke and things came into being." 58 Without in any way suggesting that Marcel thinks in terms of act and potency, it is perhaps worth noticing his remark that I must already be and be within being before I can question being. That is the basic feature of ontological mystery, that it encroaches upon its own data; "The Ontological Mystery," 19-20 and passim. 360 KENNETH L. SCHMITZ VII. THE CREATURE AS SUBSISTING RELATION It is in this sense that I dare to say that a creature is a subsisting relation, knowing full well the privileged use of the term for the persons of the Trinity. 59 The inequality and limitation inherent in the relation of dependence is such as to ensure the distinction between God and creatures. The advantage of the term is that it removes all suggestion of absolute autonomy from the creature at the originating level of its being. The foregoing reflection on the creature as subsisting (yet dependent) relation is meant to remove all traces of potency as in any way a prius to God's creative act. For His is the act which, with the touch of eternity, endows the being of the creature simultaneously with essence and existence. Once again, as with the turn to the concrete singular and its historicity, it is noteworthy that this emphasis upon the primacy of relation parallels the emphasis on relationality which has become a basic theme-one might well say, a preoccupation-of twentieth-century thought. Not surprisingly, the shift to relationality in contemporary thought arises from different considerations 59 I recognize that this term is privileged by St. Thomas for the divine persons of the Trinity and that it is one of his keenest and most fruitful insights (STh I, q. 29, a. 4: "Persona igitur divina significat relationem ut subsistentem"). I also recognize that in his argument he refers the designation human person to the individual substance and with the impeccable logic of genus and specific difference excludes subsistent relation from the term person when applied to man. It is only the identity of the relations with the divine essence itself that permits him to conclude that the divine persons are subsistent relations, or more precisely, distinct relations subsisting in the divine essence. Of course, the term relation in the two denominations is analogously diverse. Moreover, there are sufficient ways of avoiding confusion with created beings. Ian Ramsey (Religious Language [New York: Macmillan, 1957], 182ff.) has indicated the linguistic ways in which such a distinction is made: the divine person of Christ is Son of the Father, but He is begotten not made, only Son of the Father, eternally begotten, one in being with the Father, etc. These are "qualifiers" of the original model (father-son). The Father and the Spirit can be differentiated from creatures in similar ways through relations of origin. Or we can phrase the difference expressed by many of the Fathers of the Church in terms of Christ being equal to the Father in essence and His Son by nature (kata physin), whereas we are sons by the grace of adoption (kata charin) (cf. St. Athanasius, De Decretis, in The Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers, 2d ser., vol. 4 [repr.; Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1987], 156). The value of the term subsistent relation as applied to creatures is that it manifests the radical dependence for all that is in them through participation in the communicatio entis flowing from the First Being. CREATED RECEPTIVITY 361 and has taken forms other than the metaphysical relation of creation. Thus, for example, in first philosophy there is Heidegger's In-der-Welt-Sein; in philosophy of science, Ernst Cassirer's notice of the withering away of substance in favor of function and law; in philosophy of religion, Buber's relation of I-Thou and I-It; and most recently, in the philosophy of language, the postmodern stress on intertextuality. In much of the thought of the past two centuries, however, otherness has been understood in terms of conflict (dialectics) or equivocity (deconstruction). It is as though nominalism has turned twice upon itself: first in modernity which, having given the primacy to self-identity in the form of self-reference, yet re-established unity as totality through a comprehensive system of external relations among utterly simple self-identical units. 60 Then, the first post-Kantian attempts to overcome the restrictive self-reference understood otherness in terms of conflict (dialectics), whereas the full-blown rejection of self-reference and totality has given primacy to otherness in the form of a modified equivocity (deconstruction). In rejecting the modern fascination with totality, postmodernism seeks to prolong nominalism by reinstating the reign-not so much of the other, and certainly not of the Other-but of otherness in the form of relations of contrast. It seems that nominalism eats its own children. It will undoubtedly produce further variations, but what seems likely is that it will turn all relations into features that are arbitrary and quasi-external. 61 Not unaffected by the widespread promotion of relationality, Thomists of the concrete have followed their own path, drawing however upon the thought of St. Thomas. All Thomists agree that the creature exists in total dependence upon the Giver of being, and that dependence is to be understood in terms of the 60 Newton's Principles of Natural Philosophy gives us the paradigm, but Kant's architectonic system provides its philosophical justification by moving towards an incomplete internalization of relations determined by the "needs of reason." 61 The root of much linguistic theory is, of course, de Saussure, who sought a theory of language in which meaning played a minimal part, if at all, and who found in language "only [arbitrary] differences" (Course in General Linguistics [La Salle, Ill.: Open Court, 1986], 118; cf. 67-69, 115). 362 KENNETH L. SCHMITZ category of primary cause and effect. This is to look at the ontological relation from the point of view of the communication of being. What is it to look at it from the point of view of the reception of being? Since the dependence is total, everything in the creature is gifted, so that even act itself is included in that reception; created esse is itself receptive. 62 The meaning of all the causes and principles within the being are thereby transformed. What, then, is the inner content of that relation? Certainly the potentiality of the creature (essentia in the broad sense) 63 is included within that ontological relation, and it plays its role as a co-principle of "ontological reception"; essence is the principle within the created being that is the intrinsic "receptor" of being. 64 But it is not only potency that is received; the act is received as well, because the whole being (essence and existence) is received. God creates beings whole and entire, singular beings in community. He does not put together principles of act and potency that are antecedent in any sense. The ontological relation determines the act at its very core as a received act. We must, then, include created act within the notion of ontological reception. 65 Created act is a received act. Moreover, everything in the created being is 62 See the exchange between David Schindler and Norris Clarke regarding Clarke's Aquinas lecture, Person and Being, and in particular Schindler's insistence upon a threefold moment within the relation of creation: esse-ab, esse-in, and esse-ad, in which the latter two have as their prius the first, so that the esse of the creature is through and through receptive (Schindler, "Norris Clarke on Person, Being, and St. Thomas," 586-88). 63 What, as we have seen, in a felicitous phrase St. Thomas calls praeter esse. ScG 2, c. 52: "Esse autem, inquantum est esse, non potest esse diversum: potest autem diversificari per aliquid quod est praeter esse." 64 At first glance, the terms receptus and receptio are not very suitable, for they mean the "re-taking" of something, "taking again." But the "re-" also functions as a reflexive intensifier, and there are usages in which the term means "taking upon oneself" (cf. ens per se) and even "taking up an obligation" (cf. Marcel's "answering a call"). This ls surely the basis for the "re-sponse" to which all created beings, and in a special way, personal beings are called. The term can also mean "to accept" and "to preserve," and these latter senses are more suitable in the present context. 65 David Schindler puts the question well in pressing Norris Clarke's fine analysis further: "How can relationality ... be said to be ... 'an equally primordial dimension of being' ... if relationality begins not in first but in second act," that is, not in esse but in agere (Schindler, "Norris Clarke on Person, Being, and St. Thomas," 582). Clarke replies that the agere is an expression of esse, thus seeming to endorse a Thomistic version of the Dionysian principle that esse is expansive, as though to say: esse est diffusivum sui CREATED RECEPTIVITY 363 penetrated by this receptive relation. Since act determines everything within the being, it follows that the meaning of all the causes and principles of the being reflect this reception. It is not only the agency of the creature (its secondary activity) that is affected by its participation. All the causes are affected. Matter is not uncaused nor out of itself but is ex nihilo; 66 finality, as the first of causes, is no longer understood as only an immanent principle specifying the end, but is also simultaneously that immanent/transcendent principle by which the being is called forth into existence; 67 and form participates in esse as the first formal perfection of finite 68 substantial being. When the seventeenth-century philosophers threw out the four causes, they not only cast aside Aristotle, they also disavowed the transformed senses of these principles and thereby began the elimination of intelligibility from the very notion of creation, which ceased to play a role in the modern understanding of reality. So far, then, through its total dependence upon God, we have understood the creature as a subsisting relation. The creature is an effect of God's communication of being and stands in causal dependence upon God as upon the Cause of its being. The absolute nature of ontological dependence entitles us to use the category of gift to articulate the implications of the relation, since it belongs to a gift to be uncalled for, to be given without prior conditions. Now reception is integral to the very character of a gift, for a gift refused is an unfinished gift. At this absolute level of the reception of being the refusal can only occur within the primordial reception, even as the non-being of privation can (ibid., 593). I find the invocation of the expansive principle an interesting opening to further reflection, but at the same time I agree with Schindler that we must press home the received character of created act in the most explicit and intensive manner, finding its receptive character not simply in the expression of the creature's activity or its tendency towards expression but in the very character of the instituting act itself. 66 STh I, q. 44, a. 2: "Utrum materia prima sit creata a deo." 67 See the analysis of finality by Gerard Smith, S.J., The Philosophy of Being (New York: Macmillan, 1961), ch. 8, esp. p. 109, which brings out the double determinant in final causality, its formal and its existential role. The whole book considers the transformed meanings of act, potency, and the causes in the light of existential act. 68 See Hegel's acute discussion of the difference between the mere limit (die Grenze, Aristotle) and the positive finite (das Endliche, Christianity) in The Science of Logic, book 1, sect. 1, ch. 2, B. 364 KENNETH L. SCHMITZ arise only on the supposit of finite being. And just as non-being threatens the destruction of being, so too the refusal can penetrate to the depths of a received being, distorting it in the most radical way. 69 On the other hand, the acceptance completes the gift, fulfills it. This creaturely acceptance takes the form of ontological self-affirmation (ens per se subsistens).70 And, since it is first act that is being received, it is received as act at a level deeper and more original than secondary activity which is grounded in and expressive of first act. It follows, then, that both first act and secondary activity are re-sponses. At the level of first act, however paradoxical it sounds, the creature accepts its being in the very reception of it (esse-ab). How are we to understand this, since the creature does not stand outside the relation so as to receive being before it even exists? We must understand the acceptance as expressed by its subsistent self-reference (autos, per se) and within its primordial ordination towards the Source of the being communicated to it without which there would be no self (autos), so that its original reception is communicated to it in its very institution. This relation to self and Source is the tension-one might say, paradox-of finite being. Metaphorically, the flow from God (influxus entis, esse-ab) is such that it is completed only in a flow back towards the source (reditus entis, esse-ad). This means that the created "self" of each being is preserved only through reference to the Creative Other. This communication and response is the initial generosity, the initial deposit of being, that is inseparable from the creative endowment and that weights created being towards the actual 69 Cf. Gabriel Marcel, Du refus al'invocation. And so, at the personal level, there can be loss through generosity refused, or through abuse of freedom (moral evil), but this spiritual loss does not of itself entail physical mutation. Cf. St. Thomas 's "absque ... abiiciatur" (above, n. 9). At the subpersonal level the "refusal" is manifest in the privations endemic to the rule of finitude (ontological evil), which God freely respects for the good of the finite. 7° Cf. Schindler's esse-in ("Norris Clarke on Person, Being, and St. Thomas," 586, 582). I find this acceptance recognized in the popular and subsequently the learned sense of ousia and substantia which take the form of an ontological self-reference (autos). See my "Selves and Persons," Communio 18 (Summer 1991), esp. 184-96. CREATED RECEPTIVITY 365 good (i.e., the good of its own being and the Good that is its Source). And this is the meaning of final causality in the ontological relation, that is, insofar as final causality bears first of all on created being and only then on its agency. For there is more than passivity in reception; there is also self-possession and ordination to the good. Esse as the supposit of secondary activity already possesses the integral mode of potency and act in the form of an integral ordination towards (esse-ad). The notion of an integral mode of act and potency is not entirely alien to Thomistic metaphysics. If one considers the elusive concept of active potency,11 we recognize here a principle that is not simply that of passive potency. Created active potency needs initiation in order to be actuated and in that aspect may be said to be passive, but the power itself (potentia activa) is not simply a mutable subject, a capacity awaiting in-formation; it is a capability, the ability to respond to the initiative that first institutes it. The notion of active potency is usually considered at the level of secondary activity, insofar as it is the potency of specific powers; but if it is deepened to mean the re-sponse to the primary institution of created being, its primordial reception, such active potency is enfolded within the integral mode of non-privative receptivity. Now, this endowment and reception of being is constitutive of the created being and cannot, therefore, be understood as an external relation. It is the very inner constitution of the being itself. It is imperative, therefore, to release interiority from its modern prison in human subjectivity and to restore to natural things (res) the appropriate kind of interiority which they have in a metaphysics of being, where they are not mere objects standing before the human subject. For the principles that constitute a created being comprise the complex depth appropriate to the things we have not made. Indeed, they lead us back to the Source of being, so that the depth in created things is without measure. 71 Cf. the many senses of the term potency (dunamis) considered by Aristotle, Metaphysics 5, c. 13, 1019a15ff. The privileged sense is the active, in keeping with the primacy of act over passivity. Nevertheless, the distinction is between poiein and paschein within the analysis of change and not within that of creation. Compare St. Thomas on the many senses of potency in note 53. 366 KENNETH L. SCHMITZ It is not only human subjectivity that has an interior, then; things do too. 12 Once that interiority is recognized, things receive the name of "subject" (suppositum entis), the privileged name we give to primary centers. And this ontological interiority lends its character to all interior relations, including the spiritual interiority encountered in personal beings. If, however, the very subsistence of a creature is relational, then the understanding of the reality of created substance is thereby transformed. For substance is now understood to rest ultimately not on uncreated matter, nor does it have the ambiguous status of an ens possibile. Instead, substance is determined in and through its radical participation in and relation to the Source of its existence. The supposit of the creature does not stand in any way "outside" of or "prior" to the ontological relation, not even as a possibility, but is brought into being within that relation. "Before" the world came to be it was not "possible" for it to be (potentia passiva), except in the actual power (potentia activa) of God. The primacy of the ontological relation may seem to threaten the reality of substance by undercutting it. That would be so only if the notion of created substance were thought somehow to retain a sort of quasi-independence apart from the ontological relation. Nonetheless, given the proven effectiveness of the logic of substantive predication and its prominent use by St. Thomas the concern is legitimate and more needs to be said in order to offset the charge that substance itself is being dissolved in this radical relation. Such a defense is especially important today, if only because the metaphysical sense of substance is not readily understood or tolerated in the contemporary thought-world. A full defense of the pre-eminence of relation needs to show that the integrity of created substance is not dissolved in the relation.73 This requires an adequate notion of spirit which brings forward the intransitive character of spiritual relations. Creation is the effect of Perfect Intelligence, but it is not a motion. The 12 On natural interiority, see Schmitz, "The First Principle of Personal Becoming," 763-68. 73 I have indicated the basic outlines of tbe argument in The Gift: Creation, 81-86. CREATED RECEPTIVITY 367 relations of intelligence and love, with their spiritual nature, are the specific ways in which God communicates being to his creatures. The traditional first way names him the First Mover, but it adds, Unmoved, meaning that He "moves" without moving. Now, even human intelligence can enter into relation with its objects without mutating them; so too human love. Indeed the search for truth demands that the knower respect the integrity of the known, even when (as in experiments) the search for knowledge calls for the manipulation of the knowable. But if even the incarnate human spirit can enter into such relations imperfectly, how much more can the divine intelligence and love communicate, institute, and preserve the integrity and actual existence of its creatures? Indeed, at the level of creative causality and existential effect there is no mutation: creation is not a motion. And so the "law" of creative causality may be stated thus: the non-invasive yet creative activity of (divine) spirit brings about its correlate in the non-privative receptivity of the creature. 74 Created spirit communicates without loss just because it is known (and with God this "knowing" is a creative knowing) without the creature being mutated, and is loved by a (divine) love which respects the beloved (which the Creator's free act brings into being). Spiritual relations are not transitive; the knowledge and love that sustains creatures, far from being a threat to their existence and integrity, is the very ground of their being, nature, and substance. The ontological relation as understood in creation not only rejects the primacy of external relations; it also introduces a new sense of internality that transcends the spatially restricted set of "inside-outside." In the order of constitution or creation there is nothing "outside" such a primordial relation, for the simple reason that there is literally nothing outside being. What there is is finitude, formal difference among purely spiritual creatures and formal and spatio-temporal diversity among physical beings. The immanence of the principles provides the basis for 74 In physical creatures this receptivity is the mark of the presence of the Creator within them. In created persons the receptivity is the mark of their spiritual nature and the image of the creative presence within them. 368 KENNETH L. SCHMITZ understanding relations of interiority. And, just as the transcendental ontological relation comes to prominence, so too there comes to prominence the interior character of all fundamental relations, both in the Creator and in the creature. How are we to understand an interiority that is not merely an internality correlative with an externality (inside-outside)? What we are dealing with is the notion of incomplete principles, 75 not simply correlative or reciprocal, but radically open to each other in the constitution of a single entity. They do not achieve this unity by themselves. If God's creative act is left out of the picture, it is impossible to explain how a non-existent and merely possible essence can determine the creature's act of existence. Once the co-determination of principles is situated within God's creative activity, however, these two incomplete principles play the role assigned to them by their Agent-Creator. Each principle taken in itself is incomplete; but even more, taken together they constitute a being that is no being except in relation to its primordial cause. Each principle is inherently implicated in the other through the causal activity of the First Cause, and by a subordination of the one (potency) to the other (act) rather than by a reciprocity of two complete principles. VIII. TRANSFORMATION OF THE PRINCIPLES IN CREATED PERSONS Nonetheless, the reception that is common to all creatures must be refined further, if it is to fit the analogical modes of being, a11d if it is to be of use in determining the proper character of spiritual being. For while there is a general sense of receptivity appropriate to all creatures, there is a special sense, a proper sense, in which human beings as spiritual creatures are receptive. What marks a created spirit from other created beings is that it has beei:i endowed with an ability to respond in accordance with the "law" of spirit, that is, the capacity for freedom. It is here that the integral concept of non-privative receptivity seems especially appropriate, for it illuminates the distinctive 75 Seen. 46. CREATED RECEPTIVITY 369 relation between God and spiritual creatures. The human creature receives along with its very capacity to exist (essentia) the capability of responding (actus essendi) in a way that, insofar as it is spiritual, does not involve mutation or loss. 76 The evidence for this is just the normal operations of association proper to human beings: love and knowledge, understanding and communication, which rise from the creature's primordial receptivity. In the creation of a human person, the otherness (praeter esse) is proportionate to the act that is communicated; and being proportionate it follows along lines of (incarnate) spiritual being, in which there is communication without loss and non-privative receptivity. At the level of personal being this is more adequately expressed by receptivity than by pure passive potency. In personal beings, the receptivity takes the form of a specific response. The response is in no way a causa sui, it is a re-sponse; that is, it is the primordial acknowledgment of a gift received and is expressed in the "acceptance" (i.e., the subsistence and ordination) of the creature. At the level of secondary activity this receptivity is expressed in a variety of individual and cultural ways as a seeking out of the Giver, in the search for the true and the good in the community of beings. The consequence of such an intrinsic relation is a higher degree of unity of the constitutive principles than in subpersonal beings. Here lies the ontological ground for the proper immanence of spiritual being, whereby the unity of personal being is a conscious, deliberate integrity. From this ground there follows at the level of activity the non-privative nature of personal dynamism, first manifested in communication without loss. The absence of loss is coordinate with the power of retrieval. This is seen in the distinctive relation to temporality that is characteristic of personal being. Memory, and even more the memoria of which St. Augustine wrote, is the retrieval of past time, even as 76 I add the qualifier "insofar as it is spiritual" in order to acknowledge the incarnate nature of human spirituality, which is itself a sort of integral mode of being, so that human spirituality operates within the larger context in which there is physical mutation. The physical order is given over to mutation. In created persons, on the other hand, the creature itself is properly endowed with non-privative receptivity and response in accordance with the "law" of spiritual existence. 370 KENNETH L. SCHMITZ anticipation perfected in hope is the appropriation of the structure of future time. The indefinite scope of the time-scale at the root of human culture and human history is made possible by the capability of cognition, which liberates the universal in abstract form but within the horizon of being. And so, there is a special sense in which the created person responds, for he responds in his very being through intelligence and freedom, and this response is constituted of an appropriate and proportionate act and potency, both in the constitution of its being and the overflow of its activity. 77 Here we approach once again one of the prominent themes of Marcel's philosophy of the concrete, that the fortunes of being depend in some significant way upon the use we make of our freedom. Marcel's distance from Thomism seems to have arisen from a view that it was too "objective" a mode of thinking to be sensitive to the most profound truths and realities of human existence. Moreover, his opposition was heightened by the modern dichotomy between passivity and activity, which he attributed to Kant, and which he thought approximated most closely to inanimate objects, as when the wax is utterly passive to receiving the imprint of the wholly active seal. He countered the reduction of receptivity to passivity by invoking the experience of the host who welcomes (i.e., receives) a guest into his home. This reception is no mere metaphor, nor is it mere passivity;78 it is a genuine receptivity that transcends the gulf between activity and passivity without destroying their real distinction. It does this by including them within what I have 71 It is this recognition that is so prominent among many German Catholic philosophers, who make of freedom a primary ontological principle. 78 Reflecting upon the nature of feeling (sentir), Marcel remarks that it is not only a passive submitting to sensory impulses (sensation), but also an active opening out onto ... (s'ouvrir a ... ). This is precisely the transition from the empirical to the concrete. Cf. Marcel, Du refus a /'invocation, 43: "Des le moment ou nous avons clairement reconnu que sentir ne se reduit pas a subir, tout en maintentant que c'est en quelque recevoir, nous sommes en mesure de deceler en son centre Ia presence d'un element actif, quelque chose comme le pouvoir d'assumer, ou mieux encore, de s'ouvrir a ... "Now one "opens out onto" what is able to receive one, and that cannot be an object in the modern sense, for the objectivity of the object reflects back to the knowing subject the criteria already brought to it by the subject. (See the canonical expression of this view in Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, preface to the second edition, vii-xii.) CREATED RECEPTIVITY 371 called an integral mode of being. The sense of receptivity has deeper ontological roots than either created act or potency considered in themselves. These roots are opened up to the light of a metaphysics of the concrete, a light that situates the human person and all created beings within the community as gift. REPLY STEVEN A. LONG D R. SCHMITZ 'S response to my criticism of his writing on receptivity is a model of the way in which philosophers from diverse traditions can enrich one another's reflections and understanding. Indeed, his observation (see his note 6) that he has always refused the honorific title "Thomist" will not impede the astute observer from discerning the extent and facility of his command of the texts of St. Thomas. Still, one must observe that the very approach chosen to articulate his metaphysical case-the metaphysics of esse as context for a view of creatures as themselves being "subsisting relations"-is, whatever its other merits, a clear departure from the realism of St. Thomas. Why? Moderns used to poke fun at Scholastic distinctions by saying that these were like attempts to answer the question "how many angels can dance on the head of a pin?" Their point-or at least the point of those among them who were knowledgeable enough to have a point-was not that such an absurd formulation ever found currency among the various schools of Scholasticism. Rather, they sought to suggest that realist metaphysics tends to generate abstruse and unreal distinctions and questions. Now, a hard look at either continental or analytic thought reveals that this criticism is far more applicable to either than to the thought of St. Thomas. Analytic philosophy in recent years has fallen, after Wittgenstein, into abstruse discussions of what it means to have a toothache; and continental thinkers frequentlY. articulate their accounts in a vocabulary that is almost mystagogically obtuse. By contrast St. Thomas articulates the adequacy of both sense knowledge and of intellectual knowledge, always resolving both into our knowledge of being. It is in this context that one 373 374 STEVEN A. LONG takes pause at finding personalist theorists of the Communio school transignifying Thomas 's metaphysics via the dialectical absorption of substance into relation. I should like to note only three things about the proposition that the creature is a subsisting relation. These points are, I am persuaded, the critical ones for understanding the distance between the continental appropriation of Thomas and the character of Thomas's own teaching. (1) According to St. Thomas the terminus of the divine act is a being that is really related to God-not a subsisting relation. If we treat the creature as itself a subsisting relation, then is this relation itself further related-that is, do we not end up with a Platonic "third man" difficulty? Further, what is related? The divine gift of esse posits a being that is related: but its real relation does not alter the datum that we intrinsically predicate being of the creature, nor that there is a distinction between a being's total dependence upon God and its very substantiality itself. Indeed, in creatures substance and esse are really distinct, not identical. Nor is the esse merely a relation but rather a quasiformal principle of being. Created substance is really related to God; but the substance is not this relation, any more than formal causality is final or efficient causality. The idea of the creature as subsisting relation is not only unfounded in Thomas's text, but indeed contrary to his teaching. As Dr. Schmitz admits about the view that the creature is a subsisting relation, "I recognize that this term is privileged by St. Thomas for the divine persons of the Trinity." Moreover, he observes that this construction is positively excluded by St. Thomas 's teaching: "I also recognize that in his argument he refers the designation human person to the individual substance and with the impeccable logic of genus and specific difference excludes subsistent relation from the term person when applied to man" (see his note 59). In short-and in precision from its further assessment-the idea of the creature as "subsisting relation" not only is not Thomas's metaphysics, but is excluded by his metaphysics. The value of viewing the creature as a subsisting relation is alleged to be its manifestation of the radical dependence of the REPLY 375 creature upon "the communicatio entis flowing from the first Being" (ibid.). But it is important that the status of creatures as beings be affirmed-which is that whereby they are really ordered to God. Convert the substance to a relation, and Thomas's whole account of the terminus of the divine creative act, the character of his defense of the dignity of secondary causality, and, indeed, even his path to the discovery of the real distinction are altered. Whatever else we may say, we must refuse to this doctrine the designation "Thomistic." (2) Dr. Schmitz 's masterful scholarly articulation of the idea of creature as subsisting relation, and of its pedigree in the history of ideas, should highlight one salient philosophic datum: that this idea occurs when something cognate with Hegelian dialectics is inseminated into the Thomistic metaphysics of esse at its highest point. The metaphysical category of substance is marked for abandonment in favor of relation as itself a subject of being, so that substance is absorbed into relation. But it was part of the gravamen of my case-and remains so-that we have no epistemic warrant for the metaphysics of esse itself once we separate ourselves from the ontology-including the ontology of knowledge-whence it derives. Hence if we are importing dialectics within our constitutive understanding of esse so late in the game, it must be that the path to esse rendering such a move possible has been already and diversely articulated. But insofar as such a distinct path to a dialectically altered account of esse is articulated, I suggest that it will more and more clearly be seen to have its roots in a thought-world quite distinct from-and indeed contrary to-St. Thomas 's own. The principles of being, on Thomas's account, are immutable: substance is not relation, not even transcendental relation; formal causality is not final or efficient causality. Ontology is not a mere provisional set of distinctions on the way to a new Gestalt-it is the permanent structure of being, whose permanence derives from its participation in the immutable divine wisdom. Dr. Schmitz well challenges not only Thomists but all other philosophers to grapple with continental theories whose significance for an understanding of the person is central. Whether the lingua franca of the Thomistic metaphysics of being can any 376 STEVEN A. LONG longer signify its native propensities within a regime of thought transignified by a combination of Hegelian dialectic and the aversio abstractae typical of personalist phenomenology is another issue. Of course, the idea of the creature as subsistent relation is itself a highly abstract notion-and it is in this sense unclear that it coheres more closely with the philosophy of the concrete than do more traditional Thomistic formulations. Still there is a tendency of some phenomenologists to void metaphysical conclusions solely owing to their "abstraction" or, more properly, superior remotion from matter-real principles of being are "out,'' Gestalt is "in." One point is clear: for St. Thomas metaphysical verities are neither tentative nor annulled in some higher synthesis: they are, indeed, the necessary rational prerequisites for any higher synthesis. (3) The last point leads directly to the issue of St. Thomas's ontology and theoretic account of human knowledge. The very terms in which Thomas articulates his own account of esseespecially given his teaching that the proper object of the human intellect is quiddity as found in corporeal matter-contrasts sharply not only with the continental appropriation of his thought, but with much contemporary Neoscholasticism amongst medieval historians as well. The idea that Thomas meant to articulate a real distinction between essence and existence that is ungrounded in the ontology of knowing-as though the real distinction could sink its roots in the direct intuition of spiritual verities, or proceed from terms exclusively logical-is not supported by his writing. But were it true, I for one cannot see what would stand to impede the work of appropriation of Thomas 's thought so elegantly and reconditely articulated by Dr. Schmitz. If my criticisms are only thefelix culpa meriting so scholarly and lucid a response, this may yet serve to measure the distance separating Thomistic realism from its transubstantiation within the rhythm and gait of continental reflection. A DEFENSE OF PHYSICALISM STEVEN J. JENSEN University of Mary Bismarck, North Dakota T HE CHARGE OF PHYSICALISM is often made in discussions of sexual ethics. Some people, so the accusation runs, mistakenly explain the evil of certain sexual actions, contraception in particular, in merely physical terms, while ignoring the truly human element of actions, that element essential to all moral good and evil, namely, the will. But physicalism, while especially rampant in sexual ethics, is not confined to it. It is an ailment that can afflict an entire moral outlook. And, like any affliction, philosophers hope to avoid it, making sure that they themselves are not physicalists. It seems to me that perhaps physicalism should be defended. The problem is that the accusation seems to have as many senses as there are accusers. I am forced, therefore, to settle upon a definition of physicalism with which not everyone will agree, and perhaps I will end up with a defense not of physicalism but of a physicalist look alike. 1 Physicalism, then, according to my designation, claims that the moral good or evil of an action can be determined merely by its physical features, physical features being contrasted to acts of the will. My precise definition of physicalism will involve Aquinas's distinction between exterior and interior actions within one human action. When someone opens a door, for example, he has the interior action of choosing 1 I will not focus upon natures, functions, and teleology, elements that are often seen as essential to physicalism (see Charles Curran, 1Yansitions and 1Yaditions in Moral Theology [Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1979], 31), although teleology is implied in my account. 377 378 STEVEN J. JENSEN to open the door and the exterior action of physically opening the door. Concerning the relationship between these two actions, there are two general approaches. According to the first, the exterior action has its own moral good and evil, by its very nature, and it bestows this moral character upon the will. The exterior action of killing an innocent human being, for example, is evil by its very self. On account of this evil, the will becomes evil, so that the interior act of intending to kill an innocent human being is evil only because the exterior act of killing is first of all evil. The second account is exactly opposed. The exterior action has no moral good or evil of its own but receives its moral character from the will, which is itself inherently good or evil. What matters in the act of murder is not so much the physical activity performed as the evil intention of the agent. 2 Now physicalism is the view that an action takes its moral character from its physical features, apart from the good or evil of the will. Put in terms of the interior and exterior actions, physicalism is the view that the exterior action has a moral character in itself, by the very nature of its physical features, and that acts of the will receive their good or evil from the exterior action. The opposite view I will call Abelardianism, for the common counter-accusation to physicalism often brings in Peter Abelard. In this paper I do not exactly wish to defend physicalism, to show that physicalism is true in the very nature of things; I want only to show that Aquinas thought it was. In other words, I hope to show that Aquinas was a physicalist. When we move the debate into the arena of the philosophy of Aquinas, it takes on the nature of a disagreement over what Aquinas calls "the specification of human actions." According to Aquinas human actions are good or evil in their very species or essence. Physicalists claim that this moral specification moves from the exterior act to the interior while Abelardians claim that it moves from the interior to the exterior. For example, the physi2 Thomas D. Sullivan, "Active and Passive Euthanasia: An Impertinent Distinction?" in Killing and Letting Die, 2d ed, ed. Bonnie Steinbock and Alastair Norcross (New York: Fordham University Press, 1994), 131-38. A DEFENSE OF PHYSICALISM 379 calists claim that the exterior action of killing is good or evil in its very species, and the intention to kill takes its moral species from the exterior action. Abelardians, on the other hand, claim that the act of killing receives its moral species only from the will, which has moral character by its very nature. I. THE CASE FOR ABELARDIANISM I do not presume to give every argument in favor of Abelardianism; I give, instead, what seems to be the strongest case, which depends upon the role of intention in the specification of human actions, especially as it is exemplified in the principle of double effect. 3 Consider the common example of the tactical bomber, who bombs a munitions factory located within a residential district. He not only destroys the factory and all inside it; he kills some innocent civilians as well. According to the principle of double effect, he most properly destroys the factory, while he kills the innocent civilians only as a side effect. In precise Thomistic terms, he destroys the factory per se while he kills the civilians per accidens. Of course the significant feature of his action is his intention, for he intends to destroy the factory, but the civilian deaths are outside his intention. As Aquinas puts it, what is within intention is per se and what is outside intention is per accidens. He adds that what is per se belongs to the species of an action. 4 The species of the tactical bomber's action, then, is destroying the munitions factory, for that is what he intends. Killing the civilians is per accidens and so must be something outside the essence of his action. 3 See Louis Janssens, "Ontic Evil and Moral Evil," in Readings in Moral Theology: No. 1, ed. Charles E. Curran and Richard A. McCormick (New York: Paulist Press, 1979), 49; and Joseph M. Boyle, "Praeter Intentionem in Aquinas," The Thomist 42 (1978): 653. 4 STh 11-11, q. 64, a. 7: "Morales autem actus recipiunt speciem secundum id quod intenditur, non autem ab eo quod est praeter intentionem, cum sit per accidens, ut ex supradictis patet"; and STh 1-11, q. 72, a. 8: "Dicendum quod cum in peccato sint duo, scilicet ipse actus et inordinatio eius, prout receditur ab ordine rationis et legis divinae; species peccati attenditur non ex parte inordinationis, quae est praeter intentionem peccantis, ut supra dictum est." See also STh 1-11, q. 72, a. 5; 11-11, q. 43, a. 3; 11-11, q. 70, a. 4, ad 1; 11-11, q. 109, a. 2, ad 2; 11-11, q. 110, a. 1; 11-11, q. 150, a. 2. 380 STEVEN J. JENSEN The picture we get is of an action-the deed that was doneand then certain things that are beyond the action itself but are related to it. As Aquinas puts it, certain things "stand around" an action; they are its circumstances. He compares an action to a substance and its circumstances to its properties. Just as my dog Fido is a substance who has many properties, so our actions-or the substance of our actions-have certain properties. The deed that the tactical bomber performs, for instance, is destroying the munitions factory. The killing of innocent lives that results is not precisely his action, but a circumstance of his action. Abelardianism notes that the tactical bomber's exterior action does not have moral species in and of itself; it must be specified by his intention. We cannot tell, just by looking at the exterior action, what the tactical bomber's action is. It might be merely the destruction of the factory or it might also be the killing of innocents. The exterior action by itself gives no indication. Indeed, the very same action, with a different intention, might give us a terror bomber, who intentionally kills innocent civilians in order to lower the enemy's morale, thereby bringing a quick end to the war. Both tactical bomber and terror bomber kill innocent civilians; they might even do so in the same suburban neighborhood. And yet these externally identical actions are entirely distinct in moral species. The essence of the tactical bomber's action is the destruction of the factory, while the killing of innocents is merely a circumstance. For the terror bomber, on the other hand, the killing of innocent civilians belongs to the very essence of his action. The two acts are distinguished in moral species not by any physical features, but only by the interior act of the will. Physicalism, therefore, must be false. The physical features alone of an action do not determine its moral character; the agent's intention must be included in any moral evaluation. Before we turn to what physicalism might say in its defense, I want better to understand precisely what Aquinas means by an action, its essence, and its circumstances. I will examine what he means by a per se action, since the substance of an action is what belongs to it per se and not per accidens. A DEFENSE OF PHYSICALISM 381 II. PER SE ACTIONS Aquinas lists three marks of a per se action, or rather, of a per se cause. He says first that a per se cause intends its effect; second, that a per se cause is similar to its effect; and finally, that a per se cause has a determinate order to its effect. 5 We have already seen the first point, that the agent's intention determines what is per se, in the case of the tactical bomber. The second point, that a per se cause is similar to its effect, is best illustrated through one of Aquinas's own favorite examples, fire heating. Consider four effects of a fiery furnace upon wet clay and upon a block of wax: the clay becomes hot, the wax becomes hot, the clay hardens, and the wax melts. The fire is itself hot, and through its own heat it makes the clay and wax hot as well. But the fire is neither hard nor soft, although it causes the clay to become hard and the wax to become soft. The effect of heat, then, is indeed similar to the cause, but the other effects, being hard or soft, are not similar to the cause, and as such they must be per accidens effects. While the fire heats per se, through its own heat, it may be said to harden and to soften per accidens. According to Aquinas the similarity between cause and effect need not be absolute. Consider a man building a shed. Clearly he is not absolutely similar to the shed. Nevertheless, he does 5 De Malo, q. 1, a. 3. "Sciendum est enim quod malum causam per se habere non potest. Quod quidem tripliciter apparet. Primo quidem, quia illud quod per se causam habet, est inten tum a sua causa; quod enim provenit praeter intentionem agentis, non est effectus per se, sed per accidens; sicut effossio sepulcri per accidens est causa inventionis thesauri, cum provenit praeter intentionem fodientis sepulcrum. Mal um autem, in quantum huiusmodi, non potest esse intentum, nee aliquo modo volitum vel desideratum; quia omne appetibile habet rationem boni; cui opponitur malum in quantum huiusmodi. Unde videmus quod nullus facit aliquod malum nisi intendens aliquod bonum, ut sibi videtur; sicut adulterium bonum videtur quod delectatione sensibili fruatur. Et propter hoc adulterium committit. Unde relinquitur quod malum non habeat causam per se. Secundo idem apparet, quia omnis effectus per se habet aliqualiter similitudinem suae causae, vel secundum eamdem rationem, sicut in agentibus univocis, vel secundum deficientem rationem, sicut in agentibus aequivocis; omnis enim causa agens agit secundum quod actu est, quod pertinet ad rationem boni. Unde malum, secundum quod huiusmodi, non assimilatur causae agenti secundum id quod est agens. Relinquitur ergo quod malum non habeat causam per se. Tertio idem apparet ex hoc quod omnis causa per se, habet certum et determinatum ordinem ad suum effect.um; quod autem fit secundum ordinem non est malum, sed malum accidit in praetermittendo ordinem." 382 STEVEN J. JENSEN already possess the likeness of the shed, and through this likeness he acts. For in building the shed he has some conception of what the shed will Be like, and it is by means of this idea that he builds the shed. 6 The third mark of a per se action, that it is determinately ordered to its effect, is illustrated through a man writing with a pen upon a piece of paper. The pen does not move of its own accord; we would say that it is moved by the man, who gives the pen impetus to move and thereby to act. More than that, the man directs the pen so that it moves precisely to form letters and then words. Aquinas speaks of two ways that something might be directed or ordered to an end: either from an intrinsic characteristic or from an external impetus. An archer aims at the target from an internal impetus-knowledge and intention-while an arrow aims at the target only because it receives external direction. 7 Similarly, both the man writing and the pen are directed toward writing. But the man's direction arises from an internal sourcehis knowledge and intention-while the pen receives a guiding impetus from outside. This example epitomizes human actions in the world around us, for we act by moving events toward some desired effects. Just as the man moves the pen to write, so the tactical bomber moves events to destroy the factory. These actions do not result randomly in some effect; they are directed toward it. We can now picture a per se action as a certain movement, arising in an agent, directed toward some end effect. The tactical bomber's action, for example, is a certain movement that he initiates, directed toward the effect of the destruction of the munitions factory. The heart of an action, its substance or essence, is a movement from an agent to an end. If we understand the direction of an action, where it is headed, then we have grasped its substance, and all else is merely accidental. Besides destroying the factory, for instance, the tactical bomber kills 6 This "intellectual" likeness is expressed in ScG III, c. 2, no. 5, "Adhuc. Omne agens." I, q. 103, a. 8; and STh 1-11, q. 91, a. 2. 7 De Verit., q. 22, a. 1; STh A DEFENSE OF PHYSICALISM 383 innocent civilians, but his action does not originate from this goal nor is it headed in that direction. It is moving toward the destruction of the factory and no more. The species of an action, then, is taken from its direction, and all that is extraneous to this order to an end is per accidens and a circumstance. We are now in a position to consider the arguments in favor of physicalism. Ill. THE CASE FOR PHYSICALISM Physicalism often bases its claim that the exterior action has moral character in itself, apart from the will, upon another specifying element of human actions beyond intention, namely, the object. Indeed, the whole debate before us is sometimes cast in terms of two different ends or objects, namely, the finis operis and thefinis operantis. 8 Thefinis operis, the end of the action, refers to the end of the exterior action; for example, the finis operis of killing is death. Thefinis operantis, on the other hand, refers to the end intended by the agent. Physicalism says that moral actions are specified by thefinis operis, and that thefinis operantis is merely a circumstance. For instance, the terror bomber's action is specified by its end, which is the death of innocent human beings, and the bomber's intention to shorten the war is merely a circumstance. Abelardianism responds to this claim in two different ways. One response, which I will call extreme Abelardianism, may be associated with the proportionalists, who claim that the end of the action does indeed give species to the act, but not its moral species; it determines merely the natural species of an action. 9 For example, the natural act of killing is indeed specified by the finis operis of death. But moral actions must include the end intended within their object, so that the moral action of murder 8 See Janssens, "Ontic Evil," 42-43; and Peter Knauer, "The Hermeneutic Function of the Principle of Double Effect," in Curran and McCormick, eds., Readings in Moral Theology: No. 1, 5. 9 See Janssens, "Ontic Evil," 49; and Knauer, "Hermeneutic," 5 (although Knauer defines thefinis operis so that it includes thefinis operantis). 384 STEVEN J. JENSEN must include, within its specification, not only the end of death, but the reason why the agent has chosen to kill. Natural actions are specified by the finis operis, moral actions are specified by the finis operantis. The terror bomber, for instance, intends to end the suffering of war. Perhaps his action should not, therefore, be described as murder. It is better, suggests extreme Abelardianism, to describe the action through the finis operantis, perhaps as saving lives. 10 A second response from the Abelardians gives us yet a third view, moderate Abelardianism, 11 which insists that there is really not much difference between thefinis operis and thefinis operantis. In the final analysis the end of the action reduces to the end of the agent. The appropriate distinction to be made is between the proximate end and the remote end, both of which are ends of the agent. The proximate end of the terror bomber, for instance, is the death of innocents; the close of the war is his remote end. The moral species of actions is taken not from this remote end, as the proportionalists would have it, but from the proximate end. 12 Let us begin, then, to consider the case for physicalism by examining how thefinis operis specifies human actions. Aquinas says repeatedly that an action is specified by its end; 13 for example, we identify the action of heating through its end, which is 10 The proportionalists themselves might not wish to defend terror bombing, but in principle they should allow that under some circumstances it might be permissible. 11 This view seems to be expressed by Boyle, "Praeter Intentionem"; John Finnis, Moral Absolutes: Tradition, Revision, and Truth (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1991), 37-40; and Sullivan, "Active and Passive." 12 We should note that we need not get caught up with the termsfinis operis andfinis operantis. It has been pointed out that Aquinas himself rarely uses these two terms (see Servais Pinckaers, "La role de la fin dans l'action morale selon Saint Thomas," in Le renouveau de la morale [Paris-Tournai, 1964], 129). The terms are irrelevant, for the ideas are clearly present in Aquinas, who tends to speak of the end of the action and the end of the will. We will see shortly that even the termfinis will be discarded. Nevertheless, one idea will remain intact, namely, that the exterior action has a term of its own, through which it is specified. 13 Q. D. de Anima, a. 13: "Actus autem ex obiectis speciem habent, nam si sint actus passivarum potentiarum, obiecta sunt activa; si autem sint activarum potentiarum, obiecta sunt ut fines"; and STh I, q. 77, a. 3: "Ad actum autem potentiae activae comparatur obiectum ut terminus et finis; sicut augmentativae virtutis obiectum est quantum perfectum, quod est finis augmenti." Also see In De Anima II, c. 6, nos. 137-44; STh I, q. 14, a. 2;,and 1-11, q. 18, a. 2. A DEFENSE OF PHYSICALISM 385 heat. Similarly, the act of killing is characterized through its end, which is death. The end of building is some structure, and the end of growth is increased size. In general, it seems that many actions have a defining effect. The importance of the end is no surprise, for it fits neatly into our picture of a per se action. We said that actions are not just random but are headed toward some end. It follows that an action is characterized through its end. Just as a trip to Chicago is characterized by its goal, so an action is characterized through the end toward which it is headed. This explanation of physicalism, however, is at best incomplete. Aquinas not only says that actions are specified by their ends; he often says that actions are specified by what he calls the "material" of the action. What he means may be understood through a few examples. The action of adultery is specified by the material "another's spouse." 14 Similarly, the action of theft is specified through the material "another's property." 15 The material, clearly, is not the same thing as the end or effect of an action. The act of adultery does not end up with another's spouse the way that killing ends up with death. Rather, the material is, as Aquinas puts it, that which is acted upon. 16 While it is fairly clear that many actions are defined by the effect they bring about, even as killing is defined through death, it is not so clear that actions are defined through the material upon which they act. The act of heating, for instance, is clearly characterized by heat, but appears not to be characterized by the material of wax or clay. Of course, one might point out that a complete description of the fire's action must include the wax. The fire did not merely heat; it heated wax. Perhaps the material of an action, then, specifies by providing a complete description of an action. 14 STh 11-11, q. 154, a. 1. 15 De Malo, q. 2, a. 6. 16 STh I-II, q. 18, a. 2, ad 2. Even the termfinis has now been eliminated. We are no longer speaking of the end of the exterior act, but of its material. Still, the essence of physicalism remains: the exterior act is specified by some feature of its own, a feature Aquinas calls the "object" of the action. The physical features of the exterior action, either its end or its material, give moral character to the action independently of the will. 386 STEVEN J. JENSEN This explanation, however, fails to answer the most important question: why should the material be included within the essence of the action? Talk of a "complete description" of an action simply will not do, for a complete description will include all the circumstances. Heating wax is a more complete description of the fire's action than is merely heating, but heating wax at twelve o'clock is more complete yet. If what we want is a complete description, then we will be left with no distinction between what is essential and what is accidental to an action. No doubt a complete description of an action will include the material, but that does not explain why the material specifies an action. A good explanation must show that the material belongs to the essence of an action. The importance of the material can be understood through the example of basketball. The activity of shooting the basketball is,· in general, directed toward the end of scoring. But the precise direction that the action takes depends upon its material, namely, the basket that is shot at. If it is basket A, then the action is directed toward team A scoring; if it is basket B, then it is directed toward team B scoring. In the realm of basketball, these two different kinds of scoring are completely different goals. The material of the act, then, belongs to the essence of shooting because it determines the precise direction that the action takes. We will see that this view, that the material specifies an action insofar as it determines the direction of the action, is in fact Aquinas's own. Fornication, for instance, is specified by its material, namely, an unmarried woman, because that material determines that the action is not directed toward the full education of the offspring. 11 11 We can see the view worked out in Aquinas's commentary on the De Anima, where he discusses the activity of digestion. The material of digestion is food, but this single material can lead to different effects, either the sustenance of the organism or the growth of the organism. Therefore, depending upon the formality under which it is consideredas sustaining or as leading to increased size-this same material serves as the object of two activities, sustenance or growth. In other words, the material of food specifies the activities, as we have suggested, because it directs the activity to the diverse effects of sustenance or growth. See In De Anima II, c. 9, nos. 125-30 and 165-78. A DEFENSE OF PHYSICALISM 387 IV. THE CASE OF EXTREME ABELARDIANISM First, however, we must consider extreme Abelardianism's insistence that the finis operis, and we might include the material as well, gives merely the natural species of actions. Since moral actions are voluntary, involving deliberation and will, they are specified through the end of the will, not by the end of the action. 18 Evaluating the arguments of extreme Abelardianism requires a precise determination of the moral object of human actions. Must the moral object include the end intended or can it be constituted merely through the finis operis and material? Or more generally, we might ask, what belongs to the moral object of human actions, as opposed to the natural object? Aquinas answers this question when asking whether moral actions are good and evil in their very species. 19 He says that the same features will sometimes specify an act and sometimes not. It depends upon the active principle from which the act arises. Consider the action of knowing red and knowing a sound. Should we say that these two features, the color and the sound, give rise to two distinct species of knowing? That depends, says 18 This position may be supported, as Janssens ("Ontic Evil") does, by noting Aquinas's own strong emphasis upon the role that the end of the will plays in moral actions. He says that moral actions are specified by the end of the will (STh I-II, q. 1, a. 3); he says that the most important feature of an action is the end intended (STh I-II, q. 7, a. 4); and he says that the further end intended gives the species to moral actions more than the immediate material upon which the action bears, even going so far as to say that someone who steals in order to commit adultery is more an adulterer than a thief (STh I-II, q. 18, a. 6). 19 De Malo, q. 2, a. 4. "Ad cuius evidentiam considerandum est, quod cum actus recipiat speciem ab obiecto, secundum aliquam rationem obiecti specificabitur actus comparatus ad unum activum principium, secundum quam rationem non specificabitur comparatus ad aliud. Cognoscere enim colorem et cognoscere sonum sunt diversi actus secundum speciem, si ad sensum referantur; quia haec secundum se sensibilia sunt; non autem si referantur ad intellectum; quia ab intellectu comprehenduntur sub una communi ratione obiecti, scilicet entis aut veri. Et similiter sentire album et nigrum differt specie si referatur ad visum, non si referatur ad gustum; ex quo potest accipi quod actus cuiuslibet potentiae specificatur secundum id quod per se pertinet ad illam potentiam, non autem secundum id quod pertinet ad earn solum per accidens. Si ergo obiecta humanorum actum considerentur quae habeant differentias secundum aliquid per se ad rationem pertinens, erunt actus specie differentes, secundum quod sunt actus alicuius alterius potentiae." See also STh I-II, q. 18, a. 5. 388 STEVEN J. JENSEN Aquinas, upon what power is doing the knowing. If we are speaking of the senses, then knowing red is one kind of action, namely, seeing, and knowing sound is another kind of action, namely, hearing. But if we are speaking of the intellect, then there is only one kind of action. Knowing red and knowing sound are both instances of understanding or intellection. What matters in each case, says Aquinas, is whether the feature under consideration refers per se or per accidens to the active principle. Color and sound refer per se to the power of sensing, and so they give rise to distinct acts of sensing, but they refer per accidens to the intellect, so in that instance they do not give rise to distinct kinds of actions. 20 There are many features that appear in the objects of moral actions. For instance, the people killed by the terror bomber are innocent, German, and under eight feet tall. Our problem is to discover which of these features determine the species of moral actions. And Aquinas says that it depends upon how each refers to the active principle from which the action arises. If being German refers per se to reason, the active principle of moral actions, then the bomber's action, in its moral species, will be "killing Germans." On the other hand, if innocence refers per se to reason, then the moral species of the action will be "killing innocent human beings." An upshot of this doctrine, pertinent to the claims of extreme Abelardianism, is that two actions might be morally distinct in species but naturally of the same kind. For example, the two actions of having intercourse with one's own spouse and having ' 0 We have already run across the terms per se and per accidens in reference to the specifying role of intention, but we can be sure that the terms are not being used identically here. Without precisely spelling out how something refers per se to an active principle, Aquinas draws out certain intuitions. Since he is here talking about differences in objects, I think that when he uses the term per se he is referring to a per se difference. When dividing the genus of animal, for instance, we should not divide the category nonrational into those that have wings and those that do not, for this is not a per se division. But if we divided animal into those having legs and those without legs, then a further per se division would be those with two legs and those with more (see STh 1-11, q. 18, a. 7). The intuition at work becomes plain through a literal rendering of per seas "through itself." A division of feet is divided through itself by another division of feet, but the division of winged and non-winged is incidental to the non-rational. A DEFENSE OF PHYSICALISM 389 intercourse with someone else's spouse are indeed morally distinct species, for Aquinas says that the features "one's own" and "someone else's" refer per se to reason. However, these same features do not refer per se to the sexual power, so on a natural level these two actions both belong to the same kind, namely, sexual intercourse. 21 Extreme Abelardianism 's claim, then, that the finis operis and material of an action determine its natural species but not its moral species amounts to the claim that the end and material refer per se to a natural active principle but not to reason. The heart of the matter, as far as physicalism is concerned, is whether the finis operis and material, by themselves, without including the end intended, can ever refer per se to reason. If they can, then they give moral species and some exterior actions will be morally characterized through their own physical features. Before we can determine whether the end and material give moral species, therefore, we must better understand what Aquinas means by something referring per se to reason. Aquinas says that something refers per se to reason when it is according to reason or when it is contrary to reason, when it is fitting or not fitting to reason, 22 when it is repugnant to reason, 23 and when it is consonant or dissonant to reason. 24 I wish to follow up on what seems to be his most helpful description. He says that something refers per se to reason if it is fitting to the order of reason or if it is repugnant to the order of reason. 25 He further explains this by saying that an action is fitting to the order of reason if it is ordered to the appropriate end; it is unfitting if it is not ordered to the appropriate end. 26 Elsewhere Aquinas explains that the order of reason is nothing other than the order to the end, for it is reason that directs 21 22 STh 1-11, q. 18, a. 5, ad 3; and De Malo, q. 2, a. 4. STh 1-11, q. 18, a. 5. Ibid., ad 4. STh 1-11, q. 18, a. 10, ad 3. 25 STh 1-11, q. 18, a. 9. 26 STh 1-11, q. 18, a. 10. 23 24 390 STEVEN J. JENSEN our desires to the end. 27 The idea is best illustrated through an analogy to another field that involves an order to an end, for instance, medicine. Medical acts, Dr. Kevorkian aside, should be ordered to the end of health, and those that lack the order are bad medical acts. If a doctor prescribes a medication that will only make you worse, then his action is not ordered to health and is a bad medical act; it is, we might say, contrary to medicine. Good medical acts, on the other hand, conform to what might be called the medical order, that is, the order to health. Human actions, then, are like medical acts. Just as medical acts must conform to the medical order, so human acts should conform to the order of reason. All of this talk of orders to an end should remind us that actions are, in their essence, a movement toward an end, and that they are specified by the end to which they are directed, even as killing is specified by the end of death. Now we can add another detail. Not just any difference in the end constitutes a new kind of action. Heating to 90 degrees and heating to 100 degrees, for instance, are not two different kinds of action. The difference must refer per se to the active principle, which for human actions is reason. How this works out in practice is best illustrated through Aquinas's own practice. The end of reason, it seems, is constituted through diverse human goods, for example, human life, material possessions, friendship, offspring, and so on,28 and actions directed toward or away from these diverse ends are distinct in kind. Aquinas says, for instance, "Since virtue is ordered to the good, there is a special virtue wherever there occurs a special formality of the good." 29 And again, "When there is a special 27 STh II-II, q. 153, a. 2: "Peccatum in humanis actibus est quod est contra ordinem rationis. Habet autem hoc rationis ordo, ut quaelibet convenienter ordinet in suum finem"; and II-II, q. 141, a. 6: "Bonum virtutis moralis praecipue consistit in ordine rationis: nam bonum hominis est secundum rationem esse, ut Dionysius