The Thomist 63 (1999): 1-48 FAITH AND REASON RECONSIDERED: AQUINAS AND LUfHER ON DECIDING WHAT IS TRUE 1 BRUCE D. MARSHALL St. Olaf College Northfield, Minnesota I N WHAT MAY REMAIN the most widely read book in English about Thomas Aquinas, G. K. Chesterton locates Thomas's chief contribution to the Church, and to the whole human enterprise, by contrasting him with Luther. "It was the very life of the Thomist teaching that Reason can be trusted: it was the very life of the Lutheran teaching that Reason is utterly untrustworthy. " 2 Thomas's great achievement, Chesterton argues, was to achieve a perfect balance and harmony between faith and reason, Christ and Aristotle. Luther's great importance lay in his singleminded effort-remarkably successful, Chesterton ruefully concedes-to destroy what Thomas achieved. Luther's passionate hatred of reason rudely dissolves the problem Thomas had so exquisitely solved. Thus no comparison between them on the problem of faith and reason is really possible, since properly speaking Luther, having simply rejected reason, has no position on the issue at all. Indeed, while the two figures can rightly be compared for their great though antithetical historical influence, in the nature of the case there can be no comparison of their views on any matter of theological and philosophical substance. 1 This paper considerably revises a presentation first given at a conference on Trinitarian theology in Neuendettelsau, Germany, in March 1993, and published in German in the proceedings of that conference: Joachim Heubach, ed., Luther und die trinitarische Tradition: Okumenische und philosophische Perspektiven (Erlangen: Martin-Luther-Verlag, 1994). 2 G. K. Chesterton, Saint Thomas Aquinas (New York: Doubleday, 1956; first published 1933), 33. 2 BRUCE D. MARSHALL "To compare these two figures bulking so big in history, in any philosophical sense, would of course be futile and even unfair. On a great map like the mind of Aquinas, the mind of Luther would be almost invisible. " 3 This paper argues that Aquinas and Luther hold basically the same view of faith and reason: the view that the most central Christian beliefs, those generated by communal interpretation of Scripture according to creedal rules, enjoy unrestricted epistemic primacy. It is not my purpose here to argue that this is the right theological view to have of how to decide which beliefs (or candidates for belief} are true; that I have done elsewhere. 4 But of course in order to hold this view one need not rely upon the contemporary idiom I have just used to state it. Despite their distance from us and their genuine differences from each other, Aquinas and Luther each counts as a rich precedent for a theological epistemology which accords unrestricted epistemic primacy to the Christian community's most central convictionsto the deliverances of faith rather than to those of reason. Of course much has changed since Chesterton's dismissal of Luther sixty years ago. A generation of Catholic and Lutheran scholarship has found Aquinas and Luther to be not only comparable, but in profound agreement, on some utterly central theological matters-above all the justification of the sinner and the wider complex of issues surrounding that topic, traditionally regarded as the most important and most divisive in CatholicLutheran theological controversy. 5 Unfortunately school theology, both Catholic and Protestant, has barely begun to get the message that Aquinas and Luther might both be greatly misunderstood if they are assumed to be opposites. Perhaps nowhere is this more clearly the case than on the question of faith and reason. Though in our day few would put the matter quite so bluntly as Chesterton, the assumptions which lead him to play Aquinas and Luther off against one another remain largely in place. Defenders of Aquinas on faith and reason 3 Ibid., 194. In Trinity and Truth (Cambridge: University Press, 1999). Above all see Otto Hermann Pesch, Die Theologie der Rechtfertigung bei Martin Luther und Thomas van Aquin (Mainz: Matthias-Griinewald-Verlag, 1967; reprint 1985). 4 5 FAITH AND REASON RECONSIDERED 3 (most, though not all, Catholic) still tend to assume that Luther was a naive if perhaps admirably passionate fideist, whose hatred of reason isolates Christian theology from the rest of human knowledge and thereby makes it impossible to give reasonable people any grounds for thinking that Christian beliefs are plausible, let alone true. Defenders of Luther on faith and reason (here the Lutherans have the field pretty much to themselves) still tend to assume that Aquinas was more a philosopher than a theologian, a rationalist who skews-perhaps perverts-the gospel by trying to harmonize it with Aristotle, and thereby fails to see that the gospel contradicts all human wisdom, as it contradicts all human righteousness. Even among specialists, the suggestion that despite obvious and important differences in concept, interest, and style, Aquinas and Luther might basically agree on faith and reason has made little progress compared with the suggestion that they agree on the justification of the sinner. In part this reflects the persistence of those readings that support the assumption that their opposition on the matter of faith and reason is basic and obvious. I will therefore try to suggest how the standard readings might be undermined in both cases. In part, though, the assumption of opposition has nothing specifically to do with Aquinas and Luther, but with the vagueness of the question of "faith and reason." Our chance of progress in sorting out their respective views on this nest of issues will likely increase if we pose to each of them a more precise question: how should we decide what sentences and beliefs are true? The hope is that by attending to this question about epistemic justification we will be able to uncover broad and deep agreement between the two theologians on how it should be answered. I. AQUINAS ON FAITH, NATURAL REASON, AND EPISTEMIC PRIORITIES Since my primary aim is to test the claim that Aquinas and Luther basically agree on how to decide what is true, I will here only outline a reading of Aquinas on this matter. I have developed and defended this sort of reading in more detail 4 BRUCE D. MARSHALL elsewhere. 6 The interpretation of Aquinas outlined here is, moreover, broadly congruent with those proposed at book length by Michel Corbin and, more recently, by Thomas Hibbs and Eugene Rogers. 7 In what follows I will try to identify the main elements in Aquinas's account of how we should decide what is true, and-since the way I will read him departs rather drato some matically from standard interpretations-respond objections to this reading which naturally arise. "The chief matter in the teaching of the Christian faith," Thomas observes in commenting on 1 Corinthians 1: 17, "is the salvation accomplished by the cross of Christ." In order to teach any subject matter successfully, he goes on to say, the manner of teaching must befit the distinctive character of that subject matter. Otherwise the matter itself will be distorted or destroyed in the attempt to teach it, and the learner will come to understand and know not the intended subject matter but a different one, or perhaps none at all-as happens, for example, with those who try to teach the inexact science of ethics deductively. 8 Here as elsewhere, Thomas maintains, Aristotle had the right idea: "The way of making the truth manifest in a given science must be suitable to the matter which is the subject of that science."9 What then is the proper way to make manifest that truth which is the chief matter of Christian faith? Thomas seems to propose two main conditions for rightly teaching (or preaching) "the salvation accomplished by the cross of Christ." 6 See Bruce D. Marshall, "Aquinas as Postliberal Theologian," The Thomist 53 (1989): 353-402; idem, "Thomas, Thomisms, and Truth," The Thomist 56 (1992): 499-524; idem, "Absorbing the World: Christianity and the Universe of Truths," in Theology and Dialogue, ed. Bruce D. Marshall (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1990), 69-102, esp. 90-97. 7 Michel Corbin, Le chemin de la theologie chez Thomas dAquin (Paris: Beauchesne, 1974); Thomas S. Hibbs, Dialecticand Narrativein Aquinas:An Interpretationof the Summa Contra Gentiles (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1995); Eugene F. Rogers, Jr., Thomas Aquinasand Karl Barth: SacredDoctrineand the Natural Knowledgeof God (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1995). The last includes an instructive comparison with Barth (who, as we will argue here about Luther, apparently turns out not to be the epistemic antithesis of Thomas that he himself supposed). 8 In I Cor. c. 1, lect. 3 (no. 45). S. Thomae Aquinatis Super EpistolasS. Pauli Lectura, vol. 1, 8th ed., ed. R. Cai, O.P. (Turin: Marietti, 1953). All translations are my own. 9 S. Thomae Aquinatis in Decem Libras Ethicorum Aristotelis Expositio, ed. R. Spiazzi, O.P. (Turin: Marietti, 1949), c. 1, lect. 3 (no. 32). FAITH AND REASON RECONSIDERED 5 First, this matter cannot be taught rightly if we attempt to decide about its truth by the standards of human reason. That person teaches "according to human wisdom" (in sapientiaverbi), Thomas explains, "who accepts the wisdom of human reason as the primary basis of his teaching, so that he accepts only those teachings which are supported by human reason, and rejects those which are not. But this destroys the faith. " 10 As Thomas sees it (in, for example, his commentary on Col 2:8), the great temptation of philosophy for Christian faith and theology lies in its power to lure those who would teach the faith into this self-destruction, which happens "when someone wants to measure the things of faith according to the principles of [created] reality and not according to divine wisdom ...u Philosophy deceives when it seduces us into "measuring the truth of faith according to the truth of creatures"; the greatest temptation to this fatal epistemic reversal comes, of course, precisely from good philosophy, that which judges per principia realia philosophiae, and not per sophisticasrationes-but presumes to render a verdict where no philosophical principia have the right to judge. 12 For those who succumb to the temptation and decide about truth "according to the world" (secundum mundum) and its wisdom, the preaching of the cross of Christ inevitably turns into foolishness, "since it includes something which seems impossible according to human wisdom, namely that God dies [Deus moriatur],and that the omnipotent becomes subject to the power of the violent." 13 On Thomas's account two outcomes, in fact, seem possible when the annuntiatio crucis Christi is measured for truth by the standards of human reason: either it will be taken to propose beliefs inconsistent with these standards, and so be rejected as false, or the meaning of the sentences that make up the annuntiatio will be changed in order to make them consistent 10 In I Cor. c. 1, lect. 3 (no. 43). On the equivalence of sapientia verbi and sapientia humanae rationis, cf. ibid. (no. 42). 11 In Col. c. 2, lect. 2 (no. 92); Super Epistolas S. Pauli Lectura, vol. 2, ed. R. Cai, O.P. (Turin: Marietti, 1953). 12 Ibid. (nos. 94, 91). 13 In I Cor. c. 1, lect. 3 (no. 4 7). 6 BRUCE D. MARSHALL with, and so capable of being held true by, these same standards (so that God is not really held to die, be subject to the violent, and the like). Either way the chief matter of Christian faith fails to be taught; Paul's point in this passage, Thomas argues, is precisely that those who rely epistemically "primarily upon the wisdom of human reason" empty the cross of Christ of its power to save, because in so doing they fail to teach the chief matter of Christian faith in "a manner suitable to" the matter itself. 14 Interpreting this claim depends in part on specifying the beliefs or classes of beliefs that are supposed to count as "the wisdom of human reason," and as such may not be used to assess the truth of the chief matter of Christian faith, however legitimately they may be applied to test the truth of other beliefs. The long way to go about this would be to search out a definition (what Thomas calls a formalis ratio) of "human wisdom," "human reason," or "philosophy" that would enable us to pick out those beliefs that are humanly wise, reasonable, or philosophical, but there is, I think, a more direct way to get at what Thomas is claiming. He objects not to "human reason" and "philosophy" per se but to a particular use of those beliefs that human beings will naturally tend to regard as reasonable. That person rightly "uses the wisdom of human reason," Thomas argues, "who, presupposing the foundations of the true faith, if he finds anything true in the teachings of the philosophers, takes it into the obedience of faith." 15 Any belief, it seems, no matter how reasonable or obvious, becomes for Thomas "human wisdom" in the sense Paul rejects when it is set up as a standard by which to assess the truth of those beliefs which constitute "the foundations of the true faith"; conversely, the right use of the "true faith" is to take it as the final standard by which to assess beliefs we otherwise regard as reasonable, in order to see decisively if we can "find anything true" in them. Thomas's first rule for teaching the Christian faith is thus that we keep our epistemic priorities straight: we ought to 14 Ibid. (no. 45). On principaliter mundo innititur, cf. In I Cor. c. 3, lect. 3 (no. 179), which contrasts this sort of disordered epistemic use of the res huius mundi with use rightly ordered by the sapientia Dei. 15 In I Cor. c. 1, lect. 3 (no. 43). Thomas gets this idea from Augustine (De doctrina christiana 2.40). FAITH AND REASON RECONSIDERED 7 decide whether other beliefs are true by seeing whether their contents agree with those interpreted sentences which together identify and describe "the salvation accomplished by the cross of Christ," and we ought not to decide whether those same interpreted sentences are true by seeing whether they agree with the contents of other beliefs. (fhe precise range of "other beliefs" to which this rule applies will occupy us later on.) Thomas's second rule for teaching the Christian faith is that we treat the beliefs which together identify and describe its chief matter as a complex but indivisible whole. The Church's creed (specifically the Apostles' Creed) enumerates the leading elements in this complex of belief; Thomas counts fourteen of them, grouped into those having to do with the hidden majesty of God and those having to do with the narrative (what Thomas calls the "mystery") of Christ's particular humanity, by which we are inducted into the vision of God's otherwise hidden majesty-or, as Thomas elsewhere puts it, those pertaining to the Trinity and those pertaining to the incarnation. 16 Thus the interpreted sentences which (according to the first rule) are tests of truth for other beliefs but not tested by them are those which, when believed, shape more than any others the identity of a particular historical community; the Church is constituted as a coherent community, Thomas maintains, by its assent in love to what the creed teaches (though not, of course, only by that). 17 The articles of faith themselves collect innumerable further sentences for belief, chiefly those of Scripture. The Church's Trinitarian and Christological confession adds nothing to Scripture, but rather is drawn from Scripture in order to organize communal reading of the biblical text (an aim which includes, on Thomas's view, proposing for assent a clear summary of Scripture's content for those who would not know what to make of the text on their own). 18 "Canonical scripture alone," he Cf. STh II-II, q. 1, a. 8 (Turin: Marietti, 1948); In I Cor. c. 15, lect. 1 (no. 894). Cf. STh II-II, q. 1, a. 9, ad 3: "The confession of faith is handed on in the creed by the person, as it were, of the whole Church [quasi ex persona totius Ecclesiae],which is united by faith. Now the faith of the Church is formed faith ... ". 18 Cf. SI'h II-II, q. 1, a. 9, ad 1: The creed "is certainly not added to sacred Scripture, but rather taken from sacred Scripture"; on the creed as a binding rule for scriptural interpretation, cf. STh II-II, q. 5, a. 3 (cited below, n. 21), and ad 2. 16 17 8 BRUCE D. MARSHALL argues, "is the rule of faith," and so no one ought to teach otherwise than it does. 19 Thus the epistemic priority over other beliefs which belongs to "the salvation accomplished by the cross of Christ" may be ascribed more precisely to the body of beliefs (the specific contents of which naturally change somewhat over time) generated by Scripture interpreted in the Christian community according to shared creedal rules. Communally interpreted Scripture has this high status because "it is a kind of light, flowing like a ray from the first truth"-that is, from God, who is the source and measure of all truth. 20 So understood, Scripture is the self-testimony of God as first truth, and faith is that act and habit defined by its reliance upon this self-testifying God (and so upon "divine truth itself") in its assent to (or dissent from) interpreted sentences about God, and about creatures in their relations to God. 21 Faith, in other words, clings to the incarnate and triune 19 Thomas Aquinas, Super Evangelium S. Ioannis Lectura, 5th ed., ed. R. Cai, O.P. (furin: Marietti, 1952), c. 21, lect. 6 (no. 2656); cf. In I Tim. c. 6, lect. 1 (no. 237): "The teaching of the apostles and prophets is called canonical because it is a kind of rule for our intellect. And therefore no one ought to teach otherwise [than it does]." 20 "The truth of sacred Scriptm e is a kind of light, flowing forth like a ray from the first truth" (fhomas Aquinas, In Dion. de Div. Nom., ed. C. Pera, O.P. [furin: Marietti, 1950], c. 1, lect. 1 [no. 15]). Therefore: "If the principles on the basis of which this teaching [of the faith= theology] proceeds are those which have been received through a revelation from the Holy Spirit and handed on in the sacred Scriptures, it follows that in this teaching nothing else is handed on than those things which are contained in the sacred Scriptures" (ibid., no. 11, but I cite from the fuller text of this passage provided by Bruno Decker in "Sola Scriptura bei Thomas von Aquin," in Ludwig Lenhart, ed., Universitas: Dienst an Wahrheit und Leben, Festschrift for Albert Stohr [Mainz: Matthias-Grunewald, 1960], 117-29; here, 118). On God as prima veritas, cf. STh I, q. 16, aa. 5-6; Summa Contra Gentiles I, c. 62 (no. 519) (3 vols., ed. C. Pera et al. [furin: Marietti, 1961]). 21 STh II-II, q. 1, a. 1: "Faith ... does not assent to anything except because it is revealed by God: hence faith relies upon divine truth itself as its means [media]," that is, as the "formalis ratio obiecti" by which the act and habit of faith are defined. Regarding faith as reliance precisely on the testimony of the first truth, which therefore necessarily includes holding specific sentences true, cf. De Spe, a. 1: "Faith does not count as a virtue except insofar as it clings to the testimony of the first truth, such that it believes that which is made manifest by him" (fhomas Aquinas, Quaestiones Disputatae, vol. 2, ed. P. Bazzi, et al. [f urin: Marietti, 1965]). And: "The formal object of faith is the first truth, according as it is manifested in the sacred Scriptures and the teaching of the Church. Hence whoever does not cling to the teaching of the Church, as to an infallible and divine rule which originates [procedit] from the first truth made manifest in the sacred Scriptures, does not have the habit of faith" (STh II-II, q. 5, a. 3). FAITH AND REASON RECONSIDERED 9 God who manifests himself to us as first truth by way of the scripturally normed discourse of the Christian community. Indeed, the teaching and preaching of the Church are not simply this community's talk about God, nor even God's talk about himself, but God's way of giving the world a share in his own self-knowledge: "By assent faith . . . joins the human being to God's own knowing." 22 Epistemically, the articles of Christian faith are for Thomas strictly a package deal. The central nexus of Christian teaching is made up of many beliefs, but they are all mutually fit for one another in such a way that the "perception of divine truth" depends upon holding them all true together. 23 That is: if one of the sentences which make up the articles of faith is held true-say, "Deus est unus"-while another is not-say, "Deus est trinitas Personarum" or "Deus moritur"-then the sentence held true is, in the mind and on the lips of that holder, false. Thomas makes this point in a particularly striking way when he considers the possibility of what later came to be called "natural theology," that is, whether a person without Christian faith (specifically a pre-Christian philosopher) is able, at least in some respects, to know the truth about God. Commenting, for example, on the statement "O righteous Father, the world has not known you" Gohn 17:25), he remarks that "while some of the Gentiles knew God with respect to certain things which were knowable by reason, nevertheless they did not know him insofar as he is the Father of the only-begotten and consubstantial Son," that is, they did not know about the Trinity and the incarnation. In this way they were wrong about God, if only by error of 22 De Verit., q. 14, a. 8 (S. Thomae Aquinatis QuaestionesDisputatae, vol. 1, 8th ed., ed. R. Spiazzi, 0.P. [Turin: Marietti, 1949)). Correlatively sacra doctrina, having as its first principles the articles of faith, is able to talk about God not only with respect to what may be known per creaturas(about which more momentarily), but "with respect to that which is known to God alone concerning himself, and which is shared with others by revelation" (STh I, q. 1, a. 6). 23 STh II-II, q. 1, a. 6: "Those matters which the Christian faith proposes for belief [credibiliafidei Christianae]are said to be distinguished into various 'articles' insofar as they are divided into certain parts having a mutual fitness for one another [coaptationemad invicem]"; ibid., sed contra: "We attain the perception of divine truth in a way which involves a certain distinction, in that those things which are one in God become manifold in our intellect." 10 BRUCE D. MARSHALL omission (though Thomas also ascribes errors of commission to all the ancient philosophers, including Aristotle). But "even if they err in the smallest way regarding the knowledge of God, they are said to be completely ignorant of him [Unde etsi in minimo aliqui errent circa Dei cognitionem, dicuntur eum totaliter ignorare]."24 The beliefs that God is and is one are true on Thomas's account, it seems, only when they are held true together with the rest of the articles of faith ("under the conditions faith defines," as Thomas puts it). 25 Otherwise the holder labors under a cognitive defect so drastic that his holding true completely fails to attain any real object; in this case defectus cognitionis est so/um in non attingendo totaliter-any defect of knowledge is complete ignorance. 26 In other words: under these conditions a person's holding true lacks the adaequatio or correspondentiamentis ad rem by which (however more precisely construed) truth is defined, and so his beliefs are false.27 Thomas's technical device for making this point is a notion, derived from Aristotle, of the way a simple or incomposite reality may be known. The idea, roughly, is that while our minds can be conformed to any reality (be "true" with respect to that reality) only by holding true interpreted sentences, in "simple things," unlike the composite objects of our ordinary sense experience, there are no real distinctions which correspond to the distinctions between the relevant true sentences. As a result, while it is logically and psychologically possible to hold some of the relevant sentences true without others, in the case of "simples" there can be no partial conformity; one either believes enough sentences to bring about the conformity, or one does not have it at all. Applied 24 In Joan. c. 17, lect. 6 (no. 2265); for the text and a more detailed discussion, cf. Marshall, "Thomas, Thomisms, and Truth," 501-4. On Aristotle's errors of commission, cf. ibid., 502 n. 4. 25 SI'h 11-11, q. 2, a. 2, ad 3. For a fuller discussion of this text see Marshall, "Aquinas as Postliberal Theologian," 380-84. On the Trinity as falling "under the conditions faith defines," cf. III Sent., d. 23, q. 2, a. 2, qcla. 2, ad 2 (no. 151) (ed. P. Mandonnet, O.P., and M. F. Moos, O.P. [Paris: Lethielleux, 1929-47]). 26 SI'h 11-11, q. 2, a. 2, ad 3. 27 For a more detailed discussion of the notion of truth as adaequatio,correspondentia, and the like, see my essay, "'We Shall Bear the Image of the Man of Heaven': Theology and the Concept ofTruth," ModernTheology 11 (1995): 93-117; and Trinity and Truth, chs. 8-9. FAITH AND REASON RECONSIDERED 11 (in a supreme or supereminent sense) to God, this notion of simplicity means that "those things which are one in God become manifold in our intellect," and only taken together does the manifold yield "perception of divine truth. " 28 However, the force of Thomas's apparent claim that the prospective natural theologian-someone who believes that God exists but not that God is incarnate and dies-fails (totaliter) to "reach" God cognitively, need not depend, I think, upon recourse to a theory of the knowledge of simples. The same point can be made by attending to the way the sense or interpretation of the sentence "Deus est" is fixed in such a way that when held true, it is true. According to Thomas, someone in the epistemic situation of the would-be natural theologian "does not believe under the conditions faith defines," and therefore "does not really believe that there is a God [nee vere Deum credunt]."29 In the first place this seems simply to mean, as the conclusion of this reply goes on to state explicitly, that the natural theologian's beliefs about God (and in particular his belief that God exists) are not true (defectus ... est ... in non attingendo totaliter). But it also suggests that the natural theologian, not believing "under the conditions faith defines" (for example, together with belief in the Trinity and the incarnation), does not believe the same thing as the Christian when he asserts "Deus est" (that is, "does not 'really' [vere] believe that God exists"). The point would then be that "Deus est" when spoken by the natural theologian does not mean the same thing as it does when spoken by the believer, and indeed cannot have a meaning which agrees with the way the world is arranged, that is, which makes for a true sentence. Read in this way, Thomas's claim that "Deus est" can be, as spoken, false-even when spoken as the conclusion of a formally valid argument, as it was, so Thomas supposes, by the ancient 28 STh II-II, q. 1, a. 6, sc (cf. above, n. 23). Thomas applies this argument in both of the passages just discussed (STh II-II, q. 2, a. 2, ad 3 and In Joan. c. 17, lect. 6 [no. 2265]); cf. also IX Metaphys., lect. 11 (nos. 1905-7) (ed. M.-R. Cathala, O.P., and R. Spiazzi, O.P. [Turin: Marietti, 1964]). The general principles at work here are: "Every knower has knowledge of that which is known not in the manner of the thing known, but in the manner of the knower," and "No creature's manner [of knowing] reaches the height of the divine majesty" (I Sent., d. 3, q. 1, a. 1). 29 STh II-II, q. 2, a. 2, ad 3. 12 BRUCE D. MARSHALL philosophers-might be interpreted along the following lines. The meaning and interpretation of any one sentence a speaker utters are fixed by ascertaining the truth value the speaker assigns to that sentence, and establishing the logical location of the interpreted sentence by working out its connections to a host of other more or less closely associated sentences the speaker holds true. (I group meaning and interpretation together on the assumption, argued for in different ways by Wittgenstein, Quine, Davidson, and others, that meaning is public-that a speaker means just what an interpreter can correctly make out, where "correctly" does not involve any question-begging appeal to prior knowledge of the speaker's beliefs and intentions.) 30 When the believer asserts "Deus est," the meaning of that sentence is fixed by its location in the logical space of the articles of the creed; what the believer means by "Deus," for example, is established by his assent to closely related sentences like "Verbum [therefore "Deus"] caro factum est" and "Deus moritur." These are sentences which, per definitionem, the natural theologian does not hold true. However, if the sense of the natural theologian's "Deus est" is supposed to be what compels the believer to regard it as false (apart from a theory about the knowledge of simples), then that sense will presumably have to be incompatible with the meaning the sentence has in the logical space of assent to the creed, and not simply different from it. Now believers, according to Thomas, "recognize in the cross of Christ the death of God, by which he has conquered the devil and the world"; in so doing, as we have seen, they attribute to God what "seems impossible according to human wisdom." 31 That is: people who fix the sense of "Deus est" by holding true sentences like "Verbum [=Deus] caro factum est" and "Unus de trinitate passus est" (people who are eo ipso believers) will also, indeed necessarily, hold true "Deus moritur." By contrast, people who fix the sense of "Deus est" otherwise than by holding true 30 As Davidson observes: "We cannot hope to attach a sense to the attribution of finely discriminated intentions independently of interpreting speech ... interpreting an agent's intentions, his beliefs and his words are parts of a single project, no part of which can be assumed to be complete before the rest is" ("Radical Interpretation," in Inquiriesinto Truth and Interpretation[Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984], 127). 31 In I Cor. c. 1, lect. 3 (no. 47); cf. above, n. 13. FAITH AND REASON RECONSIDERED 13 sentences like these will, Thomas supposes, inevitably reject "Deus moritur," indeed will find it foolish. Consequently what they mean by "Deus" when they assert "Deus est" will not only be different from, but contradictory to, what the believer means; if the believer's assertion of "Deus est" is true, the natural theologian's cannot be. Of course many more people hold true the sentence "Deus est" than hold true sentences like "Verbum caro factum est" and "Deus moritur," and the existence of God can (when he is adequately identified as the God who dies on the cross) be demonstrated, while his death cannot (about which more in a moment). But it seems that on Thomas's view "Deus est" is no more central epistemically than "Deus moritur," since the latter fixes the former's sense, that is, the sense according to which "Deus est" is part of the creedal network of belief to which epistemic primacy belongs. In either case Aquinas apparently rejects natural theology in the sense in which it is usually attributed to him; people without Christian faith, despite having sometimes mastered formally valid arguments concluding in sentences like "Deus est" and "Deus est unus" (as did the ancient philosophers), do not actually speak and think truly about God--even about God's existence and unity. Despite initially appearing to offer strong resistance, Thomas's treatment of natural theology turns out, I think, to exemplify with particular force the rule that the articles of faith can only be rightly taught as a package. To be sure, Thomas thinks God can be known per creaturas, in that matters like God's existence and unity can be demonstrated on the basis of beliefs about the world one need not be a Christian to hold. He takes this to be the clear teaching of Scripture (Rom 1: 19-20a invariably serves as the textual support), but he takes it to be the equally clear teaching of Scripture that the possibility of knowing God per creaturashas been effectively withdrawn by God from fallen human beings on account of sin (for which Rom 1 :20b-21 provides some of the textual support). 32 32 For such a juxtaposition of Rom 1:21 with Rom 1:19, see In Joan. c. 17, lect. 6 (no. 2265). For more on Thomas's commentary on Rom 1, see Marshall, "Thomas, Thomisms, and Truth," 509-15; Rogers gives a much more detailed analysis in Thomas Aquinasand Karl Barth, 73-180. 14 BRUCE D. MARSHALL What the Vulgate of Romans 1: 18 calls impietas and iniustitia, caused on Thomas's account by that "vanity" in which "the human mind ... having bypassed God, relies upon some sort of creature," so that human beings "place their trust in themselves, and not in God," results in the loss of the interior light by which God enables us to know him per creaturas-a situation which can be analyzed, I have argued, in part as an inability to fix the sense of "Deus" in a way adequate to making true assertions about God. 33 The possibility of such knowledge becomes available once again only through "the salvation accomplished by the cross of Christ," that is, only through faith's reliant apprehension of the cruciform self-testimony of the prima veritas, and consequent participation in God's own knowledge: "Creatures were insufficient to lead to knowledge of the creator, hence 'the world was made through him, and knew him not' Uohn 1:10]. Therefore it was necessary that the creator himself come into the world in the flesh, and be known through himself [per seipsum]." 34 "The human mind is freed from vanity"-and so 33 In Rom. c. 1, lect. 7 (no. 129). Thus, "'Their heart has been made foolish,' that is, it has been deprived of the light of wisdom, by which a person truly knows God" (ibid. [no. 130]). 34 In Joan. c. 1, lect. 5 (no. 141). Thomas's argument here that even without sin human beings would have to believe in the future incarnation of the Word in order to know God at all contrasts sharply with the view generally attributed to him, namely that God would not have become incarnate had there been no sin-a view which, to be sure, he often enough endorses (cf. STh III, q. 1, a. 3; In I Tim. c. 1, lect. 4, [no. 40]; the latter cited in Marshall, "Thomas, Thomisms, and Truth," 514-15 n. 32). Yet in Thomas's commentary on the Johannine prologue, in contrast to the Lectura on Romans 1 just discussed, the inability of human beings to know God from creatures comes explicitly from a "defect of creatures" (creaturarum defectum), who cannot by themselves serve as an adequate basis for the knowledge of God, and not from the darkness of the human mind brought on by sin. These are two different reasons, here clearly distinguished by Aquinas, "why God willed to become incarnate." This suggestion is not without parallel in Thomas's texts. Even before the fall, he elsewhere argues, human beings could know God demonstratively per creaturasonly together with knowledge available by faith alone, in particular only together with faith in the future incarnation (though not yet passion) of the Son: "Faith, which clings to the first truth, is common to all who have knowledge of God, but have not yet reached the blessedness to come" (STh II-II, q. 5, a. 1); "Before the state of sin human beings had explicit faith concerning the incarnation of Christ, insofar as this was ordered toward the attainment of glory [consummationemgloriae],but not insofar as it was ordered toward liberation from sin through the passion and resurrection, because humans lacked foreknowledge of the sin which was to come" (STh II-II, q. 2, a. 7). For some provocative reflection on these issues in FAITH AND REASON RECONSIDERED 15 from ignorance of God-"only when it relies upon God"; God can be known through creatures only when human beings do not rely primarily upon creatures for this knowledge. 35 The believer who works out a demonstration of God's existence or unity attains genuine knowledge of God per creaturas,but continues to rely primarily on God's self-testimony in order to speak and think truly about God even with respect to these matters, rather than on his own apprehension of the principles upon which the demonstration is based or on the cogency with which he draws the conclusion. "A human being is much more certain about what he hears from God, who cannot be deceived, than about what he sees by his own reason, because his reason can be deceived. " 36 Thus if it comes to a conflict between what seems self-evident (and in that sense certain) to us and the articles of faith (which are not certain in this way), then one holds the articles true. Here too it is necessary to keep one's epistemic priorities straight, and primacy continues to belong to the articles of faith. 37 Thomas, cf. Michel Corbin, "La Parole devenue chair: Lecture de la premiere question de la Somme Theologique de Thomas d'Aquin," in L'inoui"de Dieu: Six etudes christologiques (Paris: Desclee de Brouwer, 1980), 109-58. 35 In Rom. c. 1, lect. 7 (no. 129); cf. the "credere Deo" of STh 11-11, q. 2, a. 2. 36 STh 11-11, q. 4, a. 8, ad 2. Similarly, "No one ought to have any doubt concerning the faith, but ought to believe what belongs to the faith more certainly than what he sees, since human vision can be deceived, but the knowledge [scientia] of God is never mistaken" (Nicholas Ayo, C.S.C., ed. and trans., The Sermon-Conferencesof St. Thomas Aquinason the Apostles'Creed [Notre Dame: University Press, 1988], 24. Ayo here publishes a preliminary version of the Leonine text [vol. 44, still forthcoming] of Aquinas's Collationes Credo in Deum, a work known in the "vulgate" tradition of Thomas's texts as In Symbolum ApostolorumExpositio [cf. OpusculaTheologica,vol. 2, no. 868]). Therefore, "The believer's assent to what belongs to the faith is greater and more stable even than assent to the first principles of reason" (I Sent. pro., q. 1, a. 3, qcla. 3). As a result, "just as knowledge [scientia] is certain, so also faith. Indeed much more so, since the certainty of knowledge relies upon human reason, which can be deceived, while the certainty of faith relies upon divine reason, which cannot be contradicted" (In Joan. c. 4, lect. 5 [no. 662]). And conversely: faith "does not rely upon human wisdom, which very often [plerumque]deceives human beings ... faith relies upon divine power, and therefore it cannot fail" (In I Cor. c. 2, lect. 1 [no. 79]). Regarding the believer's continuing reliance in love upon God's self-testimony even with respect to those articles (called by Thomas, in light of their demonstrability, "praeambula") which may be demonstrated, see STh 11-11, q. 2, a. 10, ad 2. 37 The way Thomas conceives the epistemic relation between what we "hear from God" and what we "see by our own reason" helps explain his lack of interest in the question, greatly troubling to rationalist apologetics since the Enlightenment (including that of many 16 BRUCE D. MARSHALL How far, then, does the epistemic primacy of the articles of faith-materially, of the beliefs sufficient to identify and describe "the salvation accomplished by the cross of Christ"--extend? Thomas, I think, dearly regards the epistemic primacy of the articles as unrestricted-as extending to decisions about the truth of all possible sentences. The articles, moreover, are unrestrictedly decisive. They are epistemic trump: whatever interpreted sentences are inconsistent with them cannot be true. In the nature of the case this unrestricted criteriological primacy of central Christian beliefs (that is, the beliefs which most centrally constitute the identity of this community) can only be stated negatively: "Whatever is not in agreement with Christ is to be rejected [lit., 'spewed out']. "38 The positive complement, of course, does not follow; whatever is in agreement with Christ is not, on that ground alone, to be accepted as true. Thomists), of how we can be sure that Scripture and creed actually are God's speech. For Thomas supreme certainty belongs not to those beliefs which seem most compelling for us in via, but to what God says-God's speech is, indeed, that than which there can be nothing more certain, since it declares and gives us a share in God's own knowledge, itself the measure of all truth. Thus, "when a person has been led to believe by [natural reason, the testimony of the law and the prophets, and the preaching of the apostles], then he can say that he does not believe on account of any of these things: not on account of natural reason, nor on account of the testimony of the law, nor on account of the preaching of others, but on account of the truth itself" (In Joan. c. 4, lect. 5 [no. 662]; cf. STh II-II, q. 4, a. 8 and above, nn. 20-22). Since what God says is much more certain for us than what we see by our own reason, anything we could without circularity adduce in support of the claim that the articles of faith are actually God's speech would be less certain than the content of the speech itself. Because the conclusion of an argument cannot be any more certain than its premises (as Thomas, following Aristotle, assumes), any attempt to conclude on the basis of what we can see by reason that the articles are God's speech will, if successful, diminish rather than enhance the certainty of the articles (since "human vision can be deceived"). Thus any attempt to demonstrate that the articles are in fact God's speech (though not the more modest effort of attempting to reply to objections which maintain they could not be) is in the nature of the case, like other endeavors to measure God's own wisdom by the principles of created reality (cf. above, n. 11), not only fruitless but counter-productive. Only the Holy Spirit can teach us to hear God's speech, and to rely upon it beyond even the most compelling of our own reason's certainties (about which more below). For a more detailed analysis of Thomas on certainty, see Marshall, "Aquinas as Postliberal Theologian," 393-401. 38 In Col. c. 2, lect. 2 (no. 95). And: "What is against [Christ] is to be spewed out, because he is God" (ibid. [no. 96]). In an earlier article I confused the issue by suggesting that the unrestricted epistemic primacy of the articles of faith could be stated positively; cf. Marshall, "Aquinas as Postliberal Theologian," 376. FAITH AND REASON RECONSIDERED 17 One way to get at Thomas's view here is to recall that for him Christian faith and Christian theology are, each in its own way, a kind of wisdom (sapientia).Wisdom for Thomas is the capacity to grasp the highest cause and to judge and order other things "most certainly" with reference to, or on the basis of, that cause (the definition is Aristotle's, and here "cause" has the roughly Aristotelian sense of "explanation"). "Highest cause," however, can be taken in an unrestricted sense or in a limited sense (simpliciter,vel in aliquo genere, as Aquinas says). When "highest cause" is taken in a limited sense, "wisdom" is the capacity to judge and order beliefs and actions according to explanatory principles of restricted application; the range of application for these principles defines a particular domain of human knowledge, like medicine or architecture. But when "highest cause" is taken simpliciter, then "wisdom" is the capacity to judge and order beliefs and actions according to the highest possible explanatory principles, which, as such, are of unrestricted application. The highest cause simpliciter is the triune God, and the highest principles are the articles of faith. Faith assents to these principles as the prima veritas (more precisely as the self-testimony of God, who is the prima veritas) and therefore not on account of any other beliefs held true (otherwise they would not linguistically embody the prima, but at best secunda, veritas). The capacity to order the total field of human belief and action according to these principles is wisdom as a gift of the Holy Spirit to believers. The unrestricted epistemic application of the articles of faith (that is, the exercise of the capacity the Spirit gives) defines not a particular domain of knowledge but a comprehensive system of the world, a world-view. This system of the world, now as content rather than capacity, constitutes the highest wisdom: the Christian faith itself. "The person who knows the highest cause without restriction [simpliciter],which is God, is said to be wise without restriction [simpliciter],insofar as he is able to judge and to order all things according to divine rules [viz., according to the articles of faith]. "39 39 STh II-II, q. 45, a. 1. On the connection between faith in the articles and the Spirit's gift of the highest wisdom, see ibid., ad 2: "Faith assents to divine truth on account of itself, and that judgment which is in accord with divine truth belongs to the gift of wisdom. Therefore the gift of wisdom presupposes faith." 18 BRUCE D. MARSHALL Thomas's discussion of the way in which theology (that is, sacra doctrina) is itself in a certain sense the highest wisdom helps to clarify the way he conceives the connection between faith's supremely wise ordering of the whole field of possible belief and the local, subordinate wisdom of medicine, architecture, and the like-that is, between the articles of faith taken as epistet;nically primary and all the rest of what we think we have good reason to believe.40 Sacra doctrina, Thomas maintains, is a science in basically Aristotle's sense, roughly, a set of interpreted sentences (or propositions) tied in logically tight ways to other interpreted sentences which are themselves either proven or beyond proof and doubt alike (and so are the "first principles" of the science). But "the knowledge proper to this science [sacra doctrina] is that which comes through revelation, not that which comes through natural reason," that is, the first principles of sacra doctrina are the articles of faith by which the prima veritas bears witness to himself. "Therefore it does not belong to sacred doctrine to prove the principles of the other sciences, but only to judge them: for whatever is found in other sciences which contradicts the truth of this science is totally to be rejected as false, according to II Cor. 10: [5]."41 40 Wisdom as a donum Spiritus sancti is related to sacra doctrina as the actual capacity to order the total field is related to the acquired ability reflectively to articulate what that capacity (which itself cannot be acquired, but only freely given by the Spirit) accomplishes. The former is wisdom per modum inclinationis, the latter is wisdom per modum cognitionis (STh I, q. 1, a. 6, ad 3). 41 STh I, q. 1, a. 6, ad 2. Similarly, "Those who use philosophy in sacred doctrine can err in two ways. In one way when they use those [philosophies] which are contrary to faith ... In another way when what belongs to faith is included within the boundaries of philosophy, such that one is only willing to believe that which can be maintained by philosophy, when, on the contrary, philosophy is to be brought within the boundaries of faith, as the Apostle teaches in 2 Cor 10" (In Boet. de Trin., q. 2, a. 3 [ed. Bruno Decker (Leiden: Brill, 1955); cf. the text from In I Cor. cited above, n. 10). Conversely, "secular wisdom and eloquence" are rightly used "in [the study of] sacred Scripture ... when they are not one's chief aim, but rather when one submits them to sacred Scripture, to which one chiefly clings, in order that in this way Scripture may take all other things into obedience to itself, according to 2 Cor. 10, 5" (Contra Impugnantes sect. 3, c. 5 [no. 414], in Opuscula Theologica, vol. 2). Indeed: "Those who use philosophical texts in sacred doctrine by bringing them into obedience to faith do not mix water with wine, but transform water into wine" (In Boet. de Trin., q. 2, a. 3, ad 5). FAITH AND REASON RECONSIDERED 19 Two points important for our purposes may be gathered from these remarks. (1) The unrestricted epistemic primacy of the articles of faith gives the content of sacra doctrina the rank of highest wisdom, as it gives the same rank to the habit of wisdom which the Spirit imparts to the faithful. Once again the logical relationship of inconsistency, not consistency, defines the unrestricted character of that primacy: of the articles of faith alone may it be said that whatever beliefs are inconsistent with them cannot be true. 42 (2) The epistemic primacy of central Christian beliefs with respect to the total field of possible belief is, by contrast, almost never deductive or inferential, and need be warranting in any sense only when the meaning of the beliefs in question is dose enough to that of the articles to call for it.43 We 42 This may seem to overstate the case, since Thomas clearly supposes that there are beliefs besides the articles of faith with which no true sentence can be inconsistent; the clearest example is what he calls principiaper se nota (lit., "principles known through themselves"), beliefs whose truth is directly and non-inferentially apparent, and thus self-evident (including particularly what Thomas calls "the first principles of reason," and beliefs like "the whole is greater than the part"; cf., e.g., STh I, q. 17, a. 3, ad 2; STh 11-11, q. 1, a. 5). But as we have already seen, (1) Thomas takes the believer's assent to the articles of faith to be "greater and more stable" (magis ... et firmius) than his assent "even to the first principles of reason" (cf. above, n. 36), and (2) consistency with the articles of faith (or with Christ) is required of "all other" (omnia alia) beliefs, such that "whatever" (quidquid)is inconsistent with them cannot be true (cf. nn. 41, 38). This suggests that in order to decide whether a belief which appears self-evident to us is actually true, we need to test it for consistency with the articles of faith; should it turn out not to be we need not suppose we have found a self-evident principle which is false, but simply that we have failed, despite initial appearances, to identify a self-evident principle (cf. In Boet. de Trin., q. 2, a. 3: "If anything is found contrary to the faith in the sayings of the philosophers, this is not philosophy, but rather an abuse of philosophy arising from a defect of reason"; the dicta philosophorumof course contain much more than principiaper se nota). Read in this way, Thomas seems to hold that principiaper se nota are indeed of unrestricted epistemic application, in that nothing inconsistent with them is true, but not of unrestricted epistemic primacy, since we decide whether we have a principiumper se notum by seeing whether the belief in question is consistent with the articles of faith, but we do not test the articles for their consistency with the principiawhich they help identify, or with any other beliefs (assuming throughout, of course, that we have interpretedthe articles correctly, on which see Marshall, "Absorbing the World," 90-97, and the penultimate section of the present article). This means, to be sure, that Thomas's account of faith and sacra doctrina as (each in its own way) the highest wisdom calls for greater revision of Aristotle's notion of self-evidence than Thomas actually undertakes (cf. VI Ethic., lect. 5 [no. 1179]); if we have to repair to other beliefs in order to decide whether a putative "principle" is actually true, we obviously do not know the principle "through itself." 43 The "almost" is to account for inferences within theology after the pattern of STh I, q. 1, a. 2; STh I, q. 1, a. 8. Cf. the remarks below, n. 58, regarding Luther on inference. 20 BRUCE D. MARSHALL cannot on Thomas's view deduce the chief points of what we ought to believe about medicine or architecture from the articles of faith, the way we can deduce, and in that sense prove, the first principles of optics from geometry. The reasons we have for holding the vast majority of our beliefs (or, if it is reasonable to have some beliefs without reasons, our very holding of them) will not be traceable to those which are central to the whole field of belief, and they need not be in order to maintain the unrestricted epistemic primacy of the articles. That the highest wisdom is a gift specifically of the Holy Spirit suggests its irreducibly Trinitarian character; formed faith and the correlated spiritual gift of sapientia (along with the gifts of intellectus and scientia) together constitute the specifically cognitive way of being drawn into the one life of the triune God, or of sharing in God's self-knowledge. Thomas's view seems to be something like this. To have the gift of the highest wisdom is to assess everything else in light of the highest cause or explanation, namely God. But "the root and source of the knowledge of God is the Word of God, that is, Christ ... insofar as human beings share in the Word of God, they know God"-not, it should be stressed, in a fleshless and therefore anonymous Verbum, but precisely in the eternal Word become our flesh, the human being Jesus of Nazareth: "this human being is divine truth itself."44 Wisdom is therefore the practice of interpreting and assessing everything else in light specifically of Scripture's identification and description of the human being Jesus Christ, and above all of the salvation accomplished by his cross. Only the Holy Spirit can teach us this practice. The beliefs according to which it is the highest wisdom to assess all others are not self-evident, empirically obvious, demonstrable, or widely shared; when assessed in light of those which are (according to what Thomas calls "the wisdom of human reason"), the articles of faith will be rejected as false (indeed, foolish), not taken as the highest wisdom. Taught by the Spirit the practice of ordering all things around the crucified and risen Jesus, however, we "become sharers in the divine wisdom 44 In Joan. c. 17, lect. 6 (no. 2267-68); ibid. c. 1, lect. 8 (no. 188). FAITH AND REASON RECONSIDERED 21 and knowers of the truth. The Son teaches us, since he is the Word, but the Holy Spirit makes us capable of being taught by him. " 45 We become sharers in the divine wisdom: we begin, however incompletely and feebly, to order all things in the way the highest and uncaused cause does, namely, the one whom Jesus calls Father, who orders all things around the Word whom he has sent into the flesh, and whom this Word alone enables us to know because, in Thomas's phrase, he "expresses the total being of the Father." 46 And we are able to be wise in this way because the Spirit gives us the gift of wisdom-inducts us into God's own wisdom-by giving us a share in the incarnate Word's total correspondence to the reality of the Father-in that unique relation to the Father on account of which Jesus Christ is "wisdom itself' and "truth itself. " 47 For Thomas, then, it seems that if "the salvation accomplished by the cross of Christ" is the "chief matter" of the Christian faith, it must turn out epistemically to be the chief matter across the board. II. LUTHER ON NATURAL REASON, FAITH, AND EPISTEMIC PRIORITIES Reading Aquinas this way greatly increases, at least at first glance, the likelihood that he and Luther basically agree on how to decide what is true. Much modern interpretation of both figures has, of course, made agreement between them seem unlikely, especially on this matter. For a great many post-Enlightenment Protestant interpreters of Aquinas (including particularly some of the leading figures in Protestant theology and Dogmengeschichte since the nineteenth century), the intellectual labor of medieval Scholasticism in which 45 46 In Joan. c. 14, lect. 6 (no. 1958). In Joan. c. 1, lect. 1 (no. 29). 47 That is, the Son's perfect correspondence to the Father is the reason why "wisdom" and "truth" are appropriated to the Son; cf. De Verit. q. 1, a. 7; STh I, q. 39, a. 8; In Joan. c. 18, lect. 6 (no. 2365). Thomas, however, has no trouble dropping the languageof appropriation: "Truth belongs to Christ through himself because he is the Word ... the Word of God is truth itself" (In Joan. c. 14, lect. 2 [no. 1869]; cf. also the text cited in n. 45). On appropriation see Trinity and Truth, ch. 9. 22 BRUCE D. MARSHALL he was (they assumed) the dominant force brought forth, in the phrase of the seventeenth-century Lutheran dogmatician Abraham Calov, an enormous "mixo-philosophico-theologica." This grotesque and sterile hybrid was both bad theology and bad philosophy. As these interpreters saw (and in some cases still see) it, Aquinas and others tried to build the chief matters of Christian faith onto a foundation already laid by philosophy. Naturally only that can be added onto a foundation which the foundation will support, so Aquinas on this view both trimmed the teachings of Christian faith to fit the requirements of reason (which is bad theology) and refused to let reason go digging about wherever it saw fit in pursuit of truth, demanding instead that it stick to constructing a foundation for a suitably trimmed Christianity (which is bad philosophy). These interpreters attribute to Aquinas, one can say, a view of the epistemic status of Christian belief roughly like Locke's: some Christian beliefs are above reason; this does not necessarily mean they are false, but they can only be true if they are not against reason, that is, not contrary to what any suitably diligent human being, regardless of his historical and communal location, can find out.48 With his battle cry "crux probat omnia," so these interpreters often suppose, Luther hit on the chief axiom of a genuinely theological epistemology and in so doing overthrew the dubious medieval "mixo. " 49 48 Cf. John Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1985), 4.18-19, especially 18, §§ 2, 10; 19, § 14. 49 For a recent reading of the medievals along these lines, and of Luther as solving medieval problems, see Ingolf U. Dalferth, Theology and Philosophy (Oxford: Blackwell, 1988), 71-88. On "crux probat omnia" cf. Gerhard Hammer and Manfred Biersack, eds., Archiv zur WeimarerAusgabeder Werke Martin Luthers, vol. 2 (Cologne and Vienna: Bohlau Verlag, 1981), 325.1 (Operationes in Psalmos, 1519-21). As Luther uses it (cf. also 301.14-17) this is not a general theological axiom, epistemological or otherwise. What the cross (more exactly, the cruciform suffering of believers) tests or proves is specifically the believer's own existence in gratia: "If the joy and praise of God continue eternal and fixed even in suffering, this cannot be a fallible sign [whether we are (as they say) 'in grace']" (324.17-20). Similarly Luther's famous remark, "CRUX sola est nostra Theologia" (319.3), functions for him not as a general dictum, but specifically as the proper basis for the mystical ascent "into the darkness ... above being and non-being": "I truly do not know whether [the mystical theologians] understand themselves when they attribute that [ascent] to elicited acts and do not rather believe that the sufferings of the cross, death, and hell are signified. THE CROSS alone is our theology" (318.20-319.3; cf. D. Martin Luthers Werke Kritische FAITH AND REASON RECONSIDERED 23 Modern defenders of Thomas on truth and justification have rightly objected to this crude reading of him, but they too have generally taken the deliverances of reason-which is to say, in practice, Thomas's refinement and elaboration of Aristotle's philosophy, including a large dollop of natural theology-to be epistemically central for him. As these interpreters read Aquinas, Scripture and creed are of course to be believed on the authority of the revealing God, but they have little or no epistemic role; their interaction with the beliefs which are epistemically central is kept (deliberately, it seems) to a minimum. Indeed, the possibility of regarding the scriptural and creedal description of "the salvation accomplished by the cross of Christ" as epistemically central in Thomas seems never to arise. One gets the impression from these interpreters that this would be a bizarre excess unsuited to serious reflection on these matters.so If correct, the reading of Aquinas I have outlined in this article obviates the main assumptions of both sides about Thomas's views, and to that extent suggests the possibility of closing the presumed distance between him and Luther. Whether this can actually be done, however, depends on what Luther's own views are. A) Epistemic Priorities In his sermons of 1532-33 on 1 Corinthians 15, Luther proposes that the resurrection of Jesus is the "chief article" (heubtstuck) of Christian doctrine.st Jesus' resurrection can only be preached and believed, however, if we take it as the decisive criterion for making judgments about the nature and destiny of Gesamtausgabe [Weimar: Herman Bohlaus Nachfolger, 1883££.], hereafter WA, 40/1:204.23-27). Note that Luther here seems to accept the ascent super ens et non ens; what he rejects is any way of ascent that bypasses the cross. 5 For a classic interpretation of Aquinas along these lines, see Etienne Gilson, The ChristianPhilosophyof St. Thomas Aquinas, trans. L. K. Shook (New York: Random House, 1956). 51 Paul "stakes everything on the ground from which he has set out: that Christ is risen from the dead, which is the chief article of Christian doctrine. No one can deny it who wants to be a Christian or a preacher of the gospel" (WA 36:524.31-34). ° BRUCE D. MARSHALL 24 the embodied beings we are-and this requires blocking inferences which would otherwise seem quite reasonable. Against everything reason proposes, or against the way reason wants to measure things and find out about them, indeed against what all the senses feel and grasp, we must learn to cleave to the word and to judge entirely according to it-even though we no doubt see before our eyes that a human being is buried in the earth, furthermore, that he or she must decay and become food for worms and finally crumble to dust. 52 There seem to be two complementary claims here about the epistemic priorities compatible with holding it true that Jesus is risen from the dead. First, our ordinary, empirically obvious beliefs about ourselves and our bodies, while surely pertinent and no doubt true as far as they go, cannot be employed as criteria by which to "judge" or "measure" the truth of those interpreted sentences which identify and describe Jesus' resurrection, nor those which promise our own resurrection in him. Luther attacks reason in many different contexts and to many different ends; here the crucial point seems not to be that beliefs which most people (Christians and non-Christians alike) regard as reasonable or obvious are false. Believing that we die and rot in the ground is not by itself the problem; evidently we do. 53 The problem arises when from these manifestly true beliefs we draw conclusions about the ultimate destiny of human beings, and so deny the resurrection of the body in general, and Jesus' resurrection in particular. Drawing inferences from these otherwise unobjectionable beliefs to conclusions about the resurrection attributes to these beliefs an epistemic centrality which must be denied to them-or, more precisely, which can be attributed to them only at the cost of "destroying and losing the gospel entirely." 54 52 WA 36:494.13-17. 53 It seems right to group these under "what nature teaches everyone and what all human reason and understanding has to allown (WA 36:526.35-36). 54 So Luther paraphrases Paul on the contrast between his own gospel and that of the Corinthian enthusiasts: "For I did not preach it, as they claim and say, in a human way, according to reason and our understanding. For to preach in such a worldly form, or to judge according to such a form, destroys and loses the gospel entirelyn (WA 36:492.23-26). Luther FAITH AND REASON RECONSIDERED 25 This reversal of epistemic priorities Luther calls "rhyming" or "harmonizing" (reimen) the gospel with reason, and it can, he observes, have two different results: either the truth value of the gospel or its interpretation will have to change. That is: because reason "sees that [the gospel] is entirely against its understanding and all sense and feeling, and against experience as well, it rejects and denies [the gospel]"; or, "when it cannot get away from God's word"-that is, supposing the interpreter wants to hold the gospel true- "it twists and trims it with glosses, so that the word must harmonize with its understanding. Then faith no longer has any room but must give way to reason and perish. " 55 One of these equally unhappy outcomes ensues when any aspect of the gospel ends up in an epistemically subordinate position; what Luther says about Jesus' resurrection recurs in his discussions of (for example) the eternal and consubstantial divinity of the Logos, and the suffering and death of God on the cross.56 Luther's second claim is the positive complement of this. People who do not already believe in the resurrection of the body, he concedes, will likely find Paul's argument for it in 1 Corinthians 15 entirely unconvincing. As Luther reads him, Paul explicitly characterizes this judging "according to reason" (and its opposite, faith in the gospel) as a matter not simply of the beliefs one holds true, but of the patterns of inference one follows: "For human wisdom and reason cannot go any higher or further than to judge and draw conclusions [scbliessen]as its eyes see and it feels, or than it grasps with its senses. But faith has to draw conclusions beyond and against such feeling and understanding, and cleave to what is presented to it by the word" (WA 36:493.4-7). ss WA 36:494.7-12. Similarly: "This article does not agree [rei1net] with [reason] at all. Indeed many foolish things have to follow if people try to judge concerning this article according to their own understanding and darkness. They must either take this article for a lie, or interpret it with great cleverness, so that it somehow harmonizes [reimeJ with their understanding" (632.13-16; cf. also 661.28-31). s6 Thus on John 1:1: "Many heretics of all kinds have attacked this article and wanted to measure, grasp, and master it by reason, but they have all gone to ground. The Holy Spirit has preserved this article against all of them, so that God's word still stands fast against all the gates of hell" (WA 46:545.23-26; cf. 551.7-9; "this article" ="the high article of our holy Christian faith, which we believe and confess: that there is a single true, almighty, and eternal God, and nonetheless that in the same single divine essence there are three distinct persons: God the Father, God the Son, and God the Holy Spirit," and with that the article "concerning the eternal divinity of Christ"; 541.5-8; 542.29). Faced with this set of beliefs, "Reason draws another conclusion, and says: if the Word is with God, are there then two Gods?" (549.21-22). On the cross, cf. WA26:321.19-28; 39/2:279.26-280.3; also the text cited below, n. 90. 26 BRUCE D. MARSHALL there infers the bodily resurrection of believers to life with Christ in God from the premise that Christ is risen. Those who want to "rhyme" the proclamation of the gospel with reason by deciding about the resurrection on the basis of what is otherwise obvious will naturally find this procedure at best a petere principium.57 But the point, as Luther sees it, is precisely that the gospel of Jesus' resurrection, together with the other articles of faith (including a nest of beliefs about the truthfulness of God, the reliability of the apostolic witness, and God's preservation of the Church in the truth), is the principium from which the Christian community draws inferences about human nature and destiny, and by decisive appeal to which this community and its members assess the truth of what they otherwise believe and infer. 58 As principia, the resurrection of Jesus and the rest of the articles of faith are criteria by which the truth of other beliefs may be assessed, but whose truth may not be assessed by those beliefs; they are, more particularly, premises from which other beliefs may be inferred, but may not themselves be inferred as conclusions from any other beliefs-or regarded as false because no such inference may be made (in this, of course, Luther follows the broad pattern of Aristotle's PosteriorAnalytics, which he would presumably have learned from his Erfurt teachers Trutfetter and Arnoldi). For Luther this side of the issue becomes particularly pressing not (as with Thomas) when the Christian community is 57 "To the heathen and unbelievers it appears to be a weak dialectic or proof, since they deny not only the article he attempts to prove, but everything which he introduces in order to prove it. This is called 'probare negatum per negatum' und 'petere principium'" (WA 36:525.16-19). 58 "These are our principles, our grounds and chief article, on which the whole of Christian teaching stands" (WA36:527.17-18). "Thus St. Paul contended for this article [the general resurrection] on the basis of the correct and strictest principles, so that whoever wants to deny the resurrection of the dead must also deny that Christ is raised" (529.28-30). Cf. 527.12-13, 34-36. This is not, it should be noted, contrary to Aquinas's denial of an inferential relationship between the articles of faith and the rest of the epistemic field; Aquinas does not deny the possibility of such inferences in certain cases (in the articles referred to above, n. 43, he insists upon it), but denies that those subordinate principia coherence with which defines various sciences (regions, one could say) within the total field can be deduced from the articles. Luther agrees with this, indeed has a strong version of it (cf. below, n. 76). For Aquinas what can be deduced from or otherwise warranted by the articles constitutes theology or sacra doctrina as a special science, which differs from the others, however, in being able to judge them all. FAlTH AND REASON RECONSIDERED 27 confronted by a powerful belief system originating from without, but in the intra-Christian conflict between the Churches of the Augsburg Confession and Rome, the outcome of which looked to Luther's eyes increasingly distressing in the late 1530s. Judging by the evidence of the senses, Rome has everything on its side: numbers, prestige, political and military power, even, Luther is willing to concede for the sake of argument, miracles. But the Christian community judges not primarily by the evidence of the senses but by the gospel of Christ; consistency with the gospel is the chief test of truth, and by this standard the Lutherans can be confident that they will carry the day. In this connection Luther argues as follows, preaching in 1534 on John 16:13 ("[The Holy Spirit] will declare to you the things that are to come"). The Holy Spirit himself must be there with his revelation in order that one may hold to the word of Christ and his wisdom, and judge in accordance with it concerning all teachings and signs, life and work. What goes against this chief doctrine and article of Christ [viz., the gospel] ... one should neither value nor accept, even if it snows miracles every day. For what is against this doctrine is certainly false, and concocted by the devil for the seduction of souls. 59 On Luther's account believing the proclamation that Jesus is risen and we too shall rise in him is not simply a matter of holding true a range of sentences, but a way of configuring a wide field of belief-of deciding where truth and falsity lie within the field. It cannot be otherwise: unless the proclamation of the resurrection orders a wider epistemic field, it will either be rejected or interpreted in a sense contrary to that which it has when it is epistemically central. Configuring a wide field of belief in this fashion involves an ongoing struggle to reconfigure the field we otherwise inhabit, since at minimum we have (1) to block a whole range of inferences from the obvious, inferences upon which our "carnal" (i.e., fallen) reason seizes in its self-destructive 59 WA 46:65.13-20; cf. also WA 45:570.19-32. On the gospel's identification of Jesus Christ as the chief test or criterion for resolving the dispute about what is true within the Church, cf. WA 45 :573.34-36: "Everything rests on this man Christ alone, for he is the test of which is the right Spirit or the Spirit of truth"; cf. also 576.28-34. For the dating of Luther's sermons on John 14-16, first published in 1538 (chaps. 14-15) and 1539 (chap. 16), cf. WA 59:255-60. 28 BRUCE D. MARSHALL defiance of God, and also (2) to make a whole range of inferences from beliefs which, in this life, can never be obvious for us. 60 Only the Holy Spirit is up to the epistemic effort involved. 61 In all this Luther seems in vigorous agreement with Thomas's first rule about teaching and preaching the Christian faith: keep your epistemic priorities straight. B) The Package of Articles Before we look at the way Luther handles Thomas's second rule, we should pause briefly to observe that a long tradition of Luther interpretation (of which Albrecht Ritschl and Wilhelm Herrmann may be regarded as the progenitors) has maintained that "faith" for Luther is at bottom not a matter of holding sentences true at all, and thus not a matter of having "beliefs" in the sense in which I am using the term. Guided by neo-Kantian philosophical assumptions, these interpreters variously contend that for Luther faith is an interior trust in Christ (Vertrauen auf Christus, or auf Gott in Christo) which can of course be expressed by, but is not dependent upon, any Fur-wahr-halten-upon having any particular beliefs about God or Christ. 62 As many of the passages we have already cited indicate, however, Luther himself seems to have no trouble supposing that faith involves holding sentences true under particular interpretations-that is, having beliefs. The interpreted sentences which faith holds true are what Luther calls Christian "articles" or "teachings"; these seem straightforwardly to be the contents of 60 On "carnal reason," see De Servo Arbitrio: "These are the arguments of human reason, which is accustomed to this sort of wisdom ... [at present] we dispute with human reason concerning an inference, for it interprets the Scriptures of God by its inferences and syllogisms, and turns them in whatever direction it wishes" r:tfA 18:673.6-10). On the equivalence of "human reason" and "carnal reason" here, cf. 676.38. 61 "Thus it was and still is with true Christians: they see and experience that this truth-that is, the faith which should hold fast to the article concerning Christ and his kingdom-cannot be held by human reason or power, but rather the Holy Spirit himself must do it" r:t!A 46:55.26-30). 62 Regarding the influence of neo-Kantian philosophical assumptions on modern Protestant Luther interpretation, see Risto Saarinen, Gottes Wirken au( Uns: Die transzendentale Deutung des Gegenwart-Christi-Motivs in der Lutherforschung (Mainz: Verlag Philipp von Zabern, 1989). FAITH AND REASON RECONSIDERED 29 propositional attitudes like "to believe" and "to hold [true]," as evinced by Luther's repeated placement of them as the objects of "that" (quad or da{5) clauses which express such attitudes. And Luther seems to make no significant distinction between having saving faith in the gospel and "holding firmly" to these articles-that is, to these sentences. So, for example, in an extended Christological commentary on Psalm 2:7, Luther argues that "you are my son; today I have . begotten you" ought to be taken to assert the following article of faith: "This person born of the Virgin Mary is at once [simul] a true human being and true God. "63 He admonishes his readers to follow "with simple faith" this "Verbum"-that is, sentencetaught to us by Christ himself. In other words: "Let us believe that this article is shown and handed on to us by God, rather than being discovered by us, and let us not judge [aestimemus] such things on the basis of our own mendacity." Indeed, in this Psalm "you have ... now shown to you the chief articles of our faith," in particular what sort of king Christ is: one begotten of the Father in eternity, and set up by the Father as king on Mount Zion in time. Christ teaches us this article-"that he is the eternal Son of God"-precisely in order that we may trust him alone for salvation: "so that he might arouse us to embrace him and to trust his merits and works." Holding true this article (that is, sentence) seems, moreover, to be a necessary condition for saving fiducia in Christ. "To the person who believes these [chief articles] the King will soon magnify himself by his words and deeds; you will not neglect his word or hold it in contempt, for you know that he is the Son of God." Christ's facta are nothing less than to liberate us from death, sin, and the tyranny of Satan. But "all these things happen, when you firmly hold [retinent] this article, that Christ is the eternal Son of God." Those (like "Turks" and "Papists," as Luther puts it) who "do not firmly hold" this article regarding the eternal generation of the Son thereby lack saving faith. They know of Christ's birth to Mary and his suffering under Pontius Pilate, but "all these things are for them mere history, and they do not arouse to faith." This notion of being "aroused to faith," such 63 WA 40/2:258.30-31. I am grateful to David Yeago for pointing out this passage to me. 30 BRUCE D. MARSHALL that the gospel becomes the message of salvation for me and not "mere history," may seem tailor-made to support the view that faith for Luther is at root a prelinguistic Vertrauen auf Christus. But Luther is quite dear that the difference between these two opposing "takes" on the gospel depends on the sentences one holds true; the believer is "aroused to faith" (that is, trust) in Christ just because he has a different propositional attitude from the Turk-just because he "firmly holds [true]" what the Turk denies: "The whole gospel becomes mere history if this primary belief about the eternal birth of Christ is lost [amissa hac capitali sententia de aeterna nativitate Christi]. For with this belief everything else is given. " 64 Luther also seems to have no trouble seeing "the heart" as the seat of both trust in Christ and having true beliefs about Christ. Indeed, these two aspects of faith are not only alike indispensable to it, but are very closely bound up with one another, as Luther suggests in remarks directly pertinent to our present concern: Faith is nothing other than the truth of the heart, that is the right knowledge [cogitationeml of the heart about God. Faith alone, and not reason, is able to think rightly about God. A person thinks rightly about God when he believes God's word. However, when he wants to measure and to believe God by his own reason, apart from the word, he does not have the truth about God, and therefore neither thinks nor judges rightly about him .... Therefore the truth is that very faith which judges rightly about God. 65 64 All quotations from WA 40/2:258.23-259.30. I have been citing the printed version of 1546; that "believing the gospel" and "firmly holding the articles" are more or less interchangeable is particularly clear from Rorer's handwritten notes of Luther's lectures, which were given in 1532. "The gospel is therefore a new teaching beyond the law of Moses, which the Son preaches at the command of the Father, namely [the teaching] that he is the true King on Mount Zion and the true Son of God. Given this article, you have the gospel [Isto posito articulo habes Euangelium]. Later he will glorify himself through his words and deeds; now you must believe that this true human being and the Son are one person. When this article is lost nothing remains of piety" (258.10--259.1). When this version goes on to say, "Christ's words and deeds become [mere] history if the gospel principle fprincipium Euangelit]is lost" (259.3-4), the "principium Euangelii" clearly refers, once again, not to an interior Vertrauen, but back to "isto posito articulo." 65 WA40/1:376.23-377.14; cf. 377.3-4: "If I believe, I have that true thought which is nothing other than faith. I can neither grasp [this thought] nor prove it by reason, but I can hear it preached." FAITH AND REASON RECONSIDERED 31 Thus it seems that for Luther faith, while it certainly involves more than holding sentences true, cannot involve less; unless we hold true particular sentences which identify and describe God in Christ, we cannot have faith, and unless those sentences are true, our faith is false-it fails "to think" and "to judge" correctly about God. Luther also agrees with Thomas's second rule, that the articles of faith come only as a package. "If you deny God in one article you have denied him in all, because God is not divided into many articles, but all of him is in each article and he is one in all the articles." 66 Luther's reasoning here seems quite close to Thomas's. We know God only by holding true a range of interconnected propositions and associated beliefs, but there is no multiplicity in God corresponding to the multiplicity of our beliefs. The articles of faith (or, we could equally well say, the constitutive features of the gospel) "all hang on one another" in what Luther takes to be a logically tight way, so that believing any one requires believing the others, and rejecting any one involves rejecting the rest. 67 Denying any one of the articles lands the denier in unbelief about all of them not only by implication, but, as it were, by definition, since one can reject an article of faith only by holding the 66 WA 40/2:48.22-24 (or as the handwritten version has it, God is "whole [totus] in every article" [48.7]). Cf. WA 28:199.21-28 (on John 17:26): "To know the Father is not only to know that he made heaven and earth, and how he helps the pious and punishes the wicked, but to know that he has sent the Son into the world and given him to us in order to take away sin and death, and to win for us and give us the Father's favor and grace. That is the right name of God; it shows us what is in his mind and opens up for us his fatherly heart, will, thought, and blessing. Whoever does not know him in this way does not know him rightly, and does not know he should serve or praise him." 67 With stress on the positive (to believe one article involves believing the rest): "Because every Christian must believe and confess that Christ is risen,he is immediately driven to grant that the resurrection of the dead must also be true-<>r else he has to deny in a heap the whole gospel and everything which is preached about Christ and God. For it all hangs together like a chain, such that where one article stands, they all stand. Thus [Paul] draws everything together, and always infers one thing from another" (WA 36:524.37-525.15). With more stress on the negative (to deny one article involves denying the rest): "Thus you see that everything hangs on our certainty about this single article [the general resurrection, in this case]. For where this article wavers or is no longer valid [nicht mehr gilt], all the others have no use or validity, because everything-Christ's coming and setting up his kingdom in the world-has occurred for the sake of the resurrection and the future life. Where this, the basis, cause, and aim of all the articles of faith, is overturned or taken away, all the others must fall away with it" (605.16-22). 32 BRUCE D. MARSHALL truthfulness of God in contempt, and this roughly defines unbelief; the person who declines to believe in the coming general resurrection, for example, rejects the trustworthiness of the God who makes this promise and thereby rejects all the other promises as well. 68 Luther's notion of the mutual inherence of the articles of faith also helps explain how he can combine insistence upon upholding the "chief article" of Christian faith with relative insouciance about what the chief article is. He variously names not only (as is well known) justification by faith, but also the Trinity, the incarnation, the distinction between law and gospel, and (as we have seen) the resurrection; since each can be understood properly and held true as so understood only in intimate connection with the others, we need not, and perhaps should not, settle which is "chief." 69 Luther is content to suggest that three complexes of belief together have primacy: Trinity, incarnation, and justification. 70 If what Thomas means by "the salvation accomplished by the cross of Christ" is at least compatible with what Luther means when he talks of "justification by faith" (and 68 In 1 Corinthians 15 Paul "thus wants to say that whoever wants to deny this article [here, Christ's resurrection and ours in him] has to deny much more. First, that you [Corinthians] believe correctly, second, that the word which you believe was correct, third, that we apostles preach correctly and are God's apostles, fourth, that God is truthful-in sum, that God is God" (WA 36:526.23-27). In Thomas's terms, someone in this epistemic situation declines not simply one article of faith, but the formal object by which faith is defined, namely God as self-revealing first truth (he does not "believe God" [credereDeo]), and so does not have faith even with regard to those creedal sentences to which he assents (d. STh II-II, q. 1, a. 1; q. 5, a. 3). 69 John's Gospel presents the Trinity as "the high article of our holy Christian faith"; therefore this article "is the highest art of Christians, who alone know and believe it" (WA 46:541.5; 550.26-27). At the same time: "This is our chief article ... and our right, true, and Christian faith, beside which there is no other, that Christ is true God and true man" (599.38-40; cf. also 601.4-12). But also: "The highest art and wisdom of Christians is not to know the law and to be ignorant of works and all active righteousness" (WA 40/1:43.25-26); "It is supremely necessary to know this matter [locus] of the distinction between law and gospel, because it contains the sum of all Christian teaching" (209.16-17). 7 Cf. the Vorrede to Luther's sermons on John 14-16: "Here [in John 14-16] the right, chief, and high articles of Christian teaching are grounded and presented in the most compelling way. Nowhere else in Scripture are they found so dose together: the article about the three distinct persons of the holy Trinity, and especially the article about the divine and human nature of the eternal and undivided person of the Lord Christ, and likewise about the righteousness of faith and the right consolation of the conscience" (WA 45:467.29-35). ° FAITH AND REASON RECONSIDERED 33 it has, as I suggested at the outset, been well demonstrated that they are more than merely compatible), then it seems that he and Luther not only agree that those beliefs which are central to the Christian community ought to be epistemically primary, they agree on what these beliefs are. C) Unrestricted Primacy The step from endorsing the two rules we have first found in Thomas to ascribing unrestricted epistemic primacy to the gospel and the articles of faith is not a long one, and Luther takes it boldly: "In God, a person who has grasped one thing has grasped all things, and a person who does not grasp God never grasps any part of the creation. "71 Believing the gospel, it seems, involves configuring (that is, interpreting and assessing) not only the local neighborhood of belief-what we hold true about God-but also all our beliefs about creatures in accordance with it. And that is the whole field; there is nothing about which to have beliefs besides God and creatures. As Luther's remarks about not accepting anything that "goes against" the gospel of Christ already suggest, the range over which the gospel and the articles of faith extend in deciding what is true-negatively, by excluding what is inconsistent-has no boundaries. Again like Thomas, Luther can also put the point in terms of higher and lower (or, one could say, more and less central) criteria of truth, with appeal to the same scriptural text Thomas favors when this issue comes up: "When it comes to the works and words of God one should take captive reason and all wisdom, as St. Paul teaches in 2 Corinthians 10, and allow them to be blinded and guided, led, instructed, and mastered, in order that we do not become judges of God in his words. "72 Ill. LUTHER ON RESOLVING EPISTEMIC CONFLICT Were this the only line of thought in Luther about deciding what is true, we could stop at this point and declare him-nolens 71 72 WA 18:605.12-14. WA 26:439.31-35. 34 BRUCE D. MARSHALL volens, to be sure-in virtually complete agreement with Aquinas on the matter. But Luther often seems to think quite differently about these issues. In an academic disputation in January 1539, for example, Luther responded to the objections of his Wittenberg colleagues and students to a series of forty-two theses he had proposed on the question, "Whether this proposition is true in philosophy: 'Et Verbum caro factum est."' 73 The text of this disputation is corrupt in places to the point of being indecipherable, but Luther's answer is unmistakable: no. 74 "In theology it is true that the Word became flesh, but in philosophy this is entirely impossible and absurd," as he puts the point in his second thesis. 75 If Luther took "Ver bum caro factum est" to be not only true but epistemically primary across the board, as my analysis to this point suggests, and if, as here, he takes "philosophy" to be committed to rejecting this belief completely, one would expect him to bite the bullet and say that "philosophy" is just false: however strongly held or well-grounded our philosophical beliefs (whatever these turn out more precisely to be), since they "go against" one of the chief articles of faith, we will have to do without them. Interestingly, he declines to do this. He argues instead that theology and philosophy, like the bishop and the prince, each ought to keep to its own territory and not try to decide about truth outside its area of competence. "For as God has created distinct spheres in the heavens, so also he has WA 39/2:1-33; here: 6.2-3. For an analysis of this text and its companion piece, the Disputatio de divinitate et humanitate Christi, including helpful suggestions for more intelligible readings of some passages, see Reinhard Schwarz, "Gott ist Mensch: Zur Lehre von der Person Christi bei den Ockhamisten und bei Luther," Zeitschrift {Ur Theologie und Kirche 63 (1966): 289-351. An alternative interpretation of both disputations, sharply critical of Schwarz's reading of both Luther and the Ockhamists (especially Biel)-and much better informed about the logical issues involved-may be found in Graham White, Luther as Nominalist (Helsinki: Luther-Agricola-Society, 1994). Cf. also Reijo Tyorinoja, "Proprietas Verbi: Luther's Conception of Philosophical and Theological Language in the Disputation: Verbum caro factum est Ooh. 1:14), 1539," in Faith, Will, and Grammar: Some Themes of Intensional Logic and Semantics in Medieval and Reformation Thought, ed. Heikki Kirjavainen (Helsinki: Luther-Agricola Society, 1986), 141-78; and Stefan Streiff, Novis Linguis Loqui: Martin LuthersDisputationuber Joh 1,14 "Verbum CaroFactumEst" ausdem]ahr 1539 (GOttingen: Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht, 1993). 75 WA 39/2:3.3-4; cf. 12.5-7; 16.12-13. 73 74 FAITH AND REASON RECONSIDERED 35 created distinct kingdoms on earth, so that every matter and art may keep to its own place and kind and not be engaged outside its own center, in which it has been placed." 76 This is not to say that theology contradicts philosophy, exactly; rather, theology is "outside and inside, above and below, on the near side and on the far side, of every philosophical truth." 77 The point seems to be that theology and philosophy each has its own legitimate sphere of judgment; one does not eliminate (and in that sense contradict) the other. But the relation between the two spheres is not a harmonious one; what theology finds most vital to hold true philosophy is compelled to hold false. Insisting as Luther does that philosophy has no business passing judgment on theological matters (or theology on philosophical ones, as the distinction of legitimate spheres also suggests) may enforce an armed truce between the two, but seems not to eliminate their logical conflict. 78 Luther himself appears to realize this, and other binary oppositions which feature prominently in parts of his theologyespecially those between law and gospel and between God hidden and revealed-sometimes seem to be used in ways which reinforce the conflict. Far from proposing a coherent Christian "system of the world" defined by the epistemic primacy of the gospel and the articles of faith across the whole range of possible belief (however incomplete and only partially coherent such a "system" will inevitably be in practice), Luther when he thinks in this vein seems convinced that we neither need nor can have a system of the world. Our most basic beliefs and epistemic commitments are locked in a conflict we cannot resolve. God will clear the matter up at the Last Judgment, and in the meantime our job is to bring even demonic--efforts to usurp down pretentious-perhaps God's prerogatives by resolving the conflict prematurely. On this 76 WA 39/2:8.5-8. n WA 39/2:4.34-35; cf. 4.33. "Theology is not contradictory to philosophy" (14.8-9). 78 "The chief issue at stake in this disputation is that God is not subject to reason and to syllogisms, but to the word of God and to faith" (WA 39/2:8.4-5). "The syllogism is not allowed [admittitur] into the mysteries of faith and theology. Philosophy is error in theology" (12.29-30). "I grant that the legal wisdom of God is not against the wisdom of the gospel-but neither is it included in the wisdom of the gospel. Theology, the incarnation, and justification are above and outside reason and philosophy" (13.27-14.26). 36 BRUCE D. MARSHALL view the gospel and the articles of faith do not have unrestricted epistemic primacy, not because other beliefs have primacy over them, but because no beliefs, not even these, have unrestricted epistemic application. Whether Luther in fact holds such a robustly paradoxical view of how to decide what is true depends at least in part on what he thinks "philosophy" is, and why he supposes philosophy will find itself compelled to reject "Verbum caro factum est." Later Protestant theologians (not least some Lutherans) have regularly assumed that when Luther talks like this he is proposing a universal dialectical conflict between theology and philosophy, which they have taken as precedent and warrant for their own love-hate relationships with philosophy. It turns out, however, that he is objecting to something quite specific. The "Parisian theologians" are the target, and more broadly the nominalist tradition stemming from Ockham, which Luther knew best in the version developed by Biel; the problem lies in the use to which they put their formal logic and philosophical grammar. For the logic and grammar themselves Luther had high respect ("My master Ockham was the greatest dialectician"). 79 But when they try to harmonize theology with philosophy-"to hold the same thing true in theology as in philosophy and vice versa"-and when they do so, more precisely, by "measuring everything theological according to their own philosophical reason," they end up holding theologically decisive sentences like "Verbum caro factum est," "Deus est homo," and "Homo est Deus" false.80 7"WATr 2:516.16-17 (no. 2544a); "I am of the Ockhamist faction" (WA 6:600.11). Cf. Peter Manns, "Zurn Gesprach zwischen M. Luther und der katholischen Theologie: Begegnung zwischen patristisch-monastischer und reformatorischer Theologie an der Scholastik vorbei," in T. Mannermaa, A. Ghiselli, and S. Peura, eds., Thesaurus Lutheri: Auf der Suche nach neuen Paradigmen der Luther-Forschung (Helsinki: Finnischen Theologischen Literaturgesellschaft, 1987), 63-154 (here: 63-64), and Heiko A. Oberman, Luther: Man between God and the Devil, trans. E. Walliser-Schwarzbart (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1989), 120. 80 "We are disputing against the Parisian Sorbonne. For the Parisian theologians have determined that the same thing is true in theology as in philosophy, and conversely" (WA 39/2:7.8-10). "The Parisian theologians ... want to measure everything theological by their philosophical reason" (7.30-31; regarding the identity of these "Parisians"and their theology, see White, Luther as Nominalist, 367-76). On Ockham and Biel, see WA 39/2: 11.35-37. Like the medievals, Luther thought that "Verbum caro factum est" should be interpreted as FAITH AND REASON RECONSIDERED 37 The "Parisian theologians" would no doubt have been surprised to hear their views put this way, since they dearly assumed, as had theologians east and west for over a millennium, that Scripture plainly teaches these things, and whatever Scripture teaches is true. But in order to hold these sentences true, Luther argues, the nominalists have to give them a forced sense contrary to that which they have when embedded in the scriptural and creedal matrix of belief, so that what Scripture (more precisely, the person who speaks scripturally) teaches when it asserts "Verbum caro factum est" the nominalists in fact hold false, and what the nominalists teach with the same sentence, Scripture holds false. As Luther reads the situation, the misguided use of two assumptions in particular drives the Parisians to this untenable position. One is logical, the other ontological. In nominalist logic--Qr so Luther seems to suppose, at any rate-an identity statement, indeed any affirmative statement, is true only if the terms it joins have the same res significata. It seems obvious enough that in order for a statement like "Hesperus is Phosphorus" to be true, the terms "Hesperus" and "Phosphorus" must refer to the same thing (have the same "supposition," in medieval logical terminology). As Luther reads the nominalists, though, such statements are true only if subject and predicate have not only the same referent, but the same meaning or sense (roughly what the medievals would have thought of as the same "signification"). "Hesperus is Phosphorus" is true, in other words, only if it can be taken to mean "Phosphorus is Phosphorus." 81 implying both "Deus est homo" and "Homo est Deus"; see, e.g., 12.5-10. 81 In a letter to Prince George of Anhalt in late 1541, Luther comments as follows: "Aristotle says in Meta. 6 [MetaphysicsE, 1027b.20-22] (if I have understood him correctly}, 'An affirmative proposition requires composition of the extremes, a negative one division, etc.,' that is, when two words refer to or are supposed to speak of the same thing [ein Ding deuten oder sprechensol/en], they have to be put together, e.g., 'God is a human being.' [fhe Scholastics, including the nominalists] have made of this text the following: subject and predicate stand for the same thing [supponunt pro eodem]'.... Their view is that the two, subject and predicate (that is, the thing signified [res significata]),must be one thing" (W ABr 9:444.37-42). That Luther has the nominalists specifically in mind here is evident from his ensuing discussion of what he took (cf. WA 39/2:95.34-37) to be distinctively nominalist Christological claims. Luther's text is unclear as to whether he accepts the logical principle the nominalists 38 BRUCE D. MARSHALL In nominalist ontology, as Luther reads it, the infinite distance between God and creatures, between uncreated and created being, must be maintained in all contexts. "In the old use of language," according to Luther, '"creature' signifies that which is separated from divinity in an infinite way." 82 The nominalists take this "old use of language" as a rule for thinking about the incarnation, and consequently propose a theology of the hypostatic union that strives to uphold the infinite distance between the divine and the human even while saying, in conformity with Chalcedon, that divine and human natures are one person in Christ. They do this by arguing on the one hand, under pressure from Chalcedon, that human nature in Christ has no independent existence or personal reality of its own; it is sustained, supported, or borne by the divine Logos. On the other hand, under pressure from the assumption of infinite distance, this human nature never becomes the nature of that divine person the way Peter's or Socrates' human nature is his own, or the Logos's divine nature is his own, namely, by sharing fully in the unique independent, personal existence of that subject; rather, the human nature always derive from Aristotle, but rejects its theological application (as White supposes; cf. Luther as Nominalist, 392-96), or whether he attributes to them a logical principle which he himself rejects (as Schwarz supposes; cf. "Gott ist Mensch," 339-43). That Luther explicitly charges the nominalists not only with basing their theology on philosophy, but "on philosophy falsely understood" (WABr 9:444.34; cf. 444.50) suggests the latter; he goes on to mock the Scholastic interpretation of Aristotle's logic, though only after considering a case of its theological application: "If Aristotle were alive and heard such a thing, he would say: 'Who in the devil has made such complete mockery and foolishness out of my book? The blockhead has no idea what I mean by "substance," "subject," or "predicate"'" (444.46-49). In any case Luther's interpretation of the nominalists on identity statements (and affirmative predications more generally) here seems implausible, since it apparently depends on his own equation of supposition and signification ("'Subiectum et predicatum supponunt pro eodem' ... Ist aber die Meinung ... res significata, mussen ein ding sein"), which the norninalists were at pains to distinguish {White questions Luther's reading on other grounds; cf. Luther as Nominalist, 394-95). For our purposes whether Luther got the norninalists right is, of course, less important than the epistemic principles which emerge from his engagement with them. 82 WA 39/2:94.19-20. We will return to Luther's talk of "old" and "new" language a bit later on. FAITH AND REASON RECONSIDERED 39 remains--or so Luther worries-"extrinsic" to the divine subject who sustains it. 83 For Luther the key problem arises not from accepting these assumptions (at least the second he clearly regards as legitimate in many contexts or "spheres"), but from interpreting "Verbum caro factum est" and its cognates so as to harmonize with them. He wants to avoid, in other words, an interpretation of "Verbum caro" (to the truth of which the nominalists are of course fully committed) which will allow these assumptions to apply as tests of truth across the board, and so be epistemically primary. From this equivocation inevitably results, and "all equivocation," Luther warns, "is the mother of errors." 84 As the nominalists interpret "Homo est Deus," for example, the rules for identity statements require that if this sentence is true, "homo" and "Deus" will not only have to refer to the same thing, but mean the same thing. So the identity statement "Homo est Deus," with help from the 83 Nominalist views of the hypostatic union are complex, and an adequate treatment of them, and of the extent to which Luther's criticisms are fair to them, is beyond the scope of this essay. For a more detailed discussion, cf. White, Luther as Nominalist, esp. 231-98. White argues that Luther is in the end much closer to the nominalists than he admits; for the older view which takes their positions to be basically opposed (and which White criticizes extensively), cf. Schwarz, "Gott ist Mensch," 293-303. While it may initially look similar to the view Luther imputes to the nominalists, on closer inspection Thomas's claim that human nature in Christ "does not exist separately, through itself, but in something more perfect, namely in the person of the Word of God" (ST'h III, q. 2, a. 2, ad 3) apparently turns out to be the opposite of the nominalists' position on this point. The nominalists typically argue that Christ's human nature "does not subsist in its own supposit, but is supported [sustentificatur]by the Word, in the manner in which an accident is supported by its subject" (the language is Ockham's, In III Sent. 1 [OperaTheologica6:9-10 (St. Bonaventure, N.Y., 1982)]). Thomas by contrast rejects (indeed considers heretical) any attempt to conceive the hypostatic union (or union "in supposit" [ST'h III, q. 2, a. 3]) along the lines of the unity of accident to substance (cf. ST'h III, q. 2, a. 6; q. 17, a. 2), while granting that certain scriptural passages, not least Philippians 2:7, require that this question be handled carefully (cf. In Phil. c. 2, lect. 2 [nos. 61-62]; In Gal. c. 4, lect. 2 [no. 204]). In the incarnation a human nature comes to be by fully acquiring the one divine act of existence (esse) of the Logos: "it comes to share that complete act of existence" (SI'h III, q. 2, a. 6, ad 2; cf. q. 17, a. 2, ad 2; I Sent. d. 16, a. 3, ad 4: "The visible nature in which the Son appears has been taken into the one act of existence in the person of the Son of God"). Thus for Thomas the assumption of a human nature by the Logos cannot leave that human nature "extrinsic" to the divine subject who sustains it, as Luther criticizes the nominalists for supposing; instead the Logos sustains his human nature precisely by making it fully intrinsic to his own act of existence. 84 WA 39/2:28.28; cf. 28.10; 17.2-3, 31-36. 40 BRUCE D. MARSHALL nominalist theology of the hypostatic union, must be taken to mean something like "the Son of God, who sustains human nature, is God. " 85 In order to hold "Homo est Deus" true, in other words, the nominalists find themselves compelled to offer "Deus est Deus" as its proper interpretation. This saves the truth value of the troublesome sentence at the cost of taking "homo" to mean "Deus"; by the nominalists' own standards (the "infinite distance" assumption), it would be hard to conceive a more radical equivocation. 86 Whether Luther's interpretation does justice to the nominalists we need not decide for our purposes. We can now see more clearly, though, what Luther means when he denies that "the same thing" can be true in both philosophy and theology: "philosophy" -that is, nominalist logic and ontology-inevitably ends up giving equivocal interpretations to sentences like "Verbum caro factum est," and so even when it holds these sentences true does not in fact assert the same thing as theology (that is, Scripture) does. The "philosophical" interpretation is equivocal precisely with respect to the theological one, which always tries to take the words of theologically decisive sentences in the same sense they have in the other sentences in which they are used (and to which we have assigned a truth value). So with regard to the case in point: The philosopher does not say that God is a human being or that a human being is God and the Son of God. But we do say that a human being is God, and we prove [or: "assert" = testamur] this by the word of God, without a syllogism and without philosophy, since philosophy is nothing in our grammar .... It is true to say that God has become a human being, just as you and I are. 87 85 "So they say, as though this were much better, 'Homo est Deus,' that is, 'The Son of God, who sustains a human nature, is God,' because it is necessary that the subject and the predicate stand for the same thing" (WABr 9:444.55-57). 86 As White puts the point: "Thus, the error is ... to argue from identity of reference to identity of sense" (Luther as Nominalist, 394). 87 WA 39/2: 12.5-10. In the same vein, on John 1: 14: "The loftiest treasure and the highest consolation of Christians is that the Word, the true, natural Son of God, has become a human being, who certainly has flesh and blood like any other human being. He has become a human being for our sake, so that we might attain the great glory of having our flesh and blood, hide and hair, hands and feet, belly and backside reside in heaven like God" (WA 46:631.26-32; cf. 625.1-10; 626.25-28). FAITH AND REASON RECONSIDERED 41 Equivocation between the interpretation of these scripturally and creedally mandated sentences and the rest of the sentences whose truth value we know (which is almost all of them) is, so far as possible, to be avoided. "Est homo" should be taken to mean the same thing when we say "Deus est homo" as it does when we say "Petrus est homo. " 88 Luther generalizes the point in his argument with the Swiss Reformers over the interpretation of another difficult but theologically crucial identity statement: "This is my body." The burden of proof always falls on taking words in any one sentence differently from the way we take them in the other sentences in which we use them. "In Scripture one should take words just as they go, according to their natural force, and give no other interpretation unless a dear article of faith requires it." About this, it seems to me, Luther shows not inconsiderable linguistic-philosophical sophistication: "Otherwise one would no longer have any definite text, interpretation, speech, or language. " 89 Remarks of this sort abound in Luther's corpus, usually in connection with the interpretation of specific scriptural passages. Let us look at a somewhat more complicated argument along the same lines, from De servo arbitrio. Luther is here arguing about the interpretation of "I will harden Pharaoh's heart" (cf. Exod 4:21; Rom 9:17f.), which Erasmus takes to mean "God allowed Pharaoh to harden his own heart." But Luther takes "Deus est homo" as the chief example of the sort of interpretive problem posed by the passages about Pharaoh's hardening. 88 "Ockham does not want to be univocal, but equivocal, so that humanity in Peter is different from humanity in Christ." Similarly, "The Sorbonne demands that we make every word ambiguous. This should be resisted. We should not allow it in order to reconcile theology and philosophy with regard to this proposition (that is, 'Deus est homo') by distinguishing between 'human being' and 'human being' [Non admittendum, ut concilietin hac propositionetheologiam et philosophiam,id est, Deus est homo, cum distinguiturinter hominem et hominem]" (WA 39/2:11.36-37; 17.32-34). Thomas's position on the Christological issue, it should be noted, is the same. In "Deus est homo" and similar sentences, the subject, the predicate, and the predication are all to be taken "in their true and proper sense [vere et proprie]"; "est homo" means the same thing when applied to "Deus" as it does when applied to "Petrus," or, to use Thomas's examples, "Socrates" and "Platon" (cf. STh III, q. 16, a. 1). 89 WA 26:403.27-29; 279.7-8. 42 BRUCE D. MARSHALL Absurdity is one of the principal reasons why the words of Moses and Paul are not taken literally [simpliciter].But what article of faith does this absurdity sin against? Who is offended by it? Human reason is offended, which, although it is blind, deaf, stupid, impious, and sacrilegious with regard to all the words and works of God, is introduced here as the judge of the words and works of God. By the same argument you will deny all the articles of faith, because it is far and away the most absurd thing of all ... that God should be a human being, the son of a virgin, crucified, and seated at the right hand of the Father. It is absurd, I say, to believe such things. Let us therefore dream up some tropes with the Arians, so that Christ might not be literally [simpliciter]God. 90 Some reflection on the logic of these passages may help us understand how the relationship between plausible interpretation, the ascription of truth to sentences, and epistemic primacy works in Luther's theology. We can begin by considering just the relationship between truth and interpretation. Luther's argument here can perhaps be put in the following terms, which owe something to Davidson. We seek an interpretation of "Homo est Deus" and "Deus est homo"; the especially problematic word for our purposes is "homo." The aim of the interpretation is to fix the sense of "homo," or perhaps the coherent range of senses which the word may have; we want what Luther calls a "definite interpretation." If the interpretation is to be genuinely radical (that is, if we do not beg the question by assuming in advance that we know what "homo" means), we will have to try to fix the sense by maximizing the ascription of truth to sentences held true by Latin speakers in which "homo" is used, and especially those in which it is used as a subject or predicate nominative. So we note that Latin speakers hold true a host of sentences like "Petrus est homo" and "Maria est homo," and from the rest of the beliefs they (and we) hold true about "Petrus," "Maria," and others, we begin to get a fix on the sense of "homo." But we also observe that these speakers hold true the sentences "Homo est Deus" and "Deus est homo" (perhaps we are conducting our radical interpretation in a far-off monastery where Latin is still spoken). This gives us pause; we already have at least a partial fix on the sense of "Deus," and this word seems to denote something of a 90 WA 18:707.19-29. FAITH AND REASON RECONSIDERED 43 radically different sort from "Petrus," "Maria," and ourselves. Assuming for present purposes that we are confident in our interpretation of "Deus" so far, and do not want to change it, we are faced with two alternatives. We can come reluctantly (since we always interpret by seeking to maximize agreement on sentences held true) to the conclusion that in the case of these particular sentences our speakers are uttering falsehoods; aiming for a coherent and "definite" interpretation of "homo," we decide we can maintain it only by holding "Homo est Deus" and the like false. Or we can sense that something strange and wonderful is going on here, perhaps that this "Deus" is giving us the gift of an inconceivably intimate share in his own life by having freely made our life absolutely one with his own; and for this reason we may come to agree with our speakers in holding "Homo est Deus" true, convinced that we can do so without sacrificing the coherence and definiteness of our interpretation of "homo," which would of course vitiate our reason for holding the sentence true. This confronts us with the additional task, of course, of trying to show how these semantically unanticipated sentences may be held true without interpretive incoherence. The one thing we cannot do, however, is agree with our speakers in holding "Homo est Deus" true by taking "homo" to mean something like "Deus"; semantic economy and plausible (that is, coherent and definite) interpretation would be served simply by taking "Homo est Deus" to be false, rather than resorting to so drastic an equivocation. And as Luther sees it, this is just what the nominalist position comes to in the end. These considerations may also help explain why the gospel and the articles of faith can retain their "natural force" or plain sense and be held true only when they function with unrestricted epistemic primacy across the whole field of possible belief. In these late disputations, Luther sometimes says theology speaks a "new language" and uses "new words," in contrast (as we have already noted) to the "old language" and "old words" of philosophy (the idea is of course not a new one in his theology; recall, inter alia, the "modus loquendi theologicus" of the early 44 BRUCE D. MARSHALL lectures on Romans).91 The "new" discourse of theology does not differ from the "old" discourse of philosophy by assigning meanings to words radically discontinuous with those they have in the rest of human speech; this would presumably be just the sort of equivocation which Luther goes out of his way to reject. Theology is new not primarily in the meaning it gives to terms but in the way it combines them, that is, in the radically unexpected sentences it holds true. Holding these sentences true may of course extend or otherwise alter the sense of their terms, but not in such a way that the terms utterly lose their "natural force"; alluding to an old medieval distinction (much exploited by Thomas Aquinas) Luther argues that the terms in theological sentences signify (or, we could say, refer to) the same thing they do in the rest of our discourse, but signify it in a new way. 92 So, to use two of Luther's examples, "mother" when applied in theology to Mary continues to signify a woman who gives birth, but does so in a new (viz., virginal) way; "creature" when applied to Christ continues to signify that which God makes by an act of will, but which he now makes by uniting it absolutely to himself, rather than by separating it infinitely from himself.93 91 "21. 'Creature' in the old use of language and in other matters signifies something separated from God in infinite ways. 22. In the new use of language it signifies something inseparably conjoined with divinity in the same person in ineffable ways" (WA39/2:94.19-22; cf. above, n. 82). "In theology a philosophical term [vox] becomes entirely new"; "the customary vocabulary of philosophy becomes new" (19.7; 19.34-35). On "modus loquendi theologicus," cf. WA 56:351-52. 92 "20. Nonetheless it is certain that all terms [vocabula] receive a new signification in Christ, although they continue to refer to the same thing [in eadem re significata].23. In this way it is necessary that the words 'human being,' 'humanity,' 'suffered,' etc., and everything said about Christ be new terms. 24. Not that they signify a new or different thing, but they signify it in a new and different way, unless you also want to call that a new thing" (WA 39/2:94.17-18; 23-26). For Thomas's understanding of the distinction between the res sign.ificataof terms and their modus sign.ificandiwhich lies in the background here, cf. STh I, q. 13, a. 3; I Sent. d. 22, q. 1, a. 2. For examples of its theological use, see STh l, q. 39; STh III, q. 16. 93 "'Mother' in philosophy signifies a woman who is impure, in theology 'mother of Christ' signifies a pure and virgin [woman]" (WA 39/2:19.33-34). "In the old language 'creature' is that which the creator makes and separates from himself, but this signification has no place in the creature Christ. There creator and creature are one and the same" (WA 39/2:105.4-7). FAITH AND REASON RECONSIDERED 45 "Philosophy" goes beyond its "sphere" and becomes a problem for theology, an "old" language to which the "new" language of theology must stand opposed, when it takes our ordinary ways of combining terms into sentences as the key to interpreting and assessing the truth of the scriptural and creedal sentences theology is charged to uphold (a temptation "reason" finds itself powerless to resist). The scripturally and creedally formed discourse of the Christian community is, as Luther sees it, God's own way of talking in our language; as such the sentences it teaches us to hold true are shockingly novel and odd by comparison with the way we combine terms in the rest of our discourse. If we take consistency with "Petrus est homo" and similarly quotidian beliefs as the chief test for deciding whether a radically unexpected sentence like "Deus est homo" is true, and we are good interpreters who know how to take words according to their natural force, then we will naturally be inclined to regard such a novel sentence as false, indeed absurd. If we (like the nominalists) are bad interpreters who also want to hold true the sentences of Scripture and creed, then we will take "Deus est homo" in a way opposed to its natural force, which an efficient theory of interpretation converts to falsity according to the natural force. If we want to be both good interpreters and believers in the teaching of Scripture and creed we must not, it seems, try to decide about the truth of sentences such as "Deus est homo" by measuring them for consistency with the rest of our beliefs, but must rather take these sentences as the standard by consistency with which the truth of all the rest of our beliefs is chiefly measured. This means, of course, that there is no standard for deciding to hold true "Deus est homo" and the nest of beliefs in which it is most closely imbedded, that is, no higher or more central beliefs against which we could test their truth. This is, I suppose, part of what Luther means when he says that theology must hold to the word of God "without a syllogism," without any further principiato which it might appeal. We seek, to be sure, an interpretation of our daily discourse-indeed our whole field of belief-which is consistent with holding true the novel sentences of Scripture and creed, an interpretation which eschews equivocation and allows the natural sense to reign wherever BRUCE D. MARSHALL 46 possible in the sentences we hold true. Such an interpretation seems to require that we proceed in a certain way, that we speak the new language of theology rather than the old language of philosophy. But this is simply to say that the discourse of Scripture and creed can be held true, and all of our beliefs together can have their natural force, only when we take that discourse in a way suited to its radical novelty: as the principle for reconfiguring the whole field of belief, that is, as epistemically primary across the board. So Luther's argument that the same thing cannot be true in theology and philosophy need not be taken for a denial of the unrestricted epistemic primacy of the gospel read in accordance with the articles of faith. Theology and philosophy each has its own "sphere"; neither provides the content for the other's discourse, and each has its own rules for forming true sentences. But this distinction turns out to be a way of insisting that theology has to keep its epistemic priorities straight. Theology's "sphere" ends up being the whole; theology puts philosophy in its place by defining philosophy's sphere, that is, by marking out the boundaries within which its rules for forming true sentences may apply (viz., wherever they do not conflict with the truth of Scripture and creed taken in their natural sense). Luther accordingly concludes his disputation on John 1:14 with an appeal to 2 Corinthians 10: This is the point of this disputation: that when it comes to the mystical articles of faith we are not permitted to rely in argument on philosophical reasons, but must cling to the naked word and truth of Scripture, and that in faith the judgment of reason should not hold sway against the word, but should submit and subject itself to the obedience of Christ. 94 IV. CONCLUSION: DESPOILING THE EGYPTIANS Despite Chesterton, to say nothing of others more ·scholarly than he, it seems that Luther was not a naive fideist who sought to isolate Christian belief and Christian theology from the rest of human knowledge and inquiry. Or if Luther was a fideist then so 94 WA 39/2:30.15-18. FAITH AND REASON RECONSIDERED . 47 was Aquinas, since the logic of their positions on how to decide what is true seems to be the same. But rather than think of either of them as fideists, it seems more plausible to think of them both as scripturalist and creedalist theologians much concerned to keep their epistemic priorities straight, and that on the widest possible scale. How then did Chesterton (and others) go so far wrong? The short answer might be that he never read Luther. But even if true, this would not really be fair. Many who have read Luther, both Catholics and Protestants, share Chesterton's conviction that the difference between Luther and Thomas on faith and reason is radical, not superficial-they share, in other words, Luther's own assumption that he and Aquinas are at fundamental odds on this issue. Luther's assumption has a certain obvious plausibility. However little he had read Thomas, Luther, like Chesterton, rightly perceives that Thomas likes Aristotle, finds him intellectually fascinating and challenging, and thinks him theologically useful. Luther, by contrast, often says that Aristotle is useful only for non-theological purposes, and expresses deep contempt for Aristotle's world-view (his ethics and metaphysics, as distinct from his logic) and for those who find that world-view theologically useful.95 If the reading I have proposed here is right, then interpreters of Luther and Aquinas, of whatever confessional stripe, have widely been mislead by surface issues-like the different attitudes the two theologians have toward Aristotleand so have missed the deeper logical and structural likeness in their views of faith and reason, a likeness which comes to the surface when one attends to the question of how to decide what is true. To be sure, the differences between Luther and Aquinas on Aristotle and philosophy generally, while not radical in the way 95 Cf. e.g., the famous comments about "the blind heathen master Aristotle" in An den christlichen Adel deutscher Nation of 1520 (WA 6:457.28-458.40). As Theodor Dieter shows in "Der junge Luther undAristoteles" (HabilitationschriftTiibingen, 1997), however, in practice Luther's attitude towards Aristotle during this period was quite different from what this sort of rhetoric suggests; he took Scholastic, including Aristotelian, questions very seriously, and sought to answer them in his own way. Cf. also White, Luther as Nominalist, 320-25. On Luther's knowledge of Thomas, cf. Denis R. Janz, Luther on Thomas Aquinas: The Angelic Doctor in the Thought of the Reformer (Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag, 1989). 48 BRUCE D. MARSHALL appearances sometimes suggest, are not trivial. If this reading is correct, however, they stem not from fundamentally different epistemic priorities and outlooks, but from the quite different, and in important respects diametrically opposed, situations in which the epistemic outlook the two theologians basically share had to work. Confronted in Aristotle and Moslem Aristotelianism with a highly sophisticated world-view new to his Christian culture and deeply challenging to some of its most basic assumptions, Thomas vigorously and self-consciously sets about despoiling the Egyptians. He follows, with astonishing thoroughness and success, Augustine's advice that Christians who find themselves in this situation sort out the "simulated and superstitious imaginings" from the useable truths. 96 He tells the difference between the useless and useful goods of the Egyptians, as we have observed, by keeping his epistemic priorities straight-by seeing whether the goods in question are compatible with the gospel and can be put to its service. Luther sees himself confronted not so much with fresh Egyptian goods as with wayward children of Israel who, enticed by the local finery, have gone native-have forgotten how to keep their epistemic priorities straight. Overwhelmed by the beauty of Egypt to the point where they can no longer tell useable goods from useless idols, these wayward Israelites must have their sights set once more on the promised land. This Luther vigorously sets out to do, by insisting that everything in Church and theology cohere with the gospel, and ruthlessly discarding whatever does not-by insisting that we keep our epistemic priorities straight. That is: logically, if not rhetorically and stylistically, Luther did just what Aquinas would have done if Aquinas had been living and writing in Luther's very different situation. Or so I would seek to argue if my aim were to account for the differences between Aquinas and Luther on faith and reason rather than to display their more fundamental likeness. But the fulfillment of that aim reaches beyond the scope of this essay. % Augustine, De doctrina christiana2.40 (cf. above, n. 15). The Thomist 63 (1999): 49-63 FROM SCHRODINGER'S CAT TO THOMISTIC ONTOLOGY 1 WOLFGANG SMITH Hayden, Idaho I AM PLEASED and honored to give this Templeton Lecture on Christianity and the Natural Sciences. I regard the objective of these Lectures as a cultural task of prime importance. I believe that the reputed conflict between science and religion does exist, and is in fact far more serious than one tends to think; but, at the same time, I am persuaded that the conflict arises not from science as such but from a penumbra of scientistic beliefs for which in reality there is no scientific support at all. This oftoverlooked distinction between scientific truth and scientistic belief has long been a special concern of mine. I have, for many years, made it my business to hunt down and ferret out major articles of scientistic belief-not as an academic exercise, but in the conviction that the acceptance of such contemporary dogmas is injurious to our spiritual well-being. I have no doubt that the ongoing de-Christianization of Western society is due in large measure to the imposition of the prevailing scientistic world-view. Meanwhile something quite unexpected and as yet largely unobserved has come to pass: this scientistic world-view, which still reigns as the official dogma of science, appears no longer to square with the scientific facts. What has happened in our century is that unprecedented discoveries at the frontiers of science seem no longer to accord with the accustomed Weltanschauung, with the result that these findings present the appearance of paradox. It seems that on its most fundamental level physics itself has disavowed the prevailing world-view. This science, therefore, can 1 The following lecture was given at Gonzaga University on February 5, 1998. 49 50 WOLFGANG SMITH no longer be interpreted in the customary ontological terms; and so, as one quantum theorist has put it, physicists have, in a sense, "lost their grip on reality." 2 But this fact is known mainly to physicists, and has been referred to, not without cause, as "one of the best-kept secrets of science." It implies that physics has been in effect reduced to a positivistic discipline, or, in Whitehead's words, to "a kind of mystic chant over an unintelligible universe. " 3 Richard Feynman once remarked: "I think it is safe to say that no one understands quantum mechanics." To be sure, the incomprehension to which Feynman alludes refers to a philosophic plane; one understands the mathematics of quantum mechanics, but not the ontology. Broadly speaking, physicists have reacted to this impasse in three principal ways. The majority, perhaps, have found comfort in a basically pragmatic outlook, while some persist, to this day, in the attempt to fit the positive findings of quantum mechanics into the pre-quantum world-picture. The third category, which includes some of the most eminent names in physics, convinced that the pre-quantum ontology is now defunct, have cast about for new philosophic postulates, in the hope of arriving at a workable conception of physical reality. There seem to be a dozen or so world-views presently competing for acceptance in the scientific community. It is not my intention to propose yet another ad hoc philosophy designed to resolve quantum paradox. I intend in fact to do the opposite: to show, namely, that there is absolutely no need for a new philosophic Ansatz, that the problem at hand can be resolved quite naturally on strictly traditional philosophic ground. What I propose to show, in particular, is that the quantum facts, divested of scientistic encrustations, can be readily integrated into a very ancient and venerable ontology: namely, the Thomistic, which traces back to Aristotle. Rejected by Galileo and Descartes, and subsequently marginalized, this reputedly outmoded medieval speculation proves now to be capable of supplying the philosophic keys for which physicists have been groping since the advent of quantum theory. 2 Nick Herbert, 3 Quantum Reality (Garden City: Doubleday, 1985), 15. Alfred North Whitehead, Nature and Life (New York: Greenwood Press, 1968), 10. THOMISTIC ONTOLOGY 51 I First formulated in 1925, quantum mechanics has shaken the foundations of science. It appears as though physics, at long last, has broken through to its own fundamental level; it has discovered what I shall henceforth term the physical universe-a world that seems to defy some of our most basic conceptions. It is a world (if we may call it such) that can be neither perceived nor imagined, but only described in abstract mathematical terms. The most useful and widely accepted representation is the one formalized in 1932 by the Hungarian mathematician John von Neumann. In this model the state of a physical system is represented by a vector in a so-called complex Hilbert space. This means, in effect, that a state can be multiplied by a complex number, and that two states can be added, and that non-zero linear combinations of states, thus formed, will again be states of the physical system. Now, it is this fundamental fact, known as the superposition principle, that gives rise to quantum strangeness. Consider, for instance, a physical system consisting of a single particle, and then consider two states, in which the particle is situated, respectively, in two disjoint regions A and B, which can be as widely separated as we like. A linear combination of these two states with non-zero coefficients will then determine a third state, in which apparently the particle is situated, neither in A nor in B, but somehow in both regions. Now, one may say: "State vectors actually describe, not the physical system as such, but our knowledge concerning the physical system. The third state vector, thus, simply signifies that so far as we know the particle can be in A or in B, with a certain probability attached to each of the two possible events." A grave difficulty, however, remains; for the state of the physical system corresponding to the third state vector can in fact be produced experimentally, and when one does produce that state one obtains interference effects which could not be there if the particle were situated in A or in B. In some unimaginable way the particle seems thus to be actually in A and B at once. What happens then if one measures or observes the position of the particle in the third state? It turns out that the act of 52 WOLFGANG SMITH measurement instantly throws the system into a new state. The detected particle, of course, is situated either in A or in B; which is to say that only unobserved particles can bilocate. All this, to be sure, is very strange; but let me emphasize that from a mathematical point of view all is well, and that in fact the theory functions magnificently. As I have said before, what puzzles physicists is not the mathematics, but the ontology. Thus far I may have conveyed the impression that superposition states are rare and somehow exceptional. What is indeed exceptional, however, are states in which a given observable does have a precise value (the so-called eigenstates); and even in that case it happens that the system remains necessarily in a superposition state with respect to other observables. The quantum system, thus, is always in a state of superposition; or more precisely, it is at one and the same time in many different states of superposition, depending upon the observable one has in view. On the quantum level superposition is not the exception, but indeed the fundamental fact. At this point one might say: "There is no reason to be unduly perplexed; superposition applies, after all, to microsystems too minute to be observable without the aid of instruments. Why worry if 'weird things' happen on the level of fundamental particles and atoms? Why expect that one can picture things or happenings which are by nature imperceptible?" Most physicists, I believe, would be happy to adopt this position, if it were not for the fact that superposition tends to spread into the macroscopic domain. It is this quantum-mechanical fact that has been dramatized in the celebrated experiment proposed by Schrodinger, in which the disintegration of a radioactive nucleus triggers the execution of the now-famous cat. According to quantum theory, the unobserved nucleus is in a superposition state, which is to say that its state vector is a linear combination of state vectors corresponding to the disintegrated and undisintegrated states. This superposition, moreover, is transmitted, by virtue of the experimental set-up, to the cat, which is consequently in a corresponding superposition state. In plain terms, the cat is both dead and alive. It remains, moreover, in this curious condition until an act of observation collapses its state vector, as the THOMISTIC ONTOLOGY 53 expression goes, and thus reduces it to one or the other classical state. Of course, the mystery here has nothing especially to do with cats; it has to do with the role of measurement in the economy of quantum mechanics. Now, measurement is a procedure in which a given physical system is made to interact with an instrument, the resultant state of which then indicates the value of some observable associated with the system. For example, a particle is made to collide with a detector (a photographic plate, perhaps) which registers its position at the moment of impact. Prior to this interaction, the particle will in general be in a superposition state involving multiple positions; we must think of it as spread out over some region of space. Its evolution or movement, moreover, is governed by the so-called Schrodinger equation, which is linear, and hence preserves superposition, and is moreover strictly deterministic: an initial state uniquely determines the future states. At the moment of impact, however, this deterministic Schrodinger evolution is superseded by another quantummechanical law, a so-called projection, which singles out one of the positions represented in the given superposition stateapparently for no good reason!-and instantly assigns the particle to the chosen location. This simple scenario exemplifies what happens generally in the act of measurement: a physical system interacts with an instrument or measuring apparatus, and this interaction causes the Schrodinger evolution of the system to be superseded by an apparently random projection. It is as though the trajectory of a particle, let us say, were suddenly altered without an assignable cause. Why does this happen? Inasmuch as the instrument is itself a physical system, one would expect that the combined system, obtained by including the instrument, should itself evolve in accordance with the corresponding Schrodinger equation; but in fact it does not! What is it, then, that distinguishes the kind of interaction we term measurement from other interactions between physical systems, in which Schrodinger evolution is not superseded? Quantum theory holds many puzzles of this kind; the scandal of superposition assumes many forms. I would like to mention one more of these enigmas, which strikes me as particularly 54 WOLFGANG SMITH central. One might think of it as a simplified version of the Schrodinger cat paradox. In the words of Roger Penrose, the problem is this: The rules are that any two states whatever, irrespective of how different from one another they may be, can coexist in any complex linear superposition. Indeed, any physical object, itself made out of individual particles, ought to be able to exist in such superpositions of spatially widely separated states, and so be "in two places at once"! ... Why, then, do we not experience macroscopic bodies, say cricket balls, or even people, having two completely different locations at once? This is a profound question, and present-day quantum theory does not really provide us with a satisfying answer. 4 These matters have been debated for a very long time, and various interpretations of the mathematical formalism have been proposed in an effort to make philosophic sense out of the theory. However, as Penrose observes, "These puzzles, in one guise or another, persist in any interpretation of quantum mechanics as the theory exists today." 5 After more than half a century of debate it appears that no clear resolution of the problem is yet in sight. One thing, however, one crucial point, has been consistently overlooked; and that is what I must now explain. II As is very well known, it was the seventeenth-century philosopher Rene Descartes who laid the philosophic foundations of modern physics. Descartes conceived of the external or objective world as made up of so-called res extensae, extended things bereft of sensible qualities, which can be fully described in purely quantitative or mathematical terms. Besides res extensae he posited also res cogitantes or "thinking entities," and it is to these that he consigned the sensible qualities, along with whatever else in the universe might be recalcitrant to mathematical definition. One generally regards this Cartesian partition of reality into res 4 Roger Penrose, The Emperor'sNew Mind (New York: Oxford University Press, 1989), 256. 5 Ibid., 296. THOMISTIC ONTOLOGY 55 extensae and res cogitantes as simply an affirmation of the mind-body dichotomy, forgetting that it is much more than that; for not only has Descartes distinguished sharply between mind and body, but he has at the same time imposed an exceedingly strange and indeed problematic conception of corporeal nature, a conception, namely, that renders the external world unperceived and unperceivable. According to Descartes, the red apple we perceive exists-not in the external world, as mankind had believed all along, but in the mind, the res cogitans; in short, it is a mental phantasm that we have naively mistaken for an external entity. Descartes admits, of course, that in normal sense perception the phantasm is causally related to an external object, a res extensa; but the fact remains that it is not the res extensa but the phantasm that is actually perceived. What was previously conceived as a single object-and what in daily life is invariably regarded as such-has now been split in two; as Whitehead has put it: "Thus there would be two natures, one is the conjecture and the other is the dream. " 6 This splitting of the object into a "conjecture" and a "dream" is what Whitehead terms "bifurcation"; and this, it turns out, is the decisive philosophic postulate that underlies and determines our interpretation of physics. Beginning with his Tarner Lectures (delivered at Cambridge University in 1919), Whitehead insistently pointed out and commented upon this fact. "The result," he declares, "is a complete muddle in scientific thought, in philosophic cosmology, and in epistemology. But any doctrine which does not implicitly presuppose this point of view is assailed as unintelligible. " 7 After seventy years of quantum debate, the situation remains fundamentally unchanged. Just about every other article of philosophic belief, it would seem, has been put on the table and subjected to scrutiny, whereas bifurcation continues to be implicitly presupposed by physicists, as if it were a sacrosanct dogma revealed from on high. And so "the muddle in scientific thought" continues, and has only been exacerbated by the demands of quantum theory. 6 Alfred North Whitehead, The Concept of Nature (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1964), 30. 7 Whitehead, Nature and Life, 6. 56 WOLFGANG SMITH That's the bad news; the good news is that the situation can be remedied. In a recent monograph I have shown that physics can indeed be interpreted on a nonbifurcationist basis, with the result that quantum paradox disappears of its own accord. 8 No need any more for such things as the "many worlds" hypothesis or other ad hoc stipulations; to resolve the semblance of paradox one needs but to relinquish a certain philosophic postulate foisted upon us by Galileo and Descartes. Quantum paradox, it appears, is Nature's way of repudiating a spurious philosophy. III We need thus to take a second look at quantum mechanics, this time from a nonbifurcationist point of view. Now, to deny bifurcation is to affirm the objective reality of the perceived entity: the red apple, thus, is once again recognized as an external object. That perceptible entity, moreover, is to be distinguished from what may be called the "molecular apple," a thing that, dearly, cannot be perceived, but can be known only through the methods of physics. One is consequently led to distinguish between two kinds of external objects: corporeal objects, which can be perceived, and physical objects, which can only be observed indirectly through the modus operandi of the experimental physicist. The two ontological domains are of course closely related, failing which there could be no science of the physical at all. The basic fact is this: Every corporeal object X is associated with a physical object SX from which it derives all of its quantitative attributes. The red apple, for example, derives its weight from the molecular. The crucial point, however, is that the two are not the same thing; X and SX belong to different ontological planes-to different worlds, one could almost say. The bifurcationist, obviously, does not recognize this distinction, since he denies the existence of the corporeal object X; but in so doing, he implicitly identifies X with SX. The credo of bifurcation thus entails a reduction of the corporeal to the 8 Wolfgang Smith, The Quantum Enigma (Peru, Ill.: Sugden, 1995). A helpful summary of the book with commentary has been given by William A. Wallace in "Thomism and the Quantum Enigma," The Thomist 61 (1997): 455-67. THOMISTIC ONTOLOGY 57 physical. And in that reductionism, I say, lies the fundamental fallacy-the illusion, if you will-of the prevailing Weltanschauung. The amazing thing is this: whereas classical physics seemingly tolerates that error, quantum mechanics does not. It turns out that the new physics itself distinguishes between X and SX; it insists in fact upon that distinction-which is precisely what perplexes the physicist. In its very structure, that is to say, in its categorical distinction between the physical system and its observables, quantum mechanics affirms in its own way the ontological distinction between the physical and the corporeal planes. The system thus belongs to the physical domain, whereas the act of measurement terminates dearly on the corporeal, in the perceptible state, namely, of a corporeal instrument. It is true that the corporeal instrument I is associated with a physical system SI: but the point, once again, is that the two are by no means the same. What is special about measurement is the fact that it realizes an ontological transition from the physical to the corporeal domain. No wonder, therefore, that quantum theory should be conversant with two very different "laws of motion," for it has now become apparent that Schrodinger evolution operates within the physical domain, whereas projection has to do with a transit out of the physical and into the corporeal. In the language of metaphysics one can say that the former describes a horizontal and the latter a vertical process. One can now see that the discontinuity of state vector collapse mirrors an ontological discontinuity; and that is the reason why the phenomenon cannot be understood from a reductionist point of view. State vector collapse is inexplicable on a physical basis because it results from the act of a corporeal entity. These considerations strongly suggest that the superposition principle must be amended for subcorporeal systems, that is to say, for the SX of a corporeal object X; for it is altogether reasonable to suppose that the state vector of SX can admit only superpositions consistent with the perceivable properties of X. That is no doubt the reason why cats cannot be both dead and alive, and why cricket balls do not bilocate. Penrose is absolutely right: if cats and cricket balls were "made of individual particles,,; 58 WOLFGANG SMITH they would indeed be able to exist in unrestricted states of superposition; but the point is that they are not thus made. From a nonbifurcationist point of view, corporeal objects, as we have seen, are not simply aggregates of particles, but something more. We need therefore to inquire what it is that differentiates X from SX; and for this we shall turn to Thomistic ontology. IV We must begin where St. Thomas himself began: namely, with the fundamental conceptions of Aristotle. The first step, if you will, in the analysis of being is to distinguish between substances and attributes: between things that exist in themselves and things that exist in another. Having thus distinguished between what is primary and what is secondary, one proceeds to the analysis of the primary thing. The problem is to break substance into its components-to split the atom of substance, if you will; and for this one evidently requires the conception of things more primitive than substances, things "out of which" substances are made. Aristotle solved this problem with one of the great master-strokes in the history of philosophy: the distinction between potency and act. The customary definition of these terms is simple and quite unimpressive: That which is capable of being a certain thing, but is not that thing, is that thing in potency; whereas that which a thing already is is so in act. A seed is a tree in potency, and a tree is a tree in act. Aristotle goes on to define matter, or prime matter, to be exact, as that which is in potency to substance, to substantial being. Prime matter as such has consequently no being; but it has nonetheless a capacity or an aptitude for being. What actualizes this capacity is indeed an act, and that act is called a form, or more precisely, a substantial form. Substance has thus been split into two components: matter and form. It is the form, moreover, that contributes to the substance its essential content, its quiddity or "whatness," what the Germans so expressively call its Sosein. And yet that form is not itself the substance, is not itself the existent thing; for the form without matter does not exist. THOMISTIC ONTOLOGY 59 It is at this point of the analysis that the genius of St. Thomas Aquinas becomes manifest. And here we come to a second master-stroke in the history of philosophy. Saint Thomas recognized that substantial form is itself in potency to something else: to an act, namely, which is not a form; and that is the act-of-being itself. To put it in his own words: "The act-of-being is the most intimate element in anything, and the most profound element in all things, because it is like a form in regard to all that is in the thing. "9 That innermost element constitutes the point of contact, as it were, between created being and its uncreated Source, which is God. The act-of-being, thus, belongs in the first place to God, who creates and sustains the universe; and yet it also belongs to created substance as its innermost reality. We may think of it as radiating outwards, through the substantial form, to the very accidents by which the being communicates itself to us. Each being, moreover, is endowed with a certain efficacy, a certain power to act outside itself, which likewise derives from its act-of-being, and thus from God. Yet that efficacy, that power, is distinctly its own. As Etienne Gilson has beautifully explained: The universe, as represented by St. Thomas, is not a mass of inert bodies passively moved by a force which passes through them, but a collection of active beings each enjoying an efficacy delegated to it by God along with actual being. At the first beginning of a world like this, we have to place not so much a force being exercised as an infinite goodness communicated. Love is the unfathomable source of all causality. 10 We are beginning, perhaps, to catch a glimpse of the Thomistic ontology; but let us continue. Not only is God's love the unfathomable source of all causality, but all causation, as we know it, imitates that love. To quote Gilson once more: Beneath each natural form lies hidden a desire to imitate by means of action the creative fecundity and pure actuality of God. This desire is quite unconscious in the domain of bodies; but it is that same straining towards God which, with intelligence and will, will blossom forth into human morality. 9 Aquinas, STh I, q. 8, a. 1. 10 Etienne Gilson, The Christian Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas (University of Notre Dame Press, 1994), 183. 60 WOLFGANG SMITH Thus, if a physics of bodies exists, it is because there exists first a mystical theology of the divine life. The natural laws of motion, and its communication from being to being, imitate the primitive creative effusion from God. The efficacy of second causes is but the counterpart of His fecundity. 11 This same Thomistic vision of Nature has been expressed by Meister Eckhart in a passage of rare beauty, where he writes: You must understand that all creatures are by nature endeavoring to be like God. The heavens would not revolve unless they followed on the track of God or of his likeness. If God were not in all things, Nature would stop dead, not working and not wanting; for whether thou like it or no, whether thou know it or not, Nature fundamentally is seeking, though obscurely, and tending towards God. No man in his extremity of thirst but would refuse the proffered draught in which there was no God. Nature's quarry is not meat or drink nor clothes nor comfort nor any things at all wherein is naught of God, but covertly she seeks and ever more hotly she pursues the trail of God therein. 12 Here we have it: a vision of Nature that penetrates to the very heart of things, to that "most profound element" which St. Thomas has identified as its act-of-being. This is no longer an Aristotelian, but an authentically Christian Weltanschauung. I propose to show next how the findings of quantum theory fit into that Christian world-view. v It needs to be pointed out, first of all, that the Thomistic philosophy, no less than the Aristotelian, is unequivocally nonbifurcationist. There is in neither philosophy the slightest trace of Cartesian doubt. What we know by way of sense perception are external objects, period; and these are the objects with which the Thomistic ontology is principally concerned. It follows that the findings of physics (in our sense) can be assimilated into the Thomistic world-view only on condition that they be interpreted in nonbifurcationist terms. 11 Ibid., 184. 12 C. de B. Evans, trans., Meister &khart (London: Watkins, 1924), 1:115. THOMISTIC ONTOLOGY 61 The fundamental problem, dearly, is to situate the physical domain in relation to the corporeal. Now, we know that transitions from the physical to the corporeal are effected by acts of measurement in which a certain possibility inherent in a given physical system is actualized; and this constitutes, Thomistically speaking, a passage from potency to act. Every physical system, in fact, is to be conceived as a potency in relation to the corporeal domain. I might add that this point has been made very forcefully by Werner Heisenberg with reference to microphysical systems: "a strange kind of physical entity just in the middle between possibility and reality" 13 he called these, and went on to observe that in certain respects they are reminiscent of what he termed "Aristotelian potentiae." When it comes to the macroscopic domain, however, Heisenberg identifies in effect the corporeal object X with the associated physical object SX, and thus submits (as does virtually everyone else!) to a reductionist view of corporeal nature-as if the mere aggregation of atoms could effect a transition from potency to act. Nonbifurcation, on the other hand, implies, as we have seen, an ontological distinction between X and SX, which is to say that SX itself, no less than the quantum particles out of which it is composed, constitutes in fact "a strange kind of physical entity just in the middle between possibility and reality." To be precise, fundamental particles and their aggregates-be they ever so macroscopic!--occupy a position, ontologically speaking, between primary matter and the corporeal domain. Contemporary physics, it appears, has discovered an intermediary level of existence unknown and undreamt of in premodern times. It is this intermediary domain below the corporeal that I term the physical universe. What then distinguishes the two ontological planes? From an Aristotelian or Thomistic point of view the answer is dear: what distinguishes a corporeal object X from SX is precisely its substantial form. It is this form that bestows upon X its corporeal nature and specific essence, its "whatness" or Sosein, as we have said. It is important to emphasize that this substantial form is not a mathematical structure; if it were, X and SX would necessarily coincide. Substantial forms fall therefore beyond the ken of an 13 Heisenberg, Physics and Philosophy (New York: Harper & Row, 1962), 41. 62 WOLFGANG SMITH exclusively quantitative science, a fact Descartes himself clearly recognized, for instance, when he writes: We can easily conceive how the motion of one body can be caused by that of another, and diversified by the size, figure and situation of its parts, but we are wholly unable to conceive how these same things can produce something else of a nature entirely different from themselves, as for example, those substantial forms and real qualities which many philosophers suppose to be in bodies. 14 But is this not in fact the reason why Galileo and Descartesprotagonists of universal mechanism-rejected substantial forms, and banished sensible qualities from the external world? In so doing, however, they cast out the very essence of corporeal being; one is left with a de-essentialized universe, a world emptied of reality. We need today to free ourselves from the iron grip of this dehumanizing scientistic dogma. We need to rediscover the fullness of the corporeal world, replete with substantial forms and real qualities, and harboring deep within itself the mystery of what St. Thomas calls "the most profound element in all things." We have need of this discovery in every domain of life, including the scientific; but most especially, we have need of it in the spiritual domain. The fullness of the Christian life, in particular, demands a sacramental capacity on the part of matter which is totally inconceivable in terms of a reductionist ontology. There is no room for the Christie mysteries in a universe made up simply of fundamental particles. The deeper truths of religion have thus become unthinkable for us. In the final count, we know neither man nor the universe, because neither can be comprehended in separation from God; "I am the truth," said Christ. To postulate, as we have, a self-existent universe productive of man is to beget an illusion. Like the prisoners in Plato's cave, we are thenceforth confined to an illusory world, constrained to gaze upon a realm of shadows. I surmise that of all the true philosophies-and I believe there are more than one-the Thomistic may be for us the safest and most efficacious means by which to effect the liberating 14 Cited in E. A. Burtt, The Metaphysical Foundations of Modem Physical Science (New York: Humanities Press, 1951), 112. THOMISTIC ONTOLOGY 63 intellectual rectification. Whosoever has sensed that "love is the unfathomable source of all causation" has already broken the chains; and whoever has grasped, even dimly, what St. Thomas terms the act-of-being, is well on his way. The Thomist 63 (1999): 65-82 ISRAEL AND THE SHAPE OF THOMAS AQUINAS'S SOTERIOLOGY MAITHEW LEVERING Boston College Chestnut Hill, Massachusetts T HE CONTEMPORARY understanding of Thomas Aquinas's soteriology has been succinctly expressed in a recent study, Christology, by Gerald O'Collins, S.J. O'Collins divides his treatment of Christo logy into three sections: biblical, historical, and systematic. In his historical section, he offers a brief appraisal of Thomas Aquinas's views. He concludes that Aquinas made both positive and negative contributions. On the positive side, Aquinas "mitigates" Anselm's theory of satisfaction by emphasizing the role of charity. Second, rather than focusing only on Christ's passion, Aquinas treats Christ's entire "human story." Third, Aquinas recognizes the redemptive role of Christ's resurrection. These positive points are followed by three criticisms. The first is that by including the question as to whether Christ would have become incarnate had Adam not sinned Aquinas separates the order of creation and redemption. O'Collins is concerned that the incarnation not be seen as a "divine rescue operation, mounted subsequently after an original plan of creation went astray." His second criticism is directed against Aquinas's theory that Christ, because of the grace of the hypostatic union, possessed the beatific vision. O'Collins speaks for many modern theologians in arguing that this theory posits a docetic Christ. His third criticism is that Aquinas contributes to the development of the notion of penal substitution. Anselm had proposed that Christ's death restored the divine order of justice; Aquinas adds a new emphasis on 65 66 MATIHEW LEVERING Christ's penal suffering. This emphasis on Christ's suffering is seen as helping to "open the door to a monstrous version of redemption: Christ as the penal substitute propitiating the divine anger." Aquinas thus stands as the unwitting predecessor of Luther. 1 Without unfairly singling out O'Collins, I wish to challenge his approach to Aquinas's soteriology. Given the breadth of his project, O'Collins could only be expected to offer a summary of the scholarly consensus about Aquinas's soteriology. Precisely for this reason, his treatment is representative of a widespread misappropriation of Aquinas. Aquinas's treatise is viewed as a collection of propositions from which the modern theologian may select the propositions that remain valuable today. This approach is justified by the assumption that Aquinas's greatness lies in his ability to collect the best Scholastic propositions and organize them according to Aristotelian rules. 2 Such an assumption is not entirely unwarranted: Aquinas certainly desired to assemble the best insights of his predecessors, and he sought to give theology scientific form. And yet, this approach fails to give due credit to Aquinas's theological gifts. When we seek what unifies the propositions of one of Aquinas's treatises, we should look for theological as well as philosophical intelligibility. In this article, I will argue that Aquinas's soteriological propositions are unified by his insight into how Christ's passion fulfills the Old Law.3 By overlooking this unifying factor, O'Collins misunderstands Aquinas's reasons for emphasizing Christ's charity, beatific vision, and penal suffering. The main task of this essay, therefore, will be to examine the role of the Old Law in Aquinas's treatise on Christ's passion. Before we undertake this 1 Gerald O'Collins, S.J., Christology (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995), 206-7. 2 A theologian as great as Hans Urs von Balthasar fell into this mistake. He treats Aquinas as "more of a philosopher than a theologian," whose gift lay in philosophical organization rather than theological insight (cited in James J. Buckley, "Balthasar's Use of the Theology of Aquinas," The Thomist 59 [1995]: 517). 3 For Aquinas, since Christ is the incarnate Word, everything that he does (from his coming into the world to his resurrection and ascension) has redemptive significance. Nonetheless, Christ's passion represents the apogee of his redemptive work, since it is primarily here that he brings the Old Law to completion. ISRAEL AND AQUINAS'S SOTERIOLOGY 67 task, however, we should briefly summarize Aquinas's conception of the place of the Old Law in the history of salvation. The rational faculties of Adam and Eve were originally rightly directed to God. This state of "original justice" was itself a gift of grace (STh I, q. 95, a. 1). Original sin, as a fall from grace, disordered the rational faculties: they no longer were subject to God, nor did they rule the sense appetites (STh I, q. 85, a. 1). Under the sway of the sense appetites, the rational faculties' promptness to perceive and obey the "natural law" (i.e., the rational creature's participation in the "eternal law," the holy order that God has inscribed in creation) was weakened. As a result, in addition to the state of sin brought about by the original rejection of God's grace, human beings became culpable for numerous personal sins. The giving of the Old Law on Sinai began in earnest the process of extricating man from sin. The Decalogue, Aquinas argues, reveals the tenets of the natural law (STh I-II, q. 100, a. 1). The other precepts of the Old Law structure Israel's cultic and political life around these tenets. Aquinas explains that in addition to the moral precepts, the Old Law contains ceremonial and judicial precepts-determinations of the moral precepts by which man is directed to God and to fellow men, respectively. These precepts, while good in themselves, are not "perfect," because they prefigure something higher (STh I-11, q. 104, a. 2). The ceremonial precepts, primarily those instituting the sacrificial system, cultically represent the right order of man to God; but the sacrifice of animals inevitably falls short of this right order. The judicial precepts, primarily those instituting the regulation of exchange and punishment for crime, are also figurative, although in a different way. By shaping the government of Israel, they suggest the right order that should exist between man and fellow men, but in practice, like any human politics, they are unable to produce this right order. Thus the Old Law could only prefigure the final restoration of "right order" and the meriting of salvation. Nonetheless, Aquinas insists, participation in the Messiah's salvific action did not begin only after the event had taken place. Rather, such participation 68 MATrnEW LEVERING was possible for the people living under the Old Law, insofar as by faith, hope, and love they were joined to the prefigured salvific action of the prophesied Messiah. 4 Since the New Law is simply the grace of the Holy Spirit that enables man to participate in the Messiah's transcendent fulfillment of the Old Law, the New Law is active even during the period of the Old. Still, the New Law is not ahistorical: it hinges upon Christ's salvific work. Aquinas emphasizes that "the New Law fulfills the Old by justifying men through the power of Christ's Passion" (STh 1-11, q. 107, a. 2). When Christ's passion occurs, of course, it brings to an end the Old Law, now taken up into his salvific action. As members of his mystical body (since his person is divine, all people can be joined to him through the grace of the Holy Spirit), we share in the profound reconciliation that his suffering brings. And by sharing in the merit of his suffering, we receive the promise of rising with him to eternal life. Having reviewed the relationship of the Old and New Laws, we are now ready to turn to Aquinas's treatise on Christ's passion. Since Adam and Eve fell through disobedience, Christ's salvific action must be (as St. Paul says) an act of obedience. In STh III, q. 4 7, a. 2, Aquinas deepens this insight. He argues that Christ's supreme act of obedience-his passion-actually fulfills the Old Law. He points to St. John's Gospel, which records Jesus's final words from the cross, "It is consummated." Aquinas understands Christ to mean that the Old Law has finally been consummated in him. Aquinas then shows briefly how Christ's perfect act of obedience, flowing from the supernatural grace that infused his soul at the moment of the hypostatic union, simultaneously fulfills all three aspects of the Old Law. Since charity is the form of all the virtues, Christ's perfect charity, which he displayed "inasmuch as he suffered both out of love of 4 Significantly, the final question that Aquinas treats before taking up Christ's passion concerns his transfiguration (STh III, q. 45). The presence of Moses and Elijah signifies Christ's intimate relationship to the saints of the Old Covenant, who recognized him in the Old Law, and foretold his coming in the prophetic books. Although these saints, by the grace of the Holy Spirit, possessed the supernatural virtue of faith in Christ's passion, as well as the virtues of hope and love, their final restoration awaited the event of Christ's passion, in which he paid the "debt" incurred by original sin (STh III, q. 49, a. 5, ad 1). ISRAEL AND AQUINAS'S SOTERIOLOGY 69 the Father ... and out of love of his neighbor," perfectly fulfilled the moral precepts of the Law. Secondly, Christ perfectly fulfilled the ceremonial precepts (which direct man to God) in the self-sacrifice that he offered upon the cross. Finally, Aquinas employs Psalm 63 :5 to explain how Christ perfectly fulfilled the judicial precepts (which direct man to fellow-man): "He paid that which He took not away, suffering Himself to be fastened to a tree on account of the apple which man had plucked from the tree against God's command." In other words, Christ, though innocent, took upon himself the suffering due to all others. In STh III, q. 4 7, a. 2, therefore, Aquinas provides the basic framework that unites the material of his treatise, which spans qq. 46-49. He seeks to explore, and to balance, the three ways in which Christ's passion simultaneously fulfilled the Old Law. Aquinas, of course, does not arrange his questions around the three kinds of precepts. He arranges his material in a more scientific order: q. 46 concerns the passion itself; q. 47, the efficient cause of the passion; and qq. 48-49, the effects of the passion. Yet in each of these questions, his concern is to show how Christ's passion is redemptive within the context established by Israel's Law. This concern enables Aquinas to achieve a profound balance between Christ's charity, his sacrifice, and his suffering. I. THE CEREMONIAL PRECEPTS We will begin with Christ's fulfillment of the ceremonial precepts, because this aspect of the Old Law has a special place in Aquinas's understanding of Christ's passion. 5 Earlier in his Christology, Aquinas had devoted an entire question to Christ's priesthood (STh III, q. 22), underscoring the special significance of the ceremonial precepts of the Old Law. The ceremonial 5 This thesis is defended by Romanus Cessario, O.P., in The Godly Image (Petersham: St. Bede's Publications, 1990). Cessario notes the dependence of Aquinas's treatment upon the Epistle to the Hebrews, which focuses upon Christ's priestly mediation. See also Albert Patfoort, O.P., "Le vrai visage de la satisfaction du Christ selon St. Thomas," in Ordo Sapientiae et Amoris, ed. Carlos-Josaphat Pinta de Oliveira, O.P. (Fribourg: Editions Universitaires Fribourg, 1993), 247-66. 70 MATIHEW LEVERING precepts, as Aquinas states in STh I-II, q. 101, a. 1, are properly the determinations of the moral law "which pertain to the Divine worship," and so it is not surprising that they have foremost dignity in his presentation. Before turning to the fulfillment of the ceremonial precepts in Christ's passion, we should examine more closely how Aquinas, in his treatise on the Old Law, interprets the ceremonial precepts, in particular the laws about sacrifices. In contrast to the modern view of sacrificial offerings, Aquinas attributes to sacrifice a positive symbolic force. In STh I-II, q. 102, a. 3, ad 8 he notes that Christ's sacrifice is prefigured in the Old Law by three kinds of sacrifices: burnt offerings, peace offerings, and sin offerings, each of which represent a stage of the spiritual life. Since Aquinas holds that people living under the Old Law truly participated (through the Old Law) in the New Law, he can apply the later Christian distinction between the "counsels" and the "commandments" to the spiritual life of the Israelites. Burnt offerings, he suggests, were intended to "show reverence to His majesty, and love of His goodness: and typified the state of perfection as regards the fulfilment of the counsels." Burnt offerings were burnt completely in order to represent the self-offering of the whole man. Similarly, peace offerings were offered out of thanksgiving for divine favors received, and also in supplication for new favors. Aquinas holds that this kind of sacrifice "typifies the state of those who are proficient in the observance of the commandments." The peace offering was divided into three parts, one to be burnt, one for the priests, and one for the offerers. Aquinas explains that this threefold division signified the way in which salvation is from God, is mediated through priests, and is received by those who ask for it. The third kind of sacrifice, the sin offering, represents (as the name implies) imperfection. Aquinas states that this kind of sacrifice "was offered to God on account of man's need for the forgiveness of sin: and this typifies the state of penitents in satisfying for sins." This sacrifice was the special duty of the priests of the Old Law. ISRAEL AND AQUINAS'S SOTERIOLOGY 71 With this background, we will understand more easily how Christ fulfills the ceremonial precepts. 6 In STh III, q. 48, a. 3, Aquinas asks whether Christ's passion operated by way of sacrifice. His answer explores the nature of Christ's sacrifice. The proper meaning of sacrifice, he notes, is "something done for that honor which is properly due to God, in order to appease him [ad eum placandum]." This definition emphasizes the reconciling aspect of sacrifice; and in this sense, Christ's sacrifice was primarily a sin offering. On the other hand, Christ's sacrifice also embodied the other two kinds of sacrifice. Aquinas cites Augustine to make clear the relationship between sacrifice as a perfect act and as a sin offering: "'A true sacrifice is every good work done in order that we may cling to God in holy fellowship, yet referred to that consummation of happiness wherein we can be truly blessed."' Christ's perfect charity meant that his sacrifice was both a burnt offering and a peace offering, since as a reverential and thankful gift of the whole person, his sacrifice anticipated the "consummation of happiness"; but his sacrifice was also a sin offering, intended to enable us to regain "holy fellowship" with God. Christ's sacrifice thus draws together the three kinds of sacrifices in the Old Law. Aquinas concludes with two more citations of Augustine. Augustine compares the relationship of Christ's one sacrifice to the various sacrifices of the Old Law with 6 See also ITh 11-11, q. 85 "Of Sacrifice," where Aquinas discusses sacrifice as part of the virtue of religion, which is in turn part of the virtue of justice. In this question, Aquinas conceives of sacrifice as part of holiness, rather than as a penance for sin. In a. 1, he holds that offering sacrifice belongs to the natural law. In a passage that might well serve as a commentary upon the famous "five ways" to show the existence of God, Aquinas explains: Natural reason tells man that he is subject to a higher being,on account of the defects which he perceives in himself, and in which he needs help and direction from someone above him: and whatever this superior being may be, it is known to all under the name of God. Now just as in natural things the lower are naturally subject to the higher, so too it is a dictate of natural reason in accordance with man's natural inclination that he should tender submission and honor, according to his mode, to that which is above man. In a. 2, Aquinas explains that "the sacrifice that is offered outwardly represents the inward spiritual sacrifice ••• since, as stated above [STh III, q. 81, a. 7; q. 84, a. 2), the outward acts of religion are directed to the inward acts." 72 MATIHEW LEVERING the relationship of a single concept to the many words in which it may be expressed. Indeed, Christ's sacrifice not only unifies the various kinds of sacrifices of the Old Law, but also unifies the priest with the victim, and the one who offers with the one who receives. Emphasizing that Christ's sacrifice unifies the various kinds of sacrifices of the Old Law leaves Aquinas with a difficult problem: if Christ's sacrifice is a "positive" sacrifice, then why is it a sacrifice of human flesh, an act explicitly forbidden in the Old Law? In the same article, Aquinas confronts this objection. Because the ceremonial precepts are "figures," we should expect that the reality would surpass them. Although it would have been unfitting to sacrifice human flesh under the Old Law, Christ's flesh is a fitting sacrifice for four reasons. As with many of his arguments from fittingness, Aquinas draws these reasons from Augustine. First, Christ's sacrifice is ordered to the redemption of human beings, and specifically to the sacramental system. Therefore, the sacrifice of Christ's flesh is fitting, since otherwise men could not truly receive Christ in the Eucharist. Second, God took on flesh precisely in order to offer it in sacrifice; otherwise, God would not have needed to become incarnate. Third, Christ's flesh was unblemished by sin, and therefore constituted a perfect offering which, when participated through the sacraments, "had virtue to cleanse from sins." Fourth, in Christ's case the offering of human flesh was acceptable, since he himself willed in perfect charity to offer his own flesh. 7 Having demonstrated that Christ's sacrifice must be seen as a positive offering, Aquinas devotes the next article (STh III, q. 48, 7 It is worth having in mind Aquinas's understanding of "charity." Charity requires expending oneself for the beloved, even to the extent of sacrificing one's own life. The well-being of the state, for example, requires a political love by which citizens "love the good of the state so that it might be preserved and defended .... So much is this so, that men would expose themselves to dangers of death or neglect of their own private good, in order to preserve or increase the good of the state" (fhomas Aquinas, On Charity, trans. Lottie H. Kendzierski [Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1984], 43). Supernatural love, therefore, requires at least a willingness to sacrifice the life of the body. Christ's bloody self-sacrifice perfectly manifests this supernatural charity. A lesser sacrifice could not have provided an adequate exemplar of supernatural charity. ISRAEL AND AQIBNAS'S SOTERIOLOGY 73 a. 4) to exploring the nature of Christ's sacrifice specifically as a sin offering. As a sin offering, Christ's sacrifice operates according to the mode of redemption. In STh 1-11, q. 87, Aquinas had already explained that mortal sin incurs a "debt" of eternal punishment, because the order of divine justice is transgressed. So long as man is infected by original sin, he owes this "debt" of punishment. Moreover, he cannot pay it of himself: "if a sin destroys the principle of the order whereby man's will is subject to God, the disorder will be such as to be considered in itself irreparable, although it is possible to repair it by the power of God" (STh 1-11, q. 87, a. 3). Original sin imposed an ontological "debt" upon human nature; precisely by turning away from God, man incurred the punishment of being turned towards death. Christ's death, as the death of a sinless man, pays this "debt." The order of divine justice is restored. Indeed, Christ's perfect sin offering is "superabundant" compensation for our sin because of the dignity of his bodily life, which is united to the divine nature in the Person of the Word. Christ's sacrifice can also be described as a "satisfaction." Anselm developed the concept of satisfaction that Aquinas uses in STh III, q. 48, a. 2: "He properly atones [satisfacit]for an offense who offers something which the offended one loves equally, or even more than he detested the offense." In this article, Aquinas notes three objections to the idea that Christ's passion brings about our salvation by way of atonement. The first objection argues that no one can make compensation for the sins of another. The second objection points out that since crucifying Christ, God incarnate, was the most grievous of all sins, the crucifixion could not atone for this new sin. The third objection holds that Christ's passion is merely one good act, which cannot balance out all sins. Aquinas's answers reveal how he overcomes the legalistic tendency of Anselm's definition by exploring the dynamics of Christ's priesthood. To the first objection, he responds that all who believe in Christ participate in his passion, as members of his mystical body. Repeating an argument previously made in STh 1-11, q. 87, a. 7, he notes that oneness in charity enables the lover to atone for the beloved. To the second, he insists once again that 74 MATfHEW LEVERING Christ's sacrifice should be seen as positive, since Christ, in his human will (perfectly conformed by charity to his divine will), chose freely to atone for our sins. To the third, Aquinas explains that the compensation offered by Christ is not merely the suffering of a particular instance of human nature, but rather the suffering of a human nature hypostatically united to the divine Person of the Logos. It is the hypostatic union which accounts for the perfect virtue of his human soul, and which makes the suffering of his human nature more than sufficient compensation for all sins. II. THE MORAL PRECEPTS Anselm is known for his theory of satisfaction, Abelard for his insistence that charity is the key to Christ's saving work. Aquinas argues that both are right. In this he is again following the Old Testament, which considered love to be the primary element of sacrifice, and indeed of worship. 8 Christ could not have fulfilled the ceremonial precepts without also perfectly fulfilling the moral precepts. The prophets of the Old Law had condemned the Temple sacrifices of their day as mere external forms, undertaken without faith or charity. Aquinas, therefore, is careful to emphasize the role of charity in Christ's sacrifice.9 In STh 11-11, qq. 23-25, Aquinas notes that charity is the movement of the will toward the Divine good as good, "according as it can be apprehended by the intellect" (q. 24, a. 1). The charitable will loves the Divine good for the Divine good's own sake, and loves all human beings insofar as they are referred to this good. As a supernatural virtue, charity is "created" participation in the Holy Spirit, who is Love. No true virtue is possible without charity, since all virtue is ordered to the good, and charity, which is ordered to the ultimate good, is necessary to direct all virtues perfectly towards the good. In this sense 8 See for example Deut 6:5; Lev 19:18; Isa l:llf.; Ps 50:8-13; Sir 34:19-21; Mic 6:7. Aquinas makes clear that although the moral precepts of the Old Law concern "natural" virtues, it is impossible to fulfill the Old Law without the supernatural virtue of charity (cf. STh 1-11, q. 100, a. l; q. 100, a. 10, ad 3). 9 Cf. STh III, q. 47, a. 4, ad 2; q. 48, aa. 2 and 3; q. 49, a. 4. ISRAEL AND AQUINAS'S SOTERIOLOGY 75 charity is called the "form" of all the virtues as well as the "source of merit" for all our acts. Although it might seem that charity is the same in every person who possesses charity, in fact there are various degrees of charity, corresponding to the degree of the person's participation of the Holy Spirit. In STh 11-11, q. 24, a. 8, Aquinas notes that human charity can be called "perfect" in three ways. For our purposes, it will be sufficient to note the highest perfection of human charity, that manifested by Christ. Aquinas explains that the most perfect kind of human charity is reserved for those who are fully united to Christ in heaven. On earth, only Christ displays this most perfect charity, which requires "that a man's whole heart is always actually borne towards God." The grace of the hypostatic union provides Christ with this perfection, which enables his human will always to be in accord with his divine will. In this state of highest human charity, the person is able to "think always actually of God, and to be moved by love towards Him." The connection that Aquinas makes here between always thinking of God and always loving him is highly significant for our purposes. Christ possesses while on earth the most perfect charity possible for man, precisely because of his possession of the beatific vision, which consists of contemplating God always. It is this perfect charity that enables Christ to fulfill perfectly all aspects of the Law. Only Christ's possession of the beatific vision enables him to love perfectly, as man, the ultimate end that his intellect fully apprehends; and thus Christ can fulfill perfectly the ceremonial precepts corresponding to this ultimate end. Likewise, Christ can fulfill perfectly the judicial precepts because he suffers out of charity for each and every man, known to him only by means of the beatific vision. 10 10 Aquinas discusses Christ's beatific knowledge (or contemplative enjoyment of God) in Sfh III, q. 10. In the first article of this question, Aquinas explains how Christ's contemplation (as man) of God includes knowledge of all created things. The soul of Christ knows all things in the Word. For every created intellect knows in the Word, not all simply, but so many more things the more perfectly it sees the Word. Yet no beatified intellect fails to know in the Word whatever pertains to itself. Now to Christ and to His dignity all things to some extent belong, inasmuch as all things are 76 MATIHEW LEVERING Christ's beatific vision, in short, enables him to know perfectly what he is doing, and this knowledge enables him to love perfectly both God and those whom he is reconciling to God. Since Christ knows, as man, how his acts fit into the divine plan, his acts truly express the incarnate manifestation of the love of God. Thus for Aquinas, as for Abelard, the person who meditates upon Christ's passion is able to "[know] thereby how much God loves him, and is thereby stirred to love Him in return, and herein lies the perfection of human salvation" (STh III, q. 46, a. 3). God's movement of love towards us inspires, by the power of the Holy Spirit, a corresponding movement in us towards God. By this love, we appropriate the reconciliation gained for us by Christ's passion. Faith alone does not cleanse from sin; only faith working through love can truly participate in Christ's passion (STh III, q. 49, a. 1, ad 5). Aquinas thus sees Christ's passion as the most complete human expression of charity. Indeed, he argues that even the smallest details of the passion are totally infused by charity. Christ, on the cross, remained always an active Lover, never a passive victim. This activity manifested itself most evidently in his prayer for his persecutors (STh III, q. 47, a. 4, ad 1). Since the perfected soul has complete governance of the body, Aquinas can also hold that Christ's charity governed the very entrance of the nail into his flesh. In Aquinas's view, Christ's charitable will must actually permit the infliction of the wounds of the crucifixion, because subject to Him. Moreover, He has been appointed Judge of all by God, because He is the Son of Man, as is said John v. 27; and therefore the soul of Christ knows in the Word all things existing in whatever time, and the thoughts of men, of which he is the Judge. The knowledge of all things in the Word cannot cause sadness, because all things are, ultimately, ordered fittingly to God. Therefore, charity, which loves all things insofar as they are ordered to the ultimate end, cannot coexist with sadness. Yet a person possessing charity in this life can have sorrow, in the practical intellect, for the temporal disorder of man. In STh 11-11, q. 28, a. 2, ad 1, discussingjoy, Aquinas explains that while the joy of charity cannot be mixed with sorrow, nonetheless in another sense "charity makes us weep with our neighbor in so far as he is hindered from participating in the Divine good." See also Guy Mansini, O.S.B., "St. Thomas on Christ's Knowledge of God," The Thomist 59 Uanuary 1995): 91-124. It should be noted that once we grant the fact of the hypostatic union, the idea that Christ's soul is beatified by this union seems unsurprising. ISRAEL AND AQUINAS'S SOTERIOLOGY 77 Christ's "spirit had the power of preserving his fleshly nature from the infliction of any injury; and Christ's soul had this power, because it was united in unity of person with the Divine Word" (STh III, q. 47, a. 1). Had Christ's soul not had this power, Aquinas suggests, his perfect freedom in submitting to his passion would have been compromised, since he would have lost his freedom at the moment when the soldiers bound him and led him away. In short, Aquinas can truly affirm that "Christ's love was greater than his slayers' malice" (STh III, q. 48, a. 2, ad 2). Although Christ's passion may seem to represent the triumph of sin, it is in fact the triumph of Christ's charitable human will, acting as an instrument of the divine will. In Aquinas's view, therefore, Christ's human will is empowered, by the grace of the hypostatic union, to embody at every moment of his life the love of God for all human beings. As he says in STh III, q. 47, a. 3, ad 3, "The Father delivered up Christ, and Christ surrendered Himself, from charity." Thus Christ, in fulfillment of the moral precepts of the Old Law, willed his death with perfect charity-that is, with complete love for his death's object, known to him by means of the beatific perfection of his human intellect. The necessary conformity between Christ's two wills provides a basis for estimating Christ's psychological state upon the Cross: both his intellect and his will must remain clear and ordered to their object, since intellectual confusion always distorts the will. Finally, by participating in Christ's passion as members of his mystical body, we are conformed to him to such a degree that his moral perfection becomes a true example for us. In STh III, q. 46, a. 3, Aquinas notes that Christ's passion was the most suitable means to achieve the end of man's salvation, first because it revealed God's charity, but second "because thereby He set us an example of obedience, humility, constancy, justice, and the other virtues displayed in the passion, which are requisite for man's salvation." Christ's perfect charity does not therefore make him "superhuman"; rather he becomes the "exemplar," or formal cause, of the holiness which is objectively the ultimate end of every human being. 78 MATIHEW LEVERING III. THE JUDICIAL PRECEPTS Thirdly and lastly, Christ fulfills the Old Law's judicial precepts, that is, those which determine the moral precepts towards our fellow man. In a sense, we have already touched upon the fulfillment of the judicial precepts by discussing how Christ's passion operates according to the modes of "redemption" and "satisfaction." Although God could have redeemed man simply by command, he chose to restore the order of justice by the death of a sinless man, in other words, by a satisfactory sin offering. By this choice, Aquinas argues, God displays "more copious mercy" than he would have had he simply forgiven sins by fiat (STh III, q. 46, a. 1, ad 3), since in Christ's passion, God enabled man to restore the order of justice. Christ, as man, restores justice both between man and God, and between men. "Redemption" and "satisfaction" primarily concern the former, since they are directed to God. However, Christ's satisfactory suffering was also a suffering for all men. He is related to all other men by his suffering, as the one who bears their suffering. In this way, his suffering is the fulfillment of the judicial precepts of the Old Law, which concerned punishment for crime and the rules of exchange. The fulfillment of the judicial precepts, like the fulfillment of the ceremonial and moral precepts, could not have been accomplished by a mere man. In his treatise on the Old Law, Aquinas had explained that some of the judicial precepts call for severe punishment "because a greater sin, other things being equal, deserves greater punishment" (STh I-II, q. 105, a. 2, ad 9). Since Christ suffers for all sins, it is fitting that he undergo the greatest punishment. He is able to do so because his human nature, as the human nature of the Logos, could suffer with more physical and spiritual sensitivity than other men. Therefore, although Christ's "slightest pain would have sufficed to secure man's salvation, because from His Divine Person it would have had infinite virtue" (STh III, q. 46, a. 6, obj. 6; cf. ad 6), Christ fulfilled the judicial precepts by undergoing the greatest suffering. Moreover, in contrast to the limited scope of the actions of a mere man, Christ was able to fulfill the judicial precepts because ISRAEL AND AQUINAS'S SOTERIOLOGY 79 he could direct his suffering to each human being: while suffering our penalty, he contemplated our ultimate end, and referred his suffering to the end of our being united with God. We have already examined why Aquinas holds that Christ must have possessed the beatific vision, even on the cross. Aquinas argues that the hypostatic union would have permanently glorified Christ's soul at the very moment of its creation. This, then, has to be balanced with the fact of Christ's supreme suffering on the cross. Aquinas explains that the higher part of Christ's soul (that is, his speculative intellect) "was not hindered in its proper acts by the lower," and therefore "the higher part of His soul enjoyed fruition perfectly while Christ was suffering" (STh III, q. 46, a. 8). But if Christ's speculative intellect was perfectly serene, how could Christ be said to suffer? Aquinas answers that if by "suffering" one means the confusion of the speculative intellect, then it is true that Christ could not have suffered in this way. According to Aquinas, Christ suffers in two ways. First, he suffers through the sensitive powers of his soul, which apprehend his bodily pain. Second, he suffers in his practical intellect by seeing what is contrary to the love of God, even while his speculative intellect continues to enjoy perfect contemplation of God. As Aquinas explains in STh I, q. 77, a. 3, the intellect is one power, but it has two functions, which may be termed the speculative and the practical intellects. The speculative intellect is concerned with the contemplation of eternal things, the practical intellect with the disposal of temporal things (STh I, q. 79, a. 9). Aquinas uses this psychology to explain Christ's suffering on the cross: Christ "suffered indeed as to all His lower powers; because in all the soul's lower powers, whose operations are but temporal, there was something to be found which was a source of woe to Christ" (STh III, q. 46, a. 7). In contrast, Christ's higher reason or speculative intellect could not experience sadness, because its object is God, who is infinite Goodness. In STh III, q. 46, a. 6, Aquinas details these two aspects of Christ's suffering. The cause of his sensitive pain is evident: the wounding of his body. In contrast, his "interior pain" or "sadness" must have had multiple causes. Aquinas suggests that 80 MATIHEW LEVERING Christ's practical intellect would have experienced acute sadness especially for the sins of humankind; for the sin of those (including his apostles) who betrayed, abandoned, or condemned him; and for his approaching death. Aquinas then argues that Christ's sensitive pain and intellectual sadness were the greatest possible on earth. In this regard, he notes that the sources of Christ's pain were the greatest, because the wounds of the crucifixion afflicted the most sensitive parts of the body, and because Christ grieved for all sins. Second, Christ's body and soul were perfectly made, and so they possessed a greater sensitivity to suffering than any inferior body and soul would po'Ssess.Third, Christ did not allow the higher powers of his soul to soothe the sensitive pain or interior sadness experienced by the lower powers of his soul. Fourth, Christ chose to suffer, "and consequently He embraced the amount of pain proportionate to the magnitude of the fruit which resulted therefrom." He freely willed to endure the greatest suffering, and all classes of suffering (STh III, q. 46, a. 5), in order to make manifest his fulfillment of the judicial precepts. Aquinas is careful to add two caveats. First, although Christ's interior sadness is "the greatest in absolute quantity," his sadness remains governed by the "rule of reason"; that is, the sadness in his lower reason is governed by his higher reason (STh III, q. 46, a. 6, ad 2). Therefore, Christ's sadness is not despairing or estranged from the truth, and so exteriorly it may not have seemed to be the greatest sadness. Interiorly, however, since his sadness is measured by his higher reason's perfect wisdom, his sadness has, of all human suffering, the greatest intensity: "this grief in Christ surpassed all grief of every contrite heart, 11 both because it flowed from a greater wisdom and charity, by which the pang of contrition is intensified, and because He grieved at the one time for all sins, according to Isa. liii. 4: Surely He hath carried our sorrows" (STh III, q. 46, a. 6, ad 4). Aquinas also points out that Christ's grief for his approaching death would, by itself, surpass every other human grief, since Christ's bodily life is that of the Son of God. 11 Guilt does not add any intensity to grief.Thomas points out that although a guilty man "grieves not merely on account of the penalty, but also because of the crime," nonetheless the grief of an innocent man is more intense "by reason of his innocence, insofar as he deems the hurt to be the more undeserved" (STh III, q. 46, a. 6, ad 5). ISRAEL AND AQUINAS'S SOTERIOLOGY 81 Second, Aquinas notes that in order to take on the penalty for our sin, Christ does not need to take on the penalty of eternal suffering, or damnation. The judicial precepts require a punishment proportionate to the sin. Since Christ bears all the sins of this world, his suffering is fittingly the greatest of this world. His suffering does not need to match the suffering of the damned, since their suffering pertains to the next world. As Aquinas states, "The pain of a suffering, separated soul belongs to the state of future condemnation, which exceeds every evil of this life, just as the glory of the saints surpasses every good of the present life" (STh III, q. 46, a. 6, ad 3). Christ could not take on this eternal suffering, since eternal suffering consists precisely in having rejected Christ's passion. This context stands behind Aquinas's interpretation of certain scriptural passages which, when not interpreted in light of Christ's perfect charity, confuse theologians. In STh III, q. 46, a. 4, ad 3, Aquinas gives his interpretation of four such passages: Deuteronomy 21:23 ("He is accursed of God that hangeth on a tree"); 2 Corinthians 5 :21 ("Him that knew no sin, for us He hath made sin"); Galatians 3:13 ("Christ hath redeemed us from the curse of the law, being made a curse for us"); and Romans 8 :3 ("having the resemblance of the flesh of sin"). Following Augustine, he holds that these texts refer to Christ having "become sin" by taking on "the penalty of sin," which is death. God willed that Christ, as man, pay this penalty. On this basis, Aquinas approaches another difficult text. He argues that Christ's words from the Cross, "My God, my God, why hast Thou forsaken me?" (Matt 27:46), are intended to reveal that God could have shielded Christ from the passion, but did not (STh III, q. 4 7, a. 4 ). The cry of abandonment reveals the central truth of the passion: God gave his only Son into the hands of sinners, to be numbered among the guilty. As we have seen, Aquinas teaches that God did this so that the order of justicemight be restored not extrinsically by divine compulsion or fiat, but intrinsically, by enabling man to fulfill the the threefold Law and merit beatitude. Christ receives this complete beatitude in his resurrection, which thus becomes the "formal" cause of our salvation. 82 MATIHEW LEVERING IV. CONCLUSION Aquinas's soteriology belongs among his more important and lasting theological achievements, if only for its articulation of the manifold way in which Christ brings Israel's history to fulfillment. Beginning with the moral precepts of the Old Law (fundamentally the Decalogue, in which Aquinas found the basic tenets of the "natural" law, our rational participation in God's divine wisdom for creation), Aquinas shows how Christ's perfect charity grounded his fulfillment on the cross of the Old Law's ceremonial and judicial precepts, through which he reconciles all things in himself. Aquinas thereby demonstrates the profound unity of the Old Law and the New Law, even while underscoring the infinite newness of the New Law, by which we share in Christ's divine Spirit. Moreover, Aquinas at the same time provides a rich understanding of the relationship between nature and grace: the moral precepts of the Old Law are "natural," but they are fulfilled and elevated to the ultimate end by Christ's supreme charity, a supernatural virtue. Calvary thus represents the transcendent fulfillment not only of Sinai, but also of the order of all creation. Aquinas was able to hold together these elements in a profound and delicate balance. Attending to his example, we should strive to do the same. The Thomist 63 (1999): 83-104 THE BROTHERS OF JESUS AND HIS MOTHER'S VIRGINITY JOSE M. PEDROZO PontificalCollegeJosephinum Columbus, Ohio I N CONNECT! ON WITH his extensive work on the historical Jesus during the last few years, John P. Meier has dealt with the issue of the "brothers and sisters of Jesus" on several occasions. 1 In particular, he has maintained that "from a purely philological and historical point of view, the most probable opinion is that the brothers and sisters of Jesus were his siblings." 2 He has arrived at this opinion from his treatment of the data in the New Testament and "a few noncanonical passages, viewed purely as potential historical sources. "3 In this paper the discussion will center on the latter, postponing a detailed study of the biblical evidence and examining only the relevant noncanonical sources. 4 1 John P. Meier, A MarginalJew: Rethinkingthe HistoricalJesus, vol. 1, The Roots of the Problem and the Person (New York: Doubleday, 1991), 318-32, 354-63. See also the two articles, "The Brothers and Sisters of Jesus in Ecumenical Perspective," Catholic Biblical Quarterly54 (1992): 1-28; and "On Retrojecting Later Questions from Later Texts: A Reply to Richard Bauckharn," Catholic BiblicalQuarterly 59 (1997): 511-27. 2 Meier, A MarginalJew, 332. 3 Cf. Meier, "The Brothers and Sisters of Jesus," 7. 4 For a concise but insightful critique of Meier's methodological and philosophical presuppositions see J. Augustine DiNoia, review of A MarginalJew: Rethinkingthe Historical Jesus, by John P. Meier, Pro &clesia 2 (Winter 1993): 122-25. Also expertly to the point is Joseph T. Lienhard, The Bible, the Church,and Authority (Collegeville, Minn.: The Liturgical Press, 1995), 1-8, who delineates some basic flaws in Meier's biblical method, including the fact that it is not quite as objective as it claims to be (cl. 7). For additional material, see Roch Kereszty, "Historical Research, Theological Inquiry, and the Reality ofjesus: Reflections on the Method of J.P. Meier," Communio 19 (1992): 576-600; Avery Dulles, "Historians and the Reality of Christ," First Things 28 (December 1992): 20-25; and Richard J. Neuhaus, 83 84 JOSE M. PEDROZO Although historical labels are often misleading, I will denote as Epiphanian 5 the notion that "the brothers and sisters of Jesus" were the children of Joseph by a previous marriage. I will denote as Helvidian 6 the opinion that "the brothers and sisters of Jesus" were the natural children of Mary and Joseph after Jesus' birth. By Jeromian 7 I denote the idea that Jesus was Mary's only child, virginally conceived, and that the "brothers and sisters of Jesus" were individuals related to him, not as true half siblings but via close non-filial blood ties to either Mary or Joseph. Meier believes that, in contrast to what he calls the "cousin approach," "both the Epiphanian solution and the view that the 'brothers of Jesus' were real brothers can find supporters in the 2d and 3d centuries." 8 He goes on to assert that "the antiquity "Reason Public and Private: The Pannenberg Project," First Things 21(March1992): 55-60. Kereszty observes that "if Meier had more 'empathy' for the biblical meaning of Mary's virginity as a definitive consecration of her body-person by the Holy Spirit, he would not be so selective in evaluating the biblical evidence" ("Historical Research," 597 n. 33). 5 After St. Epiphanius, bishop of Salamis (ca. 315-403), who opposed the antidikomariamitoi, a heretical sect in Arabia that denied Mary's virginity postpartum. Cf. Epiphanius, Panarion 78 (GCS 37:452-75); and Augustine, De haeresibus 56 (CCL46:325). 6 After the layman Helvidius who around 383 espoused the idea in Rome. Cf. Augustine, De haeresibus 84 (CCL 46:338). 7 After St. Jerome (331 ?--420) who defended Mary's perpetual virginity against Helvidius. Cf. Jerome, De perpetua virginitate beatae Mariae adversus Helvidium (PL 23:193-216). 8 Meier,A Marginal Jew, 329. The label "the cousin approach" is misleading. First of all, the argument is not that "brother" means "cousin." The argument is that, in the special case of Jesus, the term "brother" does not necessarily denote "blood brother." Secondly, no one in the early Church held the Epiphanian view and argued against aJeromian interpretation. The question was, did Mary and Joseph have children after Jesus' birth? Historically, it is more accurate to differentiate only between those who held Mary's virginity postpartum and those who held the Helvidian position. To say the Epiphanian view enjoyed support is equivalent to the assertion that the doctrine of Mary's virginity postpartum enjoyed support. Theological reflection on the virginity of Joseph was a development that simply had not occurred. During the first three centuries of the Church Christ's origins were widely challenged, his true humanity as well as his true divinity. From this point of view, it should not be surprising that the focus would be on Jesus' virginal conception and his true birth ex Maria, and less on her virginity postpartum and in partu, let alone the virginity of Joseph (a teaching not de fide, however true). Even in the fourth century, around 360, Eunomius of Cyzicus-bishop and leader of those who advocated the anomoios (the Son is "unlike" the Father) and denied the homoousios-attacked Mary's perpetual virginity in a sermon delivered on the feast of the Epiphany (d. J. Bidez, Philostorgus Kirchengeschichte 6.2 [GCS 21:71]). In another sermon ascribed to Basil of Caesarea, who supposedly answered that attack, it is proclaimed that "the lovers of Christ [philochristot] cannot bear to hear that the THE BROTHERS OF JESUS 85 and spread of the opinion that the brothers of Jesus were real brothers are often overlooked by supporters of the cousin approach. " 9 I will argue that this claim of "antiquity" and "spread" of the Helvidian opinion is an inaccurate estimation at best. Moreover, the implication that the Helvidian opinion had a genuine place in the tradition of the early Church is untenable. Although the explicit evidence in favor of Mary's virginity post partum is indeed very sparse, to assert that this doctrine had a fragile basis prior to the fourth century is quite misleading. 10 I will show for example that the lack of pre-Nicene testimony in favor of Mary's virginity post partum is not unlike that of other doctrines even more fundamental in the hierarchia veritatum. Certainly, the doctrine of Mary's perpetual virginity was not "thought up" 11 by Jerome and defended by him and other ascetics of the fourth century to justify the notion of the superiority of virginity over marriage and their "pessimistic" evaluation of human sexuality. 12 In fact, it is the Helvidian opinion that cannot Theotokos ever ceased to be a virgin" (seeln Christigenerationem[PG 41: 1468]). From other indications in the text, however, it is clear that Christ's divinity was the principal issue at stake. 9 Meier, A MarginalJew, 329. 10 Cf. ibid. See also David G. Hunter, "Helvidius, Jovinian, and the Virginity of Mary in Late Fourth Century Rome," Journal of Early ChristianStudies 1 (1993): 69. 11 Cf. Meier, A Marginal Jew, 324. 12 Cf. Hunter, "Helvidius, Jovinian, and the Virginity of Mary," 68. Hunter views the Protoevangeliumof James (known to Origen as the Book of James) as "the ultimate source of almost all later Marian doctrine" (63). He casts doubt on the veracity of Mary's perpetual virginity by associating it with "Encratite or Origenist accounts of the origin of sin and sexuality" (69). Evidently, he thinks that this doctrine represents "faulty notions of sin, sexuality and the church" (47). He seems to recognize that the Book of James had as its primary objective the defense of Mary's perpetual virginity from calumnies corning from certain Jewish and pagan circles that impugned not only the virginal conception, but also her marital chastity (see 63 and n. 66). But he seems to forget this fact and assumes a connection this work may or may not have with marginal or heretical sects such as the Encratites. The truth of the matter is that the insistence on Mary's virginity in the Book of fames represents a popular response to the vulgar slanders of that era referring to Jesus' illegitimate birth and Mary's marital infidelities. That Jesus was the son of a prostitute (quaestuiaria)was a common slander. (Cf. Tertullian, De spectaculis30.6 [CCL 1:253]: "Hie est ille, dicam, fabri aut quaestuariae filius, sabbati destructor, Samarites et daemonium habens; hie est quern a Iuda redernistis. ") In Jewish legend, Jesus was denoted as the illegitimate son of a married woman (Miriam the hairdresser), who, to top it off, had been unfaithful to her husband with a member of the oppressor's legionary forces (the soldier Panthera, so Jesus was ben panthera, 86 JOSE M. PEDROZO find one single explicit witness prior to the fourth century. 13 I Let us proceed to examine in detail the first noncanonical source. Hegesippus seems to have been a second-century Hellenistic Jew who converted to Christianity. His testimony is found only in fragments in Eusebius's Ecclesiastical History. We can gather from the text of Eccl. Hist. 4.22.2-3 that Hegesippus visited Rome during the time of Pope Anicetus (155-56) and remained there at least until the time of Pope Eleutherus (174-89). Meier stresses that he does not accept all of what perhaps a play on words for ben parthenos). Cf. S. Kraus, "Jesus of Nazareth," in The Jewish Encyclopedia (New York: KTAV Publishing House, n.d.), 7:170-73. Thus, there are no objective reasons to assume that the Book "of fames represented Encratite distortions of human sexuality. Moreover, Hunter's insinuation that second-century belief in Mary's perpetual virginity, popularly expressed in that book, was limited to Encratite circles is also mere speculation. Hunter also casts doubt on Origen's witness by associating his belief in Mary's perpetual virginity with the notion that "all sexual relations were somehow contaminating" (68). There is no doubt that Origen (and Jerome, Ambrose, Augustine, et al.) linked original sin to the act of human generation. In this sense sexual relations are "contaminating." If this is a "pessimistic" view of human sexual relations, so be it. But what is striking about Hunter's argument is the underlying assumption that this belief was held, not because it is true in itself, but because it was necessary to support other preconceived notions. Hunter's insinuation is that Origen held that Jesus was Mary's only child, virginally conceived, not because it is true, but because Origen's notions of defilement in sexual intercourse and original sin required it (68). In other words, Origen had to create a historical falsehood (e.g., Mary's perpetual virginity) to fit his preconceived notions on human sexuality and sin (e.g., that a child who is born through sexual intercourse is tainted with original sin). This is tantamount to ascribing to Origen a fundamental lack of intellectual integrity that would be appalling. An alternative, which is more consonant with what we know about Origen's character and scholarly qualities, must be considered: namely, that Origen simply knew and truly believedJesus was Mary's only child, virginally conceived, and that from this truth he theologized about things such as original sin and human sexuality, arriving at some conclusions that perhaps some would find questionable today. 13 Hunter concludes that "when Helvidius cited the evidence of scripture and the tradition of the Western church regarding Mary's other children, he had a legitimate argument which Jerome, for all his efforts, could not deny" (" Helvidius, Jovinian, and the Virginity of Mary," 70; emphasis added). Since Hunter has in mind by "the tradition of the Western church" the same sources available to Helvidius, presumably he means Tertullian and Victorin us of Pettau, the only two witnesses Helvidius could marshal for his case. It is surely an exaggeration to characterize the ambiguous testimony of two individuals (Victorinus' text is not even extant} as "the tradition of the Western church regarding Mary's other children." THE BROTHERS OF JESUS 87 Hegesippus says as historically true, but he adds that Hegesippus is "capable of distinguishing carefully between the brother, the uncle and the cousin of Jesus." 14 Meier seems to think that the simple use of the terms "cousin" and "uncle" in Eccl. Hist. 4.22.4 and the denotation of James as "the brother of the Lord" in Eccl. Hist. 2.23.4 (two texts from different contexts) are sufficient to validate his point of view. Let us look more closely at one of the texts in question: Kai µETcl TO TOY lHKalOV we; Kai 0 KUptoc; foi T4' auT4J AcSyqi ndA1v o EK 9dou mhou o wu K.Awna Ka9fomm1 fo(aKonoc; ov npoe9EvTonavTE<; ovm avEljnov Tou Kupwu (And after James the Just had been martyred for the same reason as the Lord, in turn Symeon [of Clopas, his uncle] was aypointed bishop whom they all proposed being a second cousin of the Lord.) 1 The situation seems evident. James the Just-who is known in the New Testament as "the brother of the Lord" (cf. Gal 1:19)-has been martyred. To replace him as bishop of Jerusalem, Symeon (or Simon), son of Clopas, is proposed. And why is Symeon proposed to succeed James? Symeon is proposed because he is a second cousin of the Lord. That is, second with respect to another, 16 namely James, the only other possibility. In other words, James who is known to Hegesippus as "the brother of the Lord" is also one of two cousins of Jesus who have been the first two bishops of Jerusalem. For Hegesippus, therefore, James is clearly not a true sibling of Jesus, even if he is denoted as "brother of the Lord." Note also that Symeon is not really a blood relative of Jesus. Interestingly, Symeon is denoted not only as cousin, but 14 Meier, A Marginal Jew, 329. 15 Eusebius, &clesiastical History 4.22.4 (GCS 9.1:370). Cf. Josef Blinzler, Die Briider und SchwesternJesu, Stuttgarter Bibelstudien 21 (Stuttgart, 1967), 105-8. 16 deuteros of course means second as a point of order or rank as well as a second of two (i.e., another). Note that the accusative deuteron should modify anepsion and not the nominative episkopos. Compare Hegessipus in Eccl. Hist. 4.22.4 with Eusebius in Eccl. Hist. 3.32.1 where deuteron does modify episkopon. Notice how Hegessipus emphasizes the reason for the election of Symeon while Eusebius simply recounts how Symeon "who had been appointed second bishop of the church at Jerusalem" (on deuteron katastenai tes en Ierosolymois ekklesias episkopon) was martyred, apparently during the reign of Trajan, nearly four decades after James. 88 JOSE M. PEDROZO also as a so-called cousin (cf. Eccl. Hist. 3 .11.1 ). Let us also observe that Hegesippus denotes Clopas as "his uncle." In the translation above, the brackets indicate that it is not clear whether Hegesippus means to say that Clopas is the Lord's uncle or James's uncle. However, in two other passages (Eccl. Hist. 3.32.6 and 3.11.1), Hegesippus identifies Clopas as "uncle of the Lord" (theiou tou kyriou) and as "brother of Joseph" (adelphon tou Ioseph), respectively. If Hegesippus really thought that James and Jesus were blood brothers, then it would have been natural to denote Clopas as "their uncle" and not simply as "his uncle" when he used both names ("James" and "the Lord") in the same sentence. For if James was a blood brother of Jesus (i.e., a son of Joseph and Mary), then Clopas as a brother of Joseph was a true uncle of James. Using Hegesippus's testimony there is some further evidence to be considered, independently of this passage and its translation. It involves particular qualifiers used whenever an individual is identified as a "brother" of Jesus. Meier asserts: Since Hegesippus knows perfectly well how to apply the words "cousin" and "uncle" to specific relatives of Jesus, it becomes extremely difficult to claim that a precise phrase like "brother of the Lord according to the flesh" really means "cousin," or simply refers to spiritual as opposed to physical brotherhood. 17 Meier obviously considers Hegesippus's denotation of Judas as "the brother of the Savior according to the flesh" an unambiguous indication that Judas is a blood brother of Jesus. He considers other explanations "desperation attempts at explaining away" the phrase kata sarka.18 But once again he skirts over a very significant point. Judas is equally denoted by Hegesippus as he who is "said to have been his brother [of the Lord] according to the flesh" (kata sarka legomenouautou adelphou [Eccl. Hist. 3.20.1]). Eusebius himself denotes Judas as "the so-called brother of the Savior" (ton pheromenon adelphon tou soteros [Eccl. Hist. 3.32.5]) and as he "who is said to be the brother of the Savior" Jew, 330. 17 Meier, A Marginal 18 Cf. ibid., 361 n. 42 and following. THE BROTHERS OF JESUS 89 (touton d'einai adelphon kata sarka tou soteros [Eccl. Hist. 3.19.1]). Similarly, according to Eusebius, James is he "who was called or said to have been the brother of the Lord" and he "who was named a child of Joseph" (tou kyriou legomenon adelphon and tou Joseph onomasto pais [Eccl. Hist. 2.1.2]). Meier is aware of at least some of these phrases. 19 But he does not draw the dear conclusion that by these expressions Hegesippus (and Eusebius) are indicating that they do not consider Judas to be a blood brother of Jesus but only "so-called." 20 That the unqualified term "brother" is used equally with the qualified term seems to indicate that for these authors the phrase "brother of Jesus" did not denote a true blood brother of Jesus. In general, among extant early Christian literature it seems there are no examples in which a particular person is identified as a "brother" of Jesus without some of the qualifiers we have discussed above also arising. Such "philological" observations are at odds with Meier's assessment of probabilities. 21 19 Meier, "Later Questions from Later Texts," 524 n. 27. 20 Similarly, Eusebius clearly considers James to be a so-called brother of Jesus. I have maintained a distinction between statements from Eusebius and statements from Hegesippus to avoid any charge of uncritically mixing texts (cf. Meier, "The Brothers and Sisters of Jesus," 23 n. 42). 21 As another example, what is the probability that Mary the mother of James and Joseph in Matt 27 :56 is not the mother of two of the four "brothers" ofjesus listed as James, Joseph, Symeon and Judas in Matt 13:56? Meier alludes to the modern insights of redaction criticism and narrative criticism. He asserts that "most likely" the name identification between Mark 6:3 and Mark 15:40 should not be made because the phrase "the Small" (ho mikros) modifying the name James in Mark 15:40 does not occur in Mark 6:3. Meier does not consider a possible identification between Matt 27:56 and Matt 13:56 where that particular redaction difficulty does not occur presumably because of the commonly assumed dependence of Matthew on Mark (cf. Meier, "The Brothers and Sisters of Jesus," 11 n. 21). But by comparing the names of the women listed in Mark 15:40 (Mary Magdalen, Salome, and Mary the mother of James the Less and Joseph) with those listed in Mark 16:1 (Mary Magdalen, Salome, and Mary [mother] of James), it seems highly probable this James could be identified as one of those listed as "brothers" of Jesus. Clearly, he would not a blood brother of Jesus, although his mother is also named Mary. We also could ask, what is the probability that Symeon of Clopas, who has been identified as a close relative of Jesus and as a significant figure in the early Christian community, is not the Symeon listed in the Gospels as a brother of Jesus? Already, Eusebius indicates the possible connection (cf. &cl. Hist. 3.11.1). James and Judas. known to have been significant figures in the Christian community, are mentioned as "brothers" in the Gospels. Why would the Gospels have mentioned a blood brother of Jesus called Symeon with no known historical 90 JOSE M. PEDROZO II Let us now address the testimony of Tertullian, who is often considered to be a dear witness against Mary's virginity post partum. 22 With Tertullian, however, we have a similar problem as with the New Testament evidence. That is, we can try to decipher what he means to say whenever he deals with the New Testament texts that mention the "brothers" of Jesus or whenever he discusses a relevant topic such as virginity or marriage. 23 T ertullian, however, never asserts explicitly that Mary and Joseph had children of their own. This is somewhat remarkable if one considers that the existence of a group of men and women, born from the same womb as Jesus was born, would have provided T ertullian with an effective and elegant rhetorical weapon against his Docetist adversaries. It seems unlikely that an accomplished polemicist like T ertullian would have missed the opportunity to use that weapon in a very explicit manner. 24 Hunter observes that Tertullian nowhere attacks Mary's post partum virginity explicitly. He adds, "indeed, he seems to show no awareness that such idea existed at all. " 25 He wants to make an argument from silence. But arguments from silence are notorious for begging the question. If T ertullian seems to show no awareness of Mary's virginity postpartum, it does not follow that the Helvidian opinion must have been widely held. significance? Is it also a coincidence that Maty of Clopas is mentioned quite distinctively in the gospel (cf. John 19:25)? On the other hand, what is the probability that the testimony of Flavius Josephus provides anything new? Meier assigns great significance to his witness. But that Josephus denotes James as a "brother of Jesus" is perfectly consonant with the fact that at this time James, the most prominent figure in the Jerusalem Christian community, was well known as "the brother of the Lord." Obviously a nonbeliever is not going to call Jesus Lord. Unless one assumes that Josephus took the time to inquire into the exact family tree of an "insignificant" Jew crucified over thirty years before, his testimony provides nothing new. 22 Cf.J. Quasten,Patrology, vol.2 (Westminster, Md.: Christian Oassics, 1994),329. See also Eamon R. Carroll, "Our Lady's Virginity postpartum," Marian Studies 7 (1956): 78. 23 The relevant texts from Tertullian are: AdversusMarcionem 4.19 (CCL 1:592-94); De monogamia 8.1-3 (CCL 2:1239); De came Christi 7 (CCL 2:886-89); De came Christi 23 (CCL 2:914-15); and De virginibusvelandis 6.2-3 (CCL 2:1215-16). 24 Cf. John McHugh, The Mother of Jesus in the New Testament (Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday, 1975), 458-60. 25 Hunter, "Helvidius,Jovinian, and the Virginity of Maty," 66. THE BROTHERS OF JESUS 91 By way of comparison, the divinity of the Holy Spirit (obviously a very foundational doctrine of the Christian faith) can barely count on one witness prior to 360. 26 Before then, only Origen had developed a significant pneumatology, even if it is not free from some ambiguities by post-Nicene standards. Despite the fact that he dealt at some length with the Trinity, Tertullian-a great contributor to the Trinitarian language of the Latin Church-did not write on the Holy Spirit per se in any systematic way. And apropos, Tertullian provides some "embarrassing patristic evidence" 27 when he calls the "word of God" (sermo Dei), which he equates with the Spiritus Dei, "a portion of the whole" (portio aliqua totius). 28 The main point is that explicit testimony on the Person, the divinity, and the consubstantiality of the Holy Spirit with the Father and the Son is remarkably sparse prior to the second half of the fourth century. It does not follow, however, that the tropikoi or the pneumatomachoi were the genuine bearers of a more ancient and widely held tradition in the Church. 29 Nor does it follow that the aforementioned teachings on the Holy Spirit-previously not part of the pre-Nicene literature-were post-Nicene "thought up" doctrines of Athanasius et al. The correct conclusion is that before the fourth century these teachings had not been seriously called into question and thus they had not taken up much space in the pre-Nicene literature. Even the symbol of Nicea limited itself to the plain assertion, "[we believe] in the Holy Spirit." But with the increasing number of challenges to the divinity of the Holy Spirit up until the council of Constantinople in 381, pneumatological 26 Around 360 Athanasius wrote the Epistolae ad Serapionein (PG 26:529-676), which can be considered to be the first treatise on the Holy Spirit. 27 Cf. Meier,A Marginal Jew, 362 n. 43. This is an epithet Meier uses when referring to those who defend Mary's virginity postpartum in view of Tertullian's witness, which in his opinion is clearly against it. 28 Cf. Adversus Praxean, 26.6 (CCL 2: 1197). 29 Tropikoi is the term Athanasius used to describe those who Serapion had informed him were questioning the divinity of the Holy Spirit, interpreting texts such as Amos 4: 13; Zech 1:9; and 1Tim5:21 in a tropical (i.e., figurative) manner. Cf. Ad Serapionem 1.10 (PG 26: 556B), the paragraph where I found the term tropikoi used for the first time. Basil of against the Spirit") to characterize those Caesarea uses the term pneumatomachoi who denied the consubstantiality of the Holy Spirit with the Father and the Son. Cf. Basil, On the Holy Spirit 11.27 (SC 17:340), a treatise written in 376. 92 JOSE M. PEDROZO treatises became relatively abundant. Shortly before that time, in addition to Basil, Gregory of Nazianzus, Didymus the Blind, and Ambrose of Milan wrote important works on the Holy Spirit. 30 In summary, despite the lack of pre-Nicene evidence, it would be a mistake to say that belief and reflection on the divinity of the Holy Spirit had a "fragile basis" prior to the fourth century. As Henri Crouzel has observed, that would be the same mistake "that a historian of the 21st century would make if he attempted to write the history of a period in the 20th century relying solely and uncritically on newspapers that favoured the sensational at the expense of the ordinary facts of every day life. " 31 The history of the doctrine of Mary's virginity postpartum is perfectly analogous. Until the fourth century, it had been a relatively unchallenged doctrine and thus the pre-Nicene literature is quite sparse. Among early Christian writers, only Origen can be said to have developed a significant "Mariology." Other available testimony left many questions unanswered. But once the doctrine was seriously challenged, it was defended and widely upheld. In fact, although Jerome is the only author who wrote a separate tract on Mary's virginity-the pamphlet against Helvidius--every Father of the Church in the fourth century who addressed the issue of the "brothers of Jesus" upheld Mary's virginity post partum. 32 As I have noted previously, Tertullian is often considered to be a witness against Mary's virginity post partum, even by some scholars who defend this teaching. But the fact is that Tertullian 30 See Gregory of Nazianzus, Oratio 31, theologica quinta (PG 36:133-72), written around 380; Didymus the Blind, On the Holy Spirit (SC 386), written certainly before 380; and Ambrose, On the Holy Spirit (CSEL 79:15-222), written in 381. 31 Henri Crouzel, Origen, trans. A. S. Worrall (Edinburgh: T & T. Clark, 1989), 198. The witness of other authors like Irenaeus is extremely reserved. Their pneumatological testimony-in much the same way as their Mariological testimony-left many questions unresolved. 32 Athanasius, Hilary, Ephraem, John Chrysostom, Ambrose, Basil, Gregory of Nazianzus, Jerome, Augustine, and Cyril of Alexandria-all of them designated in the Catholic Church as not only as Fathers, but also as Doctors--clearly taught Mary's virginity postpartum. There were several other Fathers such as Epiphanius, Gregory of Nyssa, Didymus the Blind, and Zeno of Verona who also clearly upheld Mary's virginity postpartum. One would be hard pressed to find a doctrine that elicited a clearer consensus (no Father ever opposed it). THE BROTHERS OF JESUS 93 could be interpreted differently. 33 As an example, let us analyze the text of De monogamia 8 .1-3. First of all, he is arguing against the remarriage of widows. To achieve Christian holiness, he believes, there are two options to follow: monogamia or continentia. He proceeds by developing an analogy between Zechariah and his son John the Baptist as representatives of these two options: "monogamia et continentia, alia pudica in Zacharia sacerdote, alia integra in Ioanne antecursore, alia placans Deum, alia praedicans Christum, alia totum praedicans sacerdotem, alia plus praeferens quam propheten." According to Tertullian, one should either be monogamous like Zechariah or remain unmarried like John the Baptist (and of course, in this case a Christian would be bound to practice continence). But the emphasis is on being married only once. Notice that the term used by Tertullian is continentia, not virginitas. In a sense, virginity has only an incidental character in this analogy. T ertullian adds that, due to Christ's holiness, it was appropriate that he was born of a woman who was both a virgin and married only once (uirgine et uniuira). This is all that Tertullian is saying. Meier assumes that since married people usually are not perpetually continent, then sexual intercourse and childbearing must have followed in the case of Mary and Joseph. But there is no reason to assume this from the text itself. That Mary must have had children is obvious to Meier by the fact that Zechariah himself had a son. But this is an irrelevant observation since only Zechariah's monogamous status is at issue in Tertullian's argument. His particular emphasis is revealed further when he mentions Anna, the female prophet in the temple (cf. Luke 2:36), who was uidua et uniuira. For T ertullian, it is irrelevant whether she had children or not. He is only interested in pointing out that Anna was married, that she became a widow, and that she remained a widow. Therefore, unless one begs the question by assuming what must be shown, this text of the De monogamia-and similarly the other four aforementioned texts from T ertullian--cannot be used as proof of Tertullian's denial of Mary's virginity postpartum. In fact, in the present example one could press the analogy in the other 33 Cf. McHugh, The Mother of Jesus in the New Testament, 448-50. 94 JOSE M. PEDROZO direction. It could imply that Mary belongs to both groups (continent and monogamous) permanently. After all, Tertullian compares Mary's virginity directly to John the Baptist's virginity (he does not compare Zechariah directly with Mary). Meier writes: "It is sad to see so fine a scholar as Blinzler (Die Brader, 139-41) strain to water down or make ambiguous what Tertullian clearly says." 34 But a careful reading of the Adversus Marcionem 4.19 (in Meier's opinion, the strongest evidence against Mary's virginity postpartum) rejects Meier's insinuation that one compromises intellectual integrity by insisting that this long text says nothing conclusive against that teaching. 35 Even if we grant that Tertullian denied Mary's virginity post partum, it would still not follow that the Helvidian opinion must have been widely held. Tertullian often rejected doctrines and customs held by orthodox Christians of his time. For instance, his purpose in writing theApologeticum (perhaps his most important work, written well before he joined the radical Montanists) was to convince the Roman government officials of the usefulness of Christian citizens to the state. 36 But by 207, Tertullian seems to be obsessed with the idea of Christians participating together with pagans in civic affairs and succumbing to idolatry as a consequence of that relationship. This real or perceived danger led T ertullian to condemn customs that his contemporaries held as perfectly legitimate. He even condemned Christian involvement Meier, A Marginal Jew, 362 n. 43. also asserts that the fact that Mary bore children to Joseph is implied in De came Christi 23, more clearly in De monogamia 8, and explicitly in Ad.versus Marcionem 4.19. Cf. "Helvidius, Jovinian, and the Virginity of Mary," 66 and 66 n. 77. However, the fact of the matter is that in the De came Christi 23 there are no statements for or against Mary's virginity beyond the birth of Christ. The brothers of Jesus are not even mentioned. Tertullian simply affirms that Mary was a virgin mother. His expression "uirgo, quantum a uiro, non uirgo, quantum a partu" reflects his anti-docetist agenda. Nothing beyond the birth of Christ is considered. The text of the De monogamia I have alreadyshown to be inconclusive at best. In theAdversus Marcionem 4 .19, T ertullian does indeed answer the Marcionites about their interpretation of Matt 12:48 by arguing that the meaning of the text is that Jesus prefers the relationship of faith to one of blood. But once again, only by assuming what needs to be shown-namely, that the brothers of Jesus are children of Mary--can one conclude that Tertullian's rhetorical statements constitute an explicit assertion against Mary's virginity postpartum. 36 Apologeticum (CCL 1:85-171). 34 35 Cf. ibid. Hunter THE BROTHERS OF JESUS 95 in professions such as school teacher and especially teacher of literature. 37 We also have, as witnessed by his De monogamia, Tertullian's denial of the legitimacy of the remarriage of widows, contrary to the dear orthopraxis of the Church, which has always praised widowhood, but has never prohibited second nuptials to widows among the laity. III Let us turn to the last patristic source Meier discusses: Irenaeus and the so-called adhuc texts found in Adversushaereses,3 .21.10 and 3.22.4. Over six decades ago Hugo Koch attempted to reconstruct the teaching of Mary's perpetual virginity from an "original" historical form, which he theorized had passed through several revisions, until the doctrine found its final form in the fourth century. 38 This original historical form had Jesus as the eldest son among many children of Mary and Joseph. Later, the myth of a virginal conception was introduced, forcing Joseph to be presented only as the foster father of Jesus, and the idea of post partum virginity forced the explanation that the brothers and sisters of Jesus were Joseph's children from a previous marriage. Finally, the ideas of Mary's virginity in partu and the virginity of Joseph were added in the fourth century, under the influence of extreme ascetical ideals. 39 Koch's use of the adhuc texts to press his argument suffered from one major deficiency, which one finds again in Meier's argument. In the texts in question, neither the words nor the terms of comparison go beyond the Incarnation and the virgin birth. Irenaeus's analogy between Virgo Eva and Virgo Maria has no connection whatsoever with the issue of the 37 Cf. De idololatria, 10 (CCL 2:1109-10). 38 For the original argument see H. Koch, Adhuc Viigo. MariensJungfrauscbaftund Ebe in der alterkircblincben Uberlieferungbis zum Ende des vierten ]ahrbunderts (Tiibingen, 1929); and also his follow-up Vngo Eva-Viigo Maria. Neue Untersucbungenuber die Lebre von der Jungfrauscbaftund der Ebe Mariens in der iiltesten IGrcbe (Berlin-Leipzig, 1937), 17-60. 39 Cf. E. R. Carroll, "Our Lady's Virginity postpartum," Marian Studies 7 (1956): 77-79; see 79 n. 20 for a list of critical responses to Koch's work at that time. See also A. Eberle, TbeologiscbeRevue 29 (1930): 153-55. 96 JOSE M. PEDROZO "brothers" of Jesus. In the long text of Adversus haereses3 .22.4 40 the analogy centers on the obedience (obaudiens) of the virgin Mary and the disobedience (inobaudiens) of the virgin Eve. To the divine commandment, the virgin Mary responded per (idem ("behold, I am the handmaid of the Lord ... ") while the virgin Eve responded per incredulitatem (that is, not believing the prohibition of Gen 2: 17). It is hardly ever noticed that Irenaeus develops the analogy even further in Adversus haereses 5.19.1. There, the virgin Eve is seduced (seducta)by the word of the (evil) angel to escape from God (effugereDeum ), disobeying his Word, while the virgin Mary is evangelized (evangelizata)through the word of the (good) angel to carry God (portare Deum), obeying his Word. 41 Irenaeus continues by noting that Eve was still a virgin ("adhuc erat uirgo") at the moment she received God's commandment to abstain from the tree of knowledge of good and evil. Thus, upon her disobedience she became a cause of death, not only for herself but also for the entire human race ("et sibi et uniuerso generi causa facta est morris"), as mother of all humanity. This is the only significance of virginity in the analogy. That is, if Eve had obeyed while still a virgin (i.e., while no member of the human had yet been born), then she would have become (as Mary did) a cause of salvation for herself and for the entire human race ("et sibi et uniuerso generi causa facta est salutis"). Instead, Eve disobeyed and became, ironically, the mother of all the dead (in sin obviously). By her obedience, Mary, "adhuc erat uirgo," becomes the mother of all the living, because she is the mother of the Firstborn from the dead who regenerates them to the life of God ("primogenitus enim mortuorum natus Dominus et in sinum suum recipiens pristinos patres regenerauit eos in uitam Dei"). Christ becomes the beginning of the living as Adam became the beginning of the dead ("initium uiuentium factus quoniam Adam initium morientium factus est"). It should be evident that the phrase "adhuc erat uirgo" when applied to Mary in the context 40 See Irenee de Lyon, Cantre les Heresies, Livre 3, SC 34 (Paris: Editions du Cerf, 1952). The Latin texts of 3.22.4 and 3.21.4 quoted throughout are taken from this edition. 41 See Irenee de Lyon, Cantre les Heresies, Livre 5, SC 153 (Paris: Editions du Cerf, 1969), 249-53. THE BROTHERS OF JESUS 97 of this analogy has absolutely nothing to do with sexuality per se, let alone Mary's virginity post partum. The parallel between Virgo Eva and Virgo Maria in Irenaeus's soteriology of recapitulation in Christ intends to say nothing about Mary's virginity beyond the virgin birth. 42 The text of Adversus haereses 3.21.10 is shorter than 3.22.4 but very similar. Irenaeus's analogy begins with the observation that the first Adam had no human father and neither did the second Adam. The first Adam was made from the earth by the hand of God. The second Adam was also from the hand of God. But unlike the first Adam, he is born from a woman, from a "virgin." In his recapitulation scheme Irenaeus finds a somewhat forced parallel. The first Adam is also born from a "virgin," the red earth ("de rudi terra") which is still (adhuc) "virgin" when the first Adam is created, since God has not rained upon the earth and man has not worked it ("nondum enim pluerat Deus et homo non erat operatus terram"). There is no other reason even to mention virginity. Since Adam himself is considered a possible cause for the earth to lose her "virginity" once it is worked by him (even though he himself comes from the "virgin" earth), to press the term adhuc in the analogy with respect to the Virgin Mary is patently absurd. In summary, to claim these two texts as possible witnesses against Mary's postpartum virginity by focusing on words such as adhuc and uirgo is simply to do violence to the texts and to their context. Irenaeus's soteriology of recapitulation in Christ has nothing to do with Mary's virginity postpartum. Even Meier shows himself to be somewhat tentative when he writes: "Since every analogy limps, it is difficult to say how far Irenaeus's analogy should be pressed. "43 But it is not a matter of pressing an 42 It should be noted that Irenaeus assigns to Eve a physical causality of death for the human race. But he does not lose track in the analogy that it is Adam who is the responsible cause. Cf. Antonio Orbe, Antropologfa de San Ireneo (Madrid: Biblioteca de Autores Cristianos, 1969), 247. 43 Meier, A Marginal few, 331. In his "Later Questions from Later Texts," 525, Meier asserts: "Irenaeus' statements are ambiguous, but I think it more likely than not that they point in the direction of the Helvidian solution." As I have shown, this assertion has no basis in the texts. For more details, see the masterful exposition of Orbe, Antropologfade San Ireneo, esp. 244-53. It is significant that, despite his anti-docetist concerns, Irenaeus is a 98 JOSE M. PEDROZO analogy that limps or that lrenaeus's statements are ambiguous. The fact of the matter is that Irenaeus is quite clear in his analogy; he is simply not saying what Meier claims. IV Although Meier considered the witness of T ertullian (born ca. 155), he omits any reference to Origen (born ca. 185). But Origen's testimony cannot be omitted in a serious treattnent of the subject. As Henri Crouzel has noted, [Origen] was the first theologian clearly to teach the perpetual virginity of Mary, for the writers of the 2nd century, like Justin and Irenaeus, only did so implicitly by calling her Mary the Virgin. For Origen this is by no means, as has been suggested, an open question, with no obligation on the Christian to believe it: it is the only "healthy" view of the matter and that word is used to express a close connection with the faith; those who uphold the contrary are treated as heretics; Mary among women is the first fruits of virginity as Jesus is among men. 44 This paragraph brings out at least two important points. First, Meier gives no historical or philological significance to the fact that in early Christian literature Mary is called "the virgin," beyond the immediate context of the virginal conception and birth of Christ. 45 Second, Meier implies that the Helvidian witness for Mary's virginity in partu. Cf. Demonstratio apost. praed. 54 (Patrologia Orienta/is 12.5:700): "Praetera de nativitate eius propheta alibi nce a close friend but later an acerbic critic-can find nothing worse to say about Jerome's translation of Origen's homilies on Luke than that he adds the words "and nature" to Origen's term "substance." Jerome also leaves intact "passagesthat would be theologically problematic to him, such as Origen's reference to Mary and Joseph's imperfect faith (Hom. 20.4)" (Origen, Homilies on Luke, Fragments on Luke, trans. Joseph T. Lienhard [Washington: The Catholic University of America Press, 1996], xxxvi). 60 Some notable adversaries of Jerome did not think much of the Helvidian opinion either. Pelagius in his Ad Galatas, 19 (PLS 1:1273) writes: "Contra eos qui dicunt beatam Mariam alios filios habuisse, quia duos Iacobos apostolos fuisse legimus, unum Alphaei et alterum Zebedaei, neminem Mariae vel Ioseph, sed fratres Domini de propinquitate dicuntur." Note that Pelagius seems to identify James the Just with James of Zebedee or James of Alphaeus. The Thomist 63 (1999): 105-24 THE RELATION OF CULTURE AND IGNORANCE TO CULPABILITYIN THOMAS AQUINAS GREGORY DOOLAN The Catholic Universityof America Washington,D.C. I N BOTH THE De Malo and the Summa Theologir.e Thomas Aquinas asks whether ignorance can diminish sin or even excuse from it altogether. Given current discussions of multi-culturalism, his consideration of this question takes on a particularly contemporary relevance. Proponents of multiculturalism argue at times that cultural influences can pose serious impediments to responsible agency. At the root of this contention is the belief that culture can cause in individuals an ignorance of the natural law which excuses them from sin. Through Thomas's writings on ignorance, conscience, and the natural law, we can discern a clear response to such arguments, delineating Thomas's sense of the culpability for such acts. I Examples of cultural practices that violate the natural law would be bride burning in India, hari-kari or ritual suicide formerly found in Japan, and polygamy in certain Arab countries. Clearly these activities are influenced by cultural norms, but can such norms be said to excuse any moral culpability whatsoever? The question is posed well by Michelle Moody-Adams, who asks, "But what might the link between culture and agency mean for the practice of holding people responsible for action, and for moral and legal conventions of praise and blame?" 105 106 GREGORY DOOLAN A currently influential answer to this question-to be found in much recent philosophical psychology, as well as in the social sciences and in history-is that cultural influences can, and often do, constitute serious impediments to responsible agency, and our attitudes toward praise and-especially-blame should acknowledge the existence of such impediments. Some of these views attempt to establish that, at least sometimes, widespread moral ign.orancecan be due principally to the cultural limitations of an entire era, rather than to individual moral defects. 1 In the De Malo Thomas acknowledges that "Since it is of the nature of sin that it is voluntary, to whatever extent ignorance excuses sin either wholly or in part, to that extent it takes away the voluntariness. " 2 Every act of the will, he explains, is preceded by an act of the intellect that presents the will with its object. If the intellect's act is excluded through ignorance, therefore, so too is the act of the will. Hence, Thomas concludes that "there is always involuntariness so far as concerns that which is unknown. " 3 Nevertheless, he cautions that while ignorance may at times excuse from sin, it does not always excuse from sin altogether.4 To discern, then, whether Thomas would accept the notion that there can be "widespread moral ignorance" due principally to cultural limitations-and whether such ignorance would alleviate or excuse from sin altogether-we must first consider those circumstances under which he says that ignorance fails to excuse from sin altogether. Thomas explains in the Summa Theologitethat there are two reasons why ignorance may fail to excuse altogether from sin. One is on the part of the ignorance itself which determines the voluntariness of the act, and the other is on the part of the thing which is not known. 5 Regarding the first, he notes that ignorance 1 Michelle M Moody-Adams, "Culture, Responsibility, and Affected Ignorance," Ethics 104 (January 1994): 291-2; emphasis added. 2 De Malo, q. 3, a. 8 (trans. Jean Osterle [Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1995]). 3 Ibid. 4 STh 1-11, q. 76, a. 3 (trans. Fathers of the English Dominican Province [New York: Christian Classics, 1981]). 5 Ibid. CULTURE,IGNORANCE, AND CULPABILITY 107 may be related to the act of the will in one of three ways: concomitantly, consequently, or antecedently. 6 Ignorance is concomitant (concomitanter) to the will's act when there is ignorance of what is done, but in such a way that even if it were known the act would be performed anyway. Thomas gives the example of a hunter who unknowingly kills a foe whom he had wished to kill anyway. The act cannot be said to be involuntary because it did not cause anything contrary to the hunter's habitual desire to kill that foe. Rather, Thomas explains, such ignorance should be called nonvoluntary since what was unknown could not have been actually willed. While the involuntary signifies that the will is opposed to what is done, the nonvoluntary signifies a mere privation of the act of the will. Thus, all ignorance causes the nonvoluntary, but not all ignorance causes the involuntary. 7 Properly speaking, concomitant ignorance is not the cause of the consequent sin because the man's habitual will was sinful before the ignorant act. For this reason, Thomas explains, such ignorance neither increases nor diminishes the sin since the outcome of the ignorant act would have been willed had the man not been ignorant from the start. 8 Thomas describes ignorance as being consequent (consequenter) to the will's act insofar as the ignorance is voluntary. In the De Malo he delineates three ways in which ignorance may be voluntary: directly, indirectly, or incidentally. In the first way, voluntary ignorance occurs when a person directly wills to be ignorant so that he may have an excuse to sin. Thomas describes this ignorance in the Summa as "affected ignorance" (ignorantia affectata). Such ignorance does not excuse sin either wholly or in part, he explains, but rather increases it, "for a person seems to be afflicted with a great love of sinning that he would will to suffer the loss of knowledge for the sake of freely engaging in sin. " 9 In the second way, ignorance can be indirectly voluntary when a person does not make an effort to know. Such ignorance Thomas calls "negligence" (negligentia) because a person omits 1-11, q. 6, a. 8. Ibid.; De Malo, q. 3, a. 8. 8 STh 1-11, q. 76, a. 4. 9 De Malo, q. 3, a. 8; STh 1-11, q. 6, a. 8. 6 STh 7 108 GREGORY DOOLAN what he is obliged to do, namely, consider that which he can and ought to consider. In the Summa, Thomas refers to this ignorance as "ignorance of evil choice" (ignorantia malce electionis) and notes that it arises from some passion or habit or when one does not make the effort to know what he is obliged to know. 10 The third manner of voluntary ignorance, the incidental (per accidens), is similar to the second. 11 Such ignorance occurs when a person directly or indirectly wills something from which ignorance follows. Thomas gives as an example of direct incidental ignorance the drunkard who wills to drink too much wine and hence deprive himself of reason; indirectly, Thomas explains, incidental ignorance occurs when one does not resist rising passions which will bind the use of reason in a particular choice. 12 Like direct ignorance, both the indirect and incidental forms are voluntary and as such do not cause involuntariness in the act that follows since the voluntariness of the ignorance makes that act to be in some measure voluntary. "But nevertheless," Thomas explains, "the preceding ignorance lessens the voluntary nature of the act, for that act is less voluntary which proceeds from ignorance of this sort than if a person knowingly would choose such an act without any ignorance, and so such ignorance does not excuse the following act altogether but only to some degree. " 13 Finally, ignorance is antecedent (antecedenter) to the will's act when it is not voluntary but is nonetheless the cause of a man's willing what he would not will otherwise. Thus, as with concomitant ignorance, a man may be ignorant of some circumstance of his act which he was not obliged to know. However, in contrast to the man with concomitant ignorance, he would not perform that act if he knew those circumstances. For example, 10 SI'h 1-11, q. 6, a. 8. 11 While Thomas considers indirect and incidental ignorance as two distinct forms of ignorance in the De Malo, in the Summa Theologitehe considers them together in opposition to direct ignorance. u De Malo, q. 3, a. 8; SI'h 1-11, q. 6, a. 8. 13De Malo, q. 3, a. 8 (emphasis added). Thomas adds, "it must be noted that sometimes both the act itself that follows and the preceding ignorance are one sin just as the will (to do a thing) and the external act are called one sin; hence it can happen that the sin is no less increased by the voluntariness of ignorance than it is excused by the diminished voluntariness of the act" (ibid.). CULTURE, IGNORANCE, AND CULPABILITY 109 after taking proper precautions, a hunter may be unaware of the presence of a passerby and shoot him, regretting the accident. "Such ignorance," Thomas explains, "causes involuntariness simply." 14 Consequently, antecedent ignorance excuses from sin altogether. In summary, then, Thomas describes the relation of ignorance to sin as follows: directly voluntary ignorance increases sin, concomitant ignorance neither increases nor diminishes it, indirect and incidental ignorance diminish sin to some degree, while antecedent ignorance excuses from sin altogether. Since ignorance excuses from sin only insofar as it removes voluntariness, and since it removes voluntariness only inasmuch as it is itself involuntary, Thomas describes only two instances of antecedent ignorance. "If the ignorance be such as to be entirely involuntary," he explains, "either [1] through being invincible [invincibilis], or [2] through being of matters one is not bound to know, then such like ignorance excuses from sin altogether. " 15 Thomas defines invincible ignorance as that which is unable to be overcome by study. 16 Given this fact, we see that ignorance excuses from sin altogether only when it is an ignorance of that which one either (1) cannot know, or (2) is not bound to know. 17 And since that which a man cannot know he is also not bound to know, in order to answer the question whether the influences of culture can excuse moral evils, we must first consider what everyone is obliged to know regardless of his cultural identity. II "Because a person is said to be negligent only when he omits what he is obliged to do," Thomas explains, "it does not seem to pertain to negligence that he fails to apply his mind to know anything whatsoever but only if he fails to apply his mind to 14 STh I-II, q. 6, a. 8. 15 STh I-II, q. 76, a. 3. 16 STh I-II, q. 76, a. 2. notes an exception that "If the ignorance be such as to exclude the use of reason entirely, it excuses from sin altogether, as is the case with madmen and imbeciles: but such is not always the ignorance that causes the sin; and so it does not always excuse from sin altogether" (STh I-II, q. 76, a. 3, ad 3). 17 Thomas 110 GREGORY DOOLAN know those things he ought to know." 18 Thomas makes dear that not all "non-knowing" is properly called ignorance. There are some things that man by nature does not have the aptitude to know (e.g., he cannot know the nature of God or of angels in this life). Such "non-knowing" Thomas calls "nescience" (nescentia) which denotes a simple negation or absence of knowledge. Hence, even a stone or a tree can be called nescient inasmuch as-