Tbe Tbomist 64 (2000): 161-210 CHRISTIANITY, "INTER CULTURALITY," AND SALVATION: SOME PERSPECTIVES FROM LONERGAN ANDREW BEARDS Ushaw College Durham, United Kingdom T he 1998 Synod of Asian Bishops in Rome helped to focus attention in a very concrete way upon theological issues surrounding notions such as "evangelization" and "inculturation," and the interplay between the mission of the Holy Spirit, preparing all humankind in the diversity of cultures and religions to receive the incarnate Word, and the mission of that Word himself, Christ Jesus. One of the participants at the Synod, Joseph Cardinal Ratzinger, was certainly no stranger ..:o the complexity of the theological issues being raised. In 1993 he had turned his attention to the issue of Christianity and inculturation in a lecture delivered in Hong Kong entitled "Christ, Faith, and the Challenge of Cultures. " 1 Some years earlier he had offered theological reflections on questions concerning "anonymous Christianity" and allied theological issues in a paper that included a discussion of Rahner's approach to these matters. 2 In his 1993 lecture the cardinal attempts an analysis of the dynamics of evangelization and inculturation that involves a critique of a Western relativist evaluation of what such a process can and should entail. He points out that such relativism was voiced against the Christian claim to uniqueness early in the 1 Joseph Cardinal Ratzinger, "Christ, Faith, and the Challenge of Cultures," Origins 24 (March 1995): 679-86. 2 Joseph Ratzinger, Principlesof Catholic Theology (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1987), 161-70. 161 162 ANDREW BEARDS Church's history by such Roman writers as Symmachus, and remains substantially the same objection today. Against such relativism he argues, firstly, that any human culture if authentic must be open to the discovery of truth-truth that may challenge and revise some of its deep-seated assumptions. Secondly, philosophical relativism is in fact alien to most cultures and religious world-views. And, thirdly, Christianity can be seen to transform and redeem other religious-cultural world-views in the way it preaches a God now brought dose, in the Incarnation-a God, or "Divinity," often implicitly recognized in these world-views as somehow "distant." A further point Ratzinger makes, and one that I wish to highlight for discussion in this article, is that the Church, the People of God, is itself a "cultural subject." Insofar as there is an intersubjective communion of heart and mind in the body of Christ this must be so. We cannot isolate the incarnate Word from the Jewish world-view and culture which he enters into, transforms, renews, "assumes," and, in doing so, confirms. This culture of the Old Covenant is itself, as Ratzinger points out, a result of what Gadamer might term a "fusion of horizons" with other cultural elements of its neighbors, taking place over centuries. However, such an evolved cultural form receives something of a definitive confirmation from the perspective of Christian faith once and insofar as it is taken into the life and mind of Christ. This process of cultural fusion then enters a new phase, but continues in the history of the Church, in which this Jewish world-view, confirmed and renewed in Christ, encounters and transforms the cultural forces it encounters in the process of evangelization. In this way Christianity, unlike some religions but akin to, for example, Buddhism, creates a universal Christian culture while also allowing (indeed, fostering) what in sociological terms one might call "subcultures" -that is, the varied local cultural forms of Christian societies, nations, cultures. This phenomenon Ratzinger terms "interculturality." 3 In some ways this analysis appears to move against the current evident in much of the theological reflection on evangelization 3 Ratzinger, "Christ, Faith and the Challenge of Cultures," 681-83. "INTERCULTURALITY" AND SALVATION 163 and inculturation this century. Pope Pius XI remarked to Fr. M. D. Roland-Gosselin that the object of the Church is not to "civilize" but to evangelize, 4 and since the encyclical Summi Pontificatus (1939) the magisterium has often repeated the need to differentiate the two processes. This process of making an increasingly sharp theological distinction between evangelization and inculturation went forward under the impetus of historical developments. A period in which evangelization had gone hand in hand with European colonization and imperial expansion was passing away, and a new appreciation of Catholicism as a world Church was emerging. In line with such developments Bernard Lonergan insisted that we were moving away from a period of "classical culture" in which Christianity was seen as linked to a view which distinguished bet:ween, on the one hand, a normative classical culture of meanings and values and, on the other, human groupings that were not cultured but barbarian. In the final section of his work Method in Theology, entitled "Communications," Lonergan treats of evangelization, the culmination of the Christian message: Now a classicist would feel it was perfectly legitimate for him to impose his culture on others. For he conceives culture normatively, and he conceives his own to be the norm. Accordingly for him to preach both the gospel and his own culture, is for him to confer the double benefit of both the true religion and the true culture. In contrast, the pluralist acknowledges a multiplicity of cultural traditions .... Rather he would proceed from within their culture and he would seek ways and means for making it into a vehicle for communicating the Christian message.5 Is Ratzinger then proposing a return to what Lonergan would term a classicist model of evangelization? Does his analysis of the People of God as a cultural subject, such that one can indeed speak of a "Christian culture," pit an ideology of normative culture against the pluralist view Lonergan outlines? Quoted in Walter Abbott, ed., The Documents of Vatican II (London: Chapman, 1967), 264 n. 192. 5 Bernard Lonergan, Method in Theology (London: Darron, Longman and Todd, 1972), 363. 4 164 ANDREW BEARDS One of my aims in this article is to attempt to provide an answer to this question. However, in attempting to answer the question further issues arise regarding the of Lonergan's work for such notions as cultural normativity, Christianity, and inculturation. I wiH also, therefore, examine some of those implications. Finally, I shall extend the discussion to further matters that arise in a consideration of Christianity and mission: the claims to uniqueness on the part of Christianity and the theological cogency and desirability of theories of "anonymous Christianity." L FROM CLASSICAL CULTURE TO HISTORICAL MINDEDNESS One phrase of Lonergan's perhaps more than any other appears to have imprinted itself upon the minds of latetwentieth-century theologians in the English-speaking world: the shift from classical culture to historical mindedness. For some it has become part of an arsenal to be deployed against anything which is deemed to be "pre-conciliar," myopic, traditionalist; a slogan with which to hail a "world come of age." For others, who react against the former view, it can appear as yet another modernist mantra which surely fails to do justice to the complexity and diversity of the Catholic ecclesiastical tradition. 6 When one takes into consideration postmodern critiques of the "modern" (appreciating that ecdesiastical modernism was and is but a subspecies of the same), one may wonder whether this 6 See, for example, Charles Curran's use of the terms in C. Curran and R. Hunt, Dissent in and for the Church: Theologians and Humanae Vitae (New York: Sheed and Ward, 1969), 155-69. In response, Janet E. Smith objects, quite rightly I believe, both to the imprecision to which Curran's use of the terms "Classicism" and "historical mindedness" leads, and to the way it is a caricature of even Platonic moral theory Ganet E. Smith, Humanae Vitae: A Generation Later [Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1991], 180 and 397). Curran's lack of real understanding of the implications of Lonergan's position is manifested in, among other things, his repeated drawing of a distinction between "classicist" thinking as deductive and modern thinking as inductive. for Lonergan, the discussions of both deduction and induction of the "modem" period fail to make the transposition from "logic to method" (see Bernard Lonergan, Insight: A Study of Human Understanding [New York: Philosophical Library, 1957], 288 and 301). On Lonergan and ethics in general see Andrew Beards, "Moral Conversion and Problems in Proportionalism," Gregorianum 78 (1997): 329-57. "INTERCULTURALITY" AND SALVATION 165 Lonerganian phrase is not a celebration of the "modem" which has now had its day. My first task in this section is, therefore, to clarify somewhat what Lonergan means by this expression. Its open-textured character, including as it does sketches of viewpoints that are actually opposed, make it ill suited to be transformed into a slogan. One should bear in mind Lonergan's own insistence that ideal-types, or models for facilitating historical explanation, should not be imposed on the data in such a way as to become, in H. Marrou's words, "great anti-comprehension machines. " 7 One of the principal means I will use to clarify Lonergan's meaning is to raise and examine the question: is Aquinas a classicist for Lonergan? A) Continuity and Diversity in Cultural Change Lonergan credited the transition in his thinking from a normative, classical notion of culture to an empirical notion of cultural diversity to the reading of Christopher Dawson's The Age of the Gods in the late 1930s, and F. E. Crowe notes the appearance of remarks on the limitations of "Classicism" in Lonergan's writing as early as 1949. 8 In works of the late 1950s and early 1960s such criticisms of classicism increase. 9 Something of the open-textured nature of the term can be seen from these early uses: in the 1959 lectures on education we read that classicism "in its best sense" is to be seen in the Greek discovery of mind, the Greek achievement of theory. This always remains a cultural achievement, despite its limitations, an instance of true progress in Lonergan's view. 10 In the 1962 paper "Time and Lonergan, Method in Theology, 226-29. Bernard Lonergan, "Insight Revisited," in A Second Collection (Darton, Longman and Todd, 1974), 264; F. E. Crowe, in Collected Works of Bernard Lonergan, vol 6, Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964 (Univ. of Toronto Press: Toronto, 1996), 154-55, n. 25. 9 See F. E. Crowe, ed., Collected Works of Bernard Lonergan, vol. 10, Topics in Education (Univ. of Toronto Press: Toronto, 1993), 74-78; and "Time and Meaning," (a 1962 paper), and "The Analogy of Meaning," (a 1963 paper), in Crowe, ed., Collected Works 6, 94-121, and 183-212. 10 Crowe, ed., Collected Works 10, 75. 7 8 166 ANDREW BEARDS Meaning" we find another attribute of the classicist highlighted, an attribute not so evident in Lonergan's later sketches: he is one who speaks in respectful and deferential tones of the "greats" of the Western intellectual tradition-Aristotle, Augustine, Aquinas, Newton, etc.-but has little if any appreciation of what it actually means to think systematically and creatively as did these cultural giants; the classicist has little real appreciation of what Lonergan calls the theoretical differentiation of consciousness. 11 In a way this echoes a constant theme in Lonergan's work: the authentic human act of understanding has no substitute in a mere parroting of formulae or theory little understood. A tension may be noted here: "classicism" denotes the theoretical differentiation of consciousness, the capacity that emerges in culture for systematic, theoretical reflection, but it is also used to denote cultural deference to such an achievement on the part of those who do not properly participate in it. The 1968 paper "Belief: Today's Issue," provides a fairly lengthy treatment of the contrast between classical and modem culture, highlighting the limitations of both. Of the limitations of classicism we read: Classicist culture was stable. It took its stand on what ought to be, and what ought to be is not refuted by what is. It legislated with an eye to the substance of things, on the unchanging essence of human living and, while it never doubted either that circumstances alter cases or that circumstances change, still it was also quite sure that essences did not change, that change affected the accidental details that were of no great account. 12 Classicist culture was also essentially "ethnocentric": it contrasted itself not with alternative cultures but with human groups which had simply to be designated "barbarian." "By conceiving itself normatively, [it] also had to think of itself as the one and only culture for all time. But modern culture is culture on the move. It is historicist. " 13 There are other examples of the indefiniteness of Lonergan's historical ideal-type of classicism. For instance, he characterizes Crowe, ed., CollectedWorks 6, 121. Second Collection, 92-93. 13 Ibid., 93. 11 12 Lonergan, "INTERCULTURALITY" AND SALVATION 167 as "classicist" both the metaphysical theorist, who tends to abstract from the particularity of human history and individuals, and the "person for whom the rhetorician or orator of Isocrates or Cicero represents the fine flower of human culture." 14 Yet while one may be both an admirer of theoretical metaphysics and of Cicero, it is dear from a study of such periods of Western cultural history as that of Renaissance humanism that admiration for the latter can entail opposition to the former. Furthermore, Lonergan says that "a classicist would maintain that one should never depart from an accepted terminology," 15 and would therefore be opposed to authentic development of dogma (i.e., development in accord with Vincent of Lerins and Vatican I). But then he demonstrates very ably in his own work on doctrinal history 16 that new terminology was accepted to express further insight into doctrine both in the patristic period, the theology of which is affected by a "tincture" of theory, and in the medieval period, whose theology exhibits a full theoretical and systematic exploration. In other words these periods, characterized in some way as classical by Lonergan, did and could accept new theological terminology, something to which the classicist is, according to the above quotation, opposed. Finally, it is important to observe that Lonergan on occasions also identifies philosophical and theological deductivism and the quest for certainty as a characteristic of classicism. In the second place, the classicist judged modern science in the light of the Aristotelian notion of science and by that standard found it wanting, for modern science does not proceed from self-evident, necessary principles and it does not demonstrate conclusions from such principles. 17 This more than anything else should make us wary of thinking that Lonergan has given us anything like an "explanatory definition" with the term "classicism." Throughout his career it 14 Bernard Lonergan, Philosophy of God and Theology (London: Darton, Longman and Todd, 1973), ix. 15 Lonergan, Method in Theology, 123-24. 16 See, for example, Bernard Lonergan, The Way to Nicea (London: Darton, Longman and Todd, 1976). 17 Lonergan, Second Collection, 112. ANDREW BEARDS 168 was such theological deductivism, arising from the fourteenthcentury nominalist use of Aristotle, that he strove to contrast with the authentic thought and methodology of St. Thomas Aquinas. If my indications here of a certain "untidiness" to Lonergan's notion of classicism may appear somewhat disingenuous I would simply reiterate the point that what we have in this notion is not an explanatory concept but something like a Wittgensteinian nominal definition through "family resemblance." Lonergan makes more or less this point himself when he writes: But I would like to say that the contrast I have drawn between classicist and modern is not based on some a priori typology or periodization. It is a summary of a whole set of conclusions concerning the defects of our theological inheritance and the remedies that can be brought to bear. More importantly, he continues, If we are not just to throw out what is good in classicism and replace it with contemporary trash, then we need to take the trouble, and it is enormous, to grasp the strength and the weakness, the power and the limitations, the good points and the shortcomings of both classicism and modernity. 18 If we now address the question "is Aquinas a classicist?" we will gain a better understanding of what Lonergan considers are the strengths of the past that we need to import into the present. B) Is Aquinas a Classicist? In Method in Theology and elsewhere Lonergan sketches an account of the evolutionary development of the history of meaning in Western culture in terms of three stages or plateaus of achievement. 19 In the first stage we witness ordinary or commonsense meaning (the plateau of "undifferentiated consciousness"). The second stage, growing out of the first, is signaled by the Greek discovery of mind; it is the period of theoretical consciousness, and in terms of Christianity Lonergan sees evidence of Ibid., 98. Lonergan, Method in Theology, 85-99; see also Bernard Lonergan, A Third Collection (London: Chapman, 1985), 179-82. 18 19 "INTERCULTURALITY" AND SALVATION 169 a "tincture" of such theory in the Christological debates of the first millennium, while a full engagement with theory is evident in the Scholastic period. The third stage grows out of the second. It is marked by the growing autonomy of the sciences, both physical and, later, human, from philosophy and the various philosophical responses to these developments, ranging from the "turn to the subject" in Descartes, Kant, and Idealism to the repudiation of such a move in positivism or linguistic analysis. While this is a general sketch of the ongoing differentiations of consciousness in the West, the models available for the cultural interpreter of the process increase as one approximates to concrete examples of historical processes, since one may also take into account some thirty-six possible combinations of these conscious differentiations. 20 It is clear from this general historical scheme both that the second stage or plateau is, for Lonergan, the stage of classicism and that it is the stage in which, historically, Aquinas is to be located. It would appear to follow, therefore, that Aquinas is a classicist. However, it is clear that Lonergan is reluctant to apply the term to St. Thomas. Rather, it is through a retrieval of Aquinas's thought that one overcomes the limitations of classicism. This is a constant theme throughout Lonergan's work, exemplified by the motto he took for his endeavors from Pope Leo XIII's Aeterni Patris: "novae vetere ex augere et perficere." From the beginning of his published work Lonergan's hermeneutic of suspicion is directed against Scotist naive realism in epistemology and its deductivist companion in theology. This conceptualism had entered through Suarezianism into the Jesuit intellectual tradition into which Lonergan was initiated in his youth. It was a breaking free from this background, being enabled to think through the challenges of historically minded modernity for Catholic thought, that characterized Lonergan's years spent "reaching up to the mind of Aquinas." 20 In addition to the three differentiations of common sense, theory, and interiority (or the turn to the subject, of stage three), there are such differentiations as, for example, the religious, artistic, and scholarly. See Lonergan, Method in Theology, 272, 275. 170 ANDREW BEARDS In such papers such as the "Future of Thomism," 21 "Aquinas Today: Tradition and Innovation," and the recently published "Fundamental Theology" 22 Lonergan continues to affirm his assessment of Aquinas as the theologian of the tradition, more than any other, whose fundamental theological and philosophical approach is that which we must appropriate in order to move forward. Although Aquinas did not explicitly move from a cognitional theory and an epistemology to ground a metaphysics based upon them, Lonergan believes that both he and Aristotle before him pointed in that direction. For, on Lonergan's view, we find in their work, implicitly and obscurely, some combination of a "phenomenology of the subject" with a "psychology of the soul. " 23 It is only through an encounter with Aquinas that Lonergan is able to deconstruct the "knowing as looking" myth that has bedeviled Western philosophy since the late Middle Ages, and in its place outline a critical realism-a realism that holds that reality is not known through sensation but through the deployment of intelligent and reasonable operations. Further, from Aquinas we learn a totally different approach to theology from that found in fourteenth-century nominalism and deductivism. One understands theology as some attempt at a fruitful understanding of revealed truths, not an exercise in logic that strives for "scientific certainty." The irony here is, of course, that such a notion of "science" itself becomes replaced, after a long historical process, with the very notion of a good theory as that which is the best possible in the circumstances, the attitude to theory which St. Thomas himself had with regard to theology. Thus, one of the characteristics of classicism we noted above, its ideal of logical deductivism in theology and science, is replaced by a return to St. Thomas. As Lonergan writes, contrasting the limitations of "classical Thomism" with the authentic mind of St. Thomas (and suggesting transpositions required to achieve the retrieval of that authentic voice): Lonergan, Second Collection,, 43-53. Lonergan, Third Collection, 35-54; Bernard Lonergan, "Fundamental Theology," Method: Journal of Lonergan Studies 16 (1998): 5-24, see 22-23. 23 Bernard Lonergan, "Introduction," in Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas, ed. David E. Burrell (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1967). 21 22 "INTERCULTURALITY"AND SALVATION 171 You may ask, however, whether after the introduction of the ... transpositions just outlined there would be anything left of Thomism. And at once I must grant that the five emphases I attributed to classical Thomism would disappear. One may doubt, however, whether such emphases are essential to the thought of St. Thomas or of the great Thomists. 24 Certainly there are transpositions to be made from Aquinas's thought to a contemporary theology and one must note the limitations of St. Thomas's horizon. One can surely say that Aquinas simply does not have the same sense of historical movement, of the ongoing genesis of methods and cognitive disciplines that we experience in contemporary culture. This is what Lonergan sees as a limitation in his thought. But even here we need to handle the word "limitation" carefully. Naturally, one does not "blame" a thinker of seven hundred years ago for not answering the questions that arise for us today; they simply did not arise for him. However, even here Lonergan's retrieval of Aquinas leads us to qualify this admission. While Aquinas's reflections on doctrinal development or the historicality of human thought are not conspicuous, the indications of an awareness of issues at stake are there. So when Lonergan insists that there is only one eternal truth, in God, and that human truth is both genuine truth but historically conditioned in its formulation (so that one may discern a genuine history of truth), that "concepts have dates," in other words, he is simply exploiting and developing insights he discovered in Aquinas. Thus Lonergan draws attention to St. Thomas's point in the Summa contra Gentiles that human insights and judgments, even in metaphysics, have some temporal reference, given the nature of human knowing. 25 Further, he draws attention to St. Thomas's point (following Aristotle) that human knowledge and understanding only occur in an ongoing, historical process of collaboration. 26 On the other hand, Scotist nominalism blocks such attention to 24 Lonergan, 25 Lonergan, Second Collection, 52. Verbum, 63-64 (fhe work originally appeared in article form between 1946 and 1949). 26 Bernard Lonergan, Understandingand Being:The Halifax Lectureson Insight, ed. E. and M. Morelli, F. E. Crowe, R. Doran, and T. Daly (foronto: University of Toronto Press, 1990), 383. 172 ANDREW BEARDS the historicity of human thought through its account of "unconscious" concept formation, and diverts attention away from concrete historical process. Unlike St. Thomas, who was concerned to understand something of the mystery of that historical event, the Incarnation, with its implications for the real world of history, the nominalist diverts our attention away from concrete historical process to speculation concerning logical possible worlds. 27 While St. Thomas could not possibly anticipate in a fulsome way the massive development of the Geisteswissenschaften in the last three centuries, still Lonergan detects heuristic anticipations of the important issues. Thus the methodological attempt to gather the authoritative texts of the tradition in the mediaeval period anticipates modern efforts in research and interpretation. 28 And the attempts of modern historical scholarship to understand the common sense of other cultures and times are obscurely anticipated in Aquinas's examination of human commonsense understanding in his analysis of prudentia. 29 There are achievements in Aquinas's theology-with respect to grace, the Trinity, and other issues-that Lonergan believes are "classic," in the sense that no theologian working in these areas today or in the future can or should ignore them. But far more important are the avenues for epistemological, metaphysical, and theological research Aquinas opens up: avenues that, Lonergan believes, open up possibilities for developing positions in these areas which admit of permanence and development-allowing for the adumbration of basic philosophical positions fostering development, but restricting radical revision at the cost of selfdestructive incoherence. What is really, profoundly important in Aquinas is the discovery of heuristic or methodological indications of what both permanence and authentic development, on the one hand, and inauthentic decline, on the other, could be in human thought and culture. This retrieval of Aquinas, which is at the core of Lonergan's whole enterprise, implies that for Lonergan there is a history of philosophical truth just as there is a parallel history of dogmatic Verbum, 69. Lonergan, Third Collection, 52. 29 Ibid., 44. 27 Lonergan, 28 "INTERCULTURALITY" AND SALVATION 173 truth. In this respect Lonergan's work can be fruitfully compared and contrasted with that of Alasdair Maclntyre's retrieval of Thomism (which emphasizes its strengths as a tradition-based form of philosophical enquiry). There are important differences between these two positions, 30 yet much also that is complementary. In fact, reading the former in light of the latter helps to highlight the postmodern moments in Lonergan's thought, particularly with regard to his retrieval of a premodern thinker, Aquinas. In many ways, then, we can see Lonergan's critique of "classicism" as a critique of "modernity." The central role played by the premodern thought of Aquinas in this critique reveals that any understanding of Lonergan's notion of the defects of classicism which reads this as a "modern" or modernist critique could not be more mistaken. Further, it is interesting to observe some of the striking postmodern themes in Lonergan's work. Even in his magnum opus, Insight, a work of "pure philosophy" if ever there was one, such elements are evident. A central theme of the work is an analysis of the way human attempts to reach cognitive and moral self-transcendence in knowing the true and the good, and acting accordingly, are stymied by the mystery of human bias and sin. The only "solution" to this human condition is the divine one of salvation. Thus a philosophical enquiry into human understanding inevitably heads towards a faith perspective. "Objectivity 30 Michael P. Maxwell, Jr., "A Dialectical Encounter Between Macintyre and Lonergan on the Thomistic Understanding of Rationality," International PhilosophicalQuarterly 33 ( 1993): 385-99; see Alasdair Macintyre, Three RivalVersionsofMoral Inquiry (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1990). Maxwell draws attention to Maclntyre's denial of the validity of nineteenth and twentieth-century attempts by Thomists to answer the epistemological questions of modernity; naturally, there is a divergence from Lonergan in this crucial area. Maxwell successfully argues that (as Lonergan points out) we cannot foist such a prejudice against meeting the epistemological challenges of modernity upon Aquinas and that there are many elements of Aquinas's thought that would allow the development of an extremely powerful critique of the deficiencies of the epistemologies of modernity. Finally, Maxwell shows that elements within Maclntyre's version of Thomism as a form of Thomistic fallibilism (akin therefore to views such as those of Popper or Davidson) become involved in incoherence (Maxwell, "Macintyre and Lonergan," 399). I would add to Maxwell's criticisms the point that if some are suspicious about a reading of Aquinas that imports his thought into the epistemological debates of modernity, it is appropriate to wonder, by parity of historical suspicion, about the Thomistic authenticity of an account like Maclntyre's, which provides a metanarrative in terms of such fallibilist criteria. 174 ANDREW BEARDS is the fruit of authentic subjectivity," and that authenticity only comes about through the divine initiative healing the broken human community. This is parallel to Maclntyre's insistence that genealogical and deconstructive critiques have unmasked the pretended impartial objectivity of the Enlightenment as flawed and, in reality, far more scattered and fragmentary in its vision of the world than its propaganda would have us believe. Without a tradition in which the virtues are cultivated truth cannot flourish and, ultimately, that tradition must be based upon resources beyond those which a mere humanism can provide. 31 More fundamentally, of course, the issue is not one of awarding marks to either Lonergan or Macintyre on the basis of how "postmodern" they appear. The issue is, more fundamentally, one of a possible critique of postmodernity, itself very difficult to delimit, and of possible hermeneutical analyses which might even redefine movements in the Western cultural heritage in a way that challenges those genealogies espoused by some of the more noted representatives of postmodernity. For Lonergan, for example, what is at stake may well have already been played out in some way in the thirteenth to fifteenth centuries; the aporias and their resolution may already be present in the dialectical relationships obtaining between Aquinas, Scotus, and Nicholas of Autrecourt. One may remark that, for all its critique of Enlightenment modernity, postmodernity cannot but be its child in the "hubristic pride" it manifests in claiming a total and revolutionary rupture from the past-a past which, in whatever circumlocutory phrases one attempts to express it, is now deemed mistaken and illusory. 32 In contrast Macintyre and Lonergan are 31 Macintyre, Three Rival Versions, 127-31. 32 Of course Derrida will claim, much to the chagrin of American parmers in debate such as Rorty, that one can never "escape" the Western intellectual tradition. But it is evident that he cannot avoid making the implicit claim that at least he has struggled free enough to achieve the elbow room that allows him to "take" and "re-take" that tradition but no longer to take it "seriously"; see Jacques Derrida, "Remarks on Deconstruction and Pragmatism," in Deconstruction and Pragmatism, ed. Chantal Mouffe (London: Routledge, 1996), 77-88. Derrida brings out in these remarks how fundamental the aporias and problems he encountered in Husserl remain for his thinking. In some ways, Derrida stands to Husserl as Wittgenstein II stands to Wittgenstein I regarding the failure of the "philosophical project." Crucial to any discussion of the relationship between Lonergan and Derrida is precisely a recognition of the way Lonergan retrieves from Aquinas perspectives and approaches that "INTERCULTURALITY"AND SALVATION 175 among those alone capable of a true deconstruction of the pretensions of the enlightenment: for only a viewpoint that sees itself as an ongoing collaboration in the discovery of truth, from past to present, from present to future, can really claim to retrieve in any meaningful way what is valid in the past, or "premodern." Before we conclude this section, examining what classicism might mean for Lonergan, it may be worth drawing attention to two further points. First, Lonergan's hermeneutical retrieval of Aquinas, although central to his appreciation of the strengths and weaknesses of the theological tradition, should not blind us to his positive evaluation of other elements in the theological tradition up to and including those evident in the nineteenth and twentieth-century Catholic tradition. Newman, for example, is a nineteenth-century theological figure who remains very important for Lonergan. Then one finds, in an early essay on the possibility of defining the dogma of the Assumption, positive evaluation of the nondeductivist approach shown to the issue of "implicit revelation" by the theological commission that prepared the dogma of the Immaculate Conception in 1854. 33 Lonergan writes, "Out of the Augustinian, Anselmian, Tho mist tradition, despite an imervening heavy overlay of conceptualism, the first Vatican Council retrieved the notion of understanding. "34 Second, given the variety of characteristics Lonergan brings under the rubric of "classicism" one may note, perhaps with some surprise, the characteristics evident in the thought of some more recent theologians which would render their work classicist. Thus in his critique of Schoonenberg's Christo logy Lonergan makes the point that the Dutch theologian's failure to understand what Chalcedon taught on the divinity of our Lord has to do, in part, with a "classicist" failure to appreciate the historical context of were simply not "available" to Husserl. Derrida is more aware than many another thinker of Hegel's dictum "all negation is determinate," but for all that, in even the most tentative or "obvious" judgment concerning a text (and Derrida is insistent on rigor in textual interpretation) one cannot avoid the exigencies of intelligence and reasonableness, nor, therefore, Lonergan would avow, one's commitment to objective reality as the intelligible. 33 See "The Assumption and Theology," in Collection (London: Darton, Longman and Todd, 1967). 34 Lonergan, Method in Theology, 336. ANDREW BEARDS 176 that council's use of the term "Person" (although the meaning of the council's teaching, Lonergan insists, is "not obscure"). 35 Further, Guy Mansini has argued forcefully for the dramatic differences that exist between Lonergan and Rabner in a number of key areas of theology, one of these being the crucial area of methodology. 36 According to Mansini (we shall return to this issue below), from a Lonerganian perspective Rabner still appears as a theologian captive to the deductivist tradition, which places a premium on philosophical proof in theology rather than nondeductive understanding or insight regarding the divinely revealed truths-the tradition that all too readily conflates intelligibility with necessity. If this is so, then we may observe something quite ironic: Lonergan, normally considered the "philosophers' theologian" may, in effect, place greater emphasis on the transcendence of the mysteries with regard to our understanding, than does the "theologian of mystery," Rahner. If this is so, Rahner's work would still be tied, in some respects, to classicist, conceptualist models from the viewpoint of Lonergan's methodology. II. CULTURE, CHRISTIANITY, AND CULTURAL NORMATIVITY Lonergan's contrast between a classicist evangelization, which regards cultures other than the Christian West as "barbaric," and a pluralist evangelization, which attempts to work within the possibilities of another culture recognized as an equal in terms of its communal sharing of values, should not blind us to the fact that there are in the Catholic historical tradition various forms of evangelization which do not work with the "non-barbarian (Christian) versus barbarian (non-Christian)" model. One can think of the evangelization undertaken by the Jesuits in China and India in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries as a fairly obvious example (one which Lonergan himself acknowledged). 37 Beyond Lonergan, Second Collection, 260. Guy Mansini, O.S.B., "Quasi-Formal Causality and 'Change in the Other': A Note on Karl Rahner's Christology," The Thomist 52 (1989): 293-306. 37 In conversation with Fr Eric O'Connor (I am unable to find the reference to this remark). 35 36 "INTERCULTURALITY" AND SALVATION 177 this, however, analyses like those of Ratzinger begin to draw our attention to something that requires a good deal of further research and reflection. We are emerging from a period in which Christian evangelization was linked to European colonial expansion. Much of the theological reflection on evangelization in this century, including that found in the magisterium, has been taking stock of this movement beyond European hegemony. But this new phase requires its own forms of reflection: in many ways the emergence of Europe and the West as post-Christian enables us to see anew the distinctions between Christianity and European culture, and between Christian mission linked to European colonial expansion and Christian mission separate from it. In the context of the latter distinction one element required for a proper understanding of evangelization is a retrieval of historical models of Christian mission prior to late medieval and Renaissance colonial expansion on the part of the West. A reflection on these earlier forms may help us move away from too rapid an identification of evangelization with the Western "imperialist" imposition of a world-view. From St. Paul's mission in the diaspora to the Franciscan missions to Beijing in the thirteenth century, one does not witness an "imposition" of Western culture on those to be evangelized, a mission backed by the "big battalions," but nevertheless an unashamed call to accept and adapt to a new truth, a new world-view, and a call to make the sacrifices, sometimes great indeed, which this change of view requires. One can reflect that the Christian mission was established in India certainly by the second century, and when "Thomas Christians" prayed for the world to accept Christ they would have been praying for many a pagan area of Northern Europe. 38 A further, important issue to draw attention to is the relativization of culture, and in some ways Western "classical" 38 See, for example, T. Puthiakunnel, "Jewish Colonies of India Paved the Way for St. Thomas," in The MalabarChurch, ed. J. Vellinan, Orientalia Christiana Analecta 186 (Rome, 1970), 187-91. It is also important to notice the dialectical encounter already under way between Christian and Hindu thought in the writings of the early Fathers, such as Irenaeus and Hippolytus. The background to such exchanges was the Alexandrian school, and the Hindu-Hellenistic cultural encounter which had been underway since Alexander's conquests in Northern India. ANDREW BEARDS 178 culture, through the emergence of Christianity itself. From the New Testament period on through the writings of the Fathers, we witness a dialectical process of reception, rejection, and transformation of that which Christianity encounters as it permeates Greco-Roman culture. Lonergan himself wrote at some length on this process in his analysis of the "Origins of Christian Realism," and to this I shall return below. But what Ratzinger's account of the Church as itself a cultural subject draws attention to (although it is not a feature of his lecture) is the process of relativization of culture which emerges. It emerges with particular clarity in St. Augustine, the cultured man of Western classicism, who had, before his conversion, despised the "barbarity" of mere Christianity, with its coarse and unappealing Hebrew Scriptures. According to Peter Brown, following H. L Marrou, this relativization of classical culture went forward in Augustine's later period in works like City of God and De Doctrina Christiana. 39 The rupture with classical ideals was radical, as Augustine began to realize the significance of the fact that God's truth had been communicated through the culture of the Hebrews, a people akin to the tribes that lived on the margins of Augustine's RomanNorth African world. Brown writes of Augustine's new approach to culture in De Doctrina Christiana: He began by remarking that culture was a product of society: it was a natural extension of language. It was so plainly the creation of social habits as to be quite relative. There could be no absolute standards of classical "purism." 40 Brown concludes: "It is a rare thing to come across a man of sixty, living on the threshold of a great change, who had already come to regard a unique culture and a unique political institution as replaceable." 41 Nor was Augustine's insight, which somehow crystallizes the attitude of the Fathers to pagan classical culture, lost in the Christian West. It is present in the Scholasticisrn of the Victorines in the High Middle Ages, and it reemerges with force in the Renaissance debate over the language of Scripture. So in Peter Brown, Augustine of Hippo (London: Faber and Faber, 1967), chap. 23. Ibid., 265. 4 I Ibid., 266. 39 40 "INTERCULTURALITY'' AND SALVATION 179 the sixteenth century we find Giles of Viterbo and Cajetan at loggerheads over the question of the value of Greek as opposed to Hebrew: for Cajetan the latter is primitive and defective, whereas for Giles it is perfect, for it is the vehicle of God's revelation. The debate seems to have constituted part of the background to the querelle des anciens et des modernes, which Gadamer sees as a feature of the emergence of modernity in the West. 42 Of course, in the period of the Enlightenment Hume and Gibbon would range themselves on the side in the debate opposite to Augustine and Giles. A) Intersubjectivity and the Christian Cultural Subject The relativization of culture that emerges with Christianity comes about, therefore, because Christianity realizes itself to be, in Ratzinger's words, a "cultural subject": it itself is a community constituted by common meanings and values, expressed and communicated in common symbols and aesthetic carriers of meaning, allowing and effecting intersubjective communication both between its members and between those members and Christ, the head of the mystical Body. Turning back to Lonergan, we do not find in chapter 14 of Method in Theology (on communications), or chapter 12 (on doctrines), which together treat of evangelization, an analysis of the Church as a "cultural subject." So we return to the question asked at the beginning of this article: is Ratzinger's notion of Christianity as a cultural subject, with his allied notion of "interculturality," a classicist approach from Lonergan's perspective? I think not. Rather, I believe there is an important complementarity between their approaches. The primary focus of Lonergan's attention in these chapters in Method is the manner in which Christian dogma develops: the truths of faith revealed in one culture may be understood in a new way (always retaining the same meaning) in another culture. A paradigmatic example Lonergan uses to illustrate this development-with-continuity comes from mathematics: the same 42 Hans-Georg Gadamar, Truth and Method, ed. J. Cummings and G. Barden (London: Sheed and Ward, 1975), 20, 242. ANDREW BEARDS 180 truth, that two plus two is four, was understood by the ancient Babylonians, later by the Greeks, and later still in modern mathematics-there is a growth of understanding of the same truth. 43 This notion of development-with-continuity is Lonergan's central concern. However, what Ratzinger's analysis of Christianity as the cultural subject indicates is that when Christianity is preached, what is primarily preached is a person, Jesus Christ. Furthermore, that person, the divine Person in a human nature and consciousness, is a cultural subject: one cannot prescind from encountering and in some way embracing the Word made flesh without at once embracing the culture taken up and transformed in his humanity-"for salvation is from the Jews" Uohn 4:22), or in the words of Pius XI, "we are all Semites spiritually." All this, however, is implicit in Lonergan's approach. What is distinctive about Christianity is the intersubjective encounter with Christ Jesus, and what Christian evangelization is about is proclaiming Christ Jesus. That communication invites an encounter with the incarnate meaning of the incarnate Word. As Lonergan writes, "The word, then, is personal. Cor ad cor loquitur: love speaks to love, and its speech is powerful. " 44 And agam: We express ourselves, we communicate, through the flesh, through words and gestures, the unnoticed movements of the countenance, pauses, all the manners in which, as Newman says, "cor ad cor loquitur," the heart speaks unto the heart. And the Incarnation and the Redemption are the supreme instance of God communicating to us in this life.45 On Lonergan's view, the person is not a monad but comes to be himself through the "mutual self-mediation" of a community or culture (such mutual self-mediation being what is written about by novelists as they trace the intricacies of interpersonal relations in community); 46 this applies equally to the Word made flesh. One 43 Lonergan, Method in Theology, 325. 44 Ibid., 113. 45 Crowe, ed., Collected Works 6, 65-66. 46 Lonergan, "The Mediation of Christ in Prayer," in ibid., 176. The theme of the Corad cor loquitur, intersubjective communion of feeling between Christ and his followers, found in Lonergan's writings could provide a starting point for a theology of the Sacred Heart; such "INfERCULTURALITY" AND SALVATION 181 cannot come close to another without in some ways coming close to his culture. The images and symbols to which the Sacred Heart responded as truly manifesting the truths and values which Jesus had come to communicate must also become the sources of my authentic feelings, my intentional responses to truth and value, if I am truly to enter into an intersubjective communion with him. And those images and symbols, signs and words are, as Ratzinger shows, that which is transformed yet fundamentally confirmed by the Word incarnate. Indeed, as Lonergan argues, our faith affirms that this Jewish culture was prepared as the seed bed of the Incarnation over generations. Following Eric Voegelin, Lonergan points out that the control or integration of symbols and signs in Israel took place not through any philosophical critique but through the purification wrought by the prophetic word which, from the viewpoint of faith, we take to have been a divine work. 47 This particular culture, then, with its world-view, its theology, and its anthropology, is, from the viewpoint of faith, a culture with a normativity no other can claim: it was a people formed by Yahweh for the coming of the Word. The account of evangelization given by Lonergan in chapters 12 and 14 of Method may benefit from an analysis such as Ratzinger's. While Lonergan's examination of the continuity and development of truths about the faith through diverse cultures is essential, still it needs to be complemented by an appreciation of the cultural implications of saying that at the center of evangelization is the intersubjective encounter with the person Jesus Christ. I have indicated already some of the elements in Lonergan's work which might prove helpful in teasing out the theological implications involved in such a reflection. The relativization of cultures which takes place in Christianity, so evident in St. Augustine's relativization of "classical culture," occurs precisely from a realization of the implications of this theological a theme could be fruitfully reflected upon in the context of what Lonergan has to say about some dogmatic developments as being characterized principally by "a refinement of feelings." 47 Lonergan, Way to Nicea, 110. It is perhaps interesting to note, given Lonergan's contention that the anthropological, as opposed to classicist, idea of culture entails study of distinctive forms of common sense, that in Insight he enumerates "Catholic" common sense as a distinct type (Lonergan, Insight, 416). 182 ANDREW BEARDS fact: the least of aH peoples, the people of Israel, has been chosen as the vehide for God's salvation of the world. Precolonial evangdization was always a realization of this. It is not ethnocentric imperialism that takes a cultural story as in some way normative for all human cultures and therefore prodaims in the name of truth that this cultural story, not the old one (however adaptable the old may be to the new), is now normative. Both Lonergan and Ratzinger argue that the authenticity of any culture is gauged precisely terms of its openness to the true and the good from whatever source this may come. There are many self-destructive inconsistencies in modem Western relativism, but one of the most evident is its own metanarrative of cultural encounter which denies what has in fact occurred through most cultures and historical periods: the permeability of cultures one to another; the abandonment, at times painful, of traditions and religious world-views because new ones have been accepted. It is not for the modern Western relativist to impose (great irony here of course) his metanarrative on the cultures of human history so as to attempt some "anti-ethnocentric" policing protection from the pain of conversion. However, beyond drawing out the implications of aspects of Lonergan's work that allow a fuller acknowledgement of Ratzinger's point that Christianity is a cultural "subject," one may observe that there is a yet more radical thesis in Lonergan's work that goes beyond Ratzinger's analysis of a certain "cultural normativity" implicit in Christianity: the thesis of "the origins of Christian realism." B) Christian Realism as a Cultural Catalyst In the chapter on "Communications" in Method Lonergan writes, concerning evangelization and inculturation: The pluralist acknowledges a multiplicity of cultural traditions. In any tradition he envisages the possibility of diverse differentiations of consciousness. But he does not consider it his task either to promote the differentiations of consciousness or to ask people to renounce their own culture. 48 48 Lonergan, Method in Theology, 363. "INTERCULTURALITY"AND SALVATION 183 Something of what Lonergan means by "differentiations of consciousness" has been sketched above. However, there is a very significant, and perhaps easily overlooked, modification made by Lonergan of the position he expresses in Method in one of his last papers, "Unity and Plurality," dating from 1982. There we read, of communications and evangelization, "There follows a manifold pluralism. It remains that within the realm of undifferentiated consciousness there is no communication of doctrine except through available rituals, narratives, titles parables, metaphors." So far this expresses the same ideas one finds in Method. However, Lonergan continues, An exception to this last statement must be noted. The educated classes in a society, such as was the Hellenic, normally are instances of undifferentiated consciousness. But their education had among its sources works of genuine philosophers, so that they could be familiar with logical operations and take propositions as objects on which they reflected and from which they inferred. In this fashion the meaning of homoousion for Athanasius was contained in a rule concerning propositions about the Father and the Son: What is true of the Father also is true of the Son, except that the Son is not the Father. Similarly, the meaning of the one person and two natures mentioned in the second paragraph of the decree of Chalcedon stands forth in the repeated affirmation of the first paragraph, namely, it is one and the same Son our Lord Jesus Christ that is perfect in divinity and the same perfect in humanity .... Now the meaning of the first paragraph can be communicated without the addition of any new technical terms. But it can give rise to reflection and to questions. Only after someone asks whether the divinity is the same as the humanity and, if not, then how can the same be both God and man, is it relevant to explain that a distinction can be drawn between person and nature, that divinity and humanity refer to two natures, that it is one and the same person that is both God and man. Such logical clarification is within the meaning of the decree. But if one goes on to raise the metaphysical question whether person and nature can be really distinct or the anthropological question whether there can be any real distinction between subject and subjectivity, then the issue is being transported from the fifth century to the thirteenth on the metaphysical issue, and to the twentieth on the anthropological issue. One not only steps beyond the context of Chalcedon, but also beyond the capacity of undifferentiated consciousness to discover any possible solution. 49 49 Lonergan, Third Collection, 243-44. 184 ANDREW BEARDS In this passage Lonergan is gesturing in the direction not only of his own contributions in the area of Christology and the Trinity but also towards his thesis concerning an implicit "differentiation of consciousness" that goes forward within the development of dogma: the emergence of "Christian realism" -that is, not only a distinctive Christian metaphysic, as integral to the Christian cultural world-view, but a distinctive Christian epistemology. The passage also places in context the previous passage from Method. In the light of the subsequent remarks one can see that in the earlier passage Lonergan has undifferentiated, or "primitive," consciousness in mind as the receiver of the Christian message. But in the later passage he takes cognizance of other stages of consciousness as possible receivers of that same message. In light of this, if one is going to communicate the Christian message effectively to cultures with a more differentiated consciousness (or rather with elements of, for example, philosophical or theoretical differentiation present in the culture), one will have to be on the level of that task. Furthermore, if the truth of Christianity is to be effectively communicated, questions and further questions have to be met. And this will only be achieved by further theoretical differentiation, or (in a "turn to the subject") by the shift to interiority, in the modern context. If this is so then it cannot be true, in an unqualified way, that the pluralist evangelizer avoids promoting differentiations of consciousness. For in order effectively to communicate Christian truth, not error or myth, he may very well have to invite the hearers of the message to move from commonsense meaning to an understanding involving some theoretical elements and, at the limit, metaphysical and psychological elements, if authentic questions are to be met. One may indeed expect such differentiated forms of evangelization to occur in cultures such as those of Asia, where commonsense and religious elements are complemented by metaphysical and psychological traditions of speculation of some sophistication. We need to understand further something of the significance of this for Lonergan's bold claim concerning a normativity implicit in Christian culture. Foundational in Lonergan's view of method in theology are three conversions: intellectual, moral, and religious. Intellectual conversion is a matter of moving away from "INTERCULTURALITY"AND SALVATION 185 all forms of naive realism, empiricism, idealism, rationalism, and relativism to an adequate cognitional theory and epistemology which can be justified in a self-referential manner; this basic position (which may be indefinitely improved but not radically revised under pain of incoherence) will then provide the basis for the adumbration of a critically grounded metaphysics, ethics, and natural theology. Being intellectually converted is a matter of moving out of the world of the infant, the world of immediacy, into the world mediated by meaning; it is being able to make explicit in knowledge of the self the intellectual and moral operations used since childhood of which, due to the "polymorphism" of consciousness, it is extremely difficult to give an accurate account. Lonergan sees this work of adumbrating a self-consistent basic philosophical position as occurring within an historical tradition and precisely because of that tradition. Not only are Aristotle and Aquinas key figures here, but because it is necessary to reappropriate their basic insights in terms of a philosophy based on the data of one's own consciousness others in the tradition such as Augustine, Descartes, and Newman are also essential contributors. Lonergan's attitude to the Western intellectual tradition, then, is one of acknowledged dependency but at the same time critical retrieval. The metaphysical terms and relations which the theologian may critically justify in terms of the evidence of consciousness are congruent with many of those found in the tradition, primarily as represented by Aquinas. Lonergan's "movement to the third stage of meaning" (focusing on consciousness, interiority) is, then, neither a Wittgensteinian kicking away of the ladder once one has used it to ascend to where one would, nor an Hegelian Aufhebung which sees past elements as "blind" in their incompleteness. Such an appropriation of Western culture, as critical of that culture's shortcomings as it truly is indeed a strong claim concerning a normativity implicit in that culture. But as it stands it is a claim that de facto through the mediation of forces within that culture one is able to mount to a critical epistemology and metaphysics. Given this thesis one could argue that since on Lonergan's view the intellectual and moral operations implicit in human acting are transcultural, other cultures could just as well 186 ANDREW BEARDS provide the milieu for the process of self-mediation required for such development" Indeed, while Lonergan did not delve much the intricacies of the religious philosophies of Asia there is plenty of evidence the theoretical differentiation has been operative there, and that the move to interiority, or reflection on consciousness, is present in such religious-philosophical speculation, just as one finds explorations into consciousness (anticipating a philosophical position that would exploit this in a systematic fashion) in Aristotle, Augustine, and Aquinas"50 However, Lonergan's analysis of the "origins of Christian realism" appears to be an even stronger thesis than this: it is a thesis concerning an intellectual normativity implicit Christianity precisely as Christian" The process that witnessed the emergence of Christian dogmas was, Lonergan believes, a dialectical one"51 The word of God as truth was apprehended in diverse differentiations of consciousness, in commonsense, symbolic, or aesthetic manners, but always as true. Furthermore, as further questions arose this word of God as truth was the subject of questioning, of attempts to understand its implications. Lonergan insists that any attempt to play off the "simple integrity of the gospel" against the "corruption of Hellenized dogma," whether this be espoused by biblical "romantics" or those operating from a philosophical position (e"g", L. Dewart or Bo Welte), does justice neither to what Catholic faith nor to what reason tells us of this process of dogmatic development" The dialectic operative in the process manifests itself in the way various philosophical tendencies resist the emergence of the Trinitarian and Christological dogmas. Lonergan stresses that the very philosophical positions that resisted their emergence are in important respects similar to the philosophies that today continue to deny the 50 On may observe how even in Anglo-American philosophical circles of late there have appeared works relating philosophical discussions well known in the Western tradition to similar debates in the history of Asian philosophy. For example, see Chakravarthi Ram-Prasad's treatment of the epistemological debate between Vasubandhu and Sankara, "Dreams and the Coherence of Experience," American Philosophical Quarterly 32 (1995): 225-39. 51 See Lonergan, Way to Nicea; also "The Origins of Christian Realism" (1961), and "Theology as Christian Phenomenon," in Crowe, ed., Collected Works 6; and "The Origins of Christian Realism," in Lonergan, Second Collection, 1974. "INfERCULTURALITY" AND SALVATION 187 cogency of the dogmas. 52 In accepting the truths of faith as taught by the magisterium the Christian is a "dogmatic realist." That is, he believes the truths proposed for him to judge as true on the authority of the Word of God. Nor, on Lonergan's view, can one play off "cold propositions" against the "interpersonal encounter" with Christ. This is a large topic, one with which Lonergan was concerned one way or another in much of his work, but a couple of points will suffice to indicate how the issue can be approached. First, in Aristotelian-Thomist terms knowledge is not primarily via correspondence (proposition over against thing with which it is concerned) but by intentional identity between knower and known. Second, propositions are means by which we necessarily express insights into fact and value in our lives, including the vital area of interpersonal relations. Without such insights, which are myriad, and occur in the complexity of relations, these relations could hardly be described as interpersonal at all-for aspects of human intersubjectivity are also shared by the higher animals. Third, affirming truths about what a relationship is can be essential to the flourishing of that relationship (truths about one's marriage, for example). And to affirm as true that God did not get a man to die for us and free us from our sins but that God did this himself makes all the difference to our intersubjective relationship with Christ Jesus. The Christian as dogmatic realist accepts the truths of faith in judgment in a way cognate with the critical realist's position that truth is known only in judgment: not in sensate experience alone, nor in a combination of that experience with understanding, but through a judgment as to the truth, falsehood, or probability of that understanding of experience. Given natural human tendencies towards various forms of picture thinking (such as empiricism or naive realism, on the one hand, or idealism and rationalism, on the other), there will be a resistance to the view, implicit in the Christian dogmatic affirmation, that truth is known in judgment. Thus Lonergan finds in T ertullian, for example, a type of Trinitarian thinking which must picture reality as the spatially extended: a form of empiricism and materialism. In Origen, on s2 Lonergan, Way to Nicea, section 1, p. 8. 188 ANDREW BEARDS the other hand, one discovers a form of Neoplatonism, caught up in philosophical confusions engendered by talking of God in terms of the Good beyond Being. It is interesting to note that on Lonergan's view the contemporary philosophical parallels to Origen are found in the post-Husserlian thought of J. Trouillard and H. Dumery. The dialectical approach he implies should be taken to their work would, I believe, extend in some way to that of Levinas and Marion. 53 To argue that Christianity fell captive to Greek thought is, therefore, to understand little of what was happening. Rather, The statement that Christ is God, that Jesus of Nazareth is God, created Christian philosophy; working from its presuppositions, you are forced to some sort of ontology. At Nicea, there was not an adequate basis provided by any Greek philosophy. The current philosophies of the time were Stoicism and Platonism and Epicureanism, and none of them would bear the type of thinking represented by the homoousion, the consubstantiale, of Nicea. A new type of philosophy would have to be developed to enshrine, to be able to include, that notion, a philosophy in terms of existence in the medieval sense. It was not something readymade that the Fathers borrowed from the Greeks; there was no Greek philosophy they could borrow to express what they concluded from revelation. Aristotle never was much esteemed by the Greek Fathers; he was looked upon, at that time, as simply an empiricist-a judgement that has not a little foundation in the Aristotelian writings. 54 According to the thesis of Christian realism, then, the world-view implicit in Christianity involves not only a distinctive theology, 53 Crowe, ed., Collected Works 6, 125 n. 8. The materials for a detailed "face-to-face" encounter between Lonergan and E. Levinas are certainly there. In his own way Lonergan acknowledges the importance of the phenomenology of the "face" (see ibid., 96-98; Method in Theology, 59-60). Like Levinas he rejects an epistemological and ethical solipsism (which Levinas detects in Husserl and Heidegger); knowledge of self or consciousness is a knowledge of an aspect of Being, and, also, it is achieved as ethical endeavor towards, ultimately, the Other of God. Further, such an endeavor can only come about, de facto, within the context of authentic community. However, much divides the two thinkers precisely in terms of the difference in traditions noted in note 33 above. From Lonergan's perspective one would have to bring out the inevitable cognitional and metaphysical consequences implicit in Derrida's critique (of course denied by him) of Levinas in terms of an incoherent attempt to slip free of the language of the "same" (which is, in fact, employed) to refer to the "Other." 54 Crowe, ed., Collected Works 6, 262. See, also, works mentioned in note 52 above, and the celebrated book review, "The Dehellenization of Dogma," in Lonergan, Second Collection. "INTERCULTURALITY"AND SALVATION 189 cosmology, and anthropology but also a distinct epistemologynamely, an epistemology that implies that forms of empiricism or idealism are inimical to Christian faith. This philosophical position becomes increasingly explicit in the tradition itself through the lived tradition of faith within which the pronouncements of the magisterium play their role, and as we move from the reflections of Augustine to those of Aquinas to those of twentieth-century Christian thinkers such as Lonergan. That Christian tradition is itself the "way down" (to use a Lonerganian expression): the culture of meanings and values in which Lonergan was able to delineate anew, with a precision and accuracy at the level of our philosophical times, that critical Christian realism from "below upwards" (i.e., from reflection on consciousness to an adumbration of a metaphysics, ethics, theology). This Christian world-view, then, is no product of Hellenized philosophy, nor of any other particular contribution made from a cultural context in which Christianity has grown. On Lonergan's view it is a distinctive Christian philosophical world-view. This thesis, then, is a claim concerning the normative elements in Christian culture even more radical than that outlined by Ratzinger. Such a thesis is cognate with the views on the origins of the scientific world-view expressed by scholars such as Whitehead and, more recently, Stanley Jaki. On their view the scientific world-view of the West can only be understood within the metaphysical context of the Judaeo-Christian world-view. One might add that, for better or worse, the scientific world-view of the West has enjoyed far more missionary success in all parts of the globe than its supposed Christian parent. Now, however, in a post-Christian Western culture one witnesses a form of tragic battle, a struggle to the death between the Cain of scientism and the Abel of philosophical relativism. According to Lonergan's notion of the origins of Christian realism, then, there was a certain inevitability about the way in which the preaching of the Christian faith in various cultural contexts during the first millennium would involve a "promotion" of the differentiations of consciousness, as that message was received and its meaning and implications for life were sought. Yet this will also be inevitable in our own day. In preaching the 190 ANDREW BEARDS Word as true in the developed cultures of Asia one will also encounter cultures suffused with elements of the theoretical, and, further, in whatever part of the globe the Christian message is preached Western science is already there proclaiming some kind of world-view which, given the exigencies of human being, will have to be related in a meaningful way to the prior cultural traditions of the region, which may or may not have already elements of the theoretical differentiation of consciousness within them. If the distorted progeny of the Christian world-view, scientism and relativism, are not to gain a foothold that would resist the preaching of the faith, then the readiness to "promote" philosophical differentiation in the culture is all the more urgent. As we have seen, Lonergan argues vigorously that Christian realism, the philosophical world-view of Christianity, arose in dialectical tension with the existing philosophies of the first millennium. This is not to deny the enormous importance of the "Greek discovery" of mind for this process, but it is to place it in proper perspective. If it is the Christian doctrines that bring about this new world-view, this new philosophy, with its metaphysics and epistemology, then it should be clearly understood that in promoting such a world-view one is not promoting European culture but Christian culture. This is witnessed to not only by the very evolution of that world-view but by the withdrawal of Western culture from this world-view in another dialectical process which has gone on apace since, at least, the Enlightenment. Today in a largely secularized West the theological, anthropological, and cosmological perspectives of Christianity are ignored or challenged in terms of materialism, relativism, and the like. Ultimately the question of evangelization and inculturation is not a matter of West and East, North and South, but of Christianity and its reception in the world as a whole. The passing of the modern period of "colonial evangelization" should help us gain this perspective ever more clearly. In reality we are in a situation more akin to those of the early centuries of evangelization: a situation in which Christianity does not enjoy cultural hegemony. In terms of the Lonerganian theory of Christian realism what is at issue here is an intellectual conversion which must take place, sooner or later, within the cultures "INTERCULTURALITY" AND SALVATION 191 Christianity encounters. Just as the intellectual and moral operations of the human person are, Lonergan argues, transcultural, so is the "polymorphism" of human consciousness; so also is the difficulty of moving from the world of infant immediacy to an account of how we come to know reality and the good in a world mediated by meaning. Significantly, in this regard, Lonergan draws attention to the family resemblances between (Western) Platonism and (Eastern) Brahminism in their failure to effect just such a philosophical transition: they are unable to express philosophically the criteria for correct knowledge of reality--criteria with which, without explicit reflection, we operate spontaneously from childhood. 55 The philosophical issue, therefore, is not primarily one of East versus West. Lonergan relates the story of a missionary who was able to convert a Japanese bonze only after he had assisted the later to grasp the principle of noncontradiction: that not all paths up Mount Fujiyama were one and the same. 56 One may reflect that the same problem occurs at present for the evangelizer in the post-Christian West, where relativism and indifferentism are the order of the day for many. Lonergan's principle, enunciated in the final chapter of Method, that the evangelist should not ask others to renounce their culture but should rather seek ways to "proceed from within their culture .. . making it into a vehicle for communicating the Christian message," 57 is totally laudable as the ideal for which to strive. But once this is situated in the context of other perspectives from his work, namely, the thesis on "Christian realism," one can appreciate that in many situations the new wine will not sit well in old bottles. Thus, a culture that has at its center human sacrifice (e.g., the Aztec) or a culture that feels its metaphysicopolitical ethic threatened by Christianity (e.g., Japan in the seventeenth century) will experience no little upheaval as the old metaphysical world-view is replaced. This is equally so in the modern West. For a post-Christian culture to accept once more the Christian metaphysic and anthropology, the relativism and Crowe, ed., Collected Works 6, 120-21. Understanding and Being, 301. 57 Lonergan, Method in Theology, 363. 55 56 Lonergan, 192 ANDREW BEARDS materialism in which the only still point in a turning world is some kind of communality based on hedonism must be repudiated and an anthropological view of the sacredness of human life from conception to death accepted, along with the social ethic of human solidarity which this anthropology implies. One may examine what Lonergan has to say about this Christian realism, as distinctive of, I would say, Christian culture, from the angle of his analysis of the three conversions (intellectual, moral, religious). He distinguishes between a general definition of religious conversion, as a "falling in love in an unrestricted way" with the otherworldly and transcendent, on the one hand, and how this may be judged to be actually achieved, on the other. 58 To be authentic, religious conversion must be ongoing; it must also promote moral and intellectual conversion. This is a methodological, or phenomenological, point concerning religion and conversion in general, without specific reference to any particular religion. But one can note that even from this perspective what Lonergan is suggesting is that a religious conversion or a religion may ultimately be assessed in terms of how well it promotes views congruent with the epistemology and metaphysics that arise, historically, from Christianity. However, there is more to be observed with regard to the analysis of the triple conversions. Later in Method Lonergan writes, "Men may or may not be converted intellectually, morally, religiously. If they are not, and the lack of conversion is conscious and thoroughgoing, it heads for loss of faith." And he continues, "while the unconverted may have no real apprehension of what it is to be converted, at least they have in doctrines the evidence both that there is something lacking in themselves and that they need to pray for illumination and seek instruction. "59 58 Lonergan, Method in Theology, 283-84. The broader and deeper perspectives opened up by Lonergan and Ratzinger for the theme of inculturation and evangelization entail that Rahner's often cited position that Vatican II marked a shift from a European to a world Church has only limited value. It is not so much the case that Christianity is or was a European phenomenon as that Europe is a Christian phenomenon. 59 Lonergan, Method in Theology, 298-99. These words of Lonergan are in some way echoed by Cardinal Ratzinger in his address to the 1998 Synod of Asian Bishops in Rome, when he affirmed that experience is not the measure of the truths of faith, rather it is itself judged and transformed by. those truths. "INTERCULTURALITY"AND SALVATION 193 When one reflects on this passage from the perspective of the Christian-realism thesis one appreciates that one of the issues being touched upon is that resistance to the rise of Christian dogmas and Christian realism can arise from philosophical positions that in some way still resist their acceptance; and such resistance, one may anticipate, is transcultural. The passage is also worth pondering with regard to a topic debated among students of Lonergan's work: how does the "phenomenologically" outlined "religious conversion" stand to conversion to a specific religion, to Christianity? One may methodologically describe some features of religious conversion in general (the orientation to other-worldliness), and even have some "religion-independent" criterion in evaluating a religion or a religious conversion in terms of how well it ultimately fosters intellectual and authentic moral conversion. However, the further question arises: above and beyond moral and intellectual criteria how can one evaluate religious conversion? The last passage cited shows that this cannot be done in a "nondenominational" way; it has to be from the viewpoint of some specific religious conversion, such as that to Christianity. Evaluating the authenticity of a religious conversion is evaluating an ongoing process, not just simply noting that religious conversion is "towards the unworldly." One can write, as Lonergan occasionally does, of being an authentic or inauthentic Buddhist, Hindu, etc., but from a religion-neutral or merely phenomenological viewpoint this cannot be consistently pursued, for it implies that when a Buddhist or Hindu rejects such and such a doctrine or typical feature of his religion then the conversion is inauthentic. But it is not for the methodologist to determine whether it is the dissident or the doctrine in question that is inauthentic; that may only be determinable from the viewpoint of the conversion to the specific faith itself. Thus when Lonergan writes that the unconverted need to pray and seek instruction in order to accept doctrine he is presuming a specific faith commitment. Finally, then, the authenticity of religious conversion, when this involves questions over and above what may be examined in terms of intellectual and moral criteria, can only be determined from within a faith context: as a Catholic I see another's rejection of some teaching 194 ANDREW BEARDS of his faith not as inauthentic but, perhaps, as a move along the road of authenticity. As an evaluation of the contextualization and embeddedness of Western intellectual endeavor Lonergan's analysis of the origins of Christian realism has a peculiarly postmodern ring to it. Where the Enlightenment sought freedom from that context, the postmodern thinker is adept at detecting just where the Christian presuppositions of Enlightenment proclamations of self-evident truths and moral principles appear at the margins. But as was noted above, both Lonergan and Macintyre as Catholic thinkers make common cause with postmodern critiques of modernity only to part company with them in showing that they are parasitic upon what they would oppose. Thus Christian realism, as providing the context for the genius of Aquinas, provides also indications of an epistemological critique of postmodernity. To say that intellectual endeavor is embedded in Christian faith is not thereby to vitiate that endeavor, but rather, just as science has relied on cultural context (Popper's "metaphysical research programmes") for genuine advance, so Christianity fosters the context and the virtues for genuine advance in truth. It was perhaps no accident that one of the most severe critiques of epistemological scepticism issued from the newly converted Augustine in the Contra Academicos. And there is deconstructive irony in the way the constitution Dei Filius of the First Vatican Council, and the encyclical Pascendi of Pope St. Pius X, provided the context in which intellectual endeavor in Catholicism could move confidently on, steering between the Scylla of nineteenth-century fideism and neo-Kantian modernism and the Charybdis of eighteenth and nineteenth-century rationalism and positivism. For the Enlightenment dream of unfettered rationality had only issued in a nightmarish oscillation between profound Nietzschean scepticism and heady Comtean positivism. At this point it would be well to sum up the principal points made in the argument of this section. First, it has been argued that Ratzinger's analysis of Christianity as a "cultural subject" is not, from the perspective of Lonergan's thought, an instance of classicism reasserting itself. Lonergan's own analysis of classicism is not to be taken out of context. Indeed Ratzinger's analysis helps "INTERCULTURALTIY"AND SALVATION 195 to draw attention to elements in Lonergan's work that may require development. Thus, insofar as for both Lonergan and Ratzinger embracing Christianity is entering into an intersubjective relationship with the Word made flesh, Jesus Christ, just so this intersubjective relationship will involve a participation in the culture that the Word assumed, transformed, but fundamentally confirmed. Second, Lonergan proposes a more radical thesis than that proposed by Ratzinger, but in the direction of Ratzinger's thought. This is Lonergan's notion of "Christian realism": a specifically Christian "philosophy" or world-view, involving theological, metaphysical, and anthropological but also epistemological elements. While this world-view emerges in clarity only over time, and through a process with particular historical and cultural features, still it is intrinsic to Christianity and is, therefore, transcultural. Therefore any culture, be it Western or Eastern, must adapt to the exigencies of this Christian world-view if the faith is authentically to take root in it; this process, ideally, will involve some "fusion of horizons" between the receptor culture and Christianity, for at base all cultures are equally human cultures. But it cannot evade the cross of conversion, which also involves leaving "home and family" to follow the Lord. III. EXTRA ECCLES/AM NULLA SALUS Towards the end of his 1993 lecture Ratzinger turns his attention to the radical nature of Christian conversion as this is seen by the Fathers. This theme is not new in his theology. It is one upon which he dwelt in the course of a critical reflection on Rahner's approach to the question of the salvation of the nonbaptized: the question of the universality yet historical particularity of Christianity, issues which Rahner has discussed under the rubric of "anonymous Christianity." 60 Ratzinger notes what he sees as positive elements in Rahner's Hearersof the Word but then goes on to outline what he sees as the heart of Rahner's conceptual solution to the questions which arise in this area, and, in 60 See Ratzinger, Principlesof Catholic Theology, 161-70. 196 ANDREW BEARDS a series of questions, asks whether this solution really does justice to the problem. He then proceeds to critique some of the more "popular" versions of "humanist Christianity" claiming to derive from Rahner but which, Ratzinger points out, do not do justice to Rahner's analyses. 61 Rahner attempts to combine the universality of history with the particularity of Christianity without sacrificing the latter's uniqueness. According to Ratzinger, Rahner makes a first attempt at this by describing Christianity as the most successful apprehension of what is always and everywhere implicitly accepted in human consciousness. 62 However, Ratzinger senses that Rahner feels more needs to be said. Rahner does so, first in terms of an analysis of Christ as the one who is apprehended as the "Absolute bringer of Salvation," the One who alone can be said to be God's final word in history since what is achieved in him is the highest that can be achieved in human nature. As the successful instance of human self-transcendence, Christ is in some sense the "concrete universal." Ratzinger continues: From what has been said, it follows "that in the meeting with him [Christ] .. . the mystery of reality itself ... " is present. Even more clearly: "The relationship to Jesus Christ, in which an individual ... makes Jesus, present within him, the mediator of his direct relationship with God" is such "that man in his existence ... is always already within this relationship whether he is explicitly aware of it or not." From this, Rahner develops his basic formula of Christian existence ... : "He who accepts his existence ... says ... Yes to Christ." 63 In response to this conceptual scheme, Ratzinger writes: This broadly outlined thesis of Rahner's has something dazzling, something stupendous, about it. The particular and the universal, history and being, seem to be reconciled .... But is that really the answer? Is it true that Christianity adds nothing to the universal but merely makes it known? Is the Christian just man as he is? ... Is not man as he is insufficient, that which must be mastered and transcended? Does not the whole dynamism of history stem from the 61 Ibid., 168-70. 62 Ibid., 164. The reference is to Karl Rahner, Foundations of Christian Faith, trans. William V. Dych (London: Darton, Longman and Todd, 1978), 151. 63 Ratzinger, Principles of Catholic Theology, 165; Rahner, Foundations, 204-6, 225-26. "INTERCULTURALITY" AND SALVATION 197 pressure to rise above man as he is? Is it not the main point of the faith of both Testaments that man is what he ought to be only by conversion, that is, when he ceases to be what he is?64 Another way to grasp what is "dazzling" about the Rahnerian thesis of "anonymous Christianity" is to reflect that what was in the tradition a mysterious "marginal" doctrine of the salvation of the unbaptized has become transformed into the norm. Does this not, one may ask, reduce the missions of the Holy Spirit and the Son one to another? Is there any longer a real urgency about hearing the word and accepting the Word, of entering into intersubjective communion with Jesus of Nazareth, whose historical, incarnate presence is mediated, for the most part, through intersubjective encounter with his Body the Church? What appears to have happened in this Rahnerian construction, which makes the mysterious and marginal central, is a buckling and bending of the data of the tradition, the preaching, prayer, and teaching concerning salvation, so that it is now forced to fit in with a thesis which began life precisely as a theological model to assist in gaining insight into the belief of the faith tradition itself. By presenting this thesis of anonymous Christianity Rahner has only made us raise a new question, a question implicit in Ratzinger's questioning: how are we to think through the eschatological urgency of conversion to Christ? This eschatological urgency, which surely cannot be rendered as peripheral to the gospel message, is what the Church in her magisterium has safeguarded through the teaching "no salvation outside the Church," a teaching which received classic formulations at Lateran IV and Florence. There are perspectives from Lonergan that would throw light on this issue, an issue intimately connected with the themes of the distinctiveness of Christianity, evangelization, and inculturation. To begin with, I think it important to return to Mansini's critique of Rahner. As was noted, Mansini believes that from Lonergan's viewpoint Rahner is still captivated by a scientific ideal in theology which has not yet appreciated the shift from proof to understanding as the ideal of systematics-a shift parallel to that 64 Ratzinger, Principlesof Catholic Theology, 166. 198 ANDREW BEARDS which has occurred in the development of modern science, but the implications of which were well known to Aquinas. 65 For example, is the thesis of "anonymous Christianity" framed and expressed as theological argument ex convenientiae (a model or hypothesis in the area of a systematic reflection on the doctrines of the tradition) or does it take on the dimensions of a quasi-philosophical anthropology in its own right, a system which appears to bend and buckle the data of the tradition? If Lonergan is right about systematics, then one should perhaps be as suspicious here as one would be of a scientific hypothesis which lacks critical control, or "modesty" with regard to the data it would explain. In other words, is the theory of anonymous Christianity somewhat extravagant, more than is needed for gaining insight into this area of the tradition? And does it actually do justice to all the data, including the eschatological urgency of conversion through intersubjective encounter with Christ and his Body? To add a prescriptive precept to these probings, one might say that for Lonergan, the last thing systematics is about is systems building. A second, yet allied, issue concerning the uniqueness of Christianity from the perspective of Lonergan's work is the distance he maintained from one of the central positions of the nouvelle theologie, as this emerged in the 1940s and 1950s. Lonergan took the view, and argued the case philosophically, that one could not rule out a "state of pure nature," while at the same time he maintained that the "state of pure nature" was itself a rather peripheral theological theorem. 66 If he held the latter, one might 65 Mansini is not alone in believing there is quite massive disagreement between the positions of these two theologians, once the implications of their positions are worked out dialectically, despite the linking of the two as "transcendental Thomists" in the standard dictionary entries. See Raymond Moloney, "The Mind of Christ in Transcendental Theology: Rabner, Lonergan and Crowe," The Heythrop Journal 25 (1984): 299-300; J. Michael Stebbins, "Introduction," in The Divine Initiative (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1995); Michael Vertin, "Marechal, Lonergan, and the Phenomenology of Knowing," in M. Lamb, ed., Creativity and Method: Studies in Honor of Bernard Lonergan (Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1981), 411-22; Guy Mansini, "Rabner and Balthasar on the Efficacy of the Cross," The Irish Theological Quarterly 63 (1998): 232-49. 66 See "The Natural Desire to See God," in Bernard Lonergan, Collection (2d ed.), ed. F.E. Crowe and R.M. Doran (Toronto Univ. Press: Toronto, 1988); also the ample treatment of this area of Lonergan's theology given in Stebbins, The Divine Initiative. "INTERCULTURALITY" AND SALVATION 199 ask, why bother to go to the trouble of defending the former notion? I think it is especially in hindsight that the point of such a defense becomes dear. What Lonergan detected in some of the aspects of the nouvelle theologie were elements cognate with a theology modeled on philosophical deduction, or demonstration, which had been manifest before in fourteenth-century nominalism and nineteenth-century semirationalism. Given this context as background, one can move on to examine some of the points relevant to our question made by Lonergan in chapter 20 of Insight, a chapter Lonergan continued to believe important in his late period as can be witnessed from his late essay "Mission and the Spirit. " 67 This chapter is a Lonerganian equivalent to Rahner's Hearers of the Word, or the philosophical reflections on the "obediential capacity" one finds in, say, BlondeL However, the differences are as significant as the similarities. For one thing, Lonergan's position runs counter to Rahner's central thesis concerning the "deduction" of the Incarnation from the phenomenon of the "final bringer of Salvation." Lonergan argues that one may anticipate a divine solution, communication to humankind, given the problem of evil and the divine goodness. However, he distinguishes between what he calls "natural solutions," "relatively supernatural solutions," and "absolutely supernatural solutions"- among the latter of which, one may infer, would be the Incarnation. 68 If Lonergan's philosophical analysis is correct here, Rahner's attempted transcendental deduction is stymied. For one could not deduce that the word of God claiming to be definitive (and part of the divine solution would be assistance offered to see that this was God's definitive word as far as human history is concerned) entailed the Incarnation of the Word. One can, of course, think of concrete historical examples which would give some idea of what this could mean: for example, the Koran accepted as God's definitive word, and ruling out an idea of Incarnation. One would be hard put to it to show that this Islamic approach was incorrect on purely philosophical grounds, and one would have to contend with Lonergan's argument to the contrary. 67 68 In Lonergan, Third Collection, 23-34. Lonergan, Insight, 725. 200 ANDREW BEARDS One of the philosophical perspectives Lonergan brings to bear on this theological issue derives from his analysis of the emergently probable course of cosmic evolution. Given the indeterminacy of stages or levels of emergence relative to future developments, the indeterminacy of the potency of a stage of cosmic development implies that one cannot always determine with exactitude what such and such a "nature" will ultimately require or demands (within the wider context of world-order) for its fulfillment. It is therefore again too quick, from a philosophical perspective, to say that human beings require divine sonship for the fulfilment "nature" demands, or that the Incarnation has any kind of cosmogenic or anthropological necessity attached to it. One might suggest that in this way, maintaining a notion of "obediential capacity" which is genuine and yet highlights indeterminacy, Lonergan does more justice to the Barthian insistence on the novelty and sovereign freedom of divine self-communication. In a number of ways Ratzinger's questions concerning the adequacy of Rahner's analysis are cognate with Lonergan's treatment in chapter 20 of Insight. Just as Ratzinger indicates that Christianity and conversion have more to do with "going beyond" being a man than with accepting oneself as such, and that history's own tension manifests this struggle, so Lonergan insists that the heightened tension, which would result from a supernatural solution, would not lack its objectification in the dialectical succession of human situations ... when this problem of evil is met by a supernatural solution, human perfection itself becomes a limit to be transcended ... there will be a humanism in revolt against the proffered supernatural solution ... rest[ing] on man's proud content to be just a man, and its tragedy is that, on the present supposition of a supernatural solution, to be just a man is what a man cannot be.69 What this analysis of Lonergan's suggests is that every form of "humanism" is some fundamental form of alienating ideology. A constant theme of the present pontificate has been the Holy Father's proclamation of the teaching of Gaudium et spes: m 69 Ibid., 728-29. "INTERCULTURALITY"AND SALVATION 201 God to Man Christ at once reveals man to himself. Perhaps one may say, then, that any form of "humanism," of human religion (and here one can include all religions of humankind to some extent which, unlike Christianity, are not the self-revelation of God, whatever their undoubted God-given goodness may be), has to it the tragic aspect of concealing and alienating man from himself, since none propose precisely that self-revelation of man as son in the Son, to which dignity he is called and compelled. To reverse Rahner's point, that to accept oneself and one's existence is to accept salvation, one may urge that the tragic element in history involves mutually self-mediating meaning and (dis)values in human beliefs which precisely prevent any real discovery of who one is or what one is, most fundamentally, called to be. Thus without the Word I cannot accept my existence, for I know not what that self and that existence are, or are meant to be. Here we may return to the methodological issue of a systematics which is truly "modest" and which truly strives to do justice, through models and analogies, to the truths of faith. For one can ask whether the Rahnerian scheme of things does justice to the massive theme in revelation of the profound tragedy which marks the history of the human race in its alienation from God, a tragedy which goes hand in hand with the wonder of redemption from the thrall of such alienation. We need, then, models that do justice to the drama of conversion, to the passionate desire for the Word, and intersubjective communion with Him and his Body-models that do justice to the eschatological urgency of conversion, and the redemption of a whole universe in the pangs of giving birth, as the Pauline vision has it. A key element in Rahner's account is the analogy or model of the move from "anonymous Christianity" to explicit conversion to Christ provided by the philosophical analysis of the way a person may move from implicit, unthematic "knowledge" to explicit, thematic knowledge regarding, for example, his own cognitive capacities. Although Lonergan and Rabner have divergent views of knowledge, consciousness, and this very process of explication, one may grant, from Lonergan's perspective, that something akin to what Rabner describes can occur in 202 ANDREW BEARDS the process of individual self-discovery. No doubt, one can say that such a process is indeed a good both for the individual and for the community, and is vitally important as history progresses: for we have seen how vitally important intellectual conversion is for Lonergan. However, the question remains whether this transition, or conversion from implicit to explicit, provides us with a dramatic enough instance for understanding the drama of conversion to Christ. For myriad are those in human history (saints included), who have lived out authentic lives without such a process of self-discovery. Can we say that for the individual such a growth in self-knowledge is so decisive or totally necessary? For it does not appear that the gospel call to conversion is offered in such an "optional" manner, or to the few who might benefit from it and mediate its benefits to others. There is, I believe, a more dramatic anthropological model to be found Lonergan's work which provides images for insight into the passionate urgency which the call to conversion has always manifested in Christianity. Writing of the necessity of the Word for human meaning and being, Lonergan uses the analogy of the couple who are in love but have not yet offered the word, or expression, of love to one another; when they do so the word is not optional, nor empty, but creates a new situation of mutual self-mediation in its expression. 70 However, while Lonergan employs this analogy when writing of the significance of the word for religion, in Method, he provides an even more powerful anthropological image of the importance of the word in an earlier section of the work, a section dealing with linguistic meaning in which the discussion has no intended theological import. The story he uses is that of the breakthrough to linguistic meaning of the dumb and mute Helen Keller. Lonergan writes, The moment of language in human development is most strikingly illustrated by the story of Helen Keller's discovery that the successive touches made on her hand by her teacher conveyed names of objects. The moment when she first caught on was marked by the expression of profound emotion and, in turn, the emotion bore fruit in so powerful an interest that she signified her desire to 70 Lonergan, Method in Theology, 113. "INTERCULTURALITY'' AND SALVATION 203 learn and did learn the names of about twenty objects in a very short time. It was the beginning of an incredible career of learning. 71 He goes on to draw out the existential and ontological significance for the becoming of the person of Helen Keller of this encounter with the liberating word: In Helen Keller's emotion and interest one can surmise the reason why ancient civilizations prized names so highly .... Prizing names is prizing the human achievement of bringing conscious intentionality into sharp focus and, thereby, setting about the double task of both ordering one's world and orienting oneself within it. Just as the dream at daybreak may be said to be the beginning of the process from impersonal existence to the presence of a person in his world, so listening and speaking are a major part in the achievement of that presence. 72 While the move from potency to act involved in the shift from adult self-consciousness to explicit self-knowledge, which provides Rahner with an analogy for the shift from unthematic anonymous Christianity to explicit Christian conversion, is no doubt an important good, the far more dramatic instance of Helen Keller's transformation from inchoate, passionately frustrated conscious disorientation to a new life of presence to self and to others through the mediation of the word is a far more appropriate instance of the movement from potency to act through which to appreciate the drama of the moment of Christian conversion. Again, returning to Rahner's point concerning self-acceptance as salvific acceptance of Christ, we can see in poor Helen Keller's example an anthropological image of helplessness such that acceptance of oneself or one's existence is impossible without the coming of the word which, as coming from the outside, both reveals the "other" of the teacher and the world and at once allows Helen's own self-discovery and selfconstitution. Sacrament-like, it effects, as effective and constitutive meaning, what it proclaims. To return to a point made above, one can perhaps say that aH "humanisms" (including all non-Christian religions), whatever noble and graced elements 71 72 Ibid., 70. Ibid. 204 ANDREW BEARDS there may be in them, nevertheless contain "words" of obfuscation and alienation within them precisely insofar as they cannot be that incarnate Word of Christianity which reveals to persons, and effects as it reveals, their new nature as sons and daughters in the Son. A further allied question may be raised at this point. Does the gospel message of salvation and the truths of faith revealed require us to say that Christian nature, the nature of adopted Divine filiation, is always and everywhere found with human nature? In other words, is Rahner's anthropological model of anonymous Christianity a cogent way of understanding the truths of faith concerning the call to conversion? Bearing in mind the methodological point made above concerning the relation between systematics and doctrines in theological method, we can ask whether there are not only rivals to Rahner's account here, but in fact models which do more justice to the eschatological urgency of the gospel call to conversion than does Rahner's view. Keeping in mind the points made so far, then, I will now move on to consider a little more explicitly some questions that arise from the teaching "no salvation outside the Church. " 73 The Church has always held to the teaching "no salvation outside the Church," which received explicit formulation in the magisterium at the councils of Lateran IV and Florence, as expressing the eschatological urgency of Christian conversion found in the gospel. Since 1863, however, there have been a number of explicit statements of the magisterium that guard against false interpretations of the Church's faith; thus it is held that in the mysterious providence of God those not now in visible communion with Christ or his members may become so and thus see the face of God. Understandably, perhaps, these two aspects of the Church's teaching in this area are sometimes felt to be in some tension. But one can point to other areas in the develop73 Still helpful in this area, for texts and commentary, are Joseph Fenton, The Catholic Church and Salvation (Glasgow: Sands and Co., 1959); and George J. Dyer, Limbo: UnsettledQuestion (New York: Sheed and Ward, 1964). A more recent treatment is Francis Sullivan, Salvationoutside the Church? (London: Chapman, 1992). Sullivan's interpretation of the data in this area of doctrinal development is, however, not without its critics: see Avery Dulles, "The Church as Locus of Salvation," in The Thought of Pope john Paul II, ed. John M. McDermott, S.J. (Rome: Gregorian University Press, 1993), 169-88. "INTERCULTURALITY'' AND SALVATION 205 ment of dogma where non-mutually-exclusive truths are finally discerned as complementing each other within the plan of salvation. One can think of the dogma of the Immaculate Conception, opposed by some in the name of the doctrine that all men and women require salvation from the fallen human state by Christ. The doctrine could be readily confessed once it was realized that it was not a negation of this truth: our Lady was truly redeemed by Christ, but in an exceptional and anticipatory manner. Perhaps the most explicit magisterial statement on the way the Church's doctrine is to be understood is the Holy Office letter "Suprema haec sacra" of 1949. The letter draws an analogy between those not visibly in the Church and those who died as catechumens, or received baptism by desire in some way (e.g., soldiers in the early centuries of persecution who expressed solidarity with their intended Christian victims and thus shared their fate). The "baptism of desire" of these persons, always admitted by tradition as genuine (thus by the fathers of Florence), may be extended so as to include an "implicit desire" for baptism on the part of those not visibly in the Church but who respond to God's grace with upright lives. It is clear, then, that salvation only comes through being incorporated into Christ. However, one should note that the document modestly states that those who live an upright life and thus may been deemed to have an implicit desire for union with Christ can be saved. It does not put flesh on the bones to say more concerning the manner of this salvation. One could go on to ask, therefore, further questions: for example, does an implicit desire need, at some point, to become more explicit if it is to be recognizably a desire for an intersubjective encounter with the incarnate Word? Indeed, other statements of the magisterium may incline one to pursue such further questions. Thus the teaching of Florence that each person must embrace the faith before death points, I believe, in the direction of some account of this "implicit" desire becoming more explicit. The alternative to Rahner's view that "Christian nature" is always and everywhere found in history which I would suggest is that, firstly, we need not make this affirmation. Rather, I would suggest the anthropological model suggested by the Helen Keller 206 ANDREW BEARDS story: without the encounter with incarnate Word, normally as mediated by the members of his Body, one neither knows the nature to which one is called nor does one yet share that nature. The mission of the Spirit is not collapsed into that of the Son on this account. For the passionate dynamism, the upward struggle towards the fullness of life, so strikingly exemplified in the Helen Keller story, is the unsettling, yet consoling, work of the Holy Spirit calling us towards knowledge of and reception filiation share this nature grace, but all experience in the Son. Not the call to it in an way. Of course, those who have received the priceless gift hear the words that "to those whom much is given much is expected," and part of that expectation is that they share the gift with those who have not yet received it. Perhaps the Keller story, of someone so heroic and so physically challenged, suggests a broader theological analogy. In the world order God has created many there are who are not destined to grow to maturity in the physical order of creation; numerous are those who have died as infants or before birth. In God's mysterious design these too will grow into maturity, and that through the grace of his life, death, and resurrection. However, one can understand that the created world order is, in some way, primarily for the full growth to maturity of human persons, without denying that these others will, in God's mercy, do so. Analogously, all are called to the fullness of life beginning here and now in encounter with Christ, but in God's providence many wiH not achieve this until an eschatological moment at the end of life; yet they will do so "through the others," through Christ and his members. What then could one suggest in place of Christian nature always and everywhere being found, if one admits of a general desire for that nature, and also admits the teaching of the magisterium that only the Church can there be salvation? To suggest reflections in this area pertaining to the theology of the moment of death would not be novel. The theologian B. C. Buder, reflecting upon the implications of Lonergan's work for ecclesiology, came to the condusion that a theological model suggesting conversion to Christ and reception into his Body at (before) the moment of death would best do justice to the "INTERCULTURALITY" AND SALVATION 207 theological data to be understood. 74 Interestingly enough the text from Lonergan that suggested such a conclusion to Butler supports the teaching of Florence. For, Lonergan insists, the divine solution must be accepted and assented to in conscious freedom. (One can understand that the Florence assertion of the need of "acceptance before death" is itself not some drawing of an artificial line but an assertion concerning freedom.) Such a theology of the moment of death need not involve itself in the problems associated with such positions as those of L. Boros (successfully criticized by G. Grisez and others). 75 In this area, I believe, there is no reason why, with due caution, theologians should not take as seriously as do a number of philosophers the data which the numerous studies on "near-death experiences" offer for analysis. One of the theologian's doughtiest opponents, A. N. Flew, a philosopher with every reason to wish for a reductive explanation of such data, has in recent work admitted that much of it is extremely difficult to explain away. 76 For our purposes it is interesting to observe that many of the accounts of such near-death experiences concern "conversions" of a moral and cognitive nature: persons have a different view of existence after them, may move from atheism to theism, and so forth. A theological model making sense of the data provided by the tradition could suggest that "before death" as the final separation there is such an encounter with Christ or his members as to constitute an explicit conversion: an acceptance of an intersubjective relationship with Christ. How "explicit" this would need to be in order to be a genuine intersubjective encounter freely welcomed before death (welcomed by one prepared through grace-filled upright living) is 74 Bishop B. C. Butler, "Lonergan and Ecclesiology," in Foundations of Theology, ed. Philip McShane (Dublin: Gill and Macmillan, 1971), 4-5. Butler refers to Lonergan, Insight, 697. 75 For Grisez's criticism of L. Boros see, G. Grisez, The Way of the Lord Jesus, vol. 1 (Chicago: Franciscan Herald Press, 1983), chap. 16. J. H. Wright's article, "Death (Theology of)," in the New Catholic Encyclopaedia (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1967), 687-95, also critical of "fundamental option" theories of the moment of death, demonstrates, however, the variety of divergent theological theories in this area at the time of the appearance of Boros's book. See also Dyer, Limbo, chapters 4 and 5, for examples of Catholic theologies from 1930 to 1960 of "the moment of death." 76 See, e.g., Anthony Flew, The Logic of Mortality (Oxford: Blackwell, 1987). 208 ANDREW BEARDS open to further reflection. But one should recall that there are lessons here in the way the tradition recognized that unbaptized catechumens or even those who died a martyrdom in solidarity with Christians were "in the Church." Their knowledge of Christianity might be very meager, rudimentary; but in such cases there was a genuine intersubjective encounter with Christ or his Body, not simply a transcendental orientation towards the divine or divine salvific acts. Ratzinger worries that the "transcendental orientation" to Christ is precisely that which tends to render the intersubjective encounter in history with Christ otiose. What is the difference between such a "relationship" and the relationship to possible nonincarnate divine salvific acts? What distinguishes our relation to the Son in his mission from that to the Spirit in his? No doubt the objection will be made that postulating some kind of encounter with Christ and his Body at (before) death, however mysterious an encounter it is acknowledged to be, smacks of a Deus ex machina solution. However, it appears to me less strained than a theory that would postulate that those who explicitly excoriate and deny Christ and his Body or are indifferent to them, for apparently upright reasons, are still, implicitly, in an intersubjective relationship of love with Him. This appears to strain the notion of intersubjective relationship with another incarnate person beyond any meaningful limit. Besides, there appear to be numerous divine interventions in the New Testament which from a variety of perspectives would be seen by opponents as marked with ex machina artificiality. One further observation concerning the "urgency" of the call to Christian conversion can be made. As was noted above, when those who in God's providence are not destined to grow to "full stature" in this life are called by Him to do so in the next, it is through the Other, Christ, and his Body that they do so. The urgency of the call to conversion to Christ is then not just for my own salvation but that I might assist in the salvation of the others. The Christian message is that I am only saved in working for the salvation of others, and this is no less true regarding the mystery of the salvation of those who enter the Church and thereby assume a new Christian nature only at the eschatological point of death. Just as the infant receives baptism through the faith of "INTERCULTURALITY"AND SALVATION 209 others (viz., the parents), so those persons also receive that faith through the mystery of the life and faith of the Church. Through the offering of the sacrifice of the Mass, the worthy celebration and reception of the sacraments, and the living from them into daily life, God's grace flows also to these others. God's victory and victorious presence in this world are assured through his death and resurrection. Yet He genuinely requires our help in continuing this work: the Church can through the lives of its members be more or less effective in being a beacon of salvation to the nations. The urgency of conversion to Christ is an urgency not only for myself but also the concern that others, including those not in communion with the Body during most of the course of their lives, enter the kingdom. CONCLUSION This article has taken the form of an extended reflection on issues raised in Cardinal Ratzinger's 1993 lecture "Christ, Faith, and the Challenge of Cultures." I have attempted an exploration of those issues from the perspective of Bernard Lonergan's philosophy and theology. In clarifying what Lonergan means by the shift from "classicism to historical mindedness" I have not only attempted to show that a more careful and nuanced appropriation of his meaning is required than is sometimes evident, but I have attempted to elucidate some quite far-reaching consequences of his position that bear upon discussions of Christianity and culture. In particular I have indicated the quite radical implications that emerge from Lonergan's analysis of the "origins of Christian realism" for discussions of inculturation and mission in a postmodern context. Lonergan's notion of the identity of Christian culture in the ongoing contexts of history is, I suggest, a strong one. It is perhaps worth reflecting on the fact that the very scholar from whom Lonergan learned an anthropological notion of culture, Christopher Dawson, also argued forcefully for a strong version of the thesis of Christian cultural identity, not 210 ANDREW BEARDS from a classicist base, but precisely in terms of anthropological and historical data. 77 Lonergan's analysis of Christian realism is both a powerful argument in favor of such cultural identity and a brilliant analysis of the way in which the divinely revealed truths of the Catholic faith are the dynamic catalysts of authentic spiritual and cultural evolution. As we now shift from a "modern" ·period, in which theological modernism found its milieu, to a postmodern, the writings of Lonergan, Macintyre, and Ratzinger, among others, point the way to an authentic appropriation of what might be entailed in such a cultural shift, sifting the wheat from the deconstructive and relativist chaff. 77 On the thought of Christopher Dawson see Stratford Caldecott and John Morrill, eds., Eternity in Time: Christopher Dawson and the Catholic Idea of History (Edinburgh: T&T Clark Publications, 1997). The Thomist 64 (2000): 211-37 ON THE POSSIBILITY OF A PURELY NATURAL END FOR MAN STEVEN A. LONG Universityof St. Thomas St. Paul, Minnesota D enis Bradley's recent book,Aquinas on the Twofold Human Good, 1 addresses St. Thomas's central and profound teaching regarding the relation of nature to grace. Bradley's interpretation of this doctrine is specially informed by the seeming contradiction between St. Thomas's affirmation of a natural desire to know the essence of God 2 and his insistence that "there is another good of man that exceeds the proportion of human nature because the natural powers are not sufficient for attaining, or thinking, or desiring it. " 3 The passages reflecting these teachings, prominently compared by Bradley,4 are further complicated by another argument he cites from Thomas: Man would have been created frustrated and in vain if he were not able to attain beatitude, as is the case with anything that is not able to attain its ultimate end. Lest man be created frustrated and inane, because he is born with original sin, God proposed from the beginning a remedy for the human race, through which man could be liberated from this inanity-the mediator, himself God and man, Jesus Christ. Through faith in Him the impediment of original sin is able to be taken away.5 1 Denis Bradley, Aquinason the Twofold Human Good (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America, 1997), hereinafter cited as Aquinas. 2 Summa theologiae, I-II, q. 3, a. 8. 3 De veritate, q. 14, a. 2, quoted from Aquinas, 457. 4 Ibid., 457. 5 De malo, q. 5, a. 1, ad 1, quoted from Aquinas, 473. 211 212 STEVEN A. LONG In a tradition of exegesis that hearkens to the influence of Henri de Lubac in this century, Bradley interprets these teachings as affirming an implicit natural desire for intrinsically supernatural beatitude. 6 He argues further that the imperfection of natural beatitude, and the doctrine that man can be intellectively and volitionally fully perfected only by the vision of God, leaves us with a nature that is "naturally endless. " 7 That is, short of supernatural beatitude, not only in this given economy of God's providence but in any possible order of divine providence, human nature would be naturally endless because "radically unfulfilled. " 8 Or, as Bradley puts it, "Natural beatitude in any form does not satisfy man's natural desire for beatitude. "9 From this proposition he derives the putative fact of human nature's endlessness. This point is further accentuated by his insistence that for St. Thomas obediential potency is merely a creature's susceptibility to miraculous divine action, rather than the passive potency distinctively characterizing a being's susceptibility to God's active agency. 10 Accordingly, I will here address five principal points, with a view toward showing the coherence of St. Thomas's teaching and thus contextualizing the problematic texts highlighted by Bradley's incisive treatment. To this end I will (1) briefly address St. Thomas's doctrine of human nature's obediential potency for grace; (2) summarize Bradley's account of the natural "endlessness" of nature; (3) present an interpretation of the natural desire for God that does not imply the "endlessness of nature" apart from intrinsically supernatural beatitude; (4) consider the inner symmetry between St. Thomas's teaching that nature would be 6 Aquinas, 445-46: "Aquinas says with unequivocal clarity that the will as a nature does have a natural appetite or an innate desire for good in general or happiness. This innate desire for happiness, which is not an elicited desire since it is antecedent to any intellectual act, is certainly an inclinatio naturae. The natural desire to see God is implicitly contained in the necessary desire for the perfect good or happiness that structures the will, or in the necessary desire, which follows upon the nature of the intellect, to know in general the cause of any known effect." I shall treat this argument of Bradley in detail below. 7 Ibid., 514. 8 Ibid. 9 Ibid., 513. 10 Aquinas, 449: "Miracles, then, serve as the Thomistic prototype for understanding the obediential potency of a creature." MAN'S NATURAL END 213 vain apart from grace and his teaching that the natural end proportioned to man could, in a different order of providence, have been a genuine (if imperfect) finality; and finally (5) attempt to show how the doctrine of obediential potency, and a correct interpretation of the natural desire for God, enable St. Thomas to affirm an ontological profundity of man which is corevealed to humanity in Christ, and which could not positively be grasped on the basis of pure nature alone. The substance of these issues-a source of mid-century crisis at the time of Humani generis,11 and of persistent controversy since-is brought to new exigence by Bradley's work, by the contributions of the Communio school of theology, 12 and even by certain strands of contemporary Greek theology. 13 Hence to this issue's systematic profundity we may add a note of contemporary significance. I. OBEDIENTIAL POTENCY Obediential potency represents the passive potency of a nature in relation to an extrinsic active agency. Hence in De virtutibus in communi, a. 10, ad 13, St. Thomas addresses an objection to the effect that acts are of the same genus as their potencies, but that 11 For an example of an effort during this time favorably to articulate certain aspects of the Dominican commentator tradition on this issue of the desire for God-especially given the prominently contrary teaching of Henri de Lubac, which was gaining widespread influence at the time-see William R. O'Connor, The Natural Desire for God (Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1948). His analysis may be found at greater length in his work The Eternal Quest (New York: Longmans, Green and Co., Inc., 194 7). O'Connor's criticisms of the Scotistic reading of St. Thomas are apt, and his insistence that the natural end is not "terminative" is striking. But in the present author's judgment his excellent analysis falls short in one critical respect: it does not sufficiently articulate the philosophic and theological richness of the conception of obediential potency as safeguarding the most profound elements in Christian anthropology. 12 Cf. Cf. David Schindler, Heart of the World, Center of the Church (Grand Rapids, Mich.: William B. Eerdmans Publishing Co., 1996); or his "Christology, Public Theology, and Thomism: De Lubac, Balthasar, and Murray," in The Future of Thomism, ed. Deal W. Hudson and Dennis Wm. Moran (Notre Dame: American Maritain Association, 1992), especially 253-54 n. 9, wherein he argues that nature is definitionally unknowable in precision from grace. 13 E.g., John D. Zizioulas, Being as Communion (Crestwood, N.Y.: St. Vladimir's Seminary Press, 1985). 214 STEVEN A. LONG creatures by definition lack potency for divine acts. Inasmuch as creatures have different passive potencies in relation to different active agencies, a passive obediential potency for acts achievable only with divine aid is intelligible. As St. Thomas writes: "and accordingly we say that the whole creation is in a certain potency of obedience, according as the whole creation obeys God to be able to receive in itself whatever God wills." 14 This "potency of obedience" is readily and initially understood by many interpreters as merely a susceptibility to divine miracle. Such a tendency is understandable, but overgeneric. The specific character of obediential potency is found in the differing passive potencies of natures in relation to different active agencies. As St. Thomas argues, water or earth have diverse passive potencies in respect of the diverse active agencies of fire, the heavenly bodies, and God. 15 And these diverse passive potencies vis-a-vis different active agencies are partially rooted in the characters of the natures involved. For example, one might say that there is an obediential potency of a stone to be miraculously transformed by God into a human being, but this would be an extremely generic and improper use of the conception of "obediential potency" since obediential potency has to do with what a nature can receive from the active agency of God, and in this case the nature of the stone in fact receives nothing, but is simply transformed so as no longer to be a stone. Properly speaking, it is dear that a 'stone does not have an obediential potency to perform specifically human acts, because a rock lacks any passive potency-even with divine aid -either to understand or to will (it naturally lacks these faculties, and hence it cannot even be "helped" to understand and love). By contrast, the human soul does have an obediential potency for the supernatural gift of divine friendship, because-owing to the natural character of intellect and will-it can, with divine aid, be brought to intimate knowledge and love of God. This human obediential potency for intrinsically supernatural friendship is purely passive, for the human intellect and will can reach to 14 "et secundum hoc dicimus quod in tota creatura est quaedam obedientialis potentia, prout tota creatura obedit Deo ad suscipiendum in se quidquid Deus voluerit." 1.1 St. Thomas Aquinas, De virtutibus in communi, a. 10, ad 13. MAN'S NATURAL END 215 intimate knowledge and love of God solely through divine aid. Yet the passive potency is conditioned by the actual nature God has bestowed-it is only because of man's essentially spiritual nature that he has an obediential potency to the supernatural life. Bradley argues that whereas obediential potency is spoken of by St. Thomas in relation to Christ's possession of infused miraculous or prophetic knowledge, Thomas expressly fails to mention obediential potency in relation to Christ's knowledge of the beatific vision. Thus, for example, "The term is not mentioned at the very juncture where it could be used if Aquinas had thought it should be used. " 16 Sed contra: if the notion of obediential potency must be deployed to account for our Lord's human possession of lesser instances of supernatural knowledge, a fortiori must it be deployed to account for his possession of the beatific vision. If obediential potency merely referred to susceptibility to transmutative miracle, then this conception could not be used by Thomas regarding Christ's possession of infused miraculous or prophetic knowledge. It is human nature, under the active agency of God, which in a sense is capable of such knowledge-and so this knowledge is not mere extrinsic susceptibility to miracle. The supernatural vision of God, being starkly supernatural, dearly outstrips the capacity of unaided nature. 17 The phrase actually used by St. Thomas about beatific vision as being "in a certain way above the nature of the rational soul, according as it cannot come to it of its own strength" ("quodammodo supra naturam animae rationalis, inquantum scilicet propria virtute ad earn pervenire non potest"), while yet affirming that "in another way it does accord with its [the soul's] nature according as it is capable of it as made according to the likeness of God" ("Alio vero modo est secundum naturam ipsius, inquantum scilicet For this whole discussion see Aquinas, 453-55. The quotation is taken from p. 455. CL Aquinas, Summa Theologiae III, q. 9, a. 2, ad 3: "Dicendum quod visio seu scientia beata est quodammodo supra naturam animae rationalis, inquantum scilicet propria virtute ad earn pervenire non potest. Alio vero modo est secundum naturam ipsius, inquantum scilicet per naturam suam est capax eius, prout scilicet ad imaginem Dei facta est, ut supra dictum est. Sed scientia increata est omnibus modis supra naturam animae humanae." 16 17 216 STEVEN A. LONG secundum naturam suam est capax eius, prout sdlicet est imaginem Dei facta"), conforms perfectly to the doctrine of an obediential potency to grace and glory. In other words, human nature, with divine aid, is capable of beatitude. Alone it is not capable of attaining it, but even so it does retain the remote capacity to be so aided by God-a capacity lacking in any noncognitive being. Further, it ought be noted that St. Thomas considers the "capacity" of a nature relation to that which God can bring forth from it precisely in addressing the capacity of human nature for "the grace of union, which is the greatest grace." Referring to this grace of union, he writes that A double capability may be perceived in human nature: one, according to the order of natural power, and this is always fulfilled by God, Who apportions to each according to its natural capability; the other according to the order of divine power, which all creatures implicitly obey; and the capability we speak of pertains to this. But God does not fulfill all such capabilities, otherwise God could do only what He has done in creatures, and this is false, as earlier stated. 18 Surely it is noteworthy that St. Thomas here states that a "duplex capacitas attendi potest in human natura." For this capacity of human nature for the grace of union under the active agency of God (1) is a capacity-for only a cognitive being can be so uplifted to the grace of union-and (2) is thus a "potency under obedience" or obediential potency-that is, a "capacity" that can be realized only under the active agency of God and is purely 18 SI'h HI, q. 1, a. 3, obj. 3, wherein the objection hinges on human nature's capacity for the greatest grace as not increased by sin; and then ad 3, wherein we are instructed: "Dicendum quod duplex capacitas attendi potest in humana natura. Una quidem secundum ordinem potentiae naturalis. Quae a Deo semper impletur, qui dat unicuique rei secundum suam capacitatem naturalem. Alia vero secundum orclinem divinae potentiae, cui omnis creatura obedit ad nutum. Et ad hoc pertinet ista capa,citas. Non autem Deus omnem talem capacitatem naturae imp let; alioquin Deus non posset facere in creatura nisi quod facit; quod falsum est, ut in Primo habitum est.-Nihil autem prohibet ad aliquicl maius humanam naturam productam esse post peccatum; Deus enim permittit mala fieri ut incle aliquid melius eliciat. Uncle dicitur Rom. V: 'ubi abundavit delictum, superabundavit et gratia'. Uncle et in benedictione cerei paschalis dicitur: 'O felix culpa, quae talem ac tantum meruit habere Redemptorem"' (emphasis added). MAN'S NATIJRAL END 217 passive on the part of the creature, yet founded on the character of the creature's nature as susceptible to a given kind of divine aid. Ergo Bradley's argument that "the term is not mentioned at the very juncture where it could be used if Aquinas had thought it should be used" preoccupies itself solely with terminology where the identical principle, however accidentally divergent in terminological expression, ought to be discerned. For in the relevant passage the purely passive capacity of human nature to be aided by God to achieve the grace of divine union is identified, and this capacity is founded on two elements: the spiritual nature of man and the active agency of God. The nature and role of the doctrine of obediential potency within St. Thomas's doctrine is much controverted, and in this century figures such as LaPorta and de Lubac have argued vigorously against it being a constituent of St. Thomas's teaching of the relation of nature and grace. 19 In another context I have tried to address in depth the anthropological structure upon which the obediential potency for grace is conditioned, and to 19 See, for example, Henri de Lubac, Surnaturel: Etude historiques (Paris: Aubier, 1946); Augustinisme et theologie moderne (Paris: Aubier, 1965), 242-51; Le mystere du surnaturel (Paris: Aubier, 1965), noteworthy for its criticism of the Dominican commentator tradition, 87-88, 142, 179-89; in English, see de Lubac's The Mystery of the Supernatural, trans. Rosemary Sheed (New York: Herder & Herder, 1967). See also J. Laporta, La destinee de la nature humane selon Thomas d'Aquin (Paris: J. Vrin, 1965). Laporta devotes an appendix to arguing that St. Thomas does not use the language of obediential potency in his account of the supernatural destiny of man (133-46). In a recent article, Brian Shanley approvingly cites Bradley's "challenge to the legitimacy of any allegedly Thomistic ethic based on the fictitious 'natural end' of man," noting that Bradley is in line with Laporta on this point (Brian J. Shanley, O.P., "Aquinas on Pagan Virtue," The Thomist 63 [1999]: 555). Shanley himself argues that acquired natural virtue as efficacious apart from grace is localized wholly Within political order, apparently because of the realization that after the Fall man is no longer able naturally to love God above himself (see STh 1-11, q. 109, a. 4). The point is well taken. However, once acquired natural virtue is defined exclusively within a limited political context, it would seem that personal ethical virtues would be subject to moral norms only from the side of grace, and not from nature-yet it is with natural love, even prior to divine charity, that we aboriginally flow forth from creation loving our Creator above ourselves. When this rational inclination is diminished through sin (as St. Thomas teaches that it is: see STh 1-11, q. 85, a. 1) the whole ethical life shivers with the tremors of alienation. As it is a natural (as well as a supernatural) ordering that is disrupted by sin, so one can identify the natural acquired virtues that, despite this disruption, are ordered to God. 218 STEVEN A. LONG give summary response to the issues raised by these critics. 2°For the present, it will suffice merely to indicate that the conception of obediential potency outlined here can apply to the relation of nature to supernatural grace (as shown regarding the "grace of union"), and that, while utterly passive, the obediential potency yet is founded upon something positive: namely, upon the intellective and volitional powers of man, which are intrinsically spiritual powers manifesting the ontological profundity of human nature. Hence the words of Jacques Maritain: "It is necessary that there be in man an 'obediential potency' which, answering to the divine omnipotence, renders him apt to receive a life which surpasses infinitely the capacities of his nature. " 21 II. THE PUTATIVE "ENDLESSNESS" OF NATURE There has long been a difficulty regarding the status of the arguments brought by St. Thomas to the effect that perfect beatitude is possible only in the next life, and that it requires vision of the divine essence. Working on the force of the conclusion that the perfectly final end is supernatural beatitude, which alone can fully perfect and satisfy intellect and will, Bradley argues that nature taken in itself, and in precision from supernatural completion, is "endless. " 22 That is, since only the vision of God can perfectly fulfill human nature-a proposition clearly asserted by Thomas-in an order of providence lacking supernatural fulfillment man's nature would be vain. In this respect, Bradley can draw heavily from the teaching of St. Thomas Aquinas in the Prima secundae: 20 I treat the anthropological structure implicit in St. Thomas's teaching regarding the human obediential potency for the supernatural life in "Obediential Potency, Human Knowledge, and the Natural Desire for God," InternationalPhilosophicalQuarterly (March, 1997). 11 Jacques Maritain, Approachesto God, trans. Peter O'Reilly (New York: Harper, 1954), 112. 22 For example, Bradley speaks forthrightly of what he describes as "Aquinas's doctrine of man's natural endlessness" (Aquinas, 529). MAN'S NATURAL END 219 It is therefore necessary for the last end so to fill man's appetite, that nothing is left besides it for man to desire. Which is not possible, if something else be required for his perfection. Consequently it is not possible for the appetite so to tend to two things, as though each were its perfect good. 23 Man must, of necessity, desire all, whatsoever he desires, for the last end. This is evident for two reasons. First, because whatever man desires, he desires it under the aspect of good. And if he desire it, not as his perfect good, which is the last end, he must, of necessity, desire it as tending to the perfect good, because the beginning of anything is always ordained to its completion; as is clearly the case in effects both of nature and of art. Wherefore every beginning of perfection is ordained to complete perfection which is achieved through the last end. Secondly, because the last end stands in the same relation in moving the appetite, as the first mover in other movements. Now it is dear that secondary moving causes do not move save inasmuch as they are moved by the first mover. Therefore secondary objects of the appetite do not move the appetite, except as ordained to the first object of the appetite, which is the last end. 24 These two passages establish, first, that the natural good cannot be construed as coequal with the supernatural good, as though the natural good in precision from supernatural beatitude were a separate and perfect end. Second, St. Thomas argues that all ends derive their "end-likeness" or very appetibility from being further ordered to the last end. Inasmuch as all Christians admit that in this order of providence the final end for man is the supernatural beatific vision, it seems to follow that the imperfect natural end is an end at all only inasmuch as it is further ordered to supernatural beatitude-of which any natural end is an imperfect similitude and participation. Moreover, it is dear that for St. Thomas no finite good can quell the will perfectly: It is impossible for any created good to constitute man's happiness. For happiness is the perfect good, which quiets the appetite altogether; else it would not be the last end, if something yet remained to be desired. Now the object of the will, i.e., of man's appetite, is the universal good; just as the object of the intellect is the universal true. Hence it is evident that nothing can quiet the will of man, save the universal good. This is to be found not in any 23 STh I-II, q. 1, a. 5. 24 STh I-II, q. 1, a. 6. 220 STEVEN A. LONG creature, but in God alone; because every creature has goodness by participation. Wherefore God alone can satisfy the will of man. 25 While some may argue that this argument is formally theological, one notes that there is no premise in the argument knowable only through revelation; rather, the argument sets forth simply from the character of the formal object of the wm, and from the datum that no finite good so comprises the good-in-general as to render the will incapable of further desire. Hence only if the universal good subsists in one unique instance, and is attained by the creature, can the will be quieted-and God uniquely comprises the universal good. Now, there is indeed no doubt that for Thomas the end of man is not only de facto that of the supernatural vision of God, but that man has some natural appetite to know God from the start. And it is in part the character of this "natural appetite" to know God that raises the question of man's natural "endlessness." If the natural "end" attainable in precision from supernatural beatitude cannot perfectly finalize the will-as we have just seen Thomas argue that it cannot (for he teaches that there is no natural knowledge of God other than that mediated by creaturely effects)-it would appear that apart from supernatural beatitude man is naturaHy "endless" and indeed (as Thomas says above) "vain." In responding to this argument and assessing it-both as it issues from Bradley, and in the roots of his interpretation within St. Thomas's text-we must first address the issue of the natural desire for God. For it is partiaHy in relation to this "natural desire" that it is supposed that man would be specifically unfulfilled and "endless" were God not to have ordained human nature to supernatural completion. 25 STh I-H, q. 2, a. 8: "Dicendum quod impossibile est beatitudinern hominis esse in aliquo bono creato. Beatitudo enim est bonum perfectum, quod totaliter quietat appetitum; alioquin non esset ultimus finis, si adhuc restaret aliquid appetendum. Obiectum autem voluntatis, quae est appetitus humanus, est universale bonum; sicut obiectum intellectus est universale vemm. Ex quo patet quod nihil potest quietare voluntatem hominis, nisi bonum universale. Quod non invenitur in aliquo creato, sed sol um in Deo, quia omnis creatura habet bonitatem parricipatam. Uncle solus Deus voluntatem hominis implere potest." MAN'S NATURAL END 221 Ill. THE NATURAL DESIRE FOR GOD The natural desire for God is a desire either elicited by prior knowledge -as when Thomas argues to this effect, "When a man knows an effect and knows that it has a cause, there remains in man a natural desire to know about the cause what it is. . . . Consequently, for perfect happiness, the intellect must reach the very essence of the First Cause" 26-or it is not merely elicited by a particular bit of knowledge, but "natural" (voluntas ut natura as opposed to any particular voluntary act elicited by special knowledge). For St. Thomas "each power desires by the natural appetite that object which is suitable to itself. " 27 This is distinguished from animal appetite and likened to "sight for seeing or sound for hearing" ("utpote visio ad videndum et auditio ad audiendum"). But what is suitable to the will by its nature in this sense is intelligible good as such. So there are two distinct types of natural desire that may be alleged: one elicited by our discovery that finite being has a unitary cause, and the other proceeding from the very nature of the will as ordered toward the universal good. In this second respect (regarding voluntas ut natura) Bradley argues that the desire for God-in whom the universal good subsists fully and uniquely-is natural and not elicited, because it is implicit in that universal good which is the formal object of the will. Hence he writes: Aquinas says with unequivocal clarity that the will as a nature does have a natural appetite or an innate desire for good in general or happiness. This innate desire for happiness, which is not an elicited desire since it is antecedent to any intellectual act, is certainly an inclinatio naturae. The natural desire to see God is implicitly contained in the necessary desire for the perfect good or happiness that structures the will, or in the necessary desire, which follows upon the nature of the intellect, to know in general the cause of any known effect. 28 26 As cited by Bradley in Aquinas, 457; originally from STh 1-11, q. 3, a. 8. 27 STh I, q. 80, a. 1, ad 3: "Unde unaquaeque appetit obiectum sibi conveniens naturali appetitu." 28 Aquinas, 445-46. 222 STEVEN A. LONG Cleady he considers the elicited desire to target the vision of God (although Bradley will not designate it as in the strongest sense "natural," howsoever necessary it may be once we know the truth of the proposition that God exists). 29 The passage quoted above also and primarily bears witness that he deems voluntas ut natura to constitute a genuinely natural desire for God the strongest sense of "natural!' Referring first to what Bradley judges the lesser or improperly natural instance of "natural desire" -the elicited desire to know God-it is important to note this desire is proportioned to the creaturely knowledge whence it originates. One may respond with adequacy to the text that the elicited desire is precisely not a supernatural desire for God. It is not a desire positively ordered to the inner being of God. Of course, whether the elicited desire to know the essence of the cause of creaturely effects is considered "natural" in the strongest sense or not, it is dearly natural as opposed to being supernatural. But it is a creaturely desire proportioned to the finite evidence whence it proceeds. This is to say that it is a desire to know the essence of the God who is incognito, known only through the effects of creatures. There is an infinite disproportion between God in Himself and God merely as "cause of these created effects," because there is infinitely more perfection in God than in the creature. It is for precisely this reason that no Leibnitzean "best of all possible worlds" is intelligible from a Thomistic point of view, for any possible creation can be indefinitely "improved" by God, owing to God's infinite power: all possible worlds are infinitely remote from the divine perfection. So to desire God merely as "cause of these effects" is to desire God under an improper and disproportionate ratio. As such the elicited desire "knows not what it asks." Hence as Maritain writes: But this desire to know the First Cause through its essence is a desire which does not know what it asks, like the sons of Zebedee when they asked to sit on the right and on the left of the Son of Man. Ye know not what ye ask, Jesus replied to them. For to know the First Cause in its essence, or without the 29 Aquinas, 447: "metaphysical desire to see God cannot, despite what Ferrariensis and Banez suggest, be called, in the precise Thomistic sense, a "natural desire." MAN'S NATURAL END 223 intermediary of any other thing, is to know the First cause otherwise than as First Cause; it is to know it by ceasing to attain it by the very means by which we attain it, by ceasing to exercise the very act which bears us up to it. 30 One recalls the cognate judgment of St. Thomas that philosophic knowledge of God should be compared with beatific knowing more as not-seeing to seeing than as not seeing so well to seeing better. 31 Because the elicited natural desire is materially a desire for God, but formally a desire for God solely under the ratio of "cause of these effects," it is not a desire for intrinsically supernatural beatitude. However, after the fact of revelation and under the light of grace, we do become aware that the object of this natural desire is in fact included within the object of the graced appetite for the beatific vision of the triune God. Yet this second graced appetite for beatific vision proceeds, not from mere natural evidence, but from the active agency of God upon the soul through supernatural grace. This leaves us to consider voluntas ut natura, the desire that Bradley underscores as natural in the strongest sense (i.e., as following upon the native tendency of the volitional power). His argument is that desire for God is actually implicit in the natural ordering of the will to its formal object, which is the universal good. Yet this argument obscures an important proposition which, once understood, makes short shrift of this position. For it is truer to say of the universal good that its full perfection inheres "in" God than to say that the supernaturally beatific good is actually and implicitly "contained" in the universal good. If it is held that naturally and in precision from grace we implicitly and actually desire God Himself in beatific vision under the ratio of the desire for intelligible-good-in-general, then the supereminent divine good is robbed of its utter perfection and transcendence. For the universal good is the-good in-general-it is the intelligible good in general to which the will is ordered by nature. 32 Yet God is no more this intelligible good in general than 30 Maritain, Approachesto God, 109-10. 31 Aquinas, De Veritate, q. 18, a. I. 32 By "in general" I mean, not that the definition of the good as such includes generality, as in this case no individual good could be desired. Rather I mean to emphasize what St. Thomas emphasizes by referring to the formal object as "universal" (whereas the good as such 224 STEVEN A. LONG he is being-in-general. The error of supposing God to be included within universal being (or good) is an error in application of analogous predicates. The full perfection of good resides in God. Hence to say that God is implicitly included in the-good-ingeneral collapses creature and creator within a imivocal framework while also defining the object of the will as naturally deific (for only God naturally and properly knows and wills the divine good). It is indeed true that transcendental being and good are more truly predicated of God than of creatures. But we do not know the mode in which these transcendental perfections exist in God, but only the truth of the proposition that they do so. Thus, to affirm that the full perfection of transcendental good resides in God is not tantamount to the confession that the formal object of the will actually and implicitly contains God, because between the good in general and ipsum bonum subsistens per se there is an infinite divide. By way of comparison one should consider the analogous ratio of being as contemplated by the metaphysician. Although the universal perfection of being subsists only in God, being is studied by the metaphysician in its created participations, which are not God. The metaphysician does not enjoy beatific knowledge in the contemplation of being, as he does not thereby enjoy direct knowledge of ipsum esse subsistens per se. Similarly, the universal truth and good, although subsisting only in God, signify truth and good in general in specifying the intellect and will, not a deific ordering of mind and will directly to the triune God. These observations do not prejudice the truth that all things find their perfection in God, and that intellective agents do so in an intellective manner. But natural knowledge of (and desire for) God remains infinitely distant from supernatural knowledge of (and desire for) God. The desire for the intelligible good-in-general is not only far from being an actually implicit desire for supernatural beatitude; it is also not simply and absolutely "pre-cognitive" -although doubtless it is, as Bradley argues, "antecedent to any intellectual in definition is neither universal nor particular)-namely, that the good as such is not any specific good. This sense of the formal object bears comparison with essence absolutely considered as neither individual nor universal by its notion. MAN'S NATURAL END 225 act. "33 Volition, howsoever natural, is defined by its relation to the form of reason. This is what will is: appetite following intellective form. Hence will is ordered to the intelligible good, and apart from the intellect the will can exhibit no tendency whatsoever, because its being is defined by its relation to intellect. 34 For this reason alone, it becomes apparent that the desire for the intelligible good-in-general bears the natural impress of our knowledge, for the formal object of the will is conveyed thereto by means of the intellect. But in human beings neither the object of knowledge nor of volition may rightly be said to be naturally deific. Recall Bradley's argument: "The natural desire to see God is implicitly contained in the necessary desire for the perfect good or happiness that structures the will, or in the necessary desire, which follows upon the nature of the intellect, to know in general the cause of any known effect." The "necessary desire for the perfect good or happiness that structures the will" is the desire for the intelligible-good-in-general. Under the active agency of God this desire is susceptible of becoming a true desire for divine beatitude. But in and of itself this natural desire is not the desire for supernatural beatitude, for the-good-in-general is neither naturally identical with, nor does it naturally "include," the divine good. The full perfection of the good subsists uniquely and supereminently in God, and hence under God's active agency we may be brought to graced desire for the divine good. Seen in this light, our ordering to the good-in-general constitutes an obediential potency or natural translucence for the supernatural vision of God. But this natural ordering is not a positive desire for 33 Aquinas, 446. 34 See, for instance, STh I, q. 82, a. 4, ad 3 (Leonine ed.): "quod non oportet procedere in infinitum, sed statur in intellectu sicut in primo. Omnem enim voluntatis motum necesse est quod praecedat apprehensio: sed non omnem apprehensionem praecedit motus voluntatis." See also Quodlibet 6, q. 2, a. 2: "motus voluntatis est inclinatio sequens formam intellectam." Likewise Summa contra Gentiles III, c. 26 (Leonine ed.): "Motus voluntatis est inclinatio sequens formam intellectam." See also STh 1-11, q. 8, a. 1 (Leonine ed.), where St. Thomas clearly argues that "Ad hoc igitur quod voluntas in aliquid tendat, non requiritur quod sit bonum in rei veritate, sed quod apprehendatur in rationi boni." For the will to tend toward anything as good, it must do so by virtue of an apprehension of the mind. 226 STEVEN A. LONG supernatural beatitude apart from its elevation and illumination by grace. Thus one may not "build into" the desire for indeterminate perfection and the good-in-general an actually implicit desire for knowledge of the triune God without doing violence to Thomas's teaching regarding the very nature of intellect and will. The immateriality of the intellective and volitional faculties constitutes, as it were, a purely passive natural translucence through which the active. agency of God may order the human subject to the infinitely higher end of supernatural beatitude. The openness of intellect and will toward the good is simply this-openness. The initiative of God in moving intellect and will to the actual desire of Himself remains essentially supernatural. IV. CAN THE NATURAL DESIRE BE IN VAIN? Bradley argues that natural desire for God cannot be vain 35 and that therefore this desire is known, from natural evidence, to be susceptible of fulfillment. Admittedly, to say that natural desire for God must be susceptible of fulfillment neither specifies precisely how this may be so, nor does it involve affirming the natural knowledge of an intrinsically supernatural mystery. It is only through revelation that we know that the object of the natural desire for God is included within the essentially supernatural object of the beatific vision. There is infinitely more in God than "cause of these effects," but the elicited desire to know God seeks to know Him under the ratio of "cause of these effects," a ratio that is infinitely inadequate to the proper inner truth of God. Hence to say that this limited desire to know God cannot be in vain even if true would still not inform us of the identity of this desideratum with that represented by the intrinsically supernatural beatific vision. The very possibility of an 35 And, it should be noted, on our analysis only the elicited desire is properly a natural desire for God, since the natural tendency of the will toward its object is not deific. This puts one in the interesting position of maintaining that that desire for God which Bradley denies to be natural is a more fit claimant to the title; while that which he affirms to be natural, is here argued not to be a desire for God at all, but merely the ordering of the will to the intelligible good in general. MAN'S NATURAL END 227 intrinsically supernatural mystery cannot be proven from natural evidence alone. The natural desire to know the essence of the unitary cause of being is conditioned by the finitude of the evidence whence it derives. In precision from grace this aforesaid desire seeks the essence of God in a manner knowably disproportionate to its object. Like the child's desire to capture the ocean, it is inefficacious. It is a conditional desire, that is, one whose satisfaction is not owed to nature. As a material prelude to consideration of the relation between natural ends and supernatural finality, it is useful to contemplate the natural desire for God as a conditional desire. One may well concur with Jacques Maritain that the natural desire for God is conditional in the sense that its fulfillment is not simply owed to nature, and that this alters when, illumined by faith, this desire is elevated to unconditionality. That whereby the natural desire for God becomes unconditional is the further ordering of nature to the beatific end, and it is only as so uplifted that it is impossible for this desire to be vain. Apart from revelation we know not what we seek by this desire, a desire whose material object wholly transcends the evidence that gives rise to and conditions it, and whose satisfaction is not due to nature. 36 We naturally seek the highest knowledge of the First Principle of which we are capable, and desire to know the divine essence while nonetheless simultaneously realizing-as a condition of this very desire-that this is a thing impossible to nature simply in its own right. But once revelation teaches us to hope for supernatural beatific vision, we realize the coextension of graced desire for God and natural desire. The natural desire for God then partakes of the supernatural finality without which, in this order of providence, human nature would be vain. Thus from being inefficacious and conditional the natural desire is elevated to become an unconditional aspiration. 37 36 On this point, note the long footnote of Maritain, no. 91, in chapter 6 of The Degrees of Knowledge.As frequently is the case, in a long note Maritain succeeds in bringing greater clarity to this issue than many another complete book or essay achieves. 37 Maritain does not much like the language of velleity, which I here avoid in stating his position although I do not share his interpretation of its past use, and consider it apt to articulate the character of a conditional natural aspiration. But he did not think this term appropriate in respect of the natural desire for God. Cf. Approachesto God, 112: "It is not 228 STEVEN A. LONG This view of the elevation of the natural desire within grace does not imply the endlessness of human nature apart from grace. In a different economy of providence wherein nature from its inception were not ordered by grace, the failure to fulfill the natural desire to know God quidditatively would not derogate from the felicity of the natural end. Within an economy of providence wherein nature were not ordered by grace, the natural desire for God would be known to be utterly disproportionate with nature, not owed to nature, and indeed impossible for nature by itself. cannot be quelled Neither the negative knowledge that the by any finite good, nor the natural elicited desire to know the essence of God-which seeks God under the ratio of "cause of these effects"-implies the impossibility of a natural end lesser than knowledge of the divine essence. The negative knowledge that no finite good may wholly quell the will, is-absent the promptings of grace-merely as it were the shadow of any natural possession of the good. Apart from the actual ordering of human nature to the supernatural, the incapacity of the will to be fulfilled by any finite good would not be tantamount to Augustinian restlessness, for this incapacity would be marked neither by nostalgia for grace nor by the corresponding normative teleology to the beatific vision. Rather, this mobilism of the wiH-its incapacity to be quelled by finite goods-naturally appears simply as the condition for human achievement of any perfection. The end proportioned to nature is thus imperfect. But knowledge of this imperfection an economy of providence wherein nature is not ordered to the supernatural) would be merely dialectical and, as it were, shallow. For, in the absence of that active agency of God which coreveals man's profundity in revealing the divine friendship, the possible supernatural object and ontological depth of human nature are not actually brought to light. Hence the supernatural vision of God "exceeds the proportion of human nature because the natural powers are not sufficient for attaining, or thinking, or desiring it." 38 One notes a simple velleity, a desire of supererogation. It is born in the very depths of the thirst of our intellect for being." It is unclear to me that Banez and others mean to suggest by their use of the term that this is a desire of supererogation. 38 De Verit., q. 14, a. 2, cited in Aquinas, 457. MAN'S NATURAL END 229 the term "desiring." Neither the elicited desire to know God, nor the natural ordination of the will toward its formal objectintelligible-good-in-general-constitutes an actual desire for supernatural beatific vision apart from grace and revelation. V. NATURE VAIN APART FROM GRACE? But what about St. Thomas's distinct argument regarding the need for grace lest man have been created "frustrated and in vain" or "inane"? These last words must be understood as presupposing this actual order of providence in which nature from its first institution is created in grace, and in which it is redeemed from sin and mercifully ordered through the redemption toward the beatific vision. 39 Within this order, surely nature if deprived of grace would be vain. This judgment is made all the stronger by the quotation whence these descriptives are drawn: "Lest man be created frustrated and inane, because he is born with original sin. "40 39 STh I, q. 95, a. 1 (Leonine, Ottawa ed.): "Sed quod fuerit conditus in gratia, ut alii dicunt, videtur requirere ipsa rectitudo primi status, in qua Deus hominem fecit, secundum illud Eccle. VII: 'Deus fecit hominem rectum'. Erat enim rectitudo secundum hoc quod ratio subdebatur Deo, rationi vero inferiores vires, et animae corpus. Prima autem subiectio erat causa et secundae et tertiae; quandiu enim ratio manebat Deo subiecta, inferiora ei subdebantur, ut Augustinus