The Thomist 65 (2001): 1-44 "DIRECT" AND "INDIRECT": A REPLY TO CRITICS OF OUR ACTION THEORY jOHNFINNIS GERMAIN GRISEZ University of Oxford Oxford, England Mount St. Mary's College St. Michael's College Emmitsburg, Maryland Toronto, Ontario, Canada JOSEPH BOYLE I T he adjectives "direct" and "indirect" have been used in some documents of the Magisterium to qualify nouns that refer to certain ways in which one brings about bad outcomes. Those adjectives are used to distinguish cases in which an acting person intends the bad outcome either as an end or as a means ("direct abortion") 1 from cases in which the moral agent, in doing some other, morally upright action, only accepts the bad outcome as its side effect. Rather than using "direct" and "indirect," it seems to us preferable to speak of what is intended and what is accepted as a side effect, 2 and we shall usually do so here. To understand this distinction, one should begin by considering free choices and the actions that carry them out. Those are good or bad-in the first instance good or bad for the human persons who shape themselves by making such choices and carrying them out. Groups of persons also deliberate and act, and their actions affect and shape them too. 1 See, e.g., Catechism of the Catholic Church (hereafter CCC) 2271; John Paul II, Evangelium vitae (25 March 1995) 62. A primary source for these and other recent documents, on this point, is the set of statements of Pius XII cited in Evangelium vitae 62 at n. 66. 2 See Germain Grisez, The Way of the Lord Jesus, vol. 2, Living a Christian Life (Quincy, Ill.: Franciscan Herald Press, 1993), 473-74. 1 2 JOHN FINNIS, GERMAIN GRISEZ, JOSEPH BOYLE Of course, each individual who participates in the communal action will in so doing make his own free choices. Moral good and evil are a matter of whether and how fully or deficiently these choices are reasonable, that is to say, in accord with fully reasonable judgments about what is to be done or avoided. 3 Before children can make free choices, emotional motivations attract them to, or avert them from, certain possibilities, and motivations of this sort are still operative in one's adult life. As one becomes capable of being motivated by reasons, one enters the moral domain by reasoning about what to do, by more or less integrating one's emotional motivations with each other and with reasons, and by more or less reasonably making free choices. But what is it to have a reason for action by which one might thus be motivated and guided towards choice? Essentially, it is to understand the intelligible con3 Of course, this statement must be qualified. People's capacities to judge correctly what to do and to exercise their freedom in acting on their judgment can be more or less limited in various ways. So, a person's moral quality depends on his selfdetermination in relation to his capacity to act reasonably. Thus a person whose capacity to act reasonably is limited may be a good person even while determining himself to an act of a kind that is wrong and would never be done by a good person free of those limitations. For that reason, Catholic moral theology and pastoral practice have recognized the difference between the "subjective" good and evil of persons and their choices, on the one hand, and, on the other, the "objective" good and evil of actions measured by unqualified practical reasonableness. This distinction can also be marked-though we do not recommend this way of speaking-by reserving the adjectives good and evil to qualify persons and choices, and the adjectives right and wrong to qualify choices and actions. Of course, the good and the right, the evil and the wrong, are sometimes distinguished in ways that we regard as inconsistent with sound morality and pastoral practice. For example, James F. Keenan, S.J., Goodness and Rjghtness in Thomas Aquinas's "Summa Theologiae" (Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University, 1992), 173-174, holds that acts commanded by charity or "benevolence" "are good, though not necessarily right"-indeed, are good even if wrong-and that "the defect in rightness does not affect" the description of the act as morally good. Again, some Christian theologians maintain that practical reasonableness sometimes requires an upright person in this fallen world to commit a sin-that is, to do what is truly wrong. Such ways of distinguishing good from right and evil from wrong separate right and wrong from the basic human good of practical reasonableness and the moral virtue of prudentia-something traditional Catholic moral theology and pastoral practice never allowed. "DIRECT" AND "INDIRECT" 3 nection between some benefit by which one and/or others could be fulfilled and some action(s) that one anticipates could involve or bring about that benefit. Choice is between alternatives. Both emotional and rational motives suggest possible purposes that seem to be within one's power to achieve in a certain way or ways. In one's deliberating about what to do, one considers both the proposal to pursue a purpose in a certain way for the sake of a benefit, and the alternative proposal to pursue the same purpose in a different way, or to pursue an alternative purpose for the same or some other benefit. One has to choose because of these options-including the alternative proposals-alternative proposal to do nothing. The ideas introduced and linked with one another in the preceding three paragraphs make possible the understanding of actions as morally significant. In making that understanding possible, they also make possible a proper understanding of the words, concepts, and realities with which moral and legal analysis is centrally concerned, not only in Judaeo-Christian but also (as we will show) in widely different cultural contexts: intention, choice, and foresight; ends, means, and side effects. The most perspicuous way of getting clear about these words, concepts, and realities is to consider some examples of proposals (options), choices adopting them, and actions carrying out those choices. Case A. A boy with money to buy Friday lunch sees a beautiful airplane in a shop window. He thinks about the alternatives: buy lunch to satisfy his hunger or buy the plane to play with on the weekend. He foresees that if he buys the plane he will be hungry that afternoon, and that if he buys lunch he will have to do without the weekend fun. He chooses to buy the plane for the sake of the weekend fun; the intended end (purpose) is the weekend fun, the chosen means is buying the plane. Being hungry follows inevitably; it is a foreseen side effect. It is a side effect precisely because it was not part of the proposal he adopted, to buy the plane for the sake of weekend 4 JOHN FINNIS, GERMAIN GRISEZ, JOSEPH BOYLE fun, just as going without the weekend fun was no part of the proposal he did not adopt, to buy lunch to avoid hunger. Case B. A man with high blood pressure is offered a drug to lower it. Taking this drug has what everyone calls side effects; some of these are very rare but lethal. He knows about these side effects, but chooses to take the drug, realizing that he is incurring some risk of earlier death; and, as it happens, he dies from one of the drug's rare side effects. In choosing to take the medication, he adopted the proposal of using it to lower his blood pressure for the purpose of living longer, but accepted the side effect: the (low) probability of dying from the drug. Though he foresaw and brought about the risk he accepted, running that risk was no part of his intention: the purpose he was trying to achieve and the means he chose for achieving it. Case C. A man at a party considers three proposals: to stay over and (uncomfortably) sleep on the sofa, to call a (costly) cab, or to drive (woozily) home. To get home cheaply he drives; risking running someone down is a side effect of his choice, and as it happens he runs someone down. This disaster is a further side effect of his choice. He is responsible for that side effect. That is to say, he should have taken such an effect into account and made the reasonable choice of one or other of the alternatives. But if his hostess has had a heart attack and, to get her to hospital, he accepts the same risk by driving in the same condition, his choice to drive may well be reasonable. Case D. A woman has decided to give testimony at her brother's trial, although she is acutely conscious of her uncontrollable stutter. Her purpose is to help her brother get justice, her means of helping is giving evidence, and a side effect is publicly stuttering. This side effect is an inseparable part of the woman's performance; her speech is always stuttering. But that side effect is unwanted in itself; indeed, it is a side effect that obstructs her purpose in testifying (because it distracts and perhaps annoys the jury). Stuttering is not included in her intentions. She chooses and tries to speak as "DIRECT" AND "INDIRECT" 5 best she can. She does not choose to stutter; indeed, she does her best not to. Case E. A farmer castrates male calves in order to change their hormonal constitution and thereby make them fat and manageable. He accepts that this will make them sterile, and if he did not find it more profitable to fatten and calm them all he would keep some unsterilized for breeding (instead of hiring bulls for breeding in season). Nothing in the behavior he does perform differentiates sterilizing the calves by castrating them from fattening and calming them by castrating them. But the proposal to fatten is quite distinct from any proposal to sterilize. So, although the performance is sterilizing (as anyone would say who looks just at the performance and its physical effects), any question as to what is included in the farmer's proposal is not settled by reference to his behavior. Indeed, since sterilizing (achieving a state of infertility) is for the farmer neither end (purpose) nor means, it is not included in the proposal he adopts, is not what he chooses, and for the purposes of an account of human action is pot what he is doing. The analysis of choice and action applies, as we have said, to groups' acts as well as individuals'. (Indeed, talk of "proposals" is adapted from the realm of deliberative assemblies.) So the next two cases we shall consider happen to be group acts but could equally have been the acts of a powerful individual. Case F. A majority of the members of a club vote for a motion to commend an outgoing president, unpopular with some. In doing so, they accept the side effect of antagonizing the minority. In voting-choosing to commend the presidentthey carry out the behavior that constitutes the act of commending her and achieve their purpose in doing so. Case G. A company's directors deliberate about a proposal to shut down the production line for January and an alternative proposal to shut it down in May. Production must be halted for a month, for retooling. For production purposes, 6 JOHN FINNIS, GERMAIN GRISEZ, JOSEPH BOYLE May would be much the best month; for short-term financial purposes, January would be marginally better. But closing in January would also have the effect of nipping unionization in the bud, whereas closing in May would have the effect of giving the unions time to organize and impose unwelcome demands on the company. If the directors choose to shut down the line in January with a view to nipping unionization in the bud, their intention is not only to shut· down the line and to retool but also to nip unionization in the bud-preventing unionization is no mere side effect. If short-term financial gain was not part of the directors' reasons for their decision, they do not intend it. Though they foresee it and will welcome it, it remains a side effect. That being so, if they learn that this time there will be no short-term financial gain, they will see no reason to reconsider their decision. If the directors choose to close for retooling in May for production purposes, the enhanced unionization is an unwelcome side effect. Case H. A spy, horrified that his house guest has become aware of his treason, deliberates about what is necessary to ensure her silence. Though wanting her continuing companionship, he very reluctantly decides to kill her. He takes her to a lovely rural spot and with feelings of great regret pushes her over a cliff. Retching with disgust at himself, he checks to make sure she is dead and then, as planned, reports the "accident." While his intention, in the sense of the purpose for the sake of which he acts, is to ensure her silence, that is not all he intends. He also intends precisely what he chooses: to kill his companion. Her death cannot be regarded as a side effect. His repugnance, regret, and remorse do not make it any less the case that he intends to kill her. Though the preceding examples could be multiplied indefinitely, even these eight alone provide enough data to show that the theory of action discussed in this paper is sound, and is applicable across the whole range of choices and actions quite independently of moral judgments about their goodness or badness, rightness or wrongness. "DIRECT" AND "INDIRECT" 7 Case A makes it dear that an action carries out a proposal adopted by choice, and that one intends 4 both to carry out that proposal and to achieve the purpose for the sake of which one adopts it. This case also makes it dear that one's actions have unintended side effects, inasmuch as some of the foreseen and inevitable consequences of one's intentional behavior are nevertheless not intended. Case B reinforces the point that, when one knowingly brings about bad effects in carrying out some choice, one need not intend them. Even though one both foresees and causes them, one does not choose them; one only accepts themindeed freely accepts them. Case C makes it clear that when one's action has foreseen but unintended side effects, one has moral responsibility in respect to accepting them. But since not all the moral criteria applicable to intending to do something apply to accepting bad side effects, one sometimes can reasonably accept something that it would be wrong to bring about intentionally. Case D makes it dear that a side effect need not be causally consequent upon the performance that carries out one's choice. Even an integral part of the behavior by which one carries out a choice can be a side effect, and such a side effect can even precede the part of the behavior that constitutes one's intended act, and all the more so can precede the effects for the sake of which one is acting. Case E makes it clear that, depending on what one proposes to do and what one only accepts as a side effect, one can be doing either of two acts different in kind even though everything about one's behavior and the observable context is the same. Case F makes it clear that the structure of actions articulated by our analysis is found even in a case where one and the same behavior is at once the choosing of the act, the 4 Common parlance (like Aquinas: see n. 22 below) talks of "intention" in two different ways: (1) that for the sake of which one does X; or (2) doing X-for-the-sakeof-that. See John Finnis, Aquinas: Moral, Political, and Legal Theory (Oxford and New York: Oxford University, 1998), 166. 8 JOHN FINNIS, GERMAIN GRISEZ, JOSEPH BOYLE doing of the act, and the realizing of the purpose for which it is done. Despite the unity of all the analytically distinct factors that constitute it, this moral act has a side effect really distinct from itself. Case G makes it clear that foreseen and welcome effects of what one is doing, effects that could have been reasons for acting, need not be intended even if one chooses precisely as one would if one did intend them. Foreseen effects of what one does are intended only if they actually are among one's reasons for acting. If they are not, they are part of neither the proposal one adopts in choosing nor the purpose(s) for the sake of which one chooses: they are part of neither the means nor the end(s). Case H makes it clear that intentions are constituted by acting persons' reasons for making their choices and by precisely what they choose to do, not by what they feel, or would like, or are reluctant or eager to do, or regret the "necessity" of doing. The preceding cases also illustrate some of the many ways employed in common speech to refer to intentions and the intentional. These ways include not only the cognates of "intend," but such phrases as "for the sake of," "for the purpose of," "with the object/purpose/aim/goal of," "in order to," "so as to," "with a view to," and often enough plain "to" -as well as other terms. The fact that in this sort of context people easily and accurately communicate, using so many different expressions synonymously, at least suggests that the concepts of intention and side effects are sound and precise, and that what all these terms signify are indeed realities. Moreover, the many formal and informal words and phrases we have just listed-like their counterparts in the idioms of other languages-all refer one to the relations we have been outlining, relations whose terms are captured in the more static-seeming idiom of philosophy: "end(s)," "means," effects" or "intentions," "choices," and "unintended (synonymously) "side effects." ..DIRECT" AND ..INDIRECT" 9 Realities, even the human realities of deliberation and action, need not be reflectively understood by those who engage in them. The understanding and analysis of intention, choice, and action has undoubtedly reached its greatest clarity in Christian reflection guided by the firm Judaeo-Christian recognition of free choice. But even cultures not shaped by that recognition have more or less clearly acknowledged the reality of intention, its distinction from certain other realities, and its significance for the moral and therefore the legal assessment of conduct. During the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries many scholars claimed that the ancients had little or no understanding of, or interest in, the distinctions between the intended and the unintended (whether negligent, truly accidental, or foreseen and reluctantly accepted). This common view about ancient thought exaggerates the distance between the later, Christian clarity and earlier, less differentiated thought. The exaggerated form of this modern view about ancient thought has been plausibly contested, notably by David Daube, Jewish biblicist and historian of Roman law. A few quotations from Daube's review of the evidence 5 suggest its force: There is not a single case in the whole of Greek literature-myth, saga, history-or, for that matter, in the Bible, of a man who killed without intent being put to death, be it in the course of self-help, blood-vengeance, be it by public authority; and this although there are laws that (as I just remarked) 6 objectivize dolus [wrongful intent] and impose the deathSee especially David Daube, Roman Law: Linguistic, Social and Philosophical Aspects (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University, 1969) 157-75. 6 See ibid., 164: "It is a dogma that, in dealing with homicide, not only does early law equate the unwitting doer with the witting, but this course is taken from blindness or indifference to what separates the two. In reality, full equation occurs much more rarely than the prevalent view has it, and where it does occur it is a pis aller, resorted to because of the insurmountable practical obstacles in the way of determining on which side of the line a given case falls: by treating as a murderer, say, anyone who kills by a direct blow or anyone who kills with a piece of iron, justice is done in the vast majority of incidents though, now and then, an innocent person gets trapped. The alternative would be for the law to abdicate altogether. In the Pentateuch both 5 10 JOHN FINNIS, GERMAIN GRISEZ, JOSEPH BOYLE penalty, say, on killing by a direct blow. Not a single case: let that fact sink in. 7 I repeat: the sources-Oriental, Greek, Roman-offer not one example of an unintentional killer being killed. I do not, of course, count the cases where the prevalent doctrine says, Ah yes, but he would have been killed were it not for such-and-such special circumstances. I want to be shown one instance where he is killed: surely a modest request. If the prevalent view is right, there ought to be hundreds. 8 So ancient thought and practice did attend to intent, and distinguished among the effects of actions--,-for example, death brought about intentionally or not intentionally. The latter, of course, includes death brought about accidentally or carelessly, but also includes death brought about as a foreseen side effect in carrying out a choice to do something else. A similar understanding can be observed in modern, secular legal thought. Legal thinkers influenced by utilitarianism's characteristic denial of free choice often argue that the law's typical concern with externally observable performances and their consequences is justified by the purpose of reducing overall net social harm. A notable element in this outlook is the claim, launched by Bentham and vigorously defended by some recent legal theorists, that consequences foreseen as certain or highly probable are intended. But even the leading proponents of this view have found themselves obliged to accept that intention is a reality quite distinguishable, as a specific kind of fact, from the "intent" which may, by a legal fiction, be imputed to someone who acts or omits while being aware-or in a position to be aware-that harm will very probably be caused by the action or omission. And there are stages-death to whoever kills by a direct blow and death to whoever kills with a piece of iron-are preserved [footnote: 'Exodus, 21.12, Numbers, 35.16-in their original setting, as yet unprovided with the reservations which in the text before us modify them.']. The latter statute is part of a legislation avowedly concerned with confining the rigor of the law to those who deserve it. But the former too is designed to get at dolus [wrongful intent]-the dolus being objectivized, established by the external situation." 7 Ibid., 165. 8 Ibid., 174. "DIRECT" AND "INDIRECT" 11 today important areas of law in which the fiction that consequences foreseen as very probable are intended is simply rejected or strictly contained. As the United States Supreme Court noted in 1980 and reaffirmed in 1997, "The ... common law of homicide often distinguishes ... between a person who knows that another person will be killed as the result of his conduct and a person who acts with the specific purpose of taking another's life. " 9 To be sure, neither present-day law nor Christian teaching and reflection deny or overlook that one is morally responsible for outcomes of one's action that are outside one's intention. The case of the drunk driver (case C) illustrates one way in which side effects that are foreseen or should be foreseen and have an impact on human well-being are morally significant and not outside the acting person's responsibility. But that case also indicates how accepting such outcomes, or the risk of such outcomes, precisely as side effects, is subject to moral (or legal) norms different from the moral (or legal) norms that bear on intended outcomes. The woozy driver is not responsible for the death in the way he would be if he chose (intended) to kill the victim. His accepting, however knowingly and willingly, of the risk to the victim is assessed under the moral and legal norms of "negligence," not the moral and legal norms forbidding intentional homicide. To say that not all the moral criteria applicable to what one chooses to do are applicable to accepting side effects is not to say that the latter are always less serious or culpable. When a 9 United States v. Bailey 444 United States Reports 394 at 405 (1980) (judgment of the Court) (emphasis added); the quoted proposition is reaffirmed in the more extensive review in Vacco v. Quill 117 Supreme Court Reporter 2293 at 2299 ( 1997) (judgment of the Court), which concludes with a quotation from an earlier judicial opinion in a lower federal court: "When General Eisenhower ordered American soldiers onto the beaches of Normandy, he knew that he was sending many American soldiers to certain death .... His purpose, though, was to ... liberate Europe from the Nazis." So he had no intent to kill Allied soldiers. The death of his soldiers was only a foreseen side effect, reasonably accepted in accord with what Catholic theologians have often called the principle of double effect (a "principle" to which the Supreme Court's judgment in Vacca v. Quill alludes with apparent assent at 2301 n. 11). 12 JOHN FINNIS, GERMAIN GRISEZ, JOSEPH BOYLE hospital doctor knows he must give a certain patient medication by midnight or she will die, but chooses to go out and complete an extremely profitable business deal that must be done by midnight (reasoning that no one will know he gave the medication later provided he gives it before the patient dies), he is guilty of manslaughter by very gross negligence. And that homicide may well be a graver sin than (say) a storekeeper's killing a mobster who is subjecting her to extortion. 10 II In describing and analyzing the cases set out in the preceding section, we adopted the perspective of the acting person or body. In morally evaluating human actions, one must identify the action to be evaluated from that perspective rather than from the perspective of an observer. Indeed, the perspective of the acting person or body is to be taken even in those contexts (such as case C) where the focus of analysis and assessment is not intention to harm but rather some failure to meet a standard such as the standard of due care or some similar moral requirement. Many theorists, even when discussing actions in the context of moral assessment, do not adopt and steadily maintain the perspective of the acting person, and many do not adopt it at all. They consider actions, behavior, and outcomes from, so to speak, the outside-from the perspective of a spectator-in which primary or exclusive attention is given to causal relationships. Such displacement or abandonment of the acting person's deliberative perspective was common among Catholic manualists of moral theology (see section III below). The observer's perspective can be adopted in other ways, for instance by trying to understand action by reference to "a 10 The moral evaluation of side effects is important and difficult, and not yet sufficiently studied in Catholic moral theology. An effort to do some of the necessary work is made in Germain Grisez, The Way of the Lord Jesus, vol. 3, Difficult Moral Questions (Quincy, Ill.: Franciscan Herald Press, 1997), appendices 1 and 2. "DIRECT" AND "INDIRECT" 13 variety of factors," 11 or to various "contexts of meaning, " 12 or to outcomes thought to be assessable by comparing the proportions of human good and bad in them. This last displacement of the perspective of the acting person is characteristic of moralists referred to as "proportionalists" in the encyclical Veritatis splendor. 13 It was appropriate for that encyclical, in the course of rejecting proportionalism 14 as incompatible with Catholic 11 See John Finnis, "The Rights and Wrongs of Abortion" in The Rjghts and Wrongs of Abortion, ed. Marshall Cohen, Thomas Nagel, and Thomas Scanlon (Princeton: Princeton University, 1974), 105: "A variety of factors are appealed to explicitly or implicitly in making a judgment that the bad effect is to count as intended-as-a-means." In this article, written in 1972, Finnis's understanding of intention and action had not reached the precision of, for example, his "The Act of the Person," in Persona verita e morale: Atti del congresso internazionale di teologia morale (Roma, 7-12 aprile 1986) (Rome: Citta Nuova, 1987), 159-75. 12 See, e.g., Jean Porter, "'Direct' and 'Indirect' in Grisez's Moral Theory," Theological Studies 57 (1996): 631: "we think of them [scil. our actions] in terms of wider contexts of meaning, some of which reflect the normal causal relationships among different primitive acts, some of which are cultural constructs, and many of which combine both kinds of considerations." Porter is right in thinking that societies develop action concepts and language to pick out any human behavior that is interesting for any of a wide variety of reasons. But those reasons often have little or nothing to do with moral evaluation, and often focus upon observable units of behavior picked out with little or no regard for the perspective of the acting person. 13 In previous writings we have criticized the accounts of action found among proportionalists. See, e.g. , Germain Grisez, The Way of the Lord Jesus, vol. 1, Christian Moral Principles (Chicago: Franciscan Herald Press, 1983), 240 with 248-49 (nn. 5 and 13); John Finnis, Moral Absolutes: Tradition, Revision, and Truth (Washington, D. C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1991 ), 77-78: "Christian reflection on God and his holy will, and Christian reflection on the morality of human choosing and doing" advance "decisively beyond the undifferentiated concept of 'cause,' replacing it with the act-analytical distinctions between choosing or intending and permitting or accepting. As one reads through the writings of sophisticated proportionalist moralists of the late twentieth century, one sees with amazement that they everywhere lose their grip on the distinction. They have fallen back into the undifferentiated problematic of 'causing' evils (including, of course, the Enlightenment extension of 'cause' to include whatever one could have prevented but did not, a concept incompatible with Christian understanding of divine holiness)." 14 The rejection of proportionalism in John Paul H's encyclical Veritatis splendor does not depend upon the encyclical's description of it in nos. 74-76, but is found rather in its formal (and repeated) condemnation of "the thesis, characteristic of teleological and proportionalist theories, which holds that it is impossible to qualify as 14 JOHN FINNIS, GERMAIN GRISEZ, JOSEPH BOYLE faith, 15 to affirm the primacy of the internal perspective in the understanding of action for the purposes of moral assessment. Immediately following its formal statement of "the thesis, characteristic of ... proportionalist theories," that is to be rejected by Catholics, the encyclical says, "The primary and decisive element for moral judgment is the object of the human act." 16 This statement recalls what was said in the previous section of the encyclical: The morality of the human act depends primarily and fundamentally on the "object" rationally chosen by the deliberate will . ... In order to be able to grasp the object of an act which specifies that act morally, it is therefore necessary to place oneself in the perspective of the acting person. 17 That last sentence is of decisive importance. It is philosophically sound, 18 even if its roots, for the purposes of morally evil according to its species-its 'object' -the deliberate choice of certain kinds of behavior or specific acts, apart from a consideration of the intention for which the choice is made or the totality of the foreseeable consequences of that act for all persons concerned" (no. 79; verbatim in no. 82). Notice that in this sentence "intention" is used in the sense in which the acting person's end is distinguished from his or her chosen means-the act's object, also described (indeed, defined) in no. 78 as the acting person's "proximate end." In a wider sense of "intention," which we generally use, both what one does and all the ends for the sake of which one does it are intended. 15 See Veritatis splendor no. 29 ("some trends of theological thinking and certain philosophical affirmations are incompatible with revealed truth"). The pope's grounds for his judgment that the theories dealt with in the encyclical, including proportionalism, are incompatible with Catholic faith are to be found, e.g., at the end of no. 52 and in the places where he repeatedly uses Scripture (see nos. 48, 78-81 quoting Romans 3:8 and 1 Cor. 6:9-10) to verify teachings with which dissenting theories are incompatible. See also Germain Grisez, "Revelation versus Dissent," The Tablet ( 16 Oct. 199 3): 1329-31, reprinted in John Wilkins, ed., Understanding Veritatis Splendor (London: Society for Promoting Christian Knowledge, 1994), 1-8. 16 Veritatis splendor no. 79; likewise no. 82; seen. 14 above. 17 Veritatis splendor no. 78. The phrases omitted in this quotation refer to the "insightful analysis, still valid" in Aquinas, Summa Theologiae I-II, q. 18, a. 6. 18 See John Finnis, Joseph Boyle, and Germain Grisez, Nuclear Deterrence, Morality and Realism (Oxford & New York: Oxford University Press, 1987), 292-93; Joseph Boyle, "Who Is Entitled to Double Effect?" journal of Medicine and Philosophy 16 (1991): 486-92; John Finnis, "Intention and Side Effects," in Liability and Responsibility: Essays in Law and Morals, ed. R. G. Frey and Christopher W. Morris (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 32-64; idem, "Intention in Tort Law," "DIRECT" AND "INDIRECT" 15 its affirmation in an encyclical, are firmly embedded in revelation's confirmation of the centrality of conscience, of the heart, the "within" 19 from which come forth actions good and bad. The importance of the perspective of the acting person was vividly emphasized in Aquinas's refutation, in one telling paragraph, of two twelfth-century currents in moral theology that, in different ways, failed to recognize the proper significance of the object of the act understood from the perspective of the acting person. The issues are so clearly framed in that debate that it is worth summarizing. 20 In the second quarter of the twelfth century, Peter Abelard had argued, ambiguously, that behavior is morally indifferent and the morality of acts depends entirely on intention. He was widely understood as denying that there are exceptionless, non-tautologous negative norms. Representatives of the in David Owen, ed., Philosophical Foundations of Tort Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995), 229-48. Some people say that the authors of this article, or at least one or two of them, are significantly responsible for the content of Veritatis splendor (see, e.g., Richard A. McCormick, S.j., "Some Early Reactions to Veritatis Splendor," Theological Studies 55 (1994): 486: "I (along with others) see [Finnis's] hands at work in Chapter 2 [of the encyclical]"). We take the opportunity here to say: (1) None of us was at any stage asked to draft anything for the document; (2) Grisez (but not Finnis) was among those asked for suggestions in November 1987, and was asked to comment on the whole first draft in April 1989 and on the second draft of part 2 in January 1990, and Finnis assisted him in preparing his comments, but after his response dated 6 February 1990 Grisez was not asked to do anything more, and (like Finnis) had no communication about the work with anyone involved in it during the subsequent 42 months before its signing on 6 August 1993; (3) in making suggestions and comments, we very firmly adhered to our view that nothing peculiar to our thought should appear in an encyclical; (4) Grisez did propose language on a number of points, but virtually none of this language and few of his substantive suggestions-and of these none involved in our disputes with dissenting Catholic moralists-appear in the encyclical; (5) while there are some important points in the encyclical that more or less coincide with views defended by Grisez (notably the treatment of faith as the fundamental option) or by all of us (notably the teaching about fundamental goods), we did not propose that the encyclical make these points and were pleasantly surprised to find them when the encyclical appeared. 19 See Mark 7:20-23 20 See also Finnis, Moral Absolutes, 65-67; Aquinas, 165-66. 16 JOHN FINNIS, GERMAIN GRISEZ, JOSEPH BOYLE tradition responded. Within a decade or two, Peter Lombard's Sentences attacked Abelard's position by contrasting it with passages from Augustine's treatises against lying, interpreted by Lombard as teaching that the acts specified in the exceptionless negative norms of Jewish and Christian tradition are called wrong "in themselves" (mala in se) precisely because-Lombard contended-their wrongfulness does not come from the purpose, will, intention, or motivation of the person who does them. In a single paragraph Aquinas refutes both Abelard (as widely understood) and Peter Lombard. There are indeed, he says, acts each of which is wrong in itself and cannot in any way be rightly done (de se malus, qui nullo modo bene fieri potest). But such acts are wrongful precisely by reason of the acting person's will, intention, purpose. When I do such an act, there may be nothing wrong with my further intentions, my voluntas intendens, my ultimate purpose (finis ultimus), for example, to give money to the poor. What is wrongful (and what is picked out for exclusion by the relevant negative norm) is, rather, my choice, my electio or voluntas eligens, my immediate purpose (obiectum proximum; finis proximus), for example, to forge this document. The goodness or badness, rightness or wrongness, of my "exterior act" (i.e., everything I do to carry out my choice) depends on the goodness or badness, rightness or wrongness, of all my relevant willing: intending ends, choosing means, and accepting side effects. 21 Aquinas's references to "proximate" and "further" objects clarify the issue, both substantially and terminologically (and are echoed in Veritatis splendor). Terminologically one can-and Aquinas not rarely does-call both proximate and 21 II Sent., d. 40, a. 2, c and ad 2-3; see De Malo, q. 2, a. 2, ad 8. Note Aquinas's thesis that "because the exterior act stands to the will as obiect, the interior act of will has its goodness from the exterior-though not, of course, from the exterior act as a performance but from the exterior act precisely as intended and willed" ("quia actus exterior comparatur ad voluntatem sicut objectum, inde est quod hanc bonitatem voluntatis actus interior ab exteriori habet, non quidem ex eo secundum quod est exercitus sed secundum quod est intentus et volitus"). "DIRECT" AND "INDIRECT" 17 remote objects "intended" or "the intention(s). " 22 But equally one can mark-and Aquinas more often does mark-the distinction between proximate and further objects by calling the former the "chosen object" (or simply the "object") and the latter the "intended end" (or simply the "intention"). The reason why both the broader and the narrower senses of "intention" are appropriate is that the distinction between proximate and further objectives is highly relative. Every means one adopts in the pursuit of some end will also be an end whenever there is a prior means-one closer in to the agent. Take Aquinas's standard example: in the sequence going to the cupboard, to get herbs, to mix a potion, to slim, to stay healthy, etc., each element is both an end relative to any preceding element and a means relative to any further element. 23 Speaking of "intention" in a broader sense, one can say that each element or phase in the sequence is intended (or an intention of the acting person). Or one can speak of "intention" in a narrower sense, and distinguish closer-in from further-out ends, reserving the term "intention" for the latter. Veritatis splendor uses "intention" in the narrower way to signify purposes beyond that object which "is the proximate end of a deliberate act of willing on the part of the acting person." 24 In a brief passage (not unlike that in which Aquinas deals at once with Abelard and Lombard), the encyclical rejects both E.g., STh 11-11, q. 64, a. 7; In Matt. c. 7 ad v. 17 [no. 661]. The distinction between the two senses of "intention" is clearly articulated in De Malo, q. 2, a. 2, ad 8, as is the applicability of the broader sense in which means qua chosen are included, along with end(s), in "my intention." 23 V Metaphys., lect. 2, n. 9 [no. 77l]:"lt is not only the ultimate end, for the sake of which the agent acts, that is called end in relation to what precedes it: each of the intermediate means which are between the primary agent and the ultimate end is called an end in relation to what precedes it" (omnia intermedia quae sunt inter primum agens et ultimum finem dicuntur finis respectu praecedentium). See also II Phys., lect. 5, n. 6 [no. 181]; STh 1-11, q. 1, a. 3, ad 3; John Finnis, "Object and Intention in Moral Judgments according to St Thomas Aquinas," The Thomist 55 (1991): 10-14 (revised in Finalite et intentionnalite: Doctrine Thomiste et perspectives modernes, ed. Jacques Follon and James McEvoy [Paris: Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin, 1992], 134-38). 24 Veritatis splendor, no. 78. 22 18 JOHN FINNIS, GERMAIN GRISEZ, JOSEPH BOYLE proportionalist overlooking of the specifying significance of object and a misunderstanding rather like Lombard's of the actions prohibited by the tradition's exceptionless moral norms: By the object of a given moral act, then, one cannot mean a process or an event of the merely physical order, to be assessed on the basis of its ability to bring about a given state of affairs in the outside world. Rather, that object is the proximate end of a deliberate decision which determines the act of willing on the part of the acting person. 25 Employing the contrast between a "proximate" end (object) and a further end (intention)-the same contrast Aquinas employs in his critique of Abelard and Lombard-the encyclical then articulates its central affirmation: it is possible, as revelation and tradition teach, "to qualify as morally evil according to its species-its 'object' -the deliberate choice of certain kinds of behavior or specific acts, apart from a consideration of the intention for which the choice is made or the totality of the foreseeable consequences of that act for all persons concerned. " 26 Here, as we said, the encyclical uses the term "intention" in its narrower sense, as contrasted with "object" (as end is contrasted with means). But since almost every means can be at the same time an end relative to means still more proximate to the acting person's behavior, the broader use of "intention" to include both means and end is also well established in the tradition. This broader sense is particularly common, and apposite, when the issue for moral analysis is not whether something good is being done for bad motives (or, as in Veritatis splendor, no. 79, something bad for good motives), but whether an outcome is intended-is part of the chosen (adopted) proposal-or rather is a side effect. Since that is the main issue in questions about the permissibility of using force, even lethal force, to defend oneself or others, it is not 25 Ibid. 26 Ibid., no. 79; verbatim in no. 82. "DIRECT" AND "INDIRECT" 19 surprising to find Aquinas framing his solution to that problem in terms of "intention" rather than "object:" Nothing prevents a single act having two effects, only one of which is intended [in intentione] while the other is a side effect [praeter intentionem: outside the intention]. Now: morally significant acts get their species [recipiunt speciem] according to what is intended, not what is a side effect (since the latter is incidental/collateral [per accidens]) . ... 27 So, from the act of one who is engaged in self-defense there can follow two effects: one, the preservation of the person's own life, and the other the killing of the attacker. 28 But the point is in no way limited to questions of defense of self or others. Quite generally: "morally significant acts get their species [species] not from what happens as a side effect [praeter intentionem ], but from precisely what it is that one intends [per se in ten tum]. " 29 III Moral theologians in recent centuries intensively discussed the legitimacy of bringing about effects that it would be wrong to intend. They tried to identify conditions under which an act's bad effects would not be part of the act considered as a chosen means. But in trying to do thii;, they unfortunately failed to adopt and consistently maintain the perspective of the acting person. Rather than focusing on the precise object of the acting person's choice, they focused on cause-effect relationships identifiable by outside observers. So, in trying to explicate the requirement that one's chosen means include nothing bad, they reduced means to cause and said that any 27 Here there is a back reference, apparently to STh I-II, q. 72, a. 1 and II-II, q. 43, a. 3. 28 STh II-II, q. 64, a. 7. The fundamental importance of this article is suggested by CCC 2263. See further n. 66 below. 29 STh II-II, q. 150, a. 2. Even more generally, "what is per se in human acts and conduct is what is intended [secundum intentionem]," and what is incidental (per accidens) is what is a side effect (praeter intentionem) (STh II-II, q. 37, a. 1; II-II, q. 38, a. 1; cf. II-II, q. 73, a. 8). 20 JOHN FINNIS, GERMAIN GRISEZ, JOSEPH BOYLE bad effect of an act must not be a cause of the good effect(s) for the sake of which it is done. For example, in his treatment of double effect, Henry Davis, S.J., at the outset of his manual, says: It is permissible to set a cause in motion, in spite of its foreseen evil effect, provided ... secondly ... that a good effect also issues from the act, at least as immediately and directly as the evil effect, that is to say, provided that the evil effect does not first arise, and from it, the good effect. " 30 This was a mistake. That a bad effect issues from an act more immediately and directly than a good effect, or precedes and causes a good effect, does not by itself make the bad effect a means to the good. A heroic soldier who throws himself on a grenade chooses to use his body as a shield so that the shrapnel will not kill his fellows. Yet he does not choose his own destruction as a means, even though the effect of throwing himself on the grenade-his body's being destroyed as it absorbs or slows down the shrapnel-is more immediate and direct than, and indeed causes, the good effect of the grenade's doing little or no injury to his fellows. More humdrum examples of the distinction between what one intends (and chooses as a means) and what one causes but only accepts as a side effect are given above, as cases A and B, with further refinements in cases C through G. The contemporary magisterium relies upon the distinction in a number of its teachings. In Evangelium vitae, for example, it is the basis for distinguishing euthanasia from (1) refusal or forgoing of extraordinary or disproportionate means of treatment, and (2) the use of painkillers "even when the result is ... a shortening of life," on the basis that "in such a case, death is not willed or sought." 31 30 Henry Davis, S.J., Moral and Pastoral Theology 1 (4'h ed.; London: Longman, 1946), 13-14. 31 Evangelium vitae, no. 65, citing inter alia Pius XII, "Address to an International Group of Physicians" (24 Feb. 1957) Ill, AAS 49 (1957): 147. Likewise CCC 2279. Similarly Vacca v. Quill 117 Supreme Court Reporter 2293 at 2301 n. 11, approving New York State Task Force on Life and the Law, When Death Is Sought: Assisted "DIRECT" AND "INDIRECT" 21 It will be helpful to consider closely the emergency obstetrical procedure usually referred to as craniotomy. Taken by itself, the word "craniotomy" strictly means cutting the cranium. 32 But the procedure in question is an operation that, at least at some times in the past, was thought to be medically indicated when a baby's head was too large to allow normal delivery: instruments could be used to crush the baby's head (perhaps after emptying its skull) so as to allow the child's removal from the birth canal and the survival of the mother who would otherwise perish in childbirth along with her child. In 1884, the Holy Office stated with papal approval that one cannot safely teach in Catholic educational institutions that this procedure is morally permissible; in 1889 it restated this, adding that one cannot safely teach that "any surgical operation directly lethal to the fetus or to the pregnant mother" is morally permissible. 33 That craniotomy is often thought to be direct killing and to be morally unacceptable is readily understandable. A number of points can be made to express or reinforce this thought: (1) Doing a craniotomy surely just is killing the baby. Anyone can see what is going on: the baby's destruction and death is observed, not merely foreseen. And (2) killing the baby by crushing its skull does not, itself, help the mother. Saving her Suicide and Euthanasia in the Medical Context (1994) at 163: "It is widely recognized that the provision of pain medication is ethically and professionally acceptable even when the treatment may hasten the patient's death, if the medication is intended to alleviate pain and severe discomfort, not to cause death." 32 "Craniotomy" can refer to very different kinds of act. At least since 1945, in medically advanced environments, the only obstetrical craniotomies are those commonly called "partial-birth abortion," where the operation's purpose is precisely to kill the unborn or partially born child. Those are not the operations discussed as problem cases for Catholic moral theology or doctrine, though reflection on the differences between partial-birth abortion and the obstetrical crises discussed in Catholic theology would shed some light on the proper description, understanding, and moral assessment of the crisis cases under discussion here. 33 DS 3258/1889-90. In 1895 the Holy Office stated, with the pope's approval, that "in accordance with the rulings of 1884 and 1889" one "cannot safely undertake" procedures which, to save the life of the mother, seek the premature expulsion of the fetus even if the intention is that the fetus be delivered if possible alive although too premature to survive (DS 3298/1890a). 22 JOHN FINNIS, GERMAIN GRISEZ, JOSEPH BOYLE depends on the further procedure of removing the baby's corpse from the birth canal. Nor (3) can the killing be said to be unintentional. If someone says to the surgeon "You're killing the baby," the surgeon cannot credibly reply "I don't mean to be doing that" or "I'm not doing it on purpose," as he can say credibly if removing a gravid cancerous uterus. Moreover (4) in any other context than this obstetrical crisis, the same kind of behavior would be intentionally killing the baby-what is nowadays called "partial-birth abortion." (5) This kind of behavior never is done to help the baby. (6) It is repugnant, horrible, and (7) contrary to Church teaching. Though plausible, these arguments are not sound, and each of them can be refuted. (1) Considering the behavior and its results as an event, or sequence of events, or set of causes and effects in the natural world, observers can readily see craniotomy to be killing the baby and rightly describe it as doing so directly. But Veritatis splendor teaches that it is wrong to consider behavior and its results in that way when carrying out moral reflection and seeking to determine what kind of human act is or was being deliberated about, chosen, and done. "By the object of a given moral act, one cannot mean a process or an event of the merely physical order, to be assessed on the basis of its ability to bring about a given state of affairs in the outside world. " 34 34 Veritatis splendor, no. 78. As no. 79 makes clear, the morally relevant species of the act is determined by-indeed, is essentially equivalent to-its object. There is no morally relevant "nature" of the act other than the species so determined. So William E. May, "The Management of Ectopic Pregnancies: A Moral Analysis," in The Fetal Tissue Issue: Medical and Ethical Aspects, ed. Peter J. Cataldo and Albert S. Moraczewski, O.P. (Braintree, Mass.: The Pope John Center, 1994), 141, is mistaken in thinking that an act-as distinct from a piece of behavior considered as a physical event-can be "one which of its very nature kills a person" if killing is not included within the proposal adopted by the acting person and so within that person's object. May's assertion that "if I adopt by choice the proposal to crush the skull and brain of an infant I simply can not ... not intend the baby's death" (ibid.) is simply unsupported by argument and, in context, a mere petitio principii. His equivalent assertion that when my proposal is to blow out someone's brains "I can not reasonably claim that I did not intend, i.e., choose, to kill that person ... [or] that I was adopting by choice a proposal to stop an unprovoked attack, i.e. to defend myself by an act of measured "DIRECT" AND "INDIRECT" 23 As Aquinas regularly puts it, the species of a human act, which (when measured by reason's requirements) settles the moral character of the act as good or bad, right or wrong, is not its species in genere naturae (in the order of nature) but its species in genere moris (in the order of human deliberating and choosing). 35 To be faithful to the tradition and to the contemporary magisterium, it is necessary to get beyond one-sided "common-sense" accounts of "what is being done"-accounts in which what can be seen, and factors such as causal sequences, are given an unreflective priority over the realities illustrated in section I above, realities that are also, as we saw there, recognizable by common-sense, when matters are viewed from the perspective of the acting person. In the wider secular debate, one-sided appeals to common-sense are regularly made to deride the position, affirmed by Popes Pius XII, Paul VI, and John Paul II, that distinguishes between administering analgesics in order to suppress pain while accepting the hastening of death as a side effect, and administering perhaps the very same dose to suppress pain by terminating life. The rejection of this and other similar intention-focused distinctions frequently appears in arguments for euthanasia and assisting suicide. (2) It is true that crushing the baby's skull does not of itself help the mother, and that to help her the surgeon must carry out additional further procedures (remove the baby's body from the birth canal). But many surgical procedures provide no immediate benefit and by themselves are simply destructive: removing the top of someone's skull, stopping someone's heart, and so forth. Proportionalist critics of the tradition frequently claim that all these are cases in which doing evil is obviously justifiable as the means to a good end. But when any force" (ibid.) is contrary to the clear sense of STh II-II, q. 64, a. 7 and to the implications of Veritatis splendor, nos. 78 and 79, as well as of CCC (rev. ed.) nos. 2263-67 (seen. 66 below). 35 See e.g. II Sent., d. 24, q. 3, a. 2; II Sent., d. 40, q. 1, a. 1, corp. and ad 4; II Sent., d. 40, q. 1, a. 4, ad 2; II Sent., d. 42, q. 1, a. 1; STh I-II, q. 20, a. 3, ad 1; STh I-II, q. 20, a. 6; De Malo, q. 2, a. 4, ad 7; De Malo, q. 7, a. 3. See further Finnis, "Object and Intention," 16-24; Finalite et intentionnalite, 140-46. 24 JOHN FINNIS, GERMAIN GRISEZ, JOSEPH BOYLE such surgical procedure, including the obstetrical-crisis craniotomy, is considered not as a mere sequence of movements but as a human act formed by the adoption of a proposal, its moral species becomes clear. (We will say more about this in section IV below.) (3) It is true that a surgeon removing a gravid cancerous uterus might credibly say "I don't mean to be killing the baby" or "I'm not killing the baby on purpose." Because craniotomy immediately causes the destruction of the baby with impressive physical directness, a surgeon performing a craniotomy would not be likely to say the same things. Still, a surgeon who performed a craniotomy and could soundly analyze the action, resisting the undue influence of physical and causal factors that would dominate the perception of observers, could rightly say "No way do I intend to kill the baby" and "It is no part of my purpose to kill the baby." Of course, the lethal damage done to the baby by a craniotomy, being foreseen and voluntarily accepted, can be called "deliberate" and/or "intentional" in various uses of those words. But when the question is whether bringing about that lethal damage violates the commandment and moral norm that exceptionlessly excludes killing the innocent, the fact that bringing it about can in those senses be called intentional and deliberate is irrelevant. What matters is whether the killing is brought about as an end sought (obviously not) or as a chosen means-in other words, whether it is the object, in the sense defined in Veritatis splendor, of the act of the surgeon who performs the craniotomy. 36 (4) Craniotomy might well be physically indistinguishable from "partial-birth abortion." But the proposals adopted by the two kinds of choices, and thus the objects of the two procedures, are entirely different. In partial-birth abortion 36 That the relevant question concerns what is intended as an end or chosen as a means is clear from the Church's teaching about a kind of act that clearly does violate the norm excluding all killing of the innocent, namely direct abortion; see Evangelium vitae no. 62 ("Pius XII excludes all direct abortion, i.e., every act tending directly to destroy human life in the womb 'whether such destruction is intended as an end or only as a means to an end'."); likewise CCC 2271. "DIRECr AND "INDIRECT" 25 done for any of the purposes for which elective abortions are done, the object of the act is to kill the baby before the killing would be classed as infanticide. In craniotomy done for the purpose of saving at least the mother's life, the object of the act is to reduce the size of the baby's head so that the baby or its corpse can be removed from the birth canal. No partialbirth abortion would ever be performed if the baby were already dead. If the baby stuck in the birth canal were already dead, craniotomy would always be performed. This difference is an important sign of the difference between the two kinds of operations considered as human acts in the morally significant sense of that term. (5) Though a craniotomy of the kind we have been discussing, in which the contents of the skull are emptied so that it can be crushed, is not a procedure that could be done to help the baby, there could be a form of craniotomy in which, though the usual outcome is the death of the baby, the surgeon nevertheless hopes that cutting and squeezing the skull without emptying its contents will not result in the baby's death. This, too, is a sign that the fact that craniotomy normally results in the baby's death does not suffice to settle what is or is not the object and therefore the moral species of the act. 37 (6) That craniotomy is repugnant and horrible is unquestionable. It is also unquestionably horrible and repugnant for doctors and nurses to stand by as both a mother and her baby die while they might be doing a craniotomy to increase the probability that at least one would survive. But in neither case can their repugnance and horror help them judge what they truly ought to do. If they correctly analyze the two options, they will see that the norm exceptionlessly excluding 37 That fact is relevant in a consideration of another important question: even if a craniotomy can be done without violating the commandment and moral norm that exceptionlessly excludes intentional killing, isn't it unfair to the baby, and as such wrongful, and therefore homicidal? We do not consider that question in this paper, since it is not settled by what the acting person intends as an end or chooses as a means. The question is briefly considered in Grisez, Living a Christian Life, 503. 26 JOHN FINNIS, GERMAIN GRISEZ, JOSEPH BOYLE intentional killing does not exclude the option of performing a craniotomy, and that their judgment should accordingly be determined by considerations of fairness to both the mother and the baby. 38 (7) Interpreting the Church's documents with precision, one finds that the Church has never taught that craniotomy is intentional killing or that performing a craniotomy is morally wrong. The three documents referring to craniotomy were responses published by the Holy Office, two of them with explicit papal approval, to questions raised by individual bishops. The first two questions (1884 and 1889) concerned craniotomy, but the response asserted only that it could not be safely taught in Catholic educational institutions to be licit. The third question (1895) concerned only premature expulsion of a nonviable fetus, and the response asserted only that such operations could not be safely done; and indicated that this response was in accordance with the earlier decrees that did refer to craniotomy. To say that something cannot be safely taught or even that it cannot be safely done is not to assert that it is immoral. Rather, it is to provide pastoral guidance for the faithful 38 Stephen L. Brock, Action and Conduct: Aquinas and the Theory of Action (Edinburgh: T & T. Clark, 1998), 204-5 n. 17, says: "Thomas's view would allow us to suppose that the surgeon is not aiming at the fetus's death, not crushing the skull in order that the fetus die. But-also on Thomas's view-regardless of his further aim, his act is aimed at producing the crushed skull of an innocent person; and surely it is to that extent How unjust is it? Well, what is the value of an intact skull? The person's life depends on it." But Brock fails to show that the object of the surgeon's chosen act is better described as "producing the crushed skull of an innocent person" than as "cranium-narrowing for the purposes of removal from the birth-canal"-a description he set aside as "a merely abstract description" or "redescribing." (See below n. 47 and text at n. 63.) Still, Brock seems to be perhaps conceding, sub silentio, that the craniotomy need not be excluded by the exceptionless moral norm against killing the innocent, and therefore letting the assessment of its moral character rest on an assessment of its fairness, its justice. To support his view that it is unjust he quotes Aquinas STh 1-11, q. 73, a. 8; but this quotation is not to the point, since it deals only with the way in which consequences, even though unintended, can aggravate the gravity of what is already judged to be wrongful. Note that whether and to what extent the life of the unborn child "depends on" not being subjected to the craniotomy is far from clear in the obstetric emergency we are considering-a situation in which the child is expected to die no matter what is done. "DIRECT" AND "INDIRECT" 27 fulfillment of one's responsibilities as a teacher, and for the formation of one's conscience. Receiving this advice, faithful and prudent teachers and doctors would have realized that, though craniotomy might possibly be morally acceptable, their moral responsibility was to proceed on the assumption that it was not. But a good deal of pastoral guidance wisely given in the nineteenth century could not be rightly followed today. These responses of the Holy Office effectively closed the debate among theologians of those days. However, since the Holy Office did not assert that craniotomy is immoral, its responses cannot ground a sound argument against a position such as ours, 39 based as it is upon an understanding of action thoroughly in line with the tradition and the contemporary magisterium-an understanding not articulated with sufficient clarity by nineteenth-century theologians. 40 Still, although those Holy Office responses refrain from asserting the immorality of the procedures in question, the Church's teaching elsewhere, especially in the twentieth century, makes it perfectly clear that direct killing of the unborn, even to save the life of the mother, is always wrong. We regard this teaching as a truth of faith. 41 Our position is that a doctor could do a craniotomy, even one involving emptying the baby's skull, without intending to kill the baby-that is, without the craniotomy being a direct killing. 42 39 Our position is shared by some theologians completely faithful to the Church's teaching; see, e.g., Marcellino Zalba, "'Nihil prohibet unius actus esse duos effectus' (Summa theologiae 2-2, q. 64, a. 7) Numquid applicari potest principium in abortu therapeutico?" inAtti del Congresso Internazionale (Roma-Napoli-17124 Aprile 1974) Tommaso D'Aquino nel suo settimo centenario, vol. 5, L 'Agire Morale (Napoli: Edizioni Domenicane ltaliane, 1977), 567-68. 40 See, e.g., J. Waffelaert, "De Abortu et Embryotomia," Nouvelle Revue 16 (1884): 160-79, especially the exegesis attempted at 165-71 of STh 1111, q. 64 a. 7. 41 See Germain Grisez, "The Definability of the Proposition: The Intentional Killing of an Innocent Human Being is Always Grave Matter," in Persona Verita e Morale, 291313. 42 Of course, even when bringing about a person's death is not direct killing, doing so is often gravely wrong. We do not deny that there might be reasons for condemning the practice of craniotomy other than that it is direct killing. Faithful Catholics who reject our account of intention and judge that craniotomy, or any other action, is direct 28 JOHN FINNIS, GERMAIN GRISEZ, JOSEPH BOYLE Besides the seven points we have now considered, an argument has recently been proposed by Kevin L. Flannery, S.J., that "there is positive reason not to separate off" the death of the baby from "the compass of the means" in the craniotomy. 43 Flannery, like virtually all Catholic moralists, holds that there is no direct killing in a case where, to save the life of the pregnant mother, her cancerous uterus is removed (hysterectomy) along with the unborn baby within it, with the inevitable result that the baby promptly dies (perhaps many weeks earlier than it otherwise would). He also accepts that "the bringing about of the death of the fetus is not conceptually related to the performance of the craniotomy" and that "there is logical independence of this sort between the crushing of a skull and the fetus's death. " 44 But he contends that "the two cases, craniotomy and hysterectomy, have different logical structures. "45 He points to two ways in which the cases differ "logically." First, the hysterectomy is performed "upon the woman," the craniotomy "upon the fetus." We reply: this difference does not show that craniotomy is direct killing. A counterexample makes this clear. All those acts of self-defense of the kind that Aquinas shows need involve no intent to kill and no direct killing are nonetheless performed "upon" the person killed. 46 And in general, the fact that an act is done to (or "upon") X for the sake ofY, or to Y for the sake of Y, provides killing certainly ought to form their consciences, in relation to such actions, by the Church's teaching that all direct killing of the innocent is gravely wrong. And, even if certain that a possible action would not be a direct killing, all faithful Catholics should form their consciences in the light of faith with regard to the requirements of both justice and mercy. 43 K. Flannery, "What is Included in a Means to an End?," Gregorianum 74 (1993): 510££. Ibid., 506. Ibid., 511. 46 In saying this we in no way suggest that the baby in the craniotomy is an unjust aggressor or any other kind of aggressor. (Indeed, we deny that the unborn baby is ever an aggressor.) Aquinas's analysis of the intention in self-defense does not depend upon there being an unjust aggression. 44 45 "DIRECT" AND "INDIRECT" 29 no criterion for distinguishing between what is intended and what is accepted as a side effect. Flannery's second "logical" distinction: whereas in the hysterectomy "the death of the fetus stands outside [the] description" of the act as "a hysterectomy on a pregnant woman in order that she might regain her health," in the craniotomy, "in order to separate off from the compass of the means the killing of the fetus, it is necessary to redescribe the act of craniotomy, calling it a cranium-narrowing operation." Such separating off or redescription is, he says, "artificial. " 47 This argument also fails. What counts for moral analysis is not what may or may not be included in various descriptions that might be given by observers, or even by acting persons reflecting on what they have done, but what is or is not included within a proposal developed in deliberation for possible adoption by choice. Only the truthful articulation of that proposal can be a description that specifies an act for the purposes of moral analysis. Our contention, which Flannery fails to discuss, much less refute, is that when someone chooses to do a craniotomy on a baby to save his or her mother's life in an obstetrical predicament, the morally relevant description of the act would not include killing the baby. As we have shown in section II above, the act analysis we have just employed in refuting Flannery's argument is not simply a philosophical and anthropological view peculiar to us, but is rooted in the tradition, employed by the magisterium, and explicitly taught in Veritatis splendor. Flannery's insufficient grip on that act analysis is indicated by 47 Flannery, "What is Included in a Means to an End?," 511-12. May, "The Management of Ectopic Pregnancies," 142, expresses his agreement with Flannery's article and expresses the thought that "Grisez and Boyle are really redescribingthe act in terms of its intended (in the sense of future, as distinct from present intentions} consequences" (ibid., 140). In both contexts, the talk of "redescription" amounts to no more than a rhetorical means of asserting, without argument, that the description of the act for which Grisez and Boyle have argued, rearticulated with further argument in the present article, is unacceptable. Pace May, it is not true that "Grisez and Boyle prefer to call [craniotomy] a 'cranium-narrowing' operation." Its physical character as a lethal crushing and emptying is not evaded or softened in our discussions. 30 JOHN FINNIS, GERMAIN GRISEZ, JOSEPH BOYLE his claim, in a subsequent article, that if a hysterectomy on the cancerous womb is performed needlessly early, it "becomes not merely performing a hysterectomy but also a direct killing. " 48 This is a significant confusion. 49 Performing a hysterectomy to save a woman from a slow-growing cancer, when her baby could have been saved by waiting a few weeks without much greater risk to her, is seriously wrongful killing inasmuch as it is unjust to the baby, and so can be called homicidal. But the injustice does not transform that homicide into direct killing; the baby's death is a side effect just as it would be if the operation were being done later and were justified. It is worth adding another example of confusion about intention, object, proposals, and directness in Flannery's recent writings: Where someone puts a bomb on an aircraft in order to collect insurance on the aircraft itself (not life insurance on its passengers or crew), Flannery rightly holds that "it is not part of this proposal that anyone be killed," and that, unlike Mr. G who walks into a restaurant and shoots down Mr. H "because he wants him dead," "the aircraft bomber's intentions ... extend only as far as destruction of the aircraft. " 50 But at the same time he says that "both the aircraft bomber and Mr. G. intend death" and both of them "intend to violate" the basic human good of life, because "destruction of the aircraft ... in fact means death for the passengers." 51 The two sets of statements contradict each other. What is true is that the passengers' death, being outside the proposal, is not intended by the bomber; and that the 48 Kevin L. Flannery, "Natural Law mens rea versus the Benthamite Tradition," American Journal of Jurisprudence 40 (1995): 395. 49 Flannery is also inaccurate in stating (ibid.) that "in Thomistic terms, the end (which a person intends) specifies the act, but it is not part of the substance of the act [Summa Theologiae, 1-11, q. 7, a. 3]: it is not part of what the person is doing. It is 'a sort of adjunct end.' [aliquis finis adiunctus- ... 1-11, q. 7 a. 3]." But in STh 1-11, q. 7, a. 3, ad 3, Aquinas does not say that an act's specifying end is "adjunct" (what Flannery calls "not part of the act's substance"); rather he says that adjunct ends are to be contrasted with specifying ends. so Flannery, "Natural Law mens rea versus the Benthamite Tradition," 393, 392, 396. 51 Ibid., 396. "DIRECT" AND "INDIRECT" 31 bomber's willingness to cause their deaths, and his doing so, is nevertheless gravely wrong. A soldier who leaps on a handgrenade to save his buddy also expects that this "in fact means" death for himself, but does not on that account intend to violate the basic good of human life, for (as we noted at the beginning of section III) he is not choosing to bring about his death. IV Jean Porter has recently devoted an article to arguing that the account of action and intention developed by Grisez (and the other authors of the present article) fails to provide a cogent account of "the distinction between direct and indirect action." "His applications of the distinction," she says, "apparently reflect prior moral judgments which the distinction serves to justify after the fact. "52 Porter gives an apparently detailed and careful statement of Grisez's account of what is a means (i.e., what is "directly" chosen and intended) rather than a side effect (i.e., what is only "indirectly" willed and done) or an end (i.e., the further intention[s] of the chooser). But she considers that his account "is spelled out most fully" in an article published in 1970, 53 and that a key to his understanding of means is a concept important in that article, "indivisibility of performance." The bulk of her article is devoted, in one way or another, to arguments that attempt to show the unsatisfactoriness of indivisibility of performance as a "criterion" of the unity of a human act to be morally evaluated (618) and/or a "criterion for distinguishing between direct and indirect harms" (627). But "indivisibility of performance" has not been used by Grisez 52 Jean Porter, '"Direct' and 'Indirect' in Grisez's Moral Theory," Theological Studies 57 (1996): 612. (Parenthetical numbers in the text below signify page numbers in her article.) In n. 4 she states that the views expressed in the writings of Boyle and Finnis on these matters are not significantly different from Grisez's. 53 Germain Grisez, "Toward a Consistent Natural-Law Ethics of Killing," American Journal of Jurisprudence 15 (1970): 88, 85. 32 JOHN FINNIS, GERMAIN GRISEZ, JOSEPH BOYLE in any of his writings on action since 1970, and it plays no part whatever in any of the work on act analysis on which we have collaborated. Though its irrelevance to our understanding of intention and action will have been evident to many careful readers of our work since 1970, it would have been helpful had we stated explicitly, somewhere, that the appeal to "indivisibility of performance" in the 1970 article was a false step caused by failure to appreciate the decisive significance of "the perspective of the acting person" and of the proposal an acting person develops in deliberation as a possibility for choice. Porter says something true and important in her critique of indivisibility of performance. In the 1970 article Grisez said that "The very act of crushing and removing the baby, an act in fact destructive of its life, saves the mother from otherwise perhaps inevitable death. " 54 But as Porter rightly notes, the performance of the craniotomy is divisible: "if the doctor were to walk away immediately after crushing the head of the child, the woman would almost certainly still die"(629). 55 This divisibility-and its irrelevance-is implicit in our discussion of craniotomy in section III above: the baby's death is a side effect of changing the dimensions of its skull, which is the means to the further actions that save the mother's life; and no side effect of a means is part of the means. 56 What should be said about Porter's central claim, that our analysis of action lacks objectivity, and is controlled by prior moral judgments derived from "other considerations" (631)? Her position is that the analysis common among postIbid., 94. ss Joseph Lombardi, "Obstetrical Dilemmas and the Principle of Double Effect," American journal of jurisprudence 3 7 ( 1992): 205-9, also notes that doing a craniotomy does not by itself save the mother's life and that further actions are required, and infers that killing the baby necessarily is a bad means to the good end of saving the mother. But Lombardi refers not to Grisez's mistake about indivisibility of performance but to Boyle's mistake of denying that further actions are needed to save the mother: see Joseph Boyle, "Double Effect and a Certain Type of Embryotomy," Irish Theological Quarterly 44 (1977): 307. s6 See also Grisez, Living a Christian Life (1993), 502-3. -'4 "DIRECT" AND "INDIRECT" 33 Tridentine moralists (see sec. III above) has an advantage over ours, and that their assimilation of cause-effect with meansend "provided an objective basis for assessing the intention of the agent" (620). There is a sense of "objective" that lends plausibility to her claim. Cause and effect in the physical world are observable. So, if killing is understood simply as bringing about death, one can observe John killing Mary just as one can observe a cat killing a mouse. But, as we have explained above, unless one adopts and steadily maintains the perspective of the acting person, one cannot provide or even recognize the only description of a moral act that is morally relevant and true, and so morally objective. Therefore, the objectivity Porter considers appropriate is not even morally relevant. It is easy to understand why this irrelevant objectivity is invoked by Porter and many others. Though observers can often infer in some respects the morally objective description of another's act, his or her proposal never can be an observable object. So people with what Bernard Lonergan calls a naive extroverted consciousness are always likely to think that the authentic objectivity of human acts is not really objective, and that the objectivity required for act analysis must be derived from external observations of causes and effects, or other factors entirely accessible to any and every observer. Accordingly, Porter thinks that our distinction between means and side effects is merely subjective because it is not based on the sequence of cause and effects ("the causal structure of the act"): Without some such basis, the agent's intention could be described in terms of whatever could be said to be the agent's purpose or motive in acting. In that case it would be difficult to see how the doctrine of double effect would rule anything out, since any act can be said to be directed to some good or other, in terms of which the agent's intention could be described . . . . The question that arises is: Does Grisez's interpretation of the direct/indirect [scil. means/side effect] distinction similarly provide an objective criterion for determining what the agent's intention is? Or does 34 JOHN FINNIS, GERMAIN GRISEZ, JOSEPH BOYLE it leave open the possibility of describing the agent's intention in terms of whatever good purposes motivate the act in question. 57 Porter maintains that Grisez's account-which we have expounded in section I of this article, and whose roots in the tradition we have shown in section II-provides no ground for an objective identification of what someone is doing, and thus leaves the moral evaluation of action at the mercy of arbitrariness or manipulation. We have emphasized in the foregoing quotation the phrases that indicate the core of Porter's view. What "could be said" about an action by people who observe its performance, and who speak about it for their multifarious purposes, is indeed, as Porter indicates, indefinitely various. Indeed, what "can be said" about an action and its intentions by the very person whose act and intent they are is various, indefinite, and unstable, if that person is reflecting, as a kind of observer, on his or her purposes and motivations. And acting persons so reflecting on their actions and intentions, and representing them to others, are indeed likely to shape their account by reference to "whatever good purposes" they have, and to suppress or misstate-perhaps even to themselves-both any other purposes that may be motivating them and any means they have adopted but would rather not think about and/or be known to have adopted. But none of this should obscure the fact that the truth about what is intended and being done is available, primarily if not exclusively to the acting person in that acting-in that deliberating, choosing, and carrying out the choice-which constitutes the reality to which all accounts of intention and action must conform if they are to be true. Each clear-headed and honest person knows what he or she is truly or objectively doing. Such persons know what end(s) they have in view, and what means they have reason, in view of such end(s), to choose, and are actually choosing in preference to alternatives. Roe knows, for example, that he saw an assailant's attack as an opportunity to kill a long-hated -17 Porter, "'Direct' and 'Indirect' in Grisez's Moral Theory," 620 (emphases added). "DIRECT" AND "INDIRECT" 35 enemy (or: a person he had contracted for money to kill), and knows that in taking steps that any observer would reasonably judge to be intended only as self-defensive measures to stop the assailant's attack, he was really and trulyobjectively-trying to kill in revenge (or: to fulfill the contract). Roe's self-knowledge is objective. So too in the converse case. Doe, a shopkeeper robbed many times may acquire a gun and-as a bluff-announce to the neighborhood that she will kill the next robber in her store. When she sees a young tough move something suspiciously in his coat, she judges that she is about to be robbed at gunpoint, tries to shoot him in the shoulder, but hits his heart. To a jury, what happened may well seem to have been a straightforward intentional killing, carrying out her deterrent threat. But in truth and reality it was no more than a self-defensive act, chosen, without any intent to kill, to stop what she mistakenly believed was an assault. The morally significant acts a person does are, objectively, what that person chooses to do for the reasons he or she has for making those choices. A true and morally objective description of such acts is the description they have, prospectively (as acts still to be done), in the proposals the acting person shapes in deliberation and adopts by choice(s). What an act objectively is, and can be known objectively to be, is not affected by what the acting person or others may say about it, or by what others may reasonably (though mistakenly) infer it to be. Nor is the reality of what an acting person is doing described adequately or objectively by describing it only in terms of the purposes that motivated it, omitting what the acting person chose to do as means of pursuing those purposes. Failing to attend to the perspective of the acting person, Porter systematically fails to attend to chosen means (to what the tradition, retrieved and restated in Veritatis splendor, calls the "objects" of acts). Her accounts of actions reduce them to intended ends and outward behavior-the "immediate bodily movements" she calls "primitive acts." Even the accounts she offers of ends or motivations for action tend to overlook 36 JOHN FINNIS, GERMAIN GRISEZ, JOSEPH BOYLE reasons for choosing means. We shall point out the oversight when commenting on her examples of types of act. For now we illustrate Porter's misunderstanding of action by pointing simply to a notable instance that occurs when she is stating her position at the level of general theory. This instance occurs at the very moment when she acknowledges that "Grisez could admit that there are indefinitely many correct descriptions for every act, and yet still hold that only one of these is morally relevant, namely, that which describes the act in terms of what the agent does in fact intend" (622). She remarks at this point that "this argument does not resolve the difficulty" that she thinks faces Grisez in trying to distinguish means from side effects. If one accepts the Thomistic principle that every action is directed knowingly towards the attainment of some good (as Grisez does), then it follows that every action can be described in terms of some good which the agent is voluntarily seeking. Why should the agent not describe his intention in terms of that good, relegating the harms which he brings about to foreseen but not chosen aspects of the act? (Ibid.) The answer to her question is clear. If a young woman chooses to have her embryonic child suctioned from her uterus as a means to forestalling the unwelcome choice between giving her baby up for adoption and raising him or her, then a description-such as "having the pregnancy terminated"-of this human action that omits her choice to have that done as a means to her end is objectively incomplete in an essential respect. But instead of attending to the answer that our theory of action gives to her question, Porter imagines that Grisez would respond to it "by claiming that the intention in question must be understood psychologically as well as logically" (623). By "psychologically" she refers not to rational but to emotional motives: "no amount of redescription can change the reality of what the agent desires" when "desires" is understood (as she takes for granted) to refer to, for example, "hatred," "desire "DIRECT" AND "INDIRECT" 37 for revenge," "malice," "envy," "cruelty," "or some similar motive" (620). However, even though some such emotional factors do help motivate adult children to decide to bring about the death of their aged parent before the insurance moneys run out and the estate is consumed, still neither the emotional motives nor the prospect of financial gain specify what it is that the children choose and do. If those emotions and reasons motivate the children to think of a way to hasten their parent's death, and the children adopt that proposal, what they choose and do is hasten their parent's death. Even if the means they use cannot be recognized by outside observers as means of hastening death, the children's practical reasoning shaped their choice to hasten her death as a means to their ends, ends arising from emotional motives and/or rational considerations. Similarly, the parents of a newly born baby afflicted with Down's syndrome may consider terminating their child's life by withholding an easy, effective, and inexpensive operation, whatever emotional motivations drive that deliberation. If they decide to withhold the operation as a way of (means to) killing the child, then, whatever they tell themselves or others, they really ("objectively") intend to kill the baby. There is little or nothing to be gained by asking whether this truth about their intentions and actions is "psychological" or "logical. "58 And it is entirely beside the point to ask (as Porter repeatedly does) whether, in cases such as these, "the agent's will must 58 If the question were pressed, we could point out that the structure of actions considered as the subject-matter of moral evaluation pertains to the third of the four types of order identified by Aquinas in the opening paragraphs of his Commentary on the Nicomachean Ethics-the kind of order that one brings into one's own behavior by deliberation and choice, as irreducibly distinct from (1) the order of nature (which includes much of what is called "psychological"), (2) the order of logic, and (4) the order of arts and techniques. See, e.g., Germain Grisez,Beyond the New Theism (Notre Dame & London: University of Notre Dame, 1975), ch. 14; Finnis,Aquinas, 20-23, 52 and index s.v. "four orders." So far forth, then, the structures considered in moral evaluation are neither "psychological" nor "logical," though there are psychological and logical, as well as ontological and technical, elements both in moral life and in reflection upon it. 38 JOHN FINNIS, GERMAIN GRISEZ, JOSEPH BOYLE necessarily 59 be focused on the killing, and not on the good which is sought" (623). An agent choosing to kill someone, for whatever good, necessarily and really focuses both on the end sought and the killing chosen as a means to it. Striving to press her claim that Grisez has no good way of distinguishing means from side effects, Porter takes up various kinds of cases. She asks, first, "how Grisez can distinguish morally between killing in self-defense and euthanasia" (624). After trying to show that the two kinds of act cannot be distinguished in various ways, she at last notices that Grisez would say, and has everywhere said, that (to use her rendering) "in the case of euthanasia, as opposed to killing in self-defense, the agent's act is aimed precisely at the death of the individual who is killed" (624 ). But instead of addressing this response, which provides precisely what she claims Grisez cannot provide, Porter changes the subject. She notices that Grisez has sometimes called attention to one sign or manifestation of the difference between engaging in lethal behavior with intent to stop an attack (accepting the attacker's death as a side effect) and engaging in the same behavior with intent to kill the attacker: that in the first case the acting person will desist from the lethal behavior if the attack is broken off by the wounding or flight of the attacker, whereas in the second the acting person will or may well press on with the lethal behavior, seizing the opportunity to finish off the attacker. Not attending to Grisez's analysis of the difference as chosen means between self-defense and euthanasia, she argues that that sign or manifestation of the difference is not an adequate criterion of it. Of course, we agree that it is not an adequate criterion, since it is no criterion at all. 59 Porter (at 621) had introduced "necessarily" into her lead-in to a quotation from Grisez in which "necessarily" nowhere appears. She then went on to say: "When Grisez says that an action with both good and bad effects is not defined by the bad effect unless it is necessarily included in the agent's intention ... " and proceeded to speculate about what kind of necessity that might be, thus constructing a dialectic irrelevant to Grisez's moral theory. "DIRECT" AND "INDIRECT" 39 In irrelevantly challenging the adequacy as a criterion of the sign, Porter considers the possibility that a woman using lethal force in self-defense against rape does not at once succeed in stopping her attacker, and says: "then presumably she would try again to kill him" (625). By saying "try again to kill," Porter inadvertently makes clear the irrelevance of her argument, for Grisez's analysis of morally acceptable lethal self-defense precisely is that it is not trying to kill. It would be logically impossible for a victim to "try again" to kill an attacker if that victim's prior behavior were genuine selfdefense. Porter also considers the possibility that a doctor trying to euthanase a patient might desist if the first attempt unexpectedly "somehow relieves the patient's suffering without killing him" (625). In this case she soundly points out that what usually is a sign of nonhomicidal intent cannot be a criterion. But she overlooks the physician's first choice: having tried to kill her patient, the doctor has done an act of homicide whether or not she herself, in subsequent reflection, Porter, or anyone else recognizes that. Another of Porter's sample cases, put forth to show that Grisez's account of action cannot (without covertly drawing upon prior moral judgments) distinguish means from side effects, is craniotomy. We have discussed this in the preceding section, but it is important now to see precisely how Grisez's view of craniotomy is handled by Porter. She invites the reader to "Consider the case of the doctor who saves the life of a woman in labor by performing a craniotomy on her child. Such an act is justified, in Grisez's view, because it is inseparably an act of killing and an act of saving the woman's life" (629). Porter obviously is referring to Grisez's 1970 formulation of his view. 60 His more recent view is set out in Living a Christian Life (1993 ), which Porter cites elsewhere in her article. On the specific question being considered by 60 Even so, she misstates that position, which was not that inseparability justifies craniotomy but only that it is a necessary condition for its moral acceptability. Even in 1970, Grisez pointed out that it is not the only necessary condition for the act's uprightness. 40 JOHN FINNIS, GERMAIN GRISEZ, JOSEPH BOYLE Porter-the question whether ending the baby's life is intended ("direct") or rather accepted as a side effect ("indirect")Grisez states his view without reference to inseparability: The baby's death need not be included in the proposal adopted in choosing to do a craniotomy. The proposal can be simply to alter the child's physical dimensions and remove him or her, because, as a physical object, this body cannot remain where it is without ending in both the baby's and the mother's deaths. To understand this proposal, it helps to notice that the baby's death contributes nothing to the objective sought; indeed, the procedure is exactly the same if the baby has already died. In adopting this proposal, the baby's death need only be accepted as a side effect. 61 Ignoring this articulation of the doctor's proposal, Porter addresses Grisez's former idea about inseparability, and argues that the "primitive acts" (immediate bodily movements) involved in craniotomy are in fact separable, since the doctor might walk away after crushing the baby's skull, omitting the further primitive acts needed to save the mother (pulling out the child, etc.). Since the same could be said of any surgical operation, "it is hard to see how he [Grisez] could allow any medical procedure that requires a series of primitive actions, some of which are destructive in their immediate effects" (629). That reductio ad absurdum would follow if Porter's interpretation of Grisez's position were sound. But it is not sound, and she concedes that "perhaps what this example shows is that we are mistaken in assuming that the Davidsonian primitive act is Grisez's unit of moral analysis" (ibid.). Her "assuming" that the "Davidsonian" or any other kind of "primitive act" (immediate bodily movement) is or ever has been Grisez's unit of moral analysis is groundless and plainly contrary to his account of acts in all the texts of his which she considers. 62 61 Ibid. 502 (emphasis added). 62 In the 1970 article to which Porter gives (inappropriate) prominence, Grisez says: "A means in the order of human action must be a single, complete human act •••. Now a human action derives its unity from two sources. One source is the unity of one's intention. ('Intention' here refers not merely to intention of the end, but also to the meaning one understands his act to have when he chooses it as a means to an intended "DIRECT" AND "INDIRECT" 41 Porter considers the possibility that "primitive acts" are not Grisez's unit of analysis. But she does not abandon her attempts to attribute to Grisez an account of action that fails to adopt the perspective of the acting person and looks only to primitive movements plus overall intention, ignoring chosen means: "Perhaps the explanation of the craniotomy example lies in the fact that the primitive act of crushing, taken together with a series of other acts, is informed by the agent's overall life-saving intention, especially since Grisez insists that what is morally significant is the will of the agent, as determined by the proposal he adopts" (ibid.). Porter's reference to "the proposal he adopts" might suggest that she has grasped the central element of Grisez's analysis. However, she still fails to notice that proposals are not of primitive movements informed by an overall intention, but of actions understood as possible means. The act of craniotomy, whatever immediate physical movements it may involve, is the act accurately described by Grisez in the passage already quoted from his book: to alter the child's physical dimensions and remove him or her. Earlier on the same page of that book he had given another, equivalent description of the proposal/act: "a craniotomy (an operation in which instruments are used to empty and crush the head of the child so that it can be removed from the birth canal)." These formulations describe the same kind of act, and do so by identifying the "object" of that act. 63 Both correspond to the ways the choice and act might be conceptualized in the deliberations of a doctor considering whether or not to perform the act, and in the deliberations of the child's parents or anyone else concerned in the decision-making. Instead of giving her own moral evaluation of craniotomyas she imagines Grisez understands it-Porter proceeds end')" (Grisez, "Toward a Consistent Natural-Law Ethics of Killing," 88 [emphasis added]). Or again: "both means and end have a behavioral aspect (Aquinas's external act) and an aspect of human meaning (Aquinas's interior act)" (ibid., 85 [emphasis added]). 63 Cf. response to Brock in n. 38 above. 42 JOHN FINNIS, GERMAIN GRISEZ, JOSEPH BOYLE immediately to assert that the account of action she (mistakenly) attributes to Grisez would justify contraception by "uniting the primitive actions of employing some contraceptive and engaging in sexual intercourse into one intention, say, an intention of expressing marital intimacy in a responsible fashion" (ibid.). Here Porter unwittingly testifies to the ease with which people can identify means for the purpose of morally significaht deliberation and choice. For "employing a contraceptive" is not the sort of thing she had been calling a "primitive act"; it does not pick out any immediate bodily movement or set of such movements. The relevant bodily movements, after all, might be those involved in putting on a condom, taking a pill, and so forth. Rather, "employing a contraceptive" is a kind of human act specified as a means to an end-that is, using something, anything whatever, to make an act of intercourse less likely than it otherwise would be to result in conception. In short, the very term "contraception" which Porter uses here refers to a means as it would usually be identified in deliberating and shaping proposals to act for an end: to prevent conception. Moreover, Porter's suggestion that our view allows an argument for contraception is incorrect. On our view, one cannot engage in what Porter calls "expressing marital intimacy in a responsible fashion" without at some time or other having adopted two proposals by making two choices: (1) to employ a contraceptive, (2) to engage here and now in marital intercourse. Each is the choice and carrying out of a means to an end; each is identifiable as a distinct kind of act (however many bodily movements it may involve); and neither can be assessed morally without reference, in the first instance, to its characteristics as an act of that kind. As noted at the beginning of this section, Porter's primary thesis is that Grisez is guilty of the same thing with which he charged Richard McCormick: 64 taking positions on moral issues and then finding reasons for them (631-32). Her article is an elaborate attempt to prove that charge against Grisez. We 64 See Grisez, Christian Moral Principles, 15 7. "DIRECT" AND "INDIRECT" 43 have shown that her account of his action theory, and her attempts to criticize it, fail radically. She also contends that our account of action is out of line with the tradition, but we have shown both here and elsewhere that the main lines of our account are entirely traditional. Porter is right in saying that our analysis of craniotomy is not defending a teaching of the Church. But that fact by itself is sufficient to falsify her primary thesis. Grisez's work has not been an effort to "provide a systematic philosophical justification for the tenets of traditional Catholic morality" (611). If that had been his purpose, he surely would not have said what he consistently has about craniotomy, and capital punishment, and killing in war. He would never have taken the position that it is wrong to try to kill a human being. He would have been satisfied instead to defend the thesis that he has argued is a truth of faith: the intentional killing of the innocent is always grave matter. But as it is, he has criticized traditional views of capital punishment and killing in warfare, and argued that capital punishment always is wrongful killing and that even the killing of enemy combatants can be justified only if the action that brings about their death is done without any intention to kill them. 65 The Catechism of the Catholic Church, most plainly in its revised edition-in relation to killing in capital punishment, and war, and in general if not on craniotomy (which is not mentioned)-has adopted a position like the one defended for thirty years by Grisez. Killing of human beings is justifiable only insofar as it is not intended. 66 This underlines the importance, for a sound understanding of the faith as well as 6 .s See, e.g., ibid. 220; Finnis, Boyle, and Grisez, Nuclear Deterrence, Morality and Realism, 309-19. 66 The revised CCC's entire treatment of cases of justifiable killing is put under the aegis of Aquinas's distinction between the "double effect" of lethal self-defensive actions that do not intend the killing of the aggressor (no. 2263; seen. 28 above). Accordingly, punishment can only be lethal "if this is the only way of effectively defending human lives against the unjust aggressor" (no. 2267). And killing in war can be justifiable only as "legitimate defense," that is, where "the defense of the common good requires that an unjust aggressor be rendered unable to cause harm," and the right to use arms is the right only "to repel aggressors." 44 JOHN FINNIS, GERMAIN GRISEZ, JOSEPH BOYLE for a sound philosophy, of understanding with precision and consistency just what it is to intend, to choose, and to act. The Thomist 65 (2001): 45-65 SIMILARITIES AND DIFFERENCES BETWEEN HUMAN AND ANIMAL EMOTION IN AQUINAS'S THOUGHT STEPHEN LOUGHLIN De Sales University Allentown, Pennsylvania 0 ne of the striking features of Aquinas's thought concerning the emotions 1 is his attribution of them to the animal lacking reason. 2 His argument in this respect is direct and simple: since the emotions constitute the various actualizations of the sensitive appetite in relation to some sensible thing considered as good or bad, whatever possesses a sensitive appetite will likewise experience the emotions. Since the animals lacking 1 The translation of the term passio as "emotion" acts here as a placeholder, so to speak, and does not intend to cover the broad usage it has in modern thought. In fact, no word in English properly signifies Aquinas's understanding of passio. In this regard, see Amelie 0. Rorty, "Aristotle on the Metaphysical Status of Pathe," Review of Metaphysics 38 (1984): 521-22, 539-46, which outlines the many problems facing the modern philosopher's approach to ancient theories concerning the pathe, particularly his "abandonment" of the metaphysical basis upon which these theories are based, a problem which is compounded by the fact that contemporary discussions of the emotions "have retained the distinctions and preoccupations which were embedded in that metaphysical setting" (522). Furthermore, as B. Inwood states: "No translation of the term is adequate, for pathos is a technical term whose meaning is determined by the theory in which it functions" (Ethicsand Human Action in Early Stoicism [Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1985), 127). Although these comments are directed specifically at the Aristotelian and Stoic understanding of pathos, they apply equally well to Aquinas's doctrine of passio, given the similarity of his metaphysics with respect to the former, and his clearly technical use of passio with respect to the latter. For a discussion concerning the difficulties of translatingpassio into an equivalent English term, see St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae,vol. 19, The Emotions (1a2te. 22-30), ed. and trans. Eric D'Arcy (Melbourne: University of Melbourne, 1967), xix-xxvi. 2 This attribution is striking given the predominant view among contemporary philosophers that the emotions are essentially rational in nature. 45 46 STEPHEN LOUGHLIN reason possess a sensitive appetite, the emotions are not peculiar to human beings.3 This position raises a number of questions. Aquinas holds that every emotion of the sensitive appetite is preceded by some kind of assessment of the sensible thing with respect to its suitability (or lack thereof) for the being apprehending it. In animals lacking reason, this assessment is performed by the estimative power, while in human beings it is accomplished by the cogitative or particular reason. This assessment is vital for emotion, for by it the sensible thing is brought under the ratio of the conveniensor inconveniens and thereby becomes the proper object of the sensitive appetite itself. Without this assessment, the sensitive appetite lacks its proper or formal object, and is thus not moved, which is to say that there is no experience of the emotions in such a situation; the simple presentation of an object apart from evaluation does not move the appetite. 4 3 For the definition of passio as a movement or actualization of the sensitive appetite, see STh 1-11, q. 22; that they are shared in common with animals lacking reason, see STh 1-11, q. 24, a. 1, ad 1; 1-11, q. 6, prol.; that the emotions are experienced by human and animal alike by reason of the sensitive appetite, see STh I, q. 80, a. 1. 4 The clearest presentation of this point is found at De anima III, leer. 4, §§634-35. The basic argument is this: the sensitive appetite is a passive power in that it is immediately moved or actualized in the presence of its proper object. This object is not the simple appearance of the sensible thing as such, but rather this as it has been assessed as conveniensor not to the being as such. This estimation is performed not by the imagination (or for that matter by the external senses, the sensuscommunis, or memory, although the latter could store previously made assessments), but rather by the estimative power in animals lacking reason, and the cogitative power in human beings (also see STh I-II, q. 9, a. 1, ad 2. Although Aquinas does not mention the particular power which performs this opinio mentioned at §635, it is clear from the context, from the corpores of STh I, q. 78, a. 4; and I, q. 81, a. 3; the principle stated at I, q. 80, a. 1, ad 2; and the discussion concerning emotion's definition at 1-11, q. 22, that the cogitative power is that which is concerned with the sensitive appetite's proper object. Opinio refers to the operation of the cogitative, but is a general enough term to indicate also that the cogitative is not alone in its activities, but that it relies upon reason, experience, and the teachings of others for its determinations of the conveniens and the inconveniens;aestimatio, on the other hand, refers specifically to the estimative power in animals, which power naturally and necessarily determines what is conveniens or inconveniens).Without this assessment, that is, without the operation of the estimative or cogitative powers, the formal object of the sensitive appetite is not obtained, and the sensitive appetite is not under any necessity to be moved or actualized with respect to it. This is one of the characteristics that distinguishes the sensitive appetite from the natural appetite, where HUMAN AND ANIMAL EMOTION 47 From Aquinas's definitions and descriptions of the irascible emotions it is clear that they all require some degree of rationality in their arousal, operation, and completion. For example, hope and despair require the capacity to consider something in future terms, that is, whether some arduous good can be obtained or not. Again, anger requires three things, namely, the abilities to understand that one has been insulted or slighted in some fashion, to recognize that one suffers presently from this evil, and to react against it, that is, to hope for and plan revenge in the future. These and other characteristics, essential to the irascible emotions, belong only to beings possessing reason. 5 In this light, then, it is asked, how could an animal lacking reason plausibly be said to experience the range of emotions enjoyed by the human being? Is not the assessment or judgment of something as suitable (or not) a rational operation, and not merely an instinctive one? Would it not be more appropriate to limit the irrational animal's experience of the sensitive appetite's movements to perhaps only the most basic movements of the concupiscible aspect, those which seem less rational in their operations, than to extend the irascible to them as well? But surely the animal lacking reason demonstrates at least the irascible emotion of anger. How, then, does one overcome the requirement of rationality necessitated for anger? Perhaps the emotions of the sensitive appetite in a rational being are qualitatively different from those of the animal lacking reason, and animals, in this respect, only exhibit an appearance of anger and the other irascible emotions. But how could this be affirmed when the prologue to question 6 of the Prima secundaestates that the emotions are shared in common between human beings and animals, and that the usage of passio, with respect to both animal and human, does not appear to be equivocal? Nevertheless, is there the former is not completely passive (as the latter is) with respect to its object as such, but requires that it be apprehended under the ratio of the conveniensif the sensitive appetite is to be moved, or rather, actualized; as above, simple apprehension alone is not enough to move the appetite (see De Verit., q. 22, a. 4). 5 See the objections to STh 1-11, q. 40, a. 3. For further comments concerning the necessity of reason for the consideration of future and past events, particularly as they relate to a being's present condition and welfare, see De anima III, lect. 15, §829. STEPHEN LOUGHLIN 48 not some sense in which the human being is said, because of his rationality, to experience the emotions in a qualitatively different way from the animal lacking reason? 6 It is the purpose of this article to clarify and defend Thomas's attribution of the emotions to the animal lacking reason, proceeding in light of these questions. I We begin with a central characteristic common to both animal and human emotion, namely, that the movement or actualization of their sensitive appetites is immediate and necessary in the presence of the appetite's proper object. This characteristic constitutes the general description of emotion, and is indicative of the sensitive appetite's natural functioning. 7 Differences between human and animal emotion arise when one considers the events that lie on both sides of this immediate and necessary movement of the sensitive appetite, that is, the cognitive events that come before it, and the actions taken by the being subsequent 6 Some of these concerns have been voiced in a recent article by R. Roberts, "Thomas Aquinas on the Morality of Emotions," History of Philosophy Quarterly 9 (1992): 287-305. He argues that since reason is intrinsically involved in the essence of emotion, "most of the emotions that humans experience are never experienced by animals, and do not, therefore, belong to a non-rational appetite" (292). Thus, an emotion, like anger, considered just in itself, shared in common with animals lacking reason, is a "fiction." For the object of anger is "accessible only through reason," a power lacking to the animal. To describe an animal as angry is thus to use the word equivocally or metaphorically (293-94). With respect to hope and despair, Roberts states: maybe dogs do have some rudimentary concept of the future, which enables them to have genuine expectations and thus perhaps an emotion a bit like human hope. But if they do have this, it is in virtue of having something like human reason. As it stands, it seems quite clear that Aquinas' account does not justify saying that non-rational creatures have hope. For hope is not a pattern of behavioral response to sense-impressions, but an intentional state with a logic something like that which Aquinas ascribes to it in lala:: 40, 1. And that is a state which, "intrinsically considered," is intrinsically (basically) rational. (294; emphasis added) 7 See STh I-II, q. 22. HUMAN AND ANIMAL EMOTION 49 to and urged by it. With respect to the animal lacking reason, Aquinas argues that the assessment of the sensible thing as suitable or unsuitable for it, as well as its actions to obtain or resist it, is a matter of instinct, something guided wholly by its nature, with no deliberation or choice on its part. The events on either side of the necessary movement of its sensitive appetite are thus also of an immediate and necessary nature. 8 However, human beings do not have this same degree of immediacy and necessity with respect to these cognitive precedents and those actions urged by the emotion aroused. The former and the latter are permeated by, and consequently come under the influence of, the reason and will of the human being. It is this very fact that prevents the total determinism observed with respect to animal assessment prior to the emotions, as well as that activity consequent to them, from occurring in the human being. 9 8 See SI'h I-II, q. 13, a. 2, c. and ad 2; I-II, q. 15, a. 2, ad 1; I-II, q. 16, a. 2; and I-II, q. 17, a. 2, c. and ad 3. 9 See the articles concerning culpability and the sensitive appetite at SI'h I-II, q. 77, as well as the questions concerning the voluntary and the sensitive appetite at SI'h I-II, qq. 9-10. See also STh 1, q. 81, a. 3; and De Verit., q. 22, a. 4. The degree to which the human being experiences instinctual assessment prior to, and activity consequent upon, the movement of the sensitive appetite itself is a complex matter warranting a separate discussion. In lieu of such, note that in the human being, the cogitative power and its operations are, for the most part, indeterminate, a situation contrary to the estimative power in animals lacking reason. Although the animals lacking reason are said to pass judgment upon the suitability or unsuitability of a sensible thing by virtue of their estimative sense, nevertheless this judgment is not a free one; it is determined by the animal's nature, so that upon the presentation of a sensible thing the assessment that follows is natural, automatic, and not subject to any important variation (see the texts cited in n. 8). G. Klubertanz (The Philosophyof Human Nature (New York: Appleton-Century-Croft, 1953), 134-39) describes this well. He characterizes animal activity as exhibiting a uniformity within its species, a certain specificitywith respect to each species, and a relativeindependencefrom learning or experience. Thus all members of a species perform their activities in much the same way, all species have activities that are proper to each of them and serve to distinguish them as such from each other, and all the activities that go into a specific behavior are often performed immediately without some period of learning or experience. This behavior depends directly upon the guidance offered by the estimative sense, which, when presented with various objects and situations, makes the appropriate assessment of them and sets the behavior of the animal with respect to them. Thus, the estimative sense is specifically determined in its assessment abilities, and this, in accordance with the nature of the animal, as this determination provides for the continued existence of the animal and the preservation of its own life and that of its species. 50 STEPHEN LOUGHLIN Clearly, the influence of the rational powers on the sensitive appetite makes a significant difference to the phenomenon of emotion itself. It should be noted that Aquinas's concept of emotion is quite broad when applied to the human being; although said primarily of his sensitive appetite, it is nevertheless not restricted solely to this aspect of his nature. This is quite clear in Thomas's extension of the language of emotion to encompass the movements or realizations of the rational appetite, the will. 10 With respect to human beings, one must be careful in the ascription of this kind of determinacy. First, there is an aspect of human activity that is determined, namely, the operations of the soul's powers, as they are specified by their respective forms in the manner in which they operate. In this sense, they do not vary; the eye sees, the ear hears, the will desires good universally, and likewise with respect to the other powers and their natural operations, as these are determined by the first actus, the soul, itself. However, when one considers that kind of determined instinctual activity proper to the animals lacking reason, one finds that its quality and extent is much different in human beings. Instead of the uniformity, specificity, and relative independence from learning that characterize animal instinctual behavior, this in human beings is characterized, states Klubertanz, by indeterminacy,complexity, and variabilityand is essentiallyconnectedwith experienceand reason. If we were to seek out in human beings that kind of instinctual behavior which is characteristic of the animals lacking reason, Klubertanz argues that we would find this only in the child. However, even this is quite different from what is observed in the animals lacking reason, in that the behaviors of the former are vague or indeterminate: the fear exhibited at sudden or loud noises, or at heights, and the rage or anger displayed when restrained (crying, shrinking back, the flailing of arms, legs, and body) are all quite far from the very specific, involved instinctual behavior displayed by animals lacking reason (see ibid., 142-45). These cannot be compared, for example, to the instincts of, or the estimations required for, nest building or mating rituals, which exhibit the characteristics of complexity, regularity, and independence from experience and learning. For these natural actions and reactions in the human being to amount to anything definite and important, the guiding powers of the rational aspect must be developed, knowledge acquired, habits established, and all of these over time, through guided study and experience itself. The point here, then, is that while human activity exhibits a certain amount of determinateness, that is, with respect both to the nature of the activities that characterize the powers themselves according to their respective forms or natures, and to some general behaviors natural to the human being, nevertheless, there is not present in human beings the same kind or quality of determination of assessment and consequent activity as is found in the animals lacking reason. Consequently, both the assessment prior to an emotion and the activity urged upon one subsequent to an emotion are not importantly instinctual, but require determination by the formation received from the reason and will of others (rearing, society, schooling, religion, friends, etc.) and by one's own reason and will. Until this occurs, all that is present is the natural inclinations consequent upon the forms or natures of these powers as made possible by the soul itself. 10 See STh 1-11, q. 22, a. 3, ad 3. HUMAN AND ANIMAL EMOTION 51 On the face of it, one could say that this extension arises from the need for an explanation for Holy Scripture's attribution of the emotions to God, the angels, and the dead. However, it is more likely that Aquinas extends language properly denoting a sensitive phenomenon to intellectual phenomena for two reasons: (1) emotion is appetitive in nature and (2) the fullness of any activity of the soul is best understood in reference to the whole being in which it occurs. Consequently, although emotion is primarily of the sensitive appetite, nevertheless, with respect to its nature as appetitive, this phenomenon can be extended to the other appetitive aspects of the person, namely, the natural and, more importantly, the rational. When these facts are viewed in light of the unity of the person's nature, the experience of emotion is broadened extensively, not only by the appearance of its rational kinds, but also by their intermingling with the sensitive and natural kinds. The emotions attributable to, or having their genesis in, the rational appetite are described by Thomas as they show a likeness to a central characteristic of sensitive emotion, namely, the approach to and withdrawal from the conveniens and inconveniens respectively. 11 In this regard, he assigns names either identical to their counterparts in the sensitive appetite or particular to them. Examples of the latter include dilectio, gaudium, and tristitia. Dilectio is distinguished from the general sensitive sense of amor as the former adds the notion of an electio made beforehand, something of which only a rational nature is capable. 12 Gaudium is that specific form of delectatio which follows from the attainment of something that is desired on account of reason, and is recognized and known by it when present. 13 And finally tristitia, as it is the contrary of gaudium and as it is the result of an interior apprehension of the intellect, is experienced only by the rational 11 See SI'h I, q. 20, a. 1, ad 1; I, q. 59, a. 4, ad 2; I, q. 64, a. 3; I, q. 82, a. 5, ad 1; I-II, q. 22, a. 3, ad 3; II-II, q. 18, a. 1; De Verit., q. 25, a. 3; q. 26, a. 3, ad 3 and 7; q. 26, a. 7, ad 5; and ScG I, qq. 89-91. Marcel Sarot, in "God, Emotion and Corporeality: A Thomist Perspective," The Thomist 58 (1994): 61-92 discusses several of these texts. See also Daniel Westberg, "Emotion and God: A Reply to Marcel Sarot," The Thomist 60 (1996): 109-21. 12 See SI'h I-II, q. 26, a. 3; see also the response to the sed contra of the same question. 13 See STh I-II, q. 31, a. 3. 52 STEPHEN LOUGHLIN being. 14 The main difference between these intellectual emotions and their sensitive counterparts (besides the lack of a transmutatio corpora/is, something not required for an operation of the rational appetite, but vital to the operation of the sensitive appetite) is that their respective objects are distinct. The lower can only regard the sensible object as it comes under the notion of the conveniens or the inconveniens, as a particular instance of suitability or unsuitability, while the higher can regard this, as well as a more universal good or evil, but both with respect to the very reasons for the appetibility of something. 15 Now, emotions of this kind clearly belong only to rational beings. Can it thus be said that the irascible emotions are also specific to the human being, since these emotions demonstrate a heavy dependence upon rational powers and operations? Take, for example, the emotion of hope, which by definition is of a future arduous possible good. Only a rational nature can consider matters of time, contingency, and truth and falsity, all of which are implied in hope's definition. 16 And yet Aquinas holds that the animal lacking reason experiences hope. He argues, first, as before, that the animal experiences hope as a consequence of its possession of a sensitive appetite, which power, for Aquinas, constitutes the "seat" of the emotions. 17 Second, he refers to a seemingly common empirical observation to support his first point, namely, that the nearness or farness of prey makes a difference to the dog's or eagle's pursuit. This demonstrates for him the occurrence of the emotions of hope and despair in the animal lacking reason, on the principle that external behavior is the means whereby one discerns the existence and operation of internal phenomena and the powers responsible for them. 18 See STh I-II, q. 35, a. 2, c., ad 2, and ad 3. Aquinas recognizes, but does not discuss at great length, the various interminglings of sensitive and intellectual emotions. The same is said with respect to the effect (he calls it an "overflowing") that the intellectual emotions can have upon both the sensitive emotions and a person's physiology. 16 See note 5 above. 17 See STh I-II, q. 22. 18 This principle highlights an important aspect of Aquinas's psychology, namely, that when the various powers of the soul are discussed, one must be careful not to understand or interpret these as 'faculties' in the pejorative sense of the term. A power of the soul is not that 14 15 HUMAN AND ANIMAL EMOTION 53 Nevertheless, Aquinas is acutely aware of the rational requirements involved in this emotion, as the three objections to STh 1-11, q. 40, a. 3 demonstrate. He states that animal hope does indeed follow from the "apprehension of an intellect," but one that is separate,so to speak, from the animal, namely, that which belongs to the Author of the animal's being, who has established the animal's nature so that it might act specifically and immediately in this fashion. Consequently, the judgment required for the emotion of hope has, in a sense, already been made according to the mind of the Creator of the animal's nature, as the instinctual behaviors of the animal represent the judgments of God in the determination of its nature. It is by reason of this determination that the animal is able to make the assessments required for the arousal of hope or despair, and exhibit that activity which follows upon it, but only in the presence of the appropriate sensible external factors. 19 The human being, on the other hand, has this judgment within his control because of his rational powers whereby this apprehension and determination of a future arduous possible good can be effected through his own efforts, in addition to that which is made possible by the natural determination of his sensitive appetite. In a word, the difference here is between being determined and being capable of determining. 20 which acts, but that by which the person acts, a potency rooted in the very essence of the soul. The principle of discovery is operatio sequitur esse, from activity, to power, to the soul itself, wherein power is ultimately defined as a proximate principle by which the person performs an activity: cf. STh l, q. 77; F. Copleston,Aquinas (London: Penguin, 1955), 163££.; and Klubertanz, The Philosophy of Human Nature, 86££. 19 See STh l, q. 83, a. 1; 1-11, q. 11, a. 2; I-II, q. 15, a. 2; and esp. I-II, q. 17, a. 2, ad 3; and I-II, q. 46, a. 4, ad 2. It is by reason of this divine determination that a certain practical wisdom or prudence is attributed to the animal lacking reason {see STh I-II, q. 13, a. 2, ad 3). See also Robert E. Brennan, Thomistic Psychology:A PhilosophicalAnalysis of the Nature of Man (New York: MacMillan, 1941), 131-33. 20 See STh I-II, q. 40, a. 3: interiores passiones animalium ex exterioribus motibus deprehendi possunt. Ex quibus apparet quod in animalibus brutis est spes. Si enim canis videat leporem, aut accipiter avem, nimis distantem, non movetur ad ipsam, quasi non sperans se earn posse adipisci: si autem sit in propinquo, movetur, quasi sub spe adipiscendi. Ut enim supra dictum 54 STEPHEN LOUGHLIN Although Aquinas does not explicitly address the irascible emotions of fear and daring, he does extend this argument to the experience of anger in the animal lacking reason. 21 On the basis of these three applications, it seems reasonable to suppose that this kind of argument would also apply to fear and daring, and, consequently, that the irascible emotions are not specific to human beings, but are also experienced by the animals lacking reason. Therefore, animals experience all eleven emotions. II This having been argued, the question of quality remains: to what degree is the experience of these eleven emotions in the animal lacking reason the same as in the human being? We will begin by examining the natural movement to which the sensitive appetite is subject. In general terms, appetitus denotes an inclination that arises from form. Three inclinations are thus distinguished, namely, that which follows upon the very form or nature of a thing or power (natural appetite), and those which follow upon the reception of a sensitive or intellectual form by the sensitive and intellectual powers respectively (sensitive and intellectual appetite). Aquinas est [STh I-II, q. 1, a. 2; I-II, q. 26, a. l; I-II, q. 35, a. l], appetitus sensitivus brutorum animalium, et etiam appetitus naturalis rerum insensibilium, sequuntur apprehensionem alicuius intellectus, sicut et appetitus naturae intellectivae, qui dicitur voluntas. Sed in hoc est differentia, quod voluntas movetur ex apprehensione intellectus coniuncti: sed motus appetitus naturalis sequitur apprehensionem intellectus separati, qui naturam instituit; et similiter appetitus sensitivus brutorum animalium, quae etiam quodam instinctu naturali agunt. Uncle in operibus brutorum animalium, et aliarum rerum naturalium, apparet similis processus sicut et in operibus artis. Et per hunc modum in animalibus brutis et spes et desperatio. Thus, with respect to the matters of time, contingency, and truth and falsity, Aquinas answers (at ad 1) in the context of the determination of instinct: "quamvis bruta animalia non cognoscant futurum, tamen ex instinctu naturali movetur animal ad aliquid in futurum, ac si futurum praevideret. Huiusmodi enim instinctus est eis inditus ab intellectu divino praevidente futura." See also III Sent., d. 26, q. 1, a. 1, c. and ad 4. 21 See STh I-II, q. 46, a. 7, ad 1. HUMAN AND ANIMAL EMOTION 55 discusses this distinction specifically in reference to the emotions at STh 1-11, q. 41, a. 3, an article that deals with the question whether there is such an emotion as natural fear. An inclination or movement is said to be natural as nature so inclines, and this occurs in two ways. First, as this movement is entirely accomplished by nature without any operation of an apprehensive power, or second, as this movement, to which nature inclines, is accomplished only by means of an apprehensive operation. Examples of the former are the upward movements natural to fire and the growth of animals and plants, while the latter includes the very operations of the apprehensive and appetitive powers, as these are considered in themselves according to their natures. 22 In the latter sense, natural emotions do occur. Aquinas thus describes natural fear as that which is of a corruptive evil, wherein one's nature shrinks naturally, or rather instinctively, from something on account of one's natural desire to exist. This is to be distingui!>:1edfrom nonnatural fear which arises as it concerns an evil repugnant, not to one's nature, but rather to some desire of the appetite that goes beyond the appetite's basic or natural determination. This is the basis upon which love, desire, and delight are divided into natural and nonnatural emotions. 23 In the 22 STh 1-11, q. 41, a. 3: aliquis motus dicitur naturalis, quia ad ipsum inclinat natura. Sed hoc contingit dupliciter. Uno modo, quod totum perficitur anatura, absque aliqua operatione apprehensivae virtutis: sicut moveri sursum estmotus naturalis ignis, et augeri est motus. naturalis animalium et plantarum. Alio modo dicitur motus naturalis, ad quern natura inclinat, licet non perficiatur nisi per apprehensionem: quia, sicut supra dictum est, motus cognitivae et appetitivae virtutis reducuntur in naturam, sicut in principium primum. Et per hunc modum, etiam ipsi actus apprehensivae virtutis, ut intelligere, sentire et memorari, et etiam motus appetitus animalis, quandoque dicuntur naturales. The internal references are to STh 1-11, q. 10, a. 1; and 1-11, q. 17, a. 9, ad 2. 23 See STh 1-11, q. 26, a. 1; 1-11, q. 30, a. 3; and 1-Il, q. 31, a. 7. STh 1-11, q. 30, a. 3 states that desires common to man and beast are akin to that of natural fear. Things suitable to nature and thus desired are food and drink, while human beings alone have the ability (rational) to determine suitability for themselves beyond the basic requirements of nature. "Natural" and "nonnatural" give way to "irrational" and "rational," following Aristotle at 56 STEPHEN LOUGHLIN first sense of natural, however, only some of the emotions can be called natural, like love, desire, and hope, while the rest cannot. The reason is that the ones just mentioned include a certain inclination to pursue what is good or to avoid what is evil, which inclination belongs even to the natural appetite. Consequently, there is a natural love, and even desire and hope can be spoken of as being in natural things lacking knowledge to a certain extent. However, the other emotions of the soul include certain movements concerning which the natural inclination is not sufficient. This is due either to the fact that perception or knowledge is essential to these emotions; thus it has been said [STh 1-11, q. 31, aa. 1 and 3; I-II, q. 35, a. 1] that apprehension is required by the very nature of delight and sorrow, wherefore things devoid of knowledge cannot be said to take delight or to be sorrowful: or else it is because such like movements are contrary to the very nature of natural inclination-for instance, despair flies from good on account of some difficulty, and fear shrinks from repelling a contrary evil, both of which are contrary to natural inclination. Therefore these emotions are in no way attributed to inanimate beings.24 Rhetoric 1.11, or again to "common/necessary" and "peculiar/acquired." STh I-II, q. 30, a. 3, ad 2 states that the irrational or natural emotions come about by an absolute apprehension of the suitability or nonsuitability of something, while the rational or nonnatural emotions occur by apprehension together with some sort of deliberation. SI'h I-II, q. 31, a. 7 adds to the objects of the natural emotions: food and drink, rest and all other things which act to preserve the body, and sexual intercourse and whatever naturally promotes the preservation of the species. 24 STh 1-11, q. 41, a. 3: Et per hunc modum potest dici timor naturalis. Et distinguitur a timore non naturali, secundum diversitatem obiecti. Est enim, ut Philosophus dicit in II Rhetorica (5. 1382a22), timor de malo corruptivo, quod natura refugit propter naturale desiderium essendi: et talis timor dicitur naturalis. Est iterum de malo contristativo, quod non repugnat naturae, sed desiderio appetitus: et talis timor non est naturalis. Sicut etiam supra (I-II, q. 26. 1, 30. 3, et 31. 7) amor, concupiscentia et delectatio distincta sunt per naturale et non naturale. Sed secundum primam acceptionem naturalis, sciendum est quod quaedam de passionibus animae quandoque dicuntur naturales, ut amor, desiderium et spes: aliae vero naturales dici non possunt. Et hoc ideo, quia amor et odium, desiderium et fuga, important inclinationem quandam prosequendum bonum et fugiendum malum; quae quidem inclinatio pertinet etiam ad appetitum naturalem. Et ideo est amor quidam naturalis: et desiderium vel spes potest quodammodo dici etiam in rebus naturalibus cognitione carentibus. Sed aliae passiones animae important quosdam motus ad quos nullo modo sufficit inclinatio naturalis. Ve! quia de ratione harum HUMAN AND ANIMAL EMOTION 57 The natural emotions in the first sense of "natural" are not of any great concern in Aquinas's discussion of the eleven emotions in the Summa Theologiae. Instead, his discussion there concerns both the natural emotions in the second sense of "natural" and especially the nonnatural emotions. With respect, then, to our question concerning quality, it seems clear from the preceding that the natural passions in the second sense of "natural" are the same in both human and animal. This encompasses all eleven of the emotions, which describe, as it were, the "architecture" of the sensitive appetite, and thus constitute a more detailed definition of it as possessed by animal and human alike. What, then, of the nonnatural emotions? Note first that with respect to the human being, "the same thing which is desired by the natural appetite, can be desired by the animal appetite, once it is apprehended. And in this way there may be an animal appetite for food, drink and the like, which are desired by the natural appetite. "25 This describes what has been called a "reduplication "26 of the natural emotions according to the second sense of "natural" in the nonnatural emotions, a situation peculiar to the human being thanks to the rational powers by which he can have a nonnatural emotion for objects that elicit the natural emotions. In this respect, then, although the human is determined by his nature to desire food instinctively, this object can become the object of a nonnatural desire, and this in a passionum est sensus seu cognitio, sicut dictum est (I-II, q. 31. 1et3, 35. 1) quod apprehensiorequiritur ad rationem delectationiset doloris: unde quae carent cognitione, non possunt dici delectari vel dolere. Aut quia huiusmodi motus sunt contra rationem inclinationis naturalis: puta quod desperatio refugit bonum propter aliquam difficultatem; et timor refugit impugnationem mali contrarii, ad quod est inclinatio naturalis. Et ideo huiusmodi passiones mullo modo attribuuntur rebus inanimatis. 2-l SI'h I-II, q. 30, a. 3, ad 1: "illud idem quod appetitur appetitu naturali, potest appeti appetitu animali cum fuerit apprehensum. Et secundum hoc cibi et potus et huiusmodi, quae appetuntur naturaliter, potest esse concupiscentia naturalis." 26 For this language of "reduplication," cf. j. Maritain, A Preface to Metaphysics (New York: Sheed and Ward, 1939), 71; and Richard R. Baker, The Thomistic Theory of the Emotions and Their Infl,uence upon the Will (Ph.D. diss., University of Notre Dame, 1941), 15-16, 35. 58 STEPHEN LOUGHLIN qualitatively and quantitatively different way, particularly as the nonnatural desire refines the basic instinctual urge, going beyond the general or indeterminant requirements of nature. 27 And yet, these reduplicated emotions in themselves still appear to be the same as those natural ones experienced by the animals lacking reason, the difference being that of motive and determining forces. What, then, of those nonnatural emotions which in themselves concern sensible things beyond the basic requirements of nature, particularly those which are sought for the sake of human happiness? It seems that the difference between this kind of emotion and those experienced by the animal lacking reason (besides motive and determining forces) lies precisely with the object with which the emotion is concerned rather than with the emotion itself. Although a person can have a love and a desire for money and the animal cannot, it still remains the case that the movement of the appetite itself, apart from the object to which it tends, is the same in person and animal. Nevertheless, nonnatural emotions, considered as a whole (i.e., as they include references to their objects and rational causes), are quite beyond the experience of the animal. In the end, the only clear distinction to be noted between human and animal emotion is with respect to those which constitute the movements of the rational appetite. 28 27 Thus, one is naturally determined to desire food, but can develop a passion for a specific kind or quality or amount of food. For the language of indeterminacy as they apply to this point, see note 9 above. 28 This division of the emotions into their natural and nonnatural kinds also accounts for the way in which Thomas occasionally speaks as if the simple presentation of some sensible thing is sufficient of itself to give rise to an emotion. At the very least, with respect to the natural emotions in the second sense of "natural," this highlights the natural workings of the cogitative power, as it judges those things which are suitable or not to those most basic goods of the individual. At most, we see the latter combined with the habits one would develop with respect to these most basic goods over time and experience, as well as one's memory of prior evaluations. Except in the child, the natural passions (in the second sense of natural) are rarely encountered in their pure form, since the nature of the human being requires that these be transformed into nonnatural passions if one is to live and grow in one's humanity. Finally, although Aquinas states that imagination can supply the sensitive appetite with its proper object, this occurs, as noted above in note 4, through the cogitative, or through the memory of a prior evaluation. HUMAN AND ANIMAL EMOTION 59 In summary, although the animal does not possess the rational powers by which it can make the assessments required for the arousal of the irascible emotions, it still experiences these as it is so constituted in its nature to regard matters of the future, the contingent, and the true and the false, in an instinctual manner. This determination of its nature represents the judgments of its Creator, without which it could not experience the irascible emotions and perform in accordance with them. The rational requirements of the irascible emotions are thus recognized and accounted for. All eleven movements of the sensitive appetitive power are shared by human and animal alike, as these constitute the natural movements of the sensitive appetite, those which follow upon its form or nature, indicative, as it were, of the appetite's structure or "architecture." III The differences between animal and human emotion deal not so much with the basic movement of the sensitive appetite itself, but rather with the cognitive precedents to emotion, and the subsequent actions urged by them. Important differences thus arise when one's focus is broadened to include the being that experiences the emotions by means of its sensitive appetite. In this respect, there are four differences to be observed between animal and human emotion. First, the objects with which human emotions deal are of greater quantity and quality than those available to the animal lacking reason. This is due to man's rational nature which broadens his experience of the emotions to include their reduplicated and nonrational kinds. Second, the human being, again because of his rationality, experiences those emotions which denote the various movements of the intellectual appetite. Third, because of the unity of the human being, natural, nonnatural, and rational emotions are experienced together in varying degrees and mixtures, thus offering to human beings a richer experience of the emotions than that available to the animal lacking reason. And fourth, since the emotions of the sensitive aspect come under the influence of the rational aspect, 60 STEPHEN LOUGHLIN they do not determine a human's activity, as they do with respect to the animal lacking reason. As such, they become the matter of the moral sciences, as they play an important role in that proper human activity by which the human being attains his perfect good and end. 29 The main argument against the attribution of the emotions to the irrational animals derives from the fact that they do not possess the rational powers by which they can fully understand a situation and make those judgments necessary for the arousal of emotion; only human beings, who possess such powers, are capable of making such judgments. Given how integral the judgment of reason is to the emotions, and furthermore that the nature of the latter is thus guided and even permeated by the former, it is not unreasonable to see emotion not so much as a sensitive appetitive event but rather as more of a rational one. Does this mean that Aquinas was mistaken in his identification of the "seat" of the emotions in the sensitive appetite? I do not think so. Consider, first, one of the assumptions of this view, namely that the notion of judgment be restricted to the rational powers. Aquinas's understanding of iudicium, or judgment, is much broader than this, extending to sensitive and even natural operations, without becoming an equivocal notion. Thomas 29 This constitutes the main reason why Aquinas postponed the psychological treatment of the emotions from the Prima pars to what he considered to be its more appropriate place, namely, the Prima secundae, which deals with general moral principles and theory. As the emotions can be considered with respect to the controlling and guiding influence of reason and will, they become one of the intrinsic principles of proper human activity (the other being habitus; see SI'h 1-11, q. 6, pro!.; and 1-11, q. 49, pro!.); considered in themselves and apart from this context, the emotions are that activity common to the animal lacking reason and the human being (SI'h 1-11, q. 6, pro!.; and SI'h 1-11, q. 24, a. 1). As they constitute a proper human activity, the emotions must be ordered, along with the other operations of the human being, to the attainment of his highest good and perfection, namely, happiness or beatitude (SI'h 1-11, qq. 1-5). In this context, the emotions become the material of habits, specifically in the virtues and vices, where habitus constitutes the principium appetitivi motus, a determining principle of the appetitive movement (SI'h 1-11, q. 59, a. 1) by which human beings are directed well or badly in reference to the passions (SI'h 1-11, q. 49, a. 2). As the animals lacking reason are determined fully in their activities with respect to their perfect end, this aspect of the emotions is something outside their nature (SI'h 1-11, q. 24). HUMAN AND ANIMAL EMOTION 61 understands judgment as "a correct [right, accurate-rectal determination in any field. " 30 This "correct determination" is represented in two ways. First, it can be taken "actively and elicitively, and in this sense belongs to reason or intellect alone," or it can be taken as "the disposition according to which the one making the judgment is apt to judge correctly." 31 In this latter respect, "disposition" is taken to include not only that which is acquired, namely, the habits, and specifically the virtues and vices, but also that which is natural to the form or nature of a thing or power, whence flows its natural activity. Thus, judgment may be attributed to an activity of the rational powers, to the virtue of justice as it disposes one to judge correctly, to the other habits as they judge rightly concerning their proper objects and operations, and finally to the powers of the soul as these, in their natural operations, judge accurately concerning their proper objects. So, for example, a sheep, in the presence of the wolf, judges it to be a threat to its well-being, and thus its enemy. This judgment "proceeds from an inborn disposition of [the] determinate impulse [instinctus]" 32 of its estimative power which gives rise to the experience of the irascible emotion of fear. With respect, then, to the natural emotions in the second sense of "natural," suitability and unsuitability are determined by the judgment effected by the nature of the estimative (or cogitative) power, in accordance with the being's nature, as it has been so determined by its Author. 33 With respect to the nonnatural emotions, it is the 30 See STh 11-11, q. 60, a. 1, obj. 1, c., and ad 1, and an extensive discussion concerning iudicium in George P. Klubertanz, S.J., The DiscursivePower: Sourcesand Doctrineof the Vis Cogitativaaccordingto St. Thomas Aquinas(St. Louis: St. Louis University Press, 1952), 235. 31 Klubertanz, The DiscursivePower, 235. 32 Ibid. This extended meaning of judgment, according to Klubertanz, "is confirmed by what St. Thomas has to say about the iudicium sensus. The proper sense judges its proper sensible, in that it accurately knows and can discern one of its proper sensibles from another. This does not mean that the eye, for example, institutes a formal comparison between its various objects, nor that it knows what color is. It means only that the eye determinately and accurately knows a particular sensible appearance" (ibid., 235-36). He quotes STh I, q. 78, a. 4, ad 2 in support of his point. 33 In this respect, the criticism leveled against Aquinas by R. Roberts (see note 6, above) would seem also to apply to the very nature of any of the powers of the human soul, namely, that the power's natural descriptions and operations are nothing more than a pattern of 62 STEPHEN LOUGHLIN person, rather than his powers or nature, that judges or determines the suitability or unsuitability of a thing, specifically in relation to that which he considers as good or evil for himself. This, as we saw, includes the objects of the natural appetite (the "reduplication" of this appetite on a higher level), but more importantly goes beyond these to encompass other things, specifically those which are required for a person's happiness. With this broad understanding of iudicium, the basic conditions are fulfilled for the occurrence of even the irascible emotions in an animal lacking reason; an "accurate determination," or judgment, is performed by a specific power (the estimative) upon an intentionally received sensible thing, which judgment determines whether the thing is suitable or not to the animal as such, which subsequently supplies the sensitive appetite with its proper object, thus eliciting the appropriate emotion. It should be clear, in light of the preceding discussion, that this experience of the irascible emotions differs significantly from that of the human being. Take the experience of hope. First of all, the animal is not truly free to perform the judgment required for such an emotion; this has been determined for it beforehand by its Creator. Nor does it possess the rational ability to grasp fully the concepts necessary for freely considered choice; the animal is purely a being of the moment. Nor is there the "coloring," so to speak, of the sensitive emotion by those experienced through the intellectual appetite, a complexity available only to the human being. Consequently, the animal's overall experience of hope is behavioral or instinctual (automatic) responses to their respective objects. I doubt, however, that Roberts would want to extend this conclusion to every potentiality of the soul. The nature of the powers of the soul is determined by the kind of soul that exhibits these, as this soul has been determined to exhibit such by reason of its Author's decision and activity; the nature of the human soul precedes, in the mind of God, its actualization in this or that specific instance. Thus, just as the determination of the animal's estimative power by the Author of its being accounts for both its experience of the emotions and the rational requirements of the irascible emotions, so too does the determination of human nature by the Creator account for those activities peculiar to the human being himself, namely, discursive thought and free choice. To deny the former explanation is also to deny the latter. Thus, Thomas is well justified in his extension of the emotions to the animal lacking reason, not to mention his identification of the emotions with the various actualizations of the sensitive appetite. HUMAN AND ANIMAL EMOTION 63 not the fullness of hope of which the rational animal is capable; the animal is clearly not able to experience all that characterizes the emotions in their nonnatural forms. Nevertheless, the emotion that it does experience is not thus to be reduced to the status of an equivocal. As argued above, humans and animals share a common experience of the emotions, namely, as appetitive movements consequent upon the judgment of the suitability or unsuitability of an object for the one possessing appetite. More importantly, however, is Aquinas's manner of discussing the irascible passions. For example, with respect to hope, he does not strictly define it according to the fullness of its occurrence in the rational being. Nor does he assume that the human experience of hope constitutes the phenomenon's most basic or primitive description. Hope, like judgment, is a broadly defined phenomenon that includeswhat Roberts calls "a pattern of behavioral response to sense-impressions," namely, the automatic, instinctive movement of the sensitive appetite towards some future obtainable arduous good, but only as this movement embodies "an intentional state with a logic," namely, the judgment of God as expressed in the determination of the animal's nature which renders it capable of the basic interpretation in question, and the subsequent movement of the sensitive appetite. Accordingly, hope (as well as the other irascible emotions) experienced by the animal lacking reason is the most basic or primitive form of this phenomenon, and is related analogously 34 to the fullness and richness of hope in the human being. This determination of the animal's nature by God is the basis not only for the experience of the emotions by the animal, but also for the specificity and uniformity of animal behavior in general, as well 34 Emotion's most generic description is that of an appetitive movement consequent upon some sort of judgment of a thing as being good or evil for the one possessing appetite. It is only when one defines the kind of appetite and judgment involved in emotions (that is, natural, sensitive, or intellectual), and this with respect to the being in which they are found, that one arrives at specific definitions of emotion. Since this generic description is found intrinsically in a definite way and degree in both animals and humans, the kind of analogy at work here in emotion is that of proper proportionality. It is only in the restriction of the phenomena of appetite and judgment to the human or rational being that emotion becomes an equivocal or metaphorical term. 64 STEPHEN LOUGHLIN as its independence from learning and experience. 35 For the principle at work here is simply that an inclination follows upon every form. As the essence depends upon and reflects the mind of that which has fashioned it, so too do the essence of the animal, and all the activity that derives from it, depend upon and exhibit the rationality and judgments of its Creator. This, for Aquinas, is a solid basis for the attribution of the irascible emotions, in their most basic forms, to the animals lacking reason. It seems, then, that the essence of the distinction between the emotions experienced by both human beings and animals lies in a consideration of the nature of the being that experiences them. If our view is restricted to the movements of the sensitive appetite as such, the sensitive emotions experienced by the animal lacking reason and the human being do not differ qualitatively; they are shared in common by both. But when we view these movements in the context of their respective beings, their quality in the human being is transformed by their presence to the rational powers. Nevertheless, these sensitive emotions do not lose their basic or primitive characteristics; their transformation is an accidental, not a substantial, one. The emotions still describe the very essence of the sensitive appetite in its various relations to the external sensible thing, present to it under the interpretation of suitability or unsuitability. Thus animal and human emotions do not become equivocals, but remain analogously related to each other. That this accurately represents Aquinas's position can be seen with respect to another power of the sensitive soul that is accidentally transformed by its presence to the rational powers, namely, memory. The memorative power in the animal lacking reason becomes the power of reminiscence in the human being as it is guided by and partakes in reason, remaining all the while a memorative power in essence, but one whose operations are qualitatively affected to such an extent that they are now beyond 35 See note 9 above. HUMAN AND ANIMAL EMOTION 65 those of which the animal lacking reason is capable, particularly the syllogistic manner in which one is able to recall things past. 36 Just as Aquinas does not say that the animal is incapable of memory simply because it is unable to attain to the perfection of its operation in the human being, so too does he not say that the animal is incapable of the emotions in their most basic or primitive form because they do not attain to their perfect expression as displayed in their nonnatural forms in the human being. In the rational being, the powers operate naturally as they do in the animal lacking reason, that is, as these follow upon their form. However, in view of the whole being, these function within a rational soul, and, consequently, are heavily influenced, directed, helped, and even transformed in their own operations to the extent that the rational being determines. 37 At bottom, this transformation of the emotions reflects a development natural to a psychology that is not dualistic, but rather hylomorphic. 36 See Aristotle's De memoria et reminiscentia,and Aquinas's commentary on it. For the extent to which memory's presence to reason actually transforms memory's very operation, see the interpretative essays in Richard Sorabji's translation of Aristotle's On Memory (Providence: Brown University Press, 1972), as well as Francis A. Yates, The Art of Memory (London: Pimlico, 1966, 1992); and Mary Carruthers, The Book of Memory: A Study of Memory in MedievalCulture (London: Cambridge University Press, 1990). The last work has the virtue of illustrating medieval views on memory in the rational being by means of recent studies concerning the capacities of memory when assisted by the rational powers; see the particularly remarkable study on pp. 75-79. 37 Cf. STh 1-11, q. 74, a. 3, ad 1. The Thomist 65 (2001): 67-92 GOD AND KANT'S ETHICAL COMMONWEALTH GORDON E. MICHALSON, JR. New Collegeof the Universityof South Florida Sarasota, Florida A t one point in his recent history of modern moral philosophy, J.B. Schneewind refers to Immanuel Kant's "astonishing claim" that "God and we can share membership in a single moral community only if we all equally legislate the law we are to obey. " 1 Schneewind's remark is intended to illuminate his wider story about what he calls the Kantian "invention" of autonomy. In Schneewind's telling of this story, Kant's claim is "astonishing" because of the clear suggestion that autonomy has replaced obedience as the basis of the moral life, a transition that marks a decisive moment in the secularization of ethics in the modern period. Considered theologically, however, Schneewind's remark is simultaneously suggestive of a fundamental alteration of the traditional view of divine transcendence, an alteration implicit in the modern effort to ground morality in something other than the will of God. The vision of a moral community in which God and finite moral agents equally legislate the law probably implies that God is subject to a moral principle that can be understood apart from reference to the divine will alone. The leveling process at work in the notion of a "shared membership" in the moral community is at the same time an erosion of the distance separating heaven and earth, the transcendent and the immanent. This subterranean linkage between Kant's ideal moral community and an implicit 1 J.B. Schneewind, The Invention of Autonomy: A History of Modem Moral Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 512. 67 68 GORDON E. MICHALSON, JR. loss of divine transcendence is in fact one of the most powerful and least understood aspects of Kant's philosophy. The moral community in question is what Kant will ultimately refer to as the "ethical commonwealth," which is the refined version of what he had earlier referred to in the Founda.tionsof the Metaphysicsof Morals as the "kingdom of ends. "2 Kant defines the ethical commonwealth as a union of rational agents living under moral laws, which is to say, "laws of virtue." 3 As the contrast case to a political or what Kant calls a "juridico-civil state," the ethical commonwealth depends upon self-legislation rather than on external coercion for its maintenance and regulation. The point of the distinction is amply conveyed by Kant's admonition to all who would attempt to legislate morality: "But woe to the legislator who wishes to establish through force a polity directed to ethical ends," as it "would be a contradiction," Kant warns, "for the political commonwealth to compel its citizens to enter into an ethical commonwealth, since the very concept of the latter involves freedom from coercion. "4 The main reason Kant's position holds such theological interest is that his notion of "freedom from coercion" includes freedom from any conception of a divine will that is not itself subject to the same legislative principle that governs all members of the ethical commonwealth. What Schneewind refers to as Kant's "astonishing claim" is in fact Kant's effort to envision a kind of moral partnership between God and humanity, a project that leaves traditional conceptions of divine transcendence in a complex transitional zone. My aim in what follows is to examine further the nature of the divine-human partnership involved in Kant's conception of the ethical commonwealth, with a view to clarifying the status of divine transcendence within his position. A primary textual clue for this clarification will be a series of important shifts in Kant's 2 Immanuel Kant, Foundationsof the Metaphysicsof Morals, trans. Lewis White Beck (Indianapolis and New York: Bobbs-Merrill, 1959), 55. Hereafter Foundations. 3 Immanuel Kant, Religionwithin the Limits of ReasonAlone, trans. Theodore M. Green and Hoyt H. Hudson (New York: Harper Torchbooks, 1960), 87. Hereafter Religion. 4 Ibid. GOD AND KANT'S ETHICAL COMMONWEALTH 69 thinking occurring between the Critique of PracticalReason and Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone, works separated by five years. These shifts reveal the connection between the increasing importance of the moral community and the decreasing importance of a divine role in the realization of our moral destiny. In addition, I intend to clarify the important issue of how progress toward the moral community "appears" from both the human and the divine standpoints. Given the radical divergence of these two perspectives, Kant puts in jeopardy the very partnership he otherwise seems eager to endorse. That is, the difference in perspective is so fundamental that the notion of shared moral effort informing the idea of a partnership is strained beyond recognition. Ultimately at stake in this discussion is Kant's effort to replace an outmoded speculative theology with his own moral theism. Given his harsh treatment of the metaphysical and argumentative underpinnings of the natural theology of his day, a great deal rides on his ability to maintain a content for language about God, subsequent to the moral turn that sustains his religious thought. My suggestion here will be that, in his efforts to depict in fuller terms the social dimensions of his conception of human autonomy, Kant so compromises traditional conceptions of divine transcendence as to jeopardize the strictly theological side of his effort to mediate between tradition and modernity. Simultaneously, his dualistic account of the way actual moral progress "appears" raises serious questions, not only about the nature of the presumed partnership that generates the ethical commonwealth, but also about the sheer coherence of Kant's account of humanity's moral struggle. I A helpful way to understand Kant's conception of God's relation to the ethical commonwealth is to survey the several related yet separate tracks along which his thinking about God travels. One track-perhaps the most familiar-is basically negative in effect, since it involves a rigorously argued embargo 70 GORDON E. MICHALSON, JR. against all theoretical knowledge of God's existence. This famous result of the Critique of Pure Reason's demolition of the traditional proofs for the existence of God yields a deep skepticism toward natural theology and drives a thick wedge between metaphysics and theology. This track carries forward Kant's views toward God in a way that has earned him the label of "great destroyer. " 5 A second track results from Kant's effort to generate a theologically positive result from his own epistemological strictures. By investigating reason in its "practical" aspect, the Critiqueof PracticalReason moves from theoretical skepticism to moral certainty. Since this investigation is supplemented by the idea of the "highest good" as the proper proportioning of happiness to virtue-a state of affairs that, for Kant, ultimately requires divine agency for its implementation-moral certainty turns out to be quite specific with respect to its potential content. In short, proper reflection on practical reason and its total aim produces moral certainty of the existence of God, grounded in an apodictic awareness of moral obligation: because my sense of moral obligation is "real," God is real as well. For Kant, this "interior" moral certainty is unquestionably superior to the traditional theoretical proofs, for these are always subject to argumentive rebuttal while one's sense of moral obligation is beyond all argument. By construing the structure of reason itself in a way that entails a consciousness of the moral law, Kant thus recovers a theological content seemingly jeopardized by theoretical reason's austere results. 6 Far from being a concession to wishful thinking, "moral faith" for Kant "does not here choose but rather obeys an inexorable command of reason," one that "has its ground objectively in the character of things. "7 The 5 The expression was originally Heinrich Heine's, quoted in Allen W. Wood, Kant's Rational Theology (Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press, 1978), 17. 6 An excellent summary of how Kant arrived at the view that the moral sensibility is the result of reason's own structure is Dieter Henrich, "The Concept of Moral Insight and Kant's Doctrine of the Fact of Reason," in Henrich, AestheticJudgment and the Moral Image of the World: Studies in Kant (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1992), 55-87. 7 Immanuel Kant, Critiqueof PracticalReason, trans. Lewis White Beck (Indianapolis and New York: Bobbs-Merrill, 1956), 148. Hereafter referred to as PracticalReason. GOD AND KANT'S ETHICAL COMMONWEALTH 71 rational person does not choose to believe in God's existence but rather discoversthat such belief follows necessarily from the sheer fact of taking moral obligation seriously. There is yet a third track associated with Kant's reflection on the problem of God, one that is more complex in character as it builds on the idea of moral faith in connection with sustained reflection on the total product of humanity's moral effort. This track concerns the role played by God as Kant elaborates on what Yirmiahu Yovel has called the "historical imperative" in Kant's philosophy. 8 Due to the intrinsically teleological nature of reason's restless activity, reason is driven to consider the unconditioned totality of human endeavor. Applied to the issue of moral endeavor, this insight enables Kant to transcend the personal and individualistic conception of autonomy most familiar to readers of his ethical theory and to concentrate on the collective result of moral action. 9 Kant's mature philosophy in fact involves an ongoing development of the idea of the totalization of moral action, reflected in various strands in his thinking that beg for further systematization: for example, the "realm of ends" (Foundationsof the Metaphysicsof Morals), the "highest good" (Critique of Practical Reason), the teleological plot-lines revealed in his several essays on history, and the Critique of Judgment's attempted teleological reconciliation of freedom and nature. While it is difficult to depict these diverse strands in a coherent synthesis, it is reasonably clear where Kant is going as he reflects on the total product of moral action. 10 In effect, he is proposing 8 Yirmiahu Yovel, Kant and the Philosophy of History (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1980), 138. 9 This point is implicit in, and helps to make sense of, the seemingly odd decision of Roger Sullivan to begin his recent and admirable introduction to Kant's ethics with an account of his political theory; Roger Sullivan, An Introduction to Kant's Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994). 10 Yovel, Kant and the Philosophy of History, is perhaps the most successful effort to relate these various strands in Kant. See the general account offered in Gordon E. Michalson, Jr., Kant and the Problem of God (Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1999). A useful recent effort to frame these matters in terms of a unified account of Kant's theory of reason itself is Susan Neiman, The Unity of Reason (New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994). 72 GORDON E. MICHALSON, JR. that the very point of reality is the progressive realization of a community of rational beings for whom the moral law alone will be a sufficient incentive. This is to say that the goal of human history is the idealized community that is conveyed by Kant's notion of the ethical commonwealth. One finds in this idea something like a historicizing of the very idea of the highest good itself. The perennial question of whether this idealized ethical community will in fact be historically realized-or simply forever approximated-is less important than the fact that the drive toward this ideal constitutes humanity's moral vocation. 11 My main point for now is that Kant's insights into the role God plays in the realization of this moral goal constitute the third track of his thinking about God. Here, Kant's God has been released from the argumentative confinement characteristic of the first track as well as from the important but limited role he plays in connection with the second track, where he simply insures the correct proportioning of happiness and virtue. In this third context, God has now become a full-fledged partner and actor in the creation of what Kant will sometimes refer to as the "kingdom of heaven on earth," where all wills freely conform to the universalizability principle. In short, God is a member of the ethical commonwealth. II The point I wish to explore further concerns the implicit erosion of divine transcendence in the course of Kant's depiction of the partnership that brings about the ethical commonwealth. My point effectively amounts to the suggestion that there is an ironic side to the image of a divine partnership involved in the God of "track three." The initial appearance of an enhanced role 11 Yovel, Kant and the Philosophyof History, 72 argues that "from the third Critique on, Kant's conception [of the highest good] changes. The highest good becomes the 'final end of creation' itself, i.e., the consummate state of this world. Its realization is conceived as 'the kingdom of God on earth'; and despite its infinite remoteness, it involves a concrete synthesis, to be realized in time, between the moral will and empirical reality .... In other words, the highest good becomes a historical goal." For an opposing view, see Roger Sullivan, Immanuel Kant's Moral Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), 361-62 n. 3. GOD AND KANT'S ETHICAL COMMONWEALTH 73 for God to play in achieving a moral universe is in fact deceptive since, upon inspection, God's role thins out in ways that raise provocative questions about the actual status of language about God in Kant's vision of humanity's moral goal. Some further elaboration of the train of thought leading to Kant's ideal of the ethical commonwealth should provide additional clarifying context. Early in the critical period, at the time of the publication of the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant depicts "a moral world, in so far as it may be in accordance with all moral laws; and this is what by means of the freedom of rational beings it can be, and what according to the necessary laws of morality it ought to be." 12 Much of Kant's philosophical labor in the following two decades would be devoted to filling out this picture of a moral world, beginning with the third version of his own categorical imperative: "[E]very rational being must act as if he, by his maxims, were at all times a legislative member in the universal realm of ends. " 13 With this version, Kant deepens the social dimension already implicit in the second version of his imperative, which enjoins us to "treat humanity, whether in your own person or in that of another, always as an end and never as a means only. " 14 Whereas the universality principle highlighted in the first and most familiar form of the categorical imperative ("Act as though the maxim of your action were by your will to become a universal law of nature") 15 is the appropriate form for a truly rational principle, "humanity" is the appropriate material. 16 This deepening sense of a social dimension as Kant moves through his three versions of the categorical imperative culminates in the very notion of a realm of ends itself. We can 12 Immanuel Kant, Critiqueof Pure Reason, trans. Norman Kemp Smith (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1965), A808/B836, p. 637. Hereafter Pure Reason. 13 Kant, Foundations,57. l4 Ibid., 4 7. 15 Ibid., 39. 16 Christine Korsgaard, Creatingthe Kingdom of Ends (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 106££. There is a clear survey of the interaction of the three formulas of the categorical imperative, with a view to the ultimate ideal of a moral community, in Sullivan, Immanuel Kant's Moral Theory, 212££. 74 GORDON E. MICHALSON, JR. thus see that the social dimension of Kant's moral outlook is not an artificial addendum or contrived attachment to a basically individualist, rights-oriented moral posture. In Kant's own words, the three versions of the categorical imperative are "fundamentally only so many formulas of the very same law, and each of them unites the others in itself. " 17 An imperative that is categorically binding includes within itself the idea of a "systematic union of rational beings through common objective laws," where the "law-like" feature is imposed autonomously through each member's act of will. The social dimension is present in Kant's thinking from the very outset of his effort to ground morality in its foundational principle. By the time this originally skeletal idea of a moral community grows into the richer concept of the ethical commonwealth in Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone, Kant has placed his own moral theism on a presumably secure footing with his Critique of Practical Reason. At the same time, he has severely compromised his ability to tell a neat, linear story about human and divine cooperation in the production of the moral community with his doctrine of "radical evil," also in the Religion. Somewhat oddly, Kant continues to envision a moral telos for humanity even as he creates powerful reasons for doubting our capacity to achieve the desired and seemingly mandated moral goal. The idea of an evil that is "radical" -defined as the freely willed corruption of the underlying moral "disposition" that serves as the source of individual maxims 18-seems initially to stand in a peculiar 17 Kant, Foundations,54. The presence of a social dimension in Kant's initial formulation of morality's fundamental principle should be kept in mind in connection with contemporary discussions of liberalism and communitarianism. Too often, Kant is held up as the exemplary "liberal" who has a preoccupation with "rights" that leaves problematic any effort to justify notions of "community" and community obligations on Kantian grounds. A reading of Kant that both appreciates the social dimension present in his initial formulation of morality's fundamental principle, and then draws a line between this formulation and his later account of the ethical commonwealth, suggests the oversimplifications attending this common depiction of Kant as a purely rights-oriented liberal. 18 Kant, Religion, 20-21, 27-28. There is no simple explanation for Kant's view of the origins of radical evil, since any such explanation would, on his terms, amount to an "explanation" of an act of "freedom" (thereby robbing freedom of its point). See Gordon E. GOD AND KANT'S ETHICAL COMMONWEALTH 75 juxtaposition with our vocation as community-builders. In fact, however, it is through his own deepened reflection on the nature of the moral community that Kant finally charts a path toward the resolution of the problem of radical evil. While it is perhaps too simplistic to say that the appeal to community resolves the problems disclosed by the doctrine of radical evil, it is fair to say that the social element plays a major role in Kant's effort to overcome those problems. More to the point, it is in connection with Kant's turn to the social dimension as a possible solution to the problem of radical evil that God's role comes into view. Midway through the Religion, Kant speaks of a moral "duty which is sui generis, not of men toward men, but of the human race toward itself." This duty resides in the fact that the human race is destined for a social goal, namely, the promotion of the highest as a social good .... [T]he highest moral good cannot be achieved merely by the exertions of the single individual toward his own perfection, but rather requires a union of such individuals into a whole toward the same goal-into a system of welldisposed men, in which and through whose unity alone the highest moral good can come to pass.19 Clearly, the reality of radical evil stands between us and the easy attainment of this goal. Yet this obstacle does not invalidate the goal itself, for, as Kant goes on to explain, the "idea" of this "universal republic based on laws of virtue" is "completely distinguished from all moral laws (which concern what we know to lie in our power). "20 In other words, the objective validity of the idea of an ethical commonwealth is not undermined by the harsh things Kant has simultaneously said in the Religion about humanity's "natural propensity" to radical evil. Having secured the objective validity of the idea of the ethical commonwealth-despite the devastating problems posed to its realization by radical evil-Kant goes on to establish its real possibility through appeal to God. In other words, Kant's appeal Michalson,Jr., "The Inscrutability of Moral Evil in Kant," The Thomist 51 (1987): 246-69. 19 Kant, Religion, 89. 20 Ibid. GORDON E. MICHALSON, JR. 76 to God resolves the appearance of an impasse between demand and debility. As Kant tells us, we "can already foresee" that the duty to bring about an ethical commonwealth "will require the presupposition [Voraussetzung] of another idea, namely, that of a higher moral Being through whose universal dispensation the forces of separate individuals, insufficient in themselves, are united for a common end. " 21 This comment conveys what we might call the strong sense in which God will play the role of partner in the drive toward a moral end. Interestingly, God's chief role is to offset a presumed shortcoming on humanity's part, thus recapitulating at the social level what Kant had previously worked out at the level of the individual's recovery from radical evil. In that earlier context, the individual who is locked in the self-made grip of an evil disposition faces a seemingly impossible command: make yourself "good" again, even though the only route to virtue is the production of morally good maxims. But of course the very definition of an evil that is "radical" is that the source of one's maxims-the disposition-has been given over to the regular subordination of the incentive of moral duty to the incentive of sensuous inclination. 22 Kant's dilemma is dear: he must depict our recovery from radical evil in a way that leaves human autonomy intact; yet the problem from which we must recover has been produced by that very same autonomy which, in the choice of an evil disposition, has shown itself incapable of saving itself. The deep ambivalence of this position is openly conveyed by Kant's comment that moral recovery "must be within our power, even though what we are able to do is in itself inadequate and though we thereby only render ourselves susceptible of higher and, for us, inscrutable assistance."23 In short, the individual moral agent seems no more capable of overcoming radical evil than a community of moral agents appears capable of bringing about the ethical commonwealth. Kant's supposition of a "higher moral Being" who will somehow compensate for the "insufficient" efforts of individuals to gather 21 Ibid. 22 Ibid., 31. 23 Ibid., 40-41. GOD AND KANT'S ETHICAL COMMONWEALTH 77 themselves into a moral collective finds a parallel in his claim that, though an individual's moral efforts may be inadequate in themselves, they may find a divine supplement if the individual strives to do his or her moral best. [It] is a basic principle that each must do as much as lies in his power to become a better man, and that only when he has not buried his inborn talent but has made use of his original predisposition to good in order to become a better man, can he hope that what is not within his power will be supplied through cooperation from above. . . . "It is not essential, and hence not necessary, for everyone to know what God does or has done for his salvation"; but it is essential to know what man himself must do in order to become worthy of this assistance.24 In what ironically amounts to a camouflaged appeal to a traditional notion of grace in order to preserve the integrity of his concept of autonomy, Kant thus invokes the idea of a hidden, divine supplement to the fallen moral agent's own good-faith effort to overcome the problem of radical evil. The moral agent's attitude toward the possibility of this supplement is always one of "hope" and never one of "knowledge," which insures the epistemological integrity of Kant's speculations. The significant point is that this solution to the problem of radical evil at the individual level has an analogue in Kant's account of how the ethical commonwealth can possibly come about: in both cases, divine help is needed. A rational goal threatened by a human debility is rendered attainable through the hidden cooperation of God. Robust moral agency depends on the rational hope that this cooperation will be forthcoming, however frustrating the inevitable setbacks in the moral life may be. III The fact that Kant's discussion of the creation of the ethical commonwealth is the occasion for fresh commentary about God is interesting in part because of the way it repeats in a more social context the same moves evident in the moral proof in the second 24 Ibid., 47. 78 GORDON E. MICHALSON, JR. Critique.In both cases, a teleological totalizing process is depicted as the result of reason's natural drive toward a final end. In the Critiqueof PracticalReason, this totalizing process culminates in the proper proportioning of virtue and happiness, which clearly does not occur in this life. As the agency responsible for this proportioning process, God effectively becomes the metaphysical underwriting insuring that we do in fact live in a rational universe, worldly appearances to the contrary notwithstanding. In the terms suggested by Dieter Henrich, God's role in the proportioning of happiness and virtue eliminates the element of "luck" that appears to attend the distribution of happiness in this world. 25 In turn, God's role as "proportioner" is transformed in the Religion into his role as the hidden source of aid in community-building whose help must be "presupposed" if humanity's moral goal is to seem achievable. In the cases of both the second Critique and the Religion,the appeal to divine agency is occasioned by the need to insure the satisfaction of a need of reason. The common denominator linking these two cases is of course the idea of the highest good itself. The fact that the highest good could be put to such distinct uses reflects transitions that have occurred in Kant's thinking between these two major works. The second Critique's conception of the highest good as the proportioning of virtue and happiness is both highly abstract and associated with the postulate of the immortality of the soul, which provides the duration necessary for the required perfection of virtue. By the time of the Religion, Kant has shifted to the more historically grounded idea of "the promotion of the highest as the social good," which is to say, the ethical commonwealth. 26 The individual's perfection of virtue that is at stake in the noumenal realm of the immortality of the soul has become the community's 25 Henrich, "The Moral Image of the World," in Henrich, AestheticJudgment and the Moral Image of the World, 3-28. Henrich notes the strong influence of Rousseau at this point in Kant's moral theory. 26 Kant, Religion, 89. See Sharon Anderson-Gold, "Kant's Ethical Commonwealth: The Highest Good as a Social Goal," InternationalPhilosophicalQuarterly26 (1986): 23-32; and Philip J. Rossi, S.J., "Autonomy and Community: The Social Character of Kant's 'Moral Faith,'" The Modern Schoolman 61 (1984): 169-86. GOD AND KANT'S ETHICAL COMMONWEALTH 79 realization of itself as fashioned according to laws of virtue alone. It is presumably in light of this transformation that one commentator has suggested that, in the Religion, the "highest good and the given world no longer signify two different worlds but two states, present and ideal, of the same world. In other words, the highest good becomes a historical goal. "27 Gradually coming into focus here is a three-part shift between the Critiqueof PracticalReason and Religion within the Limits of ReasonAlone: (1) the moral task of the perfection of virtue is now rendered in terms of overcoming the problem of radical evil, (2) the relevant venue for the achievement of this moral task shifts from the immortality of the soul to the building of a moral community, and (3) God's role goes from being the "proportioner" of virtue and happiness to being the hidden source of aid in overcoming the obstacles to creating the moral community. Clearly, the increasing emphasis here on the social dimensions of moral agency involves a modification of the very idea of divine transcendence. For to the extent that God is more and more a partner in the process of community-building, God is less "other," in the sense of being less restricted to the timeless noumenal realm that frames Kant's account of the immortality of the soul in the second Critique. The infinitely distant noumenal agent who proportions virtue and happiness is now viewed, not simply as an accomplice in a common moral task, but-to return to Schneewind' s observation-as a fellow member of the same community. The threefold set of transitions that characterize the shift in perspective between the second Critiqueand the Religionis at the same time an implicit humanizing of divine activity, rendered now in terms of a common moral task rather than in terms of a task suitable only for a "God." In the Critique, God is clearly set apart as the transcendent agent who alone enjoys the 27 Yovel, Kant and the Philosophy of History, 72. Sarah Gibbons has suggested that Kant actually has two views of the highest good, a "narrow" and a "wide" view: the narrow view "focuses on the relation of the highest good to the moral law and the good will," while the wide view emphasizes "the social and historical nature of this good and the role of culture in its possible realization" (Sarah Gibbons, Kant's Theory of Imagination [Oxford: Oxford University Press,1994), 153). The difference between the two can of course be readily seen in the shift I am tracing from the second Critique to the Religion. 80 GORDON E. MICHALSON, JR. metaphysical weight necessary for the prodigious task of proportioning virtue and happiness. In the Religion,by contrast, God joins finite moral agents in promoting a dearly defined social good, the outlines of which have been sketched by the categorical imperative itself. The task at stake is a common task. One striking aspect of this transition is that, from the standpoint of the individual moral agent struggling to achieve virtue, there is no longer a fundamental difference between one's fellow finite moral agents and God. The individual moral agent stands to benefit as much from the one as from the other, insofar as "the exertions of the single individual toward his own perfection . . . requires . . . a union of such individuals into a whole toward the same goal." 28 The individual's moral vocation cannot be achieved apart from community-building, which makes other moral agents decisive for the full and authentic exercise of the individual's autonomy. 29 While God may fill the specific role of the hidden agent making up for a perceived shortfall in moral effort by the entire body of finite agents, the fact remains that other finite moral agents are now the major source of one's own moral fulfillment. In short, one's moral fulfillment depends upon the collaborative activity of community-building, suggesting an important sense in which the wider community begins to offset the individual's moral limitations. In contrast to the apparently profound isolation of the finite agent in the second Critique, the Religion offers a vision of a strengthened connection between other moral agents and the individual's personal moral progress. Indeed, the whole point of the idea of the ethical commonwealth is that moral progress can no longer be viewed in purely individual terms. The individual's moral fate is bound up with the fate of the community in ways that necessarily redirect the 28 Kant, Religion, 89. 29 Allen Wood's characterization is apt: for Kant, "our nature as sociable beings gives us a profound need" for a community involving "the collective pursuit of ends set in common with others," and "our vocation as moral beings cannot be fulfilled" without such a community (Allen Wood, Kant's Ethical Thought [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999], 315-16). GOD AND KANT'S ETHICAL COMMONWEALTH 81 individual's interest and concern toward the shared social task. The fulfillment of the individual's very autonomy resides in treating other rational beings as ends in themselves and entering into a relation of universalizing legislation with them. To the extent that I place my hope increasingly in such involvements, I recognize that the immanent zone of social activity is the locus of my individual salvation. Yet this, of course, is another way of saying that my individual salvation is inseparable from that of the group. By Kant's own terms, in fact, the group now mediates my personal relationship to God. From this point of view, we might say that any accompanying alterations in God's transcendence are the spin-off effects of God's growing redundancy or even irrelevance. The appearance of God as having a robust role to play in the task of building an ethical commonwealth is the deceptive appearance often made by a "presupposition" playing a role in a transcendental argument. The presupposition that "the forces of separate individuals, insufficient in themselves, are united for a common end" 30 with divine help may be necessary for moral encouragement, but it does not displace the agent's primary focus on other moral agents. This element of redundancy is particularly evident in Kant's efforts to preserve a special role for God to play as the socalled law-giver of the ethical commonwealth. At first glance, Kant's account of the law-giver appears to reinvigorate his conception of God with a unique and decisive role to play in the creation of a moral universe, a role that goes beyond that played by finite moral agents. Kant explains that "if the commonwealth is to be ethical, the people, as a people, cannot itself be regarded as the law-giver." Hence only he can be thought of as highest law-giver of an ethical commonwealth with respect to whom all true duties, hence also the ethical, must be represented as at the same time his commands; he must therefore also be "one who knows the heart," in order to see into the innermost parts of the disposition of each individual and, as is necessary in every commonwealth, to bring it about that each receives whatever his actions are worth. But this is the concept of God as moral ruler of the world. Hence an ethical commonwealth °Kant, Religion, 89. 3 GORDON E. MICHALSON, JR. 82 can be thought of only as a people under divine commands, i.e., as a people of God, and indeed under laws of virtue.31 Kant here runs together a point about the source of the laws defining an ethical commonwealth with a point about how one might judge who is being truly virtuous and who is not. With respect to divine agency, the emphasis clearly falls on the latter point: only God possesses the intellectual intuition capable of grasping the moral status of a finite moral agent. But this point has nothing whatsoever to do with the more foundational issue of what gives the ethical commonwealth its special character in the first place, nor does Kant ever claim that the ethical commonwealth originally receives its mandate from God. In other words, Kant's invocation of God's name in the course of speaking of the law-giver of the ethical commonwealth simply turns out to be a way of distinguishing between "public" and "inner" laws. Far from reintroducing a robust conception of God's transcendence and indispensable role, such an insight merely recycles in a fresh way Kant's previous distinction between a political community and a community of virtue. Indeed, Kant reminds us that in an ethical commonwealth all the laws are expressly designed to promote the morality of actions (which is something inner, and hence cannot be subject to public human laws) whereas, in contrast, these public laws-and this would go to constitute a juridical commonwealth-are directed only toward the legalityof actions, which meets the eye, and not toward (inner) morality, which alone is in question here. 32 What is noteworthy here is that Kant makes the connection between God and this "public/inner" distinction when he claims that there "must therefore be someone other than the populace capable of being specified as the public law-giver for an ethical commonwealth." Yet, Kant goes on, we should not think of the ethical laws themselves "as emanating originallymerely from the will of this superior being. "33 In fact, the ethical laws at stake arise 31 Ibid., 90-91. 32 Ibid., 90. 33 Ibid. GOD AND KANf'S ETHICAL COMMONWEALTH 83 out of our very own rational sense of duty and are not revealed or arbitrary statutes rendered from above or imposed from the outside. In other words, the sense in which God is viewed as the "lawgiver" of the ethical community has nothing whatever to do with the rational source of the laws governing and defining such a community. Instead, God's status as law-giver is a function of his ability to pass judgment on the inner, moral state of individual members of the community, which is a kind of carry-over from the divine activity described in the postulation of God's existence in the second Critique. The issue at stake is the integrity of the moral agent's private moral disposition and not a potentially heteronomous source of the laws governing the ethical commonwealth. The question of whether a member of the ethical commonwealth is obeying the moral law is not a matter for public debate or enforcement; instead, it is only a matter for God to apprehend and judge. But this point of course has nothing to do with the question of the rational source of moral obligation itself, which is accessible to all rational agents and not generated in some special way only by God. Indeed, Kant himself indicates in the opening pages of the Religion that the "bare idea" of a law-giver is "identical with the general moral concept of duty," even suggesting that the two are analytically equivalent. 34 Such an insight clarifies what it means to say that we share with God our membership in the ethical commonwealth. The roots of this vision of a shared membership in a moral community in fact go back to Kant's initial account of a realm or kingdom of ends in the Foundationsof the Metaphysics of Morals. In that context, as one commentator has reminded us, Kant claims we enjoy "the right to regard ourselves as sharing the headship of the kingdom of ends with God insofar as we are legislators in that world," 35 a point bearing once again on the source of moral obligation characteristic of the ethical commonwealth. In an important (and neglected)36 passage in the 34 Ibid., 6 n. Immanuel Kant's Moral Theory, 217. The Invention of Autonomy, 510-11, attempts to rescue the relevant passage in the Foundations from its traditional neglect. 35 Sullivan, 36 Schneewind, GORDON E. MICHALSON, JR. 84 Founda.tions,Kant provides further reason for his incorporation of God into the moral community when he argues that everyone "must admit that a law, if it is to hold morally, i.e., as a ground of obligation ... does not apply to men only, as if other rational beings had no need to observe it. "37 Applied to the subsequent idea of the ethical commonwealth, this claim becomes a reminder that God, too, is obligated to obey the universalizing legislation of the moral community and is not somehow superior to it. Morality is not grounded in a contingent act of the divine will that could be exercised in isolation from the universalizability principle. Rather, morality has a rational source that is binding even on the will of God. God's "partnership" with finite moral agents in the creation of the ethical commonwealth thus shrinks the distance between God and humanity precisely because it turns out to be genuine. IV God's relationship to the ethical commonwealth has one further feature, involving the divine perspective on the ultimate realization of the authentic moral community. This aspect of God's connection to the ethical commonwealth is implicit in Kant's remarks on the conversion of the individual moral agent from radical evil to a virtuous disposition, no doubt the most challenging moral problem disclosed in the Religion.In grappling with the problem of explaining how the finite moral agent freely changes itself, Kant distinguishes between the noumenal (and therefore timeless) "revolution in his cast of mind" and the phenomenal (and therefore time-bound) "gradual reform in [the agent's] sensuous nature. "38 This distinction does not explain or in any way account for the moral recovery itself. Rather, Kant is apparently making the point that even the most sincere and genuine conversion in the underlying disposition does not automatically produce a saintly life. Within the world of appearances, the moral convert is launched on a "path of 37 Kant, Foundations, 5. 38 Kant, Religion, 43. GOD AND KANT'S ETHICAL COMMONWEALTH 85 continual progress from bad to better," a path sustained by the hope that there really has been moral renewal. 39 At the epistemological level, the matter remains one of hope, for the agent can have no sure knowledge of a noumenal state of affairs such as the status of the moral disposition, even his own. 40 But God can. For Him who penetrates to the intelligible ground of the heart (the ground of all maxims of the will) and for whom this unending progress is a unity, i.e., for God, this amounts to his actually being a good man (pleasing to Him); and, thus viewed, this change can be regarded as a revolution. 41 In keeping with his systematic unwillingness ever to "explain" an act of freedom for fear of showing what "caused" it,42 Kant makes no effort in this context to account for how the change in moral disposition actually occurs. His reference to the divine perspective effectively assumes that the change has occurred, leaving us with a certain amount of insight into the divine perspective even as we have none at all into the process of moral regeneration itself. Similarly, when attempting to reconcile the notion of a renewed disposition with the fact that "conduct itself, as a continual and endless advance from a deficient to a better good, ever remains defective," Kant reminds us of what God already knows, but without any clear guidance as to how we are to understand this "already." What Kant does tell us is that, although the agent very likely experiences moral progress in fits39 Ibid. 40 "[F]or outer experience does not disclose the inner nature of the disposition but merely allows of an inference about it though not one of strict certainty. (For the matter of that, not even does a man's inner experience with regard to himself enable him so to fathom the depths of his own heart as to obtain, through self-observation, quite certain knowledge of the basis of the maxims which he professes, or of their purity and stability)" (ibid., 56-57). 41 Ibid., 43, emphasis added. 42 Roger Sullivan nicely captures the oxymoronic character of any effort to speak of "causality" in connection with freedom: "The concept of a noumenal efficient cause specifies a will free from prior causal determination and able to act only on its own Law of Autonomy" (Sullivan, Immanuel Kant's Moral Theory, 92). See Allen Wood's helpful discussion of the limited though important sense in which Kant speaks of the special kind of "causality" associated with freedom. Wood, Kant's Ethical Thought, 172ff. GORDON E. MICHALSON, JR. 86 and-starts and as a deeply challenging endless struggle, we can imagine this evolution as being judged by Him who knows the heart, through a pure intellectual intuition, as a completed whole, because of the disposition,supersensible in its nature, from which this progress is derived. Thus may man, notwithstanding his permanent deficiency, yet expect to be essentiallywell-pleasing to God, at whatever instant his existence be terminated. 43 The renewed disposition, Kant remarks in his own note to this interesting comment, "stands in the place of the totality of this series of approximations carried on without end. "44 But only God can "see" this. By contrast, we see "only that failure which is inseparable from the existence of a temporal being as such, the failure, namely, ever wholly to be what we have in mind to become. "45 Once again, the subject under discussion is not really how moral regeneration occurs but what the process looks like, in both human and divine terms. Obviously, Kant's account evokes a long-standing tradition of debate over the relation of God to time as well as over the relation between divine omniscience and human freedom. While Kant could hardly be unaware of this heritage, he does not locate his own position in terms of it. Here as elsewhere, his theological concerns are primarily shaped by the more strictly cognitive issues driving the Leibnizian-Wolffian tradition, which Kant is attempting to reshape through his emphasis on the practical over the theoretical route to theological claims. His aim throughout is "to distinguish as dearly as possible between an impersonal speculative proof and a moral certainty about God, "46 with a view to replacing his received rationalist tradition's emphasis on the former with his own broadly pietist 43 Kant, Religion, 60-61. 44 Ibid., 61 n. 45 Ibid. 46 James Collins, The Emergenceof Philosophyof Religion (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1967), 100-101. GOD AND KANT'S ETHICAL COMMONWEALTH 87 emphasis on the latter. 47 In the process, he invariably makes claims that appear to implicate his position in other thorny aspects of the Western theological tradition as well, such as the relationship between God and time. Yet his overarching concern to rectify our view of our cognitive relationship to God-with his characteristic insistence that we have no rational, theoretical knowledge of God's existence or attributes-leaves these other issues largely unaddressed. 48 Ultimately at issue in Kant's "two perspectives" approach to moral regeneration is the deeper distinction between a "sensible" and an "intellectual" intuition. A cardinal feature of the critical philosophy as a whole is Kant's claim that, as rational yet sensuous beings, we are limited by our possession of a mere sensible intuition, reflecting the receptive or passive aspect of our cognitive faculties that works together with the spontaneous or active aspect contributed by the understanding. This cognitive limitation effectively rules out any privileged insight into speculative or metaphysical truths. 49 In the context of Kant's epistemology, this limitation finally amounts to the claim that we can have experience only in terms structured by the pure intuitions of space and time. Space and time are constitutive of the way objects "appear" to us. Thus, to experience the world in a manner conditioned by a sensible intuition is to experience appearances only. While this familiar feature of Kant's philosophy 47 John H. Zarnmito, The Genesisof Kant's "CritiqueofJudgment" (Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press, 1992), 17-21; Richard L. Velkley, Freedom and the End of Reason: On the Moral Foundationof Kant's CriticalPhilosophy (Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press, 1989), 21-22. 48 A rare exception to this rule is Kant's Lectureson PhilosophicalTheology, trans. Allen W. Wood and Gertrude M. Clark (Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press, 1978) which, though they evidently postdate the publication of the Critiqueof Pure Reason, have to be handled with some care. In addition to the obvious problems associated with a text reconstructed from lectures and lecture notes, there is, in this case, the fact that Kant was lecturing on a required set text, in accordance with the university customs of the day. 49 The implications of this position are conveniently summarized in a remark by Kant in the first Critique: "Since, however, such a type of intuition, intellectual intuition, forms no part whatsoever of our faculty of knowledge, it follows that the employment of the categories can never extend further than to the objects of experience." The consequences for all forms of natural theology are obvious; Kant, Pure Reason, B308, p. 270. 88 GORDON E. MICHALSON, JR. may in some sense reflect serious cognitive limitations, they are limitations that flow quite naturally from his effort to secure the epistemological integrity of a Newtonian account of the universe, particularly in light of Humean challenges to that account. This fundamental aim of the Critiqueof Pure Reason helps to produce the austere epistemology that will inform Kant's devastating attack on speculative metaphysics at the same time that it underwrites Newtonianism. The contrast case to a sensuous intuition is an "intellectual" intuition, which involves the capacity to experience things-inthemselves, the noumenal as opposed to the phenomenal. Just as only God-in contrast to ourselves-possesses a "Holy will,"50 God-again in contrast to ourselves-possesses an intellectual intuition. Within this Kantian framework, apprehending reality as such, things-in-themselves as opposed to mere appearances, is simply constitutive of what it means to be God. In the current context, this difference in the divine point of view insures God's ability to appreciate the revolution in the (noumenal) disposition. For God, the change of heart is a completed reality, while for the moral agent "this change must be regarded as nothing but an ever-during struggle toward the better, hence as a gradual reformation. "51 Curiously, then, this most modern of philosophers effectively reverts at this point to certain medieval traditions that posit a God who is "outside" of time. But since Kant's frame of theological reference is provided more directly by the Leibnizian-Wolffian inheritance, his recycling of familiar medieval debates is never addressed in its original terms. The closest Kant comes to shedding light on this point is framed (in another context) largely as a cautionary remark that simply so Kant, PracticalReason, 84-85. The odd implications of God's "holy will" are suggested by Beck's comment that, for "a holy will, the concept of duty would have no application, since duty presupposes that there are other grounds of choice, different from and in conflict with the legislation of reason. For it, the difference between what is willed and what ought to be willed would not arise" (Lewis White Beck, A Commentary on Kant's Critique of PracticalReason [Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press, 1960], 50 n). See the discussion of the implicitly radical implications of this sort of Kantian limitation on God in Michalson, Kant and the Problem of God, ch. 2. 51 Kant, Religion, 43. GOD AND KANT'S ETHICAL COMMONWEALTH 89 reinforces his primary interest in the proper understanding of our cognitive relationship to God: If we ... want to exclude time from the concept of God, then little remains of eternity except a representation of the necessity of his existence. But we have to make do with this on account of the weakness of our reason. For it would be impertinent for us to want to lift the curtain which veils in holy darkness him who is invariably and forever. We must eliminate every sensible representation of time from the concept of God, because such representations can easily corrupt a concept which is supposed to be free from all limitation. 52 Still, the absence of a more thorough account of unresolved issues implicitly raised by Kant's outlook should not distract us from the genuinely provocative implications of the position he is staking out. What is finally interesting to consider here is that Kant's depiction of a dual perspective on the moral regeneration of the individual must apply as well to his remarks on progress toward the ethical commonwealth. While Kant himself does not make the connection between the "two perspectives" account and his discussion of the ethical commonwealth, all of the same ground rules remain in place: the shift from an account of individual moral progress to a more social conception of moral progress does not affect the issue of how this progress "appears" to both God and finite moral agents. As we have seen, the very idea of the ethical commonwealth involves the realization, in time, of a community of moral agents who increasingly bring about a "universal republic based on laws of virtue," where the coercion characteristic of the civil state is replaced by the wholly voluntary legislation of laws that could be universalized. It is not altogether dear if Kant intends the moral community to be fully realizable in history, or if he views it as an infinitely distant ideal, not realizable in time but serving as a regulative ideal toward which rational beings ought to strive.53 But there is no such question mark for God. By the very ground rules Kant lays out in relation to his account of personal moral regeneration, a dual perspective on the attainment of the ethical commonwealth is 52 Kant, Lectureson PhilosophicalTheology, 78. See note 48, above. 53 Regarding these alternative views of Kant's position, see note 11, above. 90 GORDON E. MICHALSON, JR. simply not available to God, since God possesses only an intellectual intuition. Just as God's holy will means that the difference between what is willed and what ought to be willed can never arise, God's intellectual intuition means that "the distinction between the actual and the necessary" does not arise.54 In this context, the clear implication is that God "sees" the ethical commonwealth perfected and complete, just as God "sees" the individual's disposition as completely revolutionized. The fact that humanity may have to embark on a time-bound progression toward the achievement of the ethical commonwealth is, in principle, no more relevant to the divine standpoint than the fact that the individual moral agent must undergo a seemingly endless path of moral improvement. Just as personal history drops out for God when we view moral progress at the level of the individual, history as a whole is irrelevant when we consider humanity's total moral vocation. Once again, "time" simply does not enter into the divine perspective as a morally relevant factor. God's relation to time is the flip side of the harsh reality associated with the fate of finite beings, which (as we have seen) Kant characterizes in terms of a "failure which is inseparable from the existence of a temporal being as such, the failure, namely, ever wholly to be what we have in mind to become. " 55 God's freedom from a similar tragic flaw is grounded in the divine aloofness from time. From the divine standpoint, then, Kant's ethical commonwealth implies something like a realized eschatology. The "kingdom" is indeed at hand for the one (and only one) who has the eyes to see through the possession of an intellectual intuition. Kant in fact alludes to the ethical commonwealth as both the "kingdom of heaven" and as the "kingdom of God on earth," expressions that he explicitly associates with the "victory of the good principle over evil."56 Much of the latter half of the Religion is devoted to arguing that the "visible church" is the "vehicle" for the progressive manifestation of an "invisible church" which Commentary, 50 n. Kant, Religion, 61 n. 54 Beck, 55 56 Ibid., 87££. GOD AND KANT'S ETHICAL COMMONWEALTH 91 already consists of all those who live virtuous lives.57 But, once again, the time-bound, historically progressive character of this journey toward virtue's perfection has utterly no purchase on the divine perspective. There is no reason in principle for Kant to have a different view of this point simply because we have switched from the personal and individual level to the social or community level, for surely God's own nature remains the same. v We thus have a peculiar tension affecting Kant's account of God's relation to the ethical commonwealth. On the one hand, Kant's efforts to characterize God as a partner in the task of building the moral community appear to shrink the distance between God and finite rational beings, raising questions about God's transcendence, or the sense in which God is truly "other" than humanity. These questions are important ones, for it is Kant himself who has undermined the metaphysically based natural theology that has traditionally informed accounts of God's mode of relating to the finite world. Consequently, the issue here is whether Kant's moral theism-with its deepened interest in human autonomy and the associated emphasis on the human frame of reference-can sustain an account of transcendence adequate to ward off the possibility that language about God finally dissolves into language about the total collection of rational but finite moral agents. Such a Feuerbachian result is at least one possible implication of Kant's view of the human/divine partnership in the construction of the moral community, given both the growing role of other finite moral agents in the individual's hope for moral progress and Kant's own deep suspicions toward traditional ways of talking about divine action. On the other hand, however, Kant's account of the way moral progress "appears" suggests a latent rupture in the very idea of a "partnership" in the creation of a good universe. Certainly the effect of the dual perspective on moral progress puts in question 57 Ibid., 122, 139££., 180. 92 GORDON E. MICHALSON, JR. the notion of a shared membership in the ethical commonwealth, for it is simply not clear what is "shared" if finite moral agents view the ethical commonwealth as an ideal yet to be attained, while God views it as already realized outside of time. By being outside of time, God may recover an important element of the transcendence jeopardized by the leveling process generated by the idea of a moral partnership, but the cost of this recovery would appear to be a high one. At the most, the lingering shared element in the partnership would seem simply to involve an area of overlap between God's noumenal vision and a finite humanity's rational hope. God and humanity are truly living in two different "worlds," suggesting that the immanentizing motifs in the Religion do not override the standpoint of the second Critique so much as they remain unreconciled with it. The resulting ambivalence embedded in Kant's view of God's relation to the ethical commonwealth is thus a telling one. To the extent that God is relevant to humanity's moral struggle and is understood to be in partnership with it, divine transcendence appears to be severely compromised. But to the extent that God's differentness or otherness is emphasized, God no longer fully shares in a common moral struggle. Since Kant has himself enforced a rigorous embargo against metaphysically grounded natural theology, he has no means of generating meaningful references to God other than those provided by the moral route. Yet this moral route apparently culminates in instability, with the marginalization of God-language poised opposite the potential irrelevance of God-language to our actual moral struggle. Either way, the notion of a "moral theism" would seem to be seriously compromised. The Thomist 65 (2001): 93-120 THE NATURE OF JUSTIFYING GRACE: A LACUNA IN THE JOINT DECLARATION CHRISTOPHER J. MALLOY The Catholic Universityof America Washington,D.C. I n obedience to the Father's will to unite all things in Christ, the Catholic and Lutheran communions are engaging in dialogue about various issues, most notably justification. This charitable collaboration and the renunciation of the destructive animosities of the past offer grounds for rejoicing and hope. A recent fruit of this dialogue, the joint Declarationon the Doctrine of ]ustification1 (hereafter,JD), claims to present a description of the fundamental truths about justification that conflicts with neither the Lutheran nor the Catholic anathemas from the Reformation era. Among those truths are the sinner's absolute need for God's prevenient mercy, a gradual transformation of the sinner, and a recognition of some form of merit. Despite its noteworthy accomplishments, the JD appears not to have resolved an important and contentious issue, the identity of the "formal cause" of justification or that by which a man stands just before God. The Council of Trent carefully defined this formal cause and surely counted it as one of the fundamental truths of justification. Nevertheless, none of the relevant documents even mentions the phrase "formal cause." 2 While the Origins 28:8 (1998): 120-27. Origins 29:6 (1999): 87-88; "Official Common Statement," Origins 29:6 (1999): 85-87; "Official Catholic Response," Origins28:8 (1998): 130-32. The national and I 2 "Annex," preparatory dialogues have also not faced this issue in all its rigor. Often, the Lutheran and Catholic positions are simply juxtaposed as two inseparable poles or images of redemption: Catholics emphasizing the transformative element and Lutherans emphasizing the gratuitous 93 94 CHRISTOPHER j. MALLOY phrase itself is expendable, what it signifies is of paramount importance. There has long been dispute about what constitutes that by which a man stands just before God. Catholics confess that justifying grace formally causes justification because it is an infused grace that expels all damnable sins by inhering in a man. The Lutheran confessional documents, on the other hand, teach that, since the sanctifying gifts imparted together with justification do not expel all damnable sin, the sinner cannot thereby stand just before God. 3 Thus, they hold that justifying grace itself consists in Christ's own righteousness which God attributes to the believing sinner. 4 These incompatible notions of justifying grace stand as two sides of a doctrinal chasm that divides Lutherans and Catholics. The chasm's breadth is more palpable when seen in light of "double justice," a compromise theory so named because it attempts to combine the formal causes from each communion's doctrine. The confessions reject double justice for mutually opposed reasons: Catholics, because it includes Christ's righteousness as a formal cause; Lutherans, because it includes infused righteousness. Hence, short of doctrinal change, an agreement on basic truths can be reached only through an equivocation on the term "justifying grace." Because this term serves as a focal point of reference, such an equivocation would have manifold conseelement. See, e.g., Condemnationsof the ReformationEra, ed. Karl Lehmann and Wolfhart Pannenberg (Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 1990), 47-48. See also the various essays in the second volume of this project: W. Pannenberg and K. Lehmann, eds., Justificationby Faith: Do the Sixteenth-CenturyCondemnationsStill Apply?, trans. Michael Root and William G. Rusch (New York: The Continuum Publishing Company, 1997), esp. 36-3 7, 78-79, 115-18, 13 7-38, 156-59. See also Justificationby Faith, vol. 7 of Lutheransand Catholicsin Dialogue, ed. H. George Anderson, T. Austin Murphy, and Joseph A. Burgess (Minneapolis: Augsburg Publishing House, 1985), pars. 46-48, 90-99. 3 See The Book of Concord: The Confessionsof the EvangelicalLutheran Church, trans. and ed. Theodore G. Tappert (Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1959). Although various traditions, interpretations, and emphases have arisen among Lutherans, this collection serves as a basic point of reference, and it is reaffirmed as such by the JD's and the Annex's citations of it. 4 See Apology 4:116 in The Book of Concord. See below for the variety of Lutheran theologies with regard to the attributive or declarative nature of justification. JUSTIFYINGGRACE IN THE JOINT DECLARATION 95 quences. Both communions, for instance, could agree that God forgives sin by arresting its damning effect while He also renews the inner man. Nevertheless, they would interpret this diversely. Catholics understand forgiveness as the gratuitous remission of sins through a divine rectification and elevation of a disordered and fallen will. Lutherans see forgiveness as the nonimputation of damnable sin which, although incipiently purged, still remains. The sin is damnable but not damning because it is ruled by Christ through a faith whose justifying power is not dependent upon charity. In light of the importance of the formal cause of justification, I contend first that Catholicism and traditional Lutheranism hold incompatible understandings of justifying grace, and second that the JD does not reconcile this conflict. The common and Lutheran sections of the JD offer abundant evidence for reading justifying grace as God's acquitting favor in Christ. These same sections exhibit the logical consequences of such a position. This reading of justifying grace, however, does not accord with Catholic faith. It thus appears that a doctrinal chasm, obscured by equivocal readings of the same document, still divides these partners in dialogue. Granted, the JD faithfully gathers a host of commonly accepted truths-some of which are listed above-that bridge the chasm like so many olive branches. But upon this foundation the JD further claims to resolve all that was once thought to be Church-dividing about the "basic truths" of justification (JD 5, 14, and 41 ). This weight the branches that straddle the chasm cannot bear. I. AN ORIGINAL AND SUBSTANTIAL CONFLICT The ]D's claim to reconcile Catholic and Lutheran doctrines without contradicting either of their official teachings can be valid only if no contradiction ever truly obtained. Careful consideration, however, reveals an original and substantial conflict. 96 CHRISTOPHER J. MALLOY A) TraditionalLutheranism Catholics and Lutherans have always officially taught that God alone can forgive sinful man and that, when He does so, He works some change in the sinner. But, as Martin Luther and Martin Chemnitz insist, the parties do not agree on what this means. 5 The doctrinal conflict can be summed up in four logically related points. (1) Since Lutherans deny that infused gifts (charity, and even faith itself)6 expel all damnable sins, (2) the formal cause of justification cannot be these gifts but only Christ's own righteousness, on account of which still-present sins are simply not imputed. (3) Therefore, justifying righteousness, unlike interior sanctification, remains perfect and cannot be increased through good works. (4) Much less can any man merit beatitude itself, which is tied exclusively to the promise and received through faith alone. These points should be elaborated. First, Lutherans do accept that, in the overall process of redemption, there is a "real sanctification" of man. Unfortunately, cheap Catholic polemics fail to admit this. Nevertheless, Lutherans consider this transformation, which is God-enabled, to be too weak to destroy sin and merit heaven. Philip Melanchthon writes, "The incipient keeping of the law pleases God because of faith; because of faith our failure to keep it is not imputed to us, although the sight of our impurity thoroughly frightens us. "7 Since this impurity perdures, "no one can therewith and thereby stand before the tribunal of God. " 8 5 D. Martin Luthers Werke: Kritische Gesamtausgabe (Weimar, 1883££.) 8:112, 16-21; hereafter, WA. Martin Chemnitz, Examination of the Council of Trent, Part I, trans. Fred Kramer (St. Louis: Concordia Publishing House, 1971), 467-68 and 517-18. See also Joseph Cardinal Ratzinger, Church, F.cumenism and Politics, trans. Robert Nowell (New York: Crossroad, 1988), 104-5. 6 "This is not because [faith] is a work worthy in itself, but because it receives God's promise" (Apology 4:86). 7 Apology 4: 177. See also 4: 179 and 308. 8 Formula of Concord (Solid Declaration) 3:32 in The Book of Concord. See also ibid., 3:23 and 33-36. JUSTIFYINGGRACE IN THE JOINT DECLARATION 97 Second, this perceived deficiency of sanctification offers two alternatives. Either salvation is not possible, or justifying righteousness must be distinct from what Catholics refer to as "sanctifying grace," which of its nature purges away all damnable sins. Since the former alternative is unseemly, Lutherans opt for the latter, describing justifying righteousness as extrinsic to the sinner. Sanctification is certainly not denied, but it is clearly distinguished from the formal cause of justification, which is Christ's own righteousness: [Christ] himself is their propitiation, for whose sake they are now accounted righteous. But when they are accounted righteous, the law cannot accuse or condemn them, even though they have not really satisfied the law.9 Neither renewal, sanctification, virtues, nor other good works are our righteousness before God, nor are they to be made and posited to be a [form or a] part or a cause of our justification, nor under any kind of pretense, title, or name are they to be mingled with the article of justification as pertinent or necessary to it.... Faith apprehends the grace of God in Christ whereby the person is justified.10 Because the righteousness of Christ is given to us through faith, therefore faith is righteousness in us by imputation. 11 Justification is defined as the forensic forgiveness or nonimputation of sins, even though it is always accompanied by effects which purify, but do not expel, damnable sin. 12 It should be noted that different Lutheran schools portray justification and its relation to sanctification in different ways. Melanchthon 'sApologyseems to favor the language of declarative attribution: God's declaration "synthesizes" two terms (the sinner is just) but does not regard a man's actual status. The Formula of Concord draws a strict distinction between forensic justification and interior sanctification, partly in reaction to Andreas 9 Apology 4:179. See also 4:304-8. 10 Solid Declaration3:39 and 41; see also 3:23. II Apology 4:307. 12 The "forgiveness of sins is the same as justification" (.Apology 4:76). 98 CHRISTOPHER J. MALLOY Osiander's theory that justification occurs through the indwelling of Christ's divine nature. The Formula takes issue with Osiander' s obvious Christological problems as well as with his apparent reversal or confusion of imputation and indwelling. 13 Recent Finnish research on Luther has discovered a middle ground between these two extremes. 14 For Luther and for St. Paul, faith brings a man outside of himself and places him in an ecstatic fellowship with Christ who thereby dwells within him; accordingly, God's "declaration" of justice is an analytic, not a synthetic, statement: God pronounces righteous the man who truly is righteous in Christ. The Finnish reading, although rich, poses further questions. Wolfhart Pannenberg, a proponent of this theory, notes that the relation between the in se and extra se identity of the believer is a difficult matter. His "empirical" identity only begins to be purified but remains ever tainted by sin. 15 Is this damnable sin or simply the existential sense of sinfulness, whether it be damnable or not? It would be difficult to contend that the distinction between the believer's in se and extra se identity simply parallels the Thomistic insistence that the presence of charity can be perceived only indirectly. In fact, Pannenberg disputes Trent's teaching that faith's justifying power depends upon infused charity. 16 Accordingly, justifying faith could coexist with damnable sin. Finally, the Finnish theory entails the need for considerable modification of some official Lutheran, not to mention Catholic, expressions. But the JD intends to avoid such modifications. Formula of Concord (Epitome), 3:1-3 in The Book of Concord. Wolfhart Pannenberg concisely formulates the fruits of this research. See his SystematischeTheologie,Band 3 (Gottingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1993), 263ff. For the work of the pioneering author, see Tuomo Mannermaa, Luther und Theosis, trans. Norman M. Watt (Helsinki: Luther-Agricola-Gesellschaft, 1990); ibid., "Theosis as a Subject of Finnish Luther Research," Pro Ecclesia4 (1995): 37-48; and Carl E. Braaten and Robert W.Jenson, eds., Union with Christ:The New FinnishInterpretationofLuther (Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, 1998). 15 Pannenberg, SystematischeIII, 245. The issue is raised on p. 247 but is never adequately addressed. 16 See ibid., 250; see also 252f. and 265. 13 See 14 JUSTIFYINGGRACE IN THE JOINT DECLARATION 99 Third, from the first two points there logically follows a distinction between the formal cause of sanctification and that of justification, whether or not such distinction is explicitly stated. The former consists in infused gifts that inhere in the believer and make him "so far" holy. The latter consists in the righteousness of Christ which is attributed to or grasped by faith. The fact that such a distinction is made manifests itself most notably in discussions about growth in holiness. Justification, which is the same as forgiveness of sins, cannot increase but "is the same and equal to all, as Christ is one. " 17 So, justifying righteousness, which consists formally in Christ's perfect righteousness, cannot increase. Sanctification is said to increase since it consists in imparted gifts and good works by which there is growth in the effects of God's eternal love. However, good works neither increase nor preserve justifying grace: We rightly reject the decree of the Council of Trent and anything else that tends toward the same opinion, namely, that our good works preserve salvation, or that our works either entirely or in part sustain and preserve either the righteousness of faith that we have received or even faith itself.18 Fourth, because salvation is granted together with justification, good works are equally excluded from the article of salvation, though these works are commendable and encouraged: We receive both our righteousness and our salvation in one and the same way; in fact . . . when we are justified through faith we simultaneously receive adoption and the inheritance of eternal life and salvation. For this reason Paul uses and urges exclusive terms (that is, terms that wholly exclude works and our own merit, such as "by grace" and "without works") just as emphatically in the article of salvation as he does in the article of justification.19 Like Catholics, Lutherans believe that justification cannot be merited, but unlike Catholics they believe also that eternal life itself cannot be merited, even on the basis of infused, sanctifying Apology 4:195-96. Solid Declaration4:34-35. See also Apology 4:160-61. 19 Solid Declaration3:53. 17 18 100 CHRISTOPHER]. MALLOY gifts. When they speak of reward, they always distinguish it from eternal life itself: "Good works are meritorious . . . for other physical and spiritual rewards. " 20 B) Double Justice and Its Condemnation It will be beneficial, before considering Catholic doctrine, to examine the compromise theory of double justice, which is rejected by the Lutheran and Catholic communions for mutually opposed reasons. This mutual condemnation highlights the contrast between the two communions. Girolamo Cardinal Seripando was the chief proponent of double justice at the Council of Trent. 21 Seripando's theory combines the Lutheran and Catholic notions of justification, resulting in two formal causes: inhering righteousness and Christ's righteousness. Since the former cannot satisfy God's wrath, even one who dies "justified" stands in need of a final imputation of Christ's righteousness in order to escape hell. The word "final" can be misleading. It is tempting to think that, since the formal cause is described as twofold, inhering righteousness must precede imputation, which is expressly dubbed "final. " 22 In fact, however, the phrase "final imputation" is intended, not to 20 Apology 3:194 and 4:355-62. For Luther's own formulations, see WA 2:584.7-9; and 8:115. 21 For Seripando's early formulation at the Council, see Concilii Tridentini actorum: Pars altera, ed. Stephen Ehses, vol. 5, Concilium Tridentinum: Diariorum, actorum, epistularum, tractatuum, ed. Societas Goerresiana (Freiburg: B. Herder, 1911), 332-36. Hereafter, CT; all references are to volume 5. The translations are mine. For a thorough treatment, see Alister E. McGrath, Iustitia Dei: A History of the Christian Doctrine ofJustification (2d ed.; Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 250-72. See also P. Pas, "La doctrine de la double justice au Concile de Trente" Ephemerides theologicae Lovaniensis 30 (1954): 5-53; Carl E. Maxcey, "Double Justice, Diego Laynez, and the Council of Trent," Church History 48 (1979): 269-78. For more background on Trent, see Hubert Jedin, Die erste Trienter Tagungsperiode (1545-47), vol. 2, Geschichte des Konzils von Trient (Freiburg: Herder, 1957), 139-268. 22 See Hans Kung, Rechtfertigung: Die Lehre Karl Barths und eine Katholische Besinnung (Einsiedeln: Johannes Verlag, 1957), 217. See also McGrath, Iustitia, 246. JUSTIFYINGGRACE IN THE JOINI' DECLARATION 101 exclude a prior imputation, but only to accentuate the perpetual inadequacy of inhering grace. 23 The council fathers criticized double justice for its novelty, but its subtlety instigated lengthy discussions and many revisions before a precise condemnation could be formulated. The first draft of the Decree on justification (24 July 1546) rejects only an exclusively forensic conception of justification. 24 The next two drafts, penned by Seripando, explicitly propose his theory. Justifying grace is "in addition to the most pure and most perfect justice of Christ ... , [also] the grace and charity poured into the hearts of those who are justified.... " A corresponding canon leaves room for double justice.25 The first decisive response to this theory appears in the 23 September draft, which reads: So there are not two justices which are given to us, that of God and that of Christ. There is one justice of God through Jesus Christ (this is charity itself or grace), by which we are not merely considered, but truly are named and are just.26 The phrase "not two justices . . . [but] one" was directed at Seripando's expressions. 27 Still, debates continued as the fathers strove for precision. 28 While one could truly say that a man is justified both by Christ's righteousness and by inhering righteousness, causal distinctions needed to be made. Christ alone merited redemption and God alone justifies. Yet the key issue was not the sinner's absolute need for Christ's merits and God's mercy 23 See CT 225 :25-26, 39-41; 335: 14-16; 824:4-8. According to Seripando, even our first. movements toward God arise only because of God's prevenient grace. 24 CT 386:25-26 and 34-36. 25 "Praeter purissimam illam et integerrimam Christi servatoris et capitis nostri iustitiam ... gratia seu caritas diffunditur in cordibus eorum, qui iustificantur per Spiritum Sanctum, qui datur eis" (CT 829:41-45). For the canon, see CT 832:27-32. 26 "lta non sunt duae iustitiae, quae nobis dantur, Dei et Christi, sed una iustitia Dei per Iesum Christum, (hoc est caritas ipsa vel gratia), qua iustificati non modo reputamur, sed vere iusti nominamur et sumus" (CT 423:34-36). 27 CT 505:26-27. See also the alternate form of the canons, which comes closer to excluding double justice (CT 428-430, esp. 429:9-11). 28 See, e.g., CT 550:37-40; 615:9-14. 102 CHRISTOPHER}. MALLOY but the identity of the reality by which a man stands just before God. The 31 October draft, therefore, introduced a precision in technical terminology: "The formal cause is the one justice of God." 29 Claude Le Jay later suggested that the "one" in "the one justice of God" should modify "formal cause." The council fathers followed Le Jay's suggestion 30 and even changed "una" (one) to "unica" (one and only) on 11 December: Finally, the one and only formal cause is that justice of God, not by which He Himself is just, but by which He makes us just in His sight. This justice is given by God, and by it we are renewed in the spirit of our minds. We are not merely considered but are named and truly are just, each one of us receiving his own justice according to the measure that the Holy Spirit wills to impart to each and according to the distinct dispositions and cooperation of each. 31 This passage, retained practically word for word in chapter 7 of the final decree, makes it unequivocally clear that the single formal cause of justification is created, supernatural justice. Canon 10 of the final decree condemns the errors opposed to this definition in chapter 7. 32 It reads, "If anyone says that men are justified without the justice of Christ by which he merited [our justification] or that they are formally just by that very justice: let him be anathema. " 33 Canon 10 maintains both that Christ is the meritorious cause of justification and also that He is not the formal cause. The initial formulation of this canon was a source of confusion because Christ's own righteousness is both the 29 "formalis iustitia una Dei" (CT 512:19-20). ° CT 700:25. For Le Jay's contribution, see CT 658:24-25 and McGrath, Iustitia, 264. 3 lI "Demum unica formalis causa est iustitia ilia Dei, non qua ipse iustus est, sed qua nos coram ipso iustos facit, qua videlicet ab eo donati renovamur spiritu mentis nostrae, et non modo reputamur, sed vere iusti nominamur et sumus, iustitiam in nobis recipientes unusquisque suam, secundum mensuram, quam Spiritus sanctus partitur singulis prout vult, et secundum propriam cuiusque dispositionem et cooperationem" (CT 700:25-32). 31 See CT 687:3-4 for the question to which it responds. u "Si quis dixerit, homines sine Christi iustitia, per quam nobis meruit, iustificari, aut per eam ipsam forrnaliter iustos esse: anathema sit," Decrees of the Ecumenical Councils, vol. 2, Trent to Vatican II, ed. Norman P. Tanner, S.J. (Washington: Georgetown University Press, 1990), 679:3.5-36 (emphasis added). Hereafter, DE; all translations are mine. For discussion of this canon, see CT 691:5-6; 714; 718:9-12, 25-42; 719:8-9, 14-20; 720:23-25, 50-51; 722:37-43; 759:39-44; and 760:1-21. JUSTIFYING GRACE IN THE JOINI' DECLARATION 103 exemplar and meritorious cause of justifying righteousness. The following statement, added to chapter 16 in discussions related to canon 10, resolves that confusion and further emphasizes the inhering nature of justifying grace: "[This justice] is called ours because we are justified by it inhering in us; it is that same justice of God because it is infused into us by God through the merits of Christ. " 34 Christ is neither the sole formal cause (as per Lutheranism) nor one of two formal causes (as per double justice). The formal cause is none other than inhering grace. Christ and the Trinity indeed dwell within the just through sanctifying grace, but this indwelling must be seen, not as a change in God, but as a man's new relation, worked by this grace, to God. Many scholars do not attend to canon 10 but focus on canon 11. They claim that the latter does not touch the essence of Lutheran doctrine because, as Seripando's contribution, canon 11 condemns only an exclusively forensic notion of justification.35 But it could be argued that canon 11, which includes renewal in the definition of justification proper, also condemns those Lutheran formulations that exclude sanctification from justification itself, while acknowledging a logically subsequent sanctification. The Fomzula, for example, rejects expressions 34 "Quae enim iustitia nostra dicitur, quia per earn nobis inhaerentem iustificamur, ilia eadem Dei est, quia a Deo nobis infunditur per Christi meritum" (CT 758:28-29, 31-33). This refinement of an earlier draft (CT 710:15-16) obviously relates to canon 10 (see CT 759:39-760: 21). 3·1 McGrath attends not to canon 10, but only to canon 11; see Iustitia, 272. Also, Lehmann and Pannenberg, eds., Condemnations of the Reformation Era, 46-48, refers to the former only dismissingly, while focusing on canon 11. Otto Hermann Pesch considers the formulas in canons 10 and 11 not to touch the genuine substance of Lutheran doctrine. Different conceptual frameworks, tending to obscure an adequate reception of the other communion's positions, must be surmounted in order to evaluate the real significance of the apparent conflict. See Otto Hermann Pesch, The Canons of the Tridentine Decree on Justification: To Whom Did They Apply? To Whom Do They Apply Today?, in Justification l7y Faith, 183-85 and 194-95. Kiing likewise addresses only canon 11 and dismisses its relevance (Rechtfertigung, 215-16). Jaroslav Pelikan emends canon 10, claiming that it anathematizes "both the idea 'that men are justified without the righteousness of Christ, by which he merited for us,' and the teaching (attributed to Luther) that the righteousness of Christ alone could make them 'actually [formaliter] righteous'" (Reformation of Church and Dogma [1300-1700), vol. 4 of The Christian Tradition: A History of the Development of Doctrine [Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1984), 285; emphasis added). 104 CHRISTOPHERJ. MALLOY similar to Seripando's. 36 In any case, canon 10 and the definition of the formal cause in chapter 7, in proscribing double justice, highlight the contrast between Catholic and Lutheran doctrine. C) CatholicDoctrine In light of the preceding discussion, the four key points in which Catholic teaching diverges from Lutheranism should be expounded. First, the Catholic Church teaches that justification's singular formal cause is the grace which, infused by God on account of Christ's merits, sanctifies a man by inhering within him. 37 That is, the repentant sinner is justified precisely by an infusion of the grace or charity that constitutes justification, the culmination of the instantaneous process whereby "there is a transition from that state in which a man is born a son of the first Adam to the state of grace and of adoption of the sons of God, through the second Adam, Jesus Christ our Savior. "38 Second, forgiveness of sins-as one element of justification-is formally caused by infused, sanctifying grace. This grace, together with a man's hatred of past sins, expunges all mortal sin. The initial infusion of sanctifying grace marks the moment of justification, which includes not only the remission of sins, but also the sanctification and renewal of the inner man through the voluntary acceptance of grace and gifts. Thus, a man is made just from having been unjust and is made a friend from having been an enemy. 39 36 See Epitome 3:20-21 and Solid Declaration 3:49 and 50. Luther himself described a similar compromise at Regensburg in 1541 as a "scissors and paste job" (McGrath, Iustitia,· 247-48). 37 DE 673:26-32. 38 "sit translatio ab eo statu, in quo homo nascitur filius primi Adae, in statum gratiae et adoptionis filiorum Dei, per secundum Adam lesum Christum salvatorem nostrum" (DE 672:14-16). 39 "non est sola peccatorum remissio, sed et sanctificatio et renovatio interioris hominis per voluntariam susceptionem gratiae et donorum, unde homo ex iniusto fit iustus et ex inimico amicus" (DE 673:14-17). JUSTIFYING GRACE IN THE JOINT DECLARATION 105 This conciliar expression ("not only remission . . but also sanctification") should not be misunderstood as bifurcating the formal aspect of the process of justification into forensic and intrinsic elements (double justice). Such a reading would erroneously imply that the Catholic Church simply uses one term, justification, to signify two realities whose formal causes are distinct: forensic forgiveness and interior transformation. This is not so. Both forgiveness and transformation are elements of justification, which has a singular formal cause: inhering grace. The conciliar expression is directed against those who assert justification to be "only" forgiveness, thus defining forgiveness as formally forensic. Since justification consists in a translation from an evil state to a holy state, the justified man retains no damnable sins which might or might not be imputed. 40 Baptism, for example, so purifies men that they "are made innocent, spotless, pure, blameless and beloved sons of God. "41 What distinguishes forgiveness through infusion from the infusion of grace simpliciter is the guilty person's willful renunciation of past, damnable sins. Forgiveness is not possible without such renunciation: "For the attainment of grace and justice ... it has always been necessary that, together with the rejection of what is base and an emendation of so great an offense against God, sins be detested with a hatred and a tender sorrow of spirit. "42 Third, the Church teaches that one can be more and more justified through sanctification. 43 There can be such increase because justification and sanctification share the same formal cause. An increase in sanctification is, therefore, an increase in justification. The latter first occurs when God freely infuses sanctifying grace into the man who willingly and actively accepts it, aroused by God's special and prevenient help. Sanctifying grace remains in the just man as a stable disposition, dependent, See CT 700:25-32. immaculati, puri, innoxii ac Deo dilecti filii effecti sunt" (DE 667:6-7). 42 "ad gratiam et iustitiam assequendam necessaria ..• ut perversitate abiecta et emendata tantam Dei offensionem cum peccati odio et pio animi dolore detestarentur" (DE 703:22-25; see also 673:3 and 705:11-13. 43 See DE 675:2-7 and 673:26-27. 40 41 "innocentes, CHRISTOPHERJ. MALLOY 106 like any creature, upon God's creative power. Endowed with justifying grace, a man can merit its increase through good works. Fourth, with God's help, the just man can merit an attainment and an increase of eternal life, provided he does not obstruct the continual influx of this grace by committing mortal sin.44 This fourth point provides an eschatological perspective from which the fittingness of the Catholic teaching can be more readily discerned. Mortal sin entails a habitual, willful disorder that per se ruptures a man's friendship with God. As a beatific communion of friends, heavenly life is in part constituted by the saint's supernatural love of God. Since God never changes, the movement from sin to salvation must consist formally in created changes, all of which achieve their end by uniting the human spirit to God. Paradise is not a return to the flesh-pots of Egypt, juridical admission to which could be granted to sinners and saints alike. Instead, paradise is a nuptial bliss which of its nature demands self-giving love. Justification, the key to paradise, establishes the conditions that render heavenly life possible and that determine the significance of earthly life as a preparation. Granted, the sinner cannot attract God to himself; hence, God can only mercifully or "extrinsically" decide to remit sin. But the absolution itself consists in the eradication of the offense. If, on the contrary, justification were to consist formally in the attribution of justice, the just man would die God's mortal enemy, only partly lovable in that he is only partly purged of sin. In what sense, then, could he be saved? In what sense could he-a hostile sinner-enjoy God's nuptial friendship? If, as is hypothetically possible, he could be suddenly purified of his enmity with God after death, of what dramatic relevance would his earthly life be?45 In any case, Catholics believe that God has not chosen this possibility, for those who die without charity stand condemned, and charity cannot coexist with damnable sin.46 DE 681:22-24. Cf. Epitome 4:15. See "Annex," 2-E; Solid Declaration3:32; and Greater Catechism 2.3:57-59, in The Book of Concord. Cf. William of Ockham, Quodlibet VI, 4.1: 26-33 in Opera theologica9 44 45 {St. Bonaventure, N.Y.: Saint Bonaventure University, 1980). 46 DS1970. JUSTIFYING GRACE IN THE JOINT DECLARATION 107 Catholic and Lutheran doctrines indeed conflict on more than one of the basic truths of justification. But attention must now be turned to the joint Declaration itself. II. ANALYSIS OF THE JOINT DECLARATION Although the JD emphasizes renewal and merit more than do many of the Lutheran confessional documents, its common and Lutheran sections nevertheless imply a problematic distinction between the formal cause of forgiveness-justifying grace-and that of sanctification. The names employed vary-justification and sanctification, forgiveness and renewal, complete righteousness and good works, etc.-but the realities signified are usually the same: forensic forgiveness of sins and the incipient renewal of life. For the sake of clarity, I will use the first pair of terms to refer to these two aspects of redemption, thus distinguished. A) Basic Problem with Common and Lutheran Sections: justifying Grace as God's Favor The validity of the JD depends upon the sense in which it reads the following Pauline statement: "Justification thus means that Christ himself is our righteousness, in which we share through the Holy Spirit in accord with the will of the Father" (JD 15). The precise question at stake is the following: in what way is Christ Himself our righteousness? If He is understood as the meritorious basis for justification or as the exemplar on which infused righteousness depends, then the JD is harmonious with Catholic dogma. If, however, His righteousness is understood as that by which the sinner stands just before God, then the JD contradicts a substantial piece of Catholic faith. The ]D's common and Lutheran sections offer much evidence that they hold the latter to be the case. The following passage distinguishes two aspects of God's act of forgiveness and renewal: When persons come by faith to share in Christ, God no longer imputes to them their sin and through the Holy Spirit effects in them an active love. These two 108 CHRISTOPHERJ. MALLOY aspects of God's gracious action are not to be separated, for persons are by faith united with Christ, who in his person is our righteousness. CJD 22} Forgiveness and renewal are, the JD elsewhere repeats, granted simultaneously. But declaring the simultaneity of these two aspects is not tantamount to affirming their unity in a singular formal cause. It must be determined, then, whether or not the nature of the distinction of these two aspects of God's act is indicative of two really distinct formal causes, one of which is justifying righteousness and the other of which is inhering, sanctifying righteousness. The following text points more directly toward this distinction: In the doctrine of "justification by faith alone," a distinction but not a separation is made between justification itself and the renewal of one's way of life that necessarily follows from justification and without which faith does not exist. CJD 26} A distinction between inhering righteousness and justifying grace entails that the latter consists in (or at least formally includes) Christ's own righteousness. The above citation from paragraph 22 suggests as much: "Christ, who in his person is our righteousness." Whether interpreted as referring to Christ's indwelling presence through faith (Finnish school) or forensically imputed righteousness, this statement inhibits one from naming sanctifying grace as the single formal cause of justification. A key passage, to which the sources cited for section 4.2 refer, baldly affirms Christ's own righteousness, imputed to faith, as that by which a man stands just: Uustification is] a single, total (though continually new} divine act: [consisting] in the forgiving pardon, in the non-imputation of sin, in the imputation of the righteousness of Christ-all of which are words for the same thing, namely, that the human person is again standing in a proper relationship to God. 47 This line of thought leads one, inexorably, to hold that sins are forgiven, not by being destroyed, but by being "no longer 47 Lehmann and Pannenberg, eds., Condemnations of the Reformation Era, 47. JUSTIFYING GRACE IN THE JOINT DECLARATION 109 imputed." Instead of one's own sins, it is Christ's righteousness that is attributed to the sinner. Paragraph 23 explains the imputation language of paragraph 22 as follows: When Lutherans emphasize that the righteousness of Christ is our righteousness, their intention is above all to insist that the sinner is granted righteousness before God in Christ through the declaration of forgiveness and that only in union with Christ is one's life renewed. When they stress that God's grace is forgiving love ("the favor of God" [WA 8:106; American ed., 32:227 ]), they do not thereby deny the renewal of the Christian's life. They intend rather to express that justification remains free from human cooperation and is not dependent on the life-renewing effects of grace in human beings. (Emphasis added) For Catholics, justifying grace consists in the infused grace or charity by which all damnable sins are expelled. In traditional Lutheranism, justifying grace is God's forgiving decision no longer to take such still-extant sins into account. This citation from the JD is faithful to the traditional Lutheran position. Forgiving or justifying grace, of whose effects justification is independent, is not sanctifying grace but God's extrinsic favor. This interpretation of paragraph 23 is confirmed by its citation of Luther's Confutation of Latomus. Luther denies therein that infused gifts expel all damnable sin and affirms that God's extrinsic grace in Christ is that by which a man stands just. Can it be maintained, then, that the ]D's Lutheran and common sections comport with Catholic teaching? Do they not, rather, teach that men are just by Christ's righteousness itself (JD 15, 22, 23, and 29)? B) ConsequentManifestationsof This Basic Problem The affirmation that Christ is the sinner's righteousness is correlative with other problematic notions. These include the coexistence of damnable sin and infused grace, the impossibility of an increase in justifying grace, and the exclusion of eternal life from the proper scope of meritorious works. The appearance of 110 CHRISTOPHER J. MALLOY these correlative notions would confirm my fundamental critique of the JD. 1. Simultaneously Just and Sinner If damnable sin can exist within a "justified" man, the formal cause of justification cannot be simply sanctifying grace but must be (or at least include) something extrinsic, such as the imputed righteousness of Christ. Paragraph 29 asserts the antecedent and thus implies the consequent: Looking at themselves through the law, however, they recognize that they remain also totally sinners. Sin still lives in them (1Jn.1:8; Rom. 7:17, 20), for they repeatedly turn to false gods and do not love God with that undivided love which God requires as their Creator (Dt. 6:5; Mt. 22:36-40 pr.). This contradiction to God is as such truly sin. Nevertheless, the enslaving power of sin is broken .... It no longer is a sin that "rules" the Christian for it is itself "ruled" by Christ with whom the justified are bound in faith .... Despite sin, the Christian is no longer separated from God, because in the daily return to baptism, the person who has been born anew by baptism and the Holy Spirit has this sin forgiven. Thus this sin no longer brings damnation and eternal death [cf. Apology 2:38-45; Book of Concord, 105£.]. The justified are "totally sinners" in themselves because there lives within them sin which, of its nature, can bring damnation and eternal death. The most troubling element in this passage is the damnable nature of the sin that remains. A passage noted in sources cited for section 4.4 also affirms that concupiscence is in itself damnable, although not damning: "In Lutheran phraseology, [concupiscence] is peccatum regnatum, 'controlled sin,' which is only damnable hypothetically, as it were-that is, only if God were not to forgive. "48 To maintain that still-extant, damnable sin is not mortal in its effect one must understand justification as the nonimputation of sin and the imputation of Christ's righteousness. The following sentences from paragraph 29 should be interpreted accordingly: "Believers are totally righteous in that God forgives their sins through word and sacrament and grants the righteousness of 48 Lehmann and Pannenberg, eds., Condemnations of the Reformation Era, 46. JUSTIFYING GRACE IN THE JOINT DECLARATION 111 Christ, which they appropriate in faith. In Christ, they are made just before God." The section in the Apology referred to in paragraph 29 ratifies this interpretation: "For [the fathers and Paul] clearly call lust sin, by nature worthy of death if it is not forgiven, though it is not imputed to those who are in Christ. " 49 Paragraph 2-B of the "Annex" does not resolve this problem, defining voluntary sin as follows: "Sin has a personal character and as such leads to separation from God. It is the selfish desire of the old person and the lack of trust and love toward God." In the same paragraph, the Lutherans define concupiscence as "the self-seeking desire of the human being, which in light of the law, spiritually understood, is regarded as sin." The elements of the "Annex"'s definition of voluntary sin-selfish desire and lack of love-are indistinguishable from those of the Lutheran conception of concupiscence-selfish desire, lack of love, and repeated idolatry. The textual evidence indicates that Lutherans still maintain the truly sinful and damnable nature of concupiscence. The Catholic Church recognizes the existence of venial sins and concupiscence within the justified person. Yet she dearly describes concupiscence as merely a tendency towards sin which deserves no punishment whatsoever. 50 Moreover, the Church teaches that venial sins can coexist with justifying grace not because they are "not imputed" but because sanctifying grace remains, although its effects are hindered in ways that do not render men interiorly unjust. 51 Just as with human friendships, everyday slights do not destroy the relationship of love. When God forgives mortal or venial sins He does so not by ignoring them but precisely by washing them away. 52 2. Growth in Grace Infused, sanctifying grace can always increase since it is a spiritual, creaturely perfection of the human person. As Apology 2:40. so See DE 680:38-41. Cf. WA, 2:584.39-585.1. SI DE 675:22-23. sz See DE 667:9-11. 49 CHRISTOPHERJ. MALLOY 112 something created, it can always increase. As a spiritual perfection, its increase does not destroy its bearer's nature. If, therefore, justifying righteousness cannot increase, then the formal cause of justification cannot be sanctifying grace. Paragraph 39 accepts the antecedent and thus implies the consequent: Righteousness as acceptance by God and sharing in the righteousness of Christ is always complete. At the same time •.. there can be growth in its effects in Christian living ... [which are] the fruits and signs of justification. l]D 39) According to this paragraph, justification is God's acceptance of the sinner who shares in Christ's own righteousness precisely through faith. Since this acceptance and sharing are always complete, they consist formally not in infused grace but in something extrinsic, either attributed to, or ecstatically grasped by, faith. Important source dialogues share this conception. A work cited in the sources for section 4. 7 reads: If righteousness [iustitia] in Canon 24 is understood in the sense that it [a]ffects human beings, then it does not apply to us. But if righteousness in Canon 24 refers to the Christian's acceptance by God, it applies to us; because this righteousness is always perfect; compared with it the works of Christians are only "fruits and signs." 53 This passage acknowledges a growth in the sanctifying effects of God's eternal love, but clearly distinguishes this from the righteousness by which a man is accepted as just before God. 53 From "Comments of the Joint Committee of the United Evangelical Lutheran Church of Germany and the Lutheran World Federation German National Committee regarding the document The Condemnations of the Reformation Era: Do They Still Divide," in Lehrverurteilungen im Gespriich (Gottingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1993), 94:2-14. Canon 24 reads: "If anyone says, that the justice received is neither conserved nor increased in the presence of God through good works, but that the works themselves are only fruits and signs of the justification received and not also a cause of its increase: let him be anathema" ("Si quis dixerit, iustitiam acceptam non conservari atque etiam non augeri coram Deo per bona opera, sed opera ipsa fructus solummodo et signa esse iustificationis adeptae, non etiam ipsius augendae causam: a. s.") (DE 680:35-37). JUSTIFYING GRACE IN THE JOINT DECLARATION 113 Similarly, in the American dialogue, Lutherans "describe justification as the imputation to sinners of a righteousness which is that of Christ himself (iustitiaaliena). ... Lutherans also affirm the reality of sanctification and good works, but they regard these effects as fruits rather than parts of justification itself."54 Christ's righteousness is regarded as the formal cause of justification. 3. Cooperation and Merit The elect who are admitted into eternal life consist solely in those who die justified, since justifying righteousness is the key that opens paradise to each man. If this righteousness is formally caused by sanctifying grace, the man who dies in grace can be worthy, not of damnation, but only of eternal life, a post-mortem purification of venial sins notwithstanding. If, however, the man who dies "justified" is worthy of damnation but receives eternal life simply because of his faith in the promise, his justifying righteousness must be extrinsic, even if it is accompanied by an incipient renewal. The ]D's Lutheran sections accept the antecedent and thus imply the consequent: "[Lutherans also understand] eternal life ... as an unmerited 'reward' in the sense of the fulfillment of God's promise to the believer" (ID 39). As a Reformation idiom, "promise" is tied exclusively to faith that, in accepting the promise, has saving power apart from obedience to the commandments. 55 Thus, although damnable sin remains within him, the justified man is promised salvation through faith. A Lutheran preparatory document, cited in the sources for section 4.7, states, "We grant that eternal life is a reward because it is something that is owed-not because of our merits but because of the promise."56 This statement is taken from Apology4:362, a paragraph located in the midst of a discourse in which the reward of eternal life is unequivocally excluded from works, even those based upon s• Anderson, Murphy, and Burgess, eds., Lutherans and Catholics in Dialogue, par. 98, referred to in the sources cited for section 4.2. ss See below, pp. 118-19. See also Apology 4:113. s6 "Comments of the Joint Committee," 94 (emphasis added). CHRISTOPHERJ. MALLOY 114 infused grace. The Apology connects eternal life exclusively with faith and forensic justification, although it affirms that "good works merit other rewards, both bodily and spiritual, in various degrees. "57 According to the textual evidence, Lutherans still do not admit what Catholics confess: that the justified truly merit eternal life. The "Annex" does not correct this problem. Paragraph 2-E offers a notably inadequate statement: "In the final judgment, the justified will be judged also on their works" (emphasis added). This claim, while not contrary to Catholic faith, remains open to the Apology's deficient notion of merit. A few sentences later, paragraph 2-E confirms the traditional Lutheran view of merit by citing Solid Declaration4:38 as an authority on cooperation: "It is God's will and express command that believers should do good works." This passage concludes a section that rejects both Catholic and "Epicurean" theories of salvation. 58 The latter led to a denial of the importance of works. But the rejection of this Epicurean delusion does not imply an affirmation of Catholic truth. On the contrary, the Solid Declaration takes great pains also to reject the Catholic notion of meritorious works, as betrayed in the following: "[Paul] attributes to faith alone the beginning, the middle and the end of everything .... It is evident from the Word of God that faith is the proper and the only means whereby righteousness and salvation are not only received but also preserved by God. "59 C) Inadequacyof the Catholic Sections The Catholic sections of the JD contain many distinctively Tridentine expressions and are not explicitly problematic. Still, they suffer from some deficiencies. Two can be mentioned here. 57 Apology 4:366 (emphasis added). The term "Epicurean," as used in Lutheran confessional documents, refers to certain enthusiasts for whom good works were seen not only as unnecessary for salvation but even as a positive hindrance thereto. 59 Solid Declaration4:34-35; see also 3:53. 58 JUSTIFYING GRACE IN THE JOINT DECLARATION 115 First, the description of the effects of baptismal grace in paragraph 30 does not fully express the Catholic faith. Whereas the JD rightly declares that the sin that is "worthy of death" is destroyed in baptism, Catholic faith holds, further, that all venial sins are destroyed. Unfortunately, there seems to be no real discussion of the distinction between mortal and venial sins, which distinction indeed hinges upon the presence or absence of inhering grace. Correlatively, it is an understatement to affirm that concupiscence "does not merit the punishment of eternal death" (par. 30). It merits no punishment whatsoever. It should be noted, however, that the two references to DS 1515, notes 16 and 17, can guide the reader to a more adequate interpretation. Second, there is no unambiguous definition of the formal cause of justification. This omission is notably problematic. However, one might attempt to detect the claim that justifying grace is inhering grace in the following key passage: When Catholics emphasize the renewal of the interior person through the reception of grace imparted as a gift to the believer [cf. DS 1528], they wish to insist that God's forgiving grace always brings with it a gift of new life, which in the Holy Spirit becomes effective in active love. (/D 24) As noted above the JD usually presents a merely twofold distinction between justifying grace (God's mercy in Christ) and sanctifying grace (renewal). The above passage could be read as introducing a more precise threefold distinction: God's mercy (called "justification" by Lutherans and "efficient and meritorious cause" by Catholics), imparted or infused grace (called "formal cause" by Catholics but often unexpressed by Lutherans), and renewal of life (called "fruits" by Lutherans and "good works" by Catholics). Accordingly, the ]D's descriptions of justification as distinct from the sanctifying effects of God's love could be seen as affirmations of meritorious and efficient causality. The term signify good usually paired with justification-renewal-would works. A hidden, third factor would then lie between these: imparted or justifying grace. This grace, understood as inhering righteousness, could be seen as the formal cause of justification. 116 CHRISTOPHERJ. MALLOY There is contextual support for this interpretation. The note attached to this passage (DS 1528) and another note in a parallel passage from paragraph 27 (DS 1530) refer respectively to the paragraphs in Trent that precede and follow the definition of the formal cause (DS 1529). In addition, the first sentence of "Annex" paragraph 2-D might be read as an implicit description of the inhering quality of justifying grace: "Grace, as fellowship of the justified with God in faith, hope and love, is always received from the salvific and creative work of God." Such a reading would preserve Catholic doctrine, but it would conflict with official Lutheran teaching, perhaps giving cause for some Lutherans to urge the parties to delay signing the JD. On the other hand, a case can be made for a contrary reading, which may well be the sense in which the Lutheran signatories understand the text. The validity of the above exegesis depends upon the real meaning of "imparted grace." Only if imparted grace is identified with inhering righteousness can this exegesis stand. It is useful, in analyzing this text, to restate the passage more simply: When Catholics emphasize inner renewal through imparted grace, they insist God's forgiving grace brings new life. There are four terms in this statement: "inner renewal," "imparted grace," "God's forgiving grace," and "new life." Logically transposed, it reads as follows: A comes through B; that is, C brings D. So far so good. But "inner renewal" (A) and "new life" (D) are synonymous. 60 This raises a difficulty, as may be discerned through a further simplification: Renewal comes through imparted grace; that is God's forgiving grace brings renewal. 60 A parallel passage uses the term "renewal" twice: "While Catholic teaching emphasizes the renewalof life by justifying grace, this renewalin faith, hope and love is always dependent upon God's unfathomable grace" (JD 27; emphasis added). JUSTIFYING GRACE IN THE JOINT DECLARATION 117 A comes through B; that is, C brings A. From this latter statement, one could generate a sentence such as the following: "Tim 3rd comes through Tim Jr.; that is, Tim Sr. brings about Tim 3rd." This sentence is intelligible and, if understood correctly, true. Nevertheless, it is bizarre and not informative, for it leaves one wondering why the second term was introduced and what its relation is to the third term. The passage in paragraph 24 invites similar questions regarding its second and third terms: what is imparted grace and how is it related to forgiving grace? The one way to avoid these questions is to conflate the second and third terms. The latter, God's forgiving grace, is clearly the uncreated grace.61 A conflation of the terms, then, identifies imparted grace with God's mercy through Christ. Accordingly, the independent clause in the passage merely explicates the dependent clause: Though Catholics emphasize renewal through grace, what they mean is that this grace (i.e., God's forgiving grace) always has some effect on man. As such a reading makes dear, when imparted or justifying grace is conflated with God's mercy, the distinctively Catholic doctrine is obscured. In short, the citation from paragraph 24 can be rendered in three ways: as uniquely Catholic, as uninformative and awkward, or as uniquely Lutheran. The third alternative is the most plausible, in light of the common and Lutheran sections and in light of the ]D's rejection of a caricature of the Tridentine definition of the formal cause: "Thus justifying grace never becomes a human possession to which one could appeal over against God" (fD 27). 62 61 For further evidence, see JD 23 and 27, and Lehmann and Pannenberg, eds., Condemnations of the Reformation Era, 52, cited in the sources for section 4.3. 62 The same kind of caricature appears in a passage in the sources for section 4.2: "nor does [Catholic doctrine] maintain .•• grace as an objective 'possession' (even if a conferred possession) on the part of the human being-something over which he can dispose" (Lehmann and Pannenberg, eds., Condemnations of the Reformation Era, 49). 118 CHRISTOPHER J. MALLOY D) Possible Objections to This Critique Three objections, based on texts in the JD, might be mounted against my critique. They can be noted here with brief mention of the flaws associated with each objection. First, forensic forgiveness and interior renewal are connected by qualifying phrases, such as "without separation" (JD 22, 24, 26, and 27). However, these connectors, which astute Catholics have always perceived in Lutheranism, 63 are mere conjunctions that fail to achieve the requisite unity (viz., infused justice as the single formal cause). Second, justification and renewal "are joined in Christ who is present in faith" and who "in his person is our righteousness" (JD 26 and 22). Though such expressions maintain a unity between these two aspects of justification, they also imply that Christ's righteousness itself is that by which a man stands just before God-which, Trent teaches, cannot be the formal cause of justification. The third objection is the most weighty: justifying faith is said to include "hope in God and love for him" (JD 26), thus apparently linking this faith to the full panoply of inhering, sanctifying grace. 64 However, in both traditional Lutheranism and the JD the nature of this inclusion falls short of Trent's declaration: "Faith, unless hope be added to it, and also charity, neither perfectly unites one with Christ, nor makes one a living member of his body. " 65 Granted, Luther himself insisted that love always accompanies faith, but even as early as 1519 he admitted that this infused charity coexists with damnable sin. 66 Hence, faith's justifying power does not depend upon charity's capacity or incapacity to expel such sin (see Solid Declaration3:43). The JD itself explains the nature of faith's "inclusion" of love: "Such a faith is active in love" (par. 25). Traditional Lutheranism has always maintained this, while carefully distinguishing faith's Symbolik (Cologne: Jakob Hegner, 1958), 136-42. and Pannenberg, eds., Condemnations of the Reformation Era, 52. 65 "fides, nisi ad earn spes accedat et charitas, neque unit perfecte cum Christo, neque corporis eius vivum membrum efficit" (DE 673:38-40). 66 WA 2:584.7-9. See also, WA 40/11:79.31-80.21. 63 See, e.g., J. A. Mohler, 64 See also Lehmann JUSTIFYING GRACE IN THE ]OINI' DECLARATION 119 justifying power from the love by which it is active. The ]D's explanation invites no correction to this perspective, but instead employs strictly Lutheran expressions: "justification in faith alone" CJD 26) and the more emphatic "by faith alone" ("Annex," 2-C). One dialogue distinguishes faith's justifying power from the renewal that necessarily accompanies it. 67 Another reads: "if however Canon 20 affirms that faith has salvific power only on condition of keeping the commandments, this applies to us."68 Is it surprising that so eminent a theologian as Wolfhart Pannenberg could ascribe to Catholics a substantial modification of dogma: "The Catholic side no longer calls faith-as at the Council of Trent (DS 1532)-the mere 'beginning' of justification"? 69 CONCLUSION If, as I contend, traditional Lutheran doctrine and Catholic faith offer incompatible understandings of justifying grace, are there not a priori grounds to question the substantive nature of any reconciliation that truly evades the Reformation-era condemnations of both communions? Would not an unacknowledged disagreement about justifying grace, with all its consequent difficulties, render fundamental elements of the joint Declaration unstable? 70 But since the call to unity must issue in hope, some points whose discussion might foster a doctrinal rapprochement should be noted. First, the distinctions between sanctifying grace and virtue and between virtue and works resonate with the salutary Lutheran desire to emphasize the total person over individual deeds. Second, consideration of the participatory relation of 67 Lehmann and Pannenberg, eds., Condemnations of the Reformation Era, 50-52, cited in the sources for section 4.3. 68 "Comments of the Joint Committee," 89, cited in the sources for section 4.5. Cf. DE 680:24-25 and 685:36-37. 69 Wolfhart Pannenberg, "Theses to the 'Joint Declaration' about Justification," Pro &clesia 7 (1998): 136. Seen in light of his critique of Trent, the thrust of this statement can be discerned more easily (see above, p. 98). 7 For another critique, see Ansgar Santogrossi, "Un accord oecumenique en fauxsemblant," Catholica 66 (1999): 51-68. ° 120 CHRISTOPHERJ. MALLOY justifying grace to Christ's own righteousness should dispel a false dialectic between the Giver and the gift. The image, after all, strives of its very nature towards the Archetype. An existential approach, as long as it carefully avoided attributing damnable sin to the justified, could situate itself within the relationship of being from and being towards the Archetype. Third, inhering grace justifies, not as some object-less item in man, but as the power for relation to the Divine Friend-a kind of ecstatic fellowship. What Catholics insist is that this fellowship with Christ can subsist only with the love of charity, by which a man, who is ever loved by the Father, offers his whole being to the Trinity. Fourth, Catholics must emphasize the distinctions between formal, meritorious, and efficient causality: infused grace is only that by which (formal cause), not that on account of which (meritorious cause), God freely justifies (efficient cause) a man. In the end, the eschatological implications of justification highlight the intelligibility of the Catholic position. If heaven is an eternal espousal, should not justifying righteousness, which grants entrance to the wedding chamber, be the very holiness that God pours out upon His bride, cleansing her of sins, fitting her for nuptial bliss, and equipping her for the drama of earthly preparation? The Thomist 65 (2001): 121-36 THE SYMBOLIC THEOLOGY OF ROGER HAIGHT THOMAS WEINANDY,0.F.M.CAP. Greyfriars Oxford, England R oger Haight, S.J., of the Weston Jesuit School of Theology, in his approximately 5 00-page book, Jesus Symbol of God, 1 follows closely the conclusions first offered in his article "The Case for Spirit Christology. " 2 He has not substantially advanced his arguments, but he has expanded them and so has attempted to substantiate further his theological and Christological position. For this reason his book deserves a careful reading and a judicious assessment. 3 I. IN SEARCH OF A HERMENEUTIC Within each successive chapter of his book Haight cyclically advances a herrneneutical principle located in his understanding of the symbolic nature of religious knowledge and language. This, he argues, is not only in accord with postmodernity with its 1 New York: Or bis Books, 1999. 2 Theological Studies 53 (1992): 257-87. 3 I responded to Haight's article in "The Case for Spirit Christology: Some Reflections," The Thomist 59 (1995): 173-88. There I critically addressed his historical and systematic arguments and doctrinal conclusions. Because Haight has not substantially changed his thinking (nor taken account of my criticism), I will, for the most part, not address these same issues here. Thus, this present review article should be read in conjunction with my previous article. Here I will focus my analysis on Haight's understanding of symbolic religious knowledge and language and its ramifications, since these form the basis of his theological and Christological stance. It should also be noted that Haight has not addressed or even noted in his book J. Wright's critical but insightful article, "Roger Haight's Spirit Christology," Theological Studies 53 (1992): 729-35. 121 122 THOMAS WEINANDY,O.F.M.CAP. rightful emphasis on historical consciousness, but also the only means for making Christianity credible today. 4 God's transcendence necessitates, for Haight, that theological language be symbolic. As transcendent God is beyond the confines of this world and its history, and therefore he cannot be an object that is directly experienced and known. Human beings can only directly experience, know, and express as objectively factual that which exists within the this-worldly historical order. However, symbols and symbolic language provide an opening, Haight maintains, to the transcendent God, for "a symbol mediates awareness of something else" (8 ). More specifically "religious symbols . . . point to and mediate transcendent realities in response to religious questioning." For Haight the knowledge that is obtained through religious symbols "is not an attenuated form of cognition, but an extension of the range of human awareness," that is, it is not a different way of knowing from that of normal human knowing, but rather "symbols may be called engaged participatory knowledge. This means that it is the product of becoming conscious existentially and experientially of that which is mediated by the symbol." Haight draws two very critical "axioms" from this understanding of religious symbols, "which interact dialectically." The first is negative: "because theology is symbolic, its assertions are not direct statements of information about God. Information here connotes a kind of objectified datum that is asserted about God the way information about other things of this world are known." This is in accordance with 4 For Haight's understanding of postrnodernity see pp. 24-26 and 330-34. Historical consciousness, for Haight, is that contemporary intellectual mindset that founds scholarly assessment solely upon historical and factual data; thus he places all Christology under the normative eye and the final arbitration of contemporary "Jesus research" (see pp. 30-40). It also represents the intellectual posture that all scholarly analysis of past beliefs must be measured from within their relative historical and cultural settings and judged in the light of their current existing intellectual, educated, historical, and cultural surroundings. Moreover, all new theological proposals must harmonize with these same criteria. This accounts for Haight's uncritical partiality to what postmodernity, with its historical consciousness, will or will not tolerate and permit concerning Christian doctrine and religious belief. See pp. 21, 26, 39, 48-51, 120, 126, 217, 221-22, 237, 242, 249, 273-74, 278, 280-81, 290-97, 319, 331-35, 339, 342-45, 348-52, 364, 369, 384, 396, 404-5, 422, 431, 433-35, 439, 445, 447, 458,461,465-66,468,470,474,477-78,490. THE SYMBOLIC THEOLOGY OF ROGER HAIGHT 123 the transcendent nature of faith and revelation and thus "theology communicates no immediate information about God." The second axiom is positive: "the symbolic assertions of theology communicate through the engaged participatory experience which they invite and actively engender. The symbolic assertions of theology draw one into the mystery of the transcendent" (all above quotations are from p. 9). Haight holds that even though symbolic statements do not give us factual and objective knowledge of God, yet this "does not lessen their epistemological value," for they (and this is the dialectic) draw one into "a participatory encounter with its object ... the meaning and truth" of which "have to be found in the present-day experience of the community" (9-10). Haight summarizes his position as follows. The idea of a symbol is essentially tensive, dynamic, and dialectical; a symbol mediates something other than itself by drawing or leading beyond itself to a deeper or higher truth. By conceiving theology as a symbolic discipline and by consistently using the language of symbol, one is able to ensure respect for its elementary character. Symbols do not provide objective information about God; but symbols draw human consciousness and life into a deeper world of encounter with transcendent reality. This represents epistemologically a symbolic realism. (11; see 12). 5 II. A CLEAR HERMENEUTIC OF DENIAL The negative axiom concerning religious symbolic language allows Haight not only to deny the validity and truth of the central doctrines of Christianity as they have been defined and traditionally understood, but it also permits him to eradicate the premise upon which they were founded. To reduce religious knowledge to symbols that are generated from within the thisHaight distinguishes "concrete symbols" such as Jesus, who in his person and life "concretely" symbolizes God, and "conceptual symbols" such as scripture, which are the words or concepts that symbolically mediate a transcendent reality (see 13-14). He sometimes speaks of symbols as metaphorical, "metaphor" being a conceptual symbol. While he holds that "symbolic predication preserves the realism of the analogy of being" it only does so in the sense that the symbolic predication mediates the transcendent reality symbolized and not that one actually possesses objective and factual knowledge of the transcendent reality itself (see 11-13). 124 THOMAS WEINANDY,O.F.M.CAP. worldly order prohibits what has now come to be termed as an "interventionist" view of God acting, that is, God acting in time and history in a manner that is peculiar and singular to himself. Such divine action could not be accounted for solely by the laws of nature nor merely from within the created order, and traditionally was designated as "supernatural. "6 By employing his negative axiom Haight is able to deny that Scripture, and particularly the New Testament, provides any specific objective knowledge about the nature of God and of his actions. Scripture must not be read simply from within its original meaning, but must be read from within the confines of postmodernity where the prevailing hermeneutic is that of "symbol" (7). From a doctrinal perspective, Scripture is essentially a book of religious symbols, and thus the mere citation of Scripture, as testimony to past belief, by itself bears little weight for belief today; the dynamic process by which scriptural testimony can win authority is one of disclosure and elaboration, that is, symbolic mediation and argument. (12)7 Thus Haight can deny the traditional interpretation of the New Testament that gave rise to the defined doctrine of the Incarnation, and so deny the doctrine itself. The Fathers and even the early councils "used scripture in a way that implied that it communicated what amounted to representative knowledge about transcendent reality" (279; see 247, 261, and 270). They did not apprehend the symbolic nature of scriptural affirmations and so objectified the knowledge of God which led them, falsely, to 6 Haight explicitly disallows a "supernatural" or "interventionist" view of God acting (see 66 and434). 7 Scripture does, undoubtedly, employ symbolic language. It speaks symbolically, for example, of God's "Word" or "Wisdom," or "Spirit." Such language is not to be taken literally as if God had a mouth, or possesses wisdom in the same manner as humans, or acts precisely like the wind. Nonetheless, these scriptural metaphors were understood to articulate something that is objective and factual (and in this sense literal) about God. This Haight's understanding of religious symbolic language will not allow, for it is devoid of the authentic traditional understanding of the analogy of being whereby what is predicated of God actually corresponds, in an analogous manner, to something that is objectively true about God and his actions. THE SYMBOLIC THEOLOGY OF ROGER HAIGHT 125 hypostatize "the Son/Word" as a distinct "being" (Haight' sword), rather than recognize that such terms were symbolic personifications. More specifically Haight can deny that the Son of God is an eternal divine subject, equal to and one in being with the Father, who came to exist as a man. By not taking into account the symbolic nature of God's presence in Jesus, such a Christo logy "from above" is viewed today as "fantastic" and "anthropomorphic," for it "depicts a mythological fable" (273; see 177). 8 Equally Haight can deny the bodily resurrection of Jesus as it has been traditionally understood within the New Testament and articulated within classic theology. Neither the empty tomb, nor the bodily appearances, nor even the resurrection itself should be taken as historical objective fact, as has been done in the past, but must now be interpreted as symbols of Christ's new life within "the sphere of God" (see 119-51). 9 8 Haight interprets all interventionist views of God acting in a supernatural manner as mythological; see 177, 240, and 352. The reason for this is that, in accordance with his notion of religious symbolic knowledge, all theological knowing is initiated from within and confined to this world. Moreover, Haight insists that historical consciousness, as found within contemporary "Jesus research," demands that all Christology be "from below" (see 29-30). This requires for him that the historical Jesus not be a divine person but solely a human person (see 288-97). In his discussion of Christology "from above" and "from below" Haight makes a fundamental error. All Christology, even traditional Christology, begins epistemologically "from below." There is nowhere else to begin than from coming to know the historical human Jesus. Haight draws the false conclusion, though within his symbolic system it is the only conclusion he can draw, that this epistemology "from below" demands an ontology "from below," that is, that coming to know Jesus though his humanity demands that he ontologically only be a man. The New Testament and the Christo logical tradition it spawned, however, concluded that this man Jesus was none other than the eternal Son of God, and thus that this Son of God became man ('from above"). Epistemologically, Christology is always "from below." Ontologically, Christology is always "from above." 9 Because the symbol of the resurrection pertains to God's unknowable transcendent reality, Haight insists that the resurrection "is not an historical fact" (124). He is correct in that the resurrection was not brought about historically through human or natural causality. However, he conflates divine causality with historical effects. Jesus' resurrection may be regarded as an historical fact if one holds, which Haight does not, that God acted in such a manner that on a given day within history a man, who actually died, was glorious raised from the dead, and that one of the bits of evidence.is that on a given day his tomb was found empty. The cause of the resurrection may require an act of God who exists apart from time and history but the effect of such an act took place within time and history, and in this sense it is an historical fact. 126 THOMAS WEINANDY, O.F.M.CAP. Similarly Haight can deny a great portion of traditional soteriology, particularly the interpretation of Jesus' death on the cross as sacrificial, atoning or reparational, substitutionary, and reconciling. BecauseJesus' redemptive work on the cross was not, in the past, interpreted symbolically but understood literally, traditional soteriology became "bizarre, extravagant, and at times grotesque" (237). The language of "Jesus suffering for us, of being a sacrifice to God, of absorbing punishment for sin in our place, of being required to die to render satisfaction to God, hardly communicates meaningfully in our age" (241). Such a literalist and nonsymbolic use of language is offensive and even repulsive to "postmodern sensibility" (241). 10 Haight's negative axiom also authorizes him to deny that Jesus is the sole definitive revelation of God and the sole indispensable means of humankind's salvation, and so unique among the founders of religions. The early church and its subsequent tradition read the New Testament in a "literalist manner" that constituted a "lapse into a propositional view of revelation and fundamentalism" when asserting the uniqueness of Jesus and his work of salvation (404 ). Instead of rightfully conceding that Jesus is a symbol of what God has always been doing and continues to do throughout the whole of history and within all religions, the Christian tradition has falsely, and often arrogantly, insisted that Jesus be the unique definitive revelation of God and the sole and singular cause of humankind's salvation (see 395-423). 11 10 For a critique of Haight's own "revelational" and "exemplarist" view of salvation see my article cited in note 3. 11 Haight argues that while Jesus is normative for Christianity, God can also reveal himself normatively in other religions. Moreover, Jesus is not the universal cause of salvation, but merely reveals and exemplifies, within a Christian symbolic context, what God is doing always and everywhere, and thus within other religions as well (see 350 and 422). As to the different religious symbolic expressions "of ultimate reality, these are always generated historically through particular, individual, specific historical media. The attachment of all knowing to the sensible historical world accounts for the pluralism of religious experiences" (401; see 402). While Haight affirms a plurality of religions and the need to respect such plurality, what he has actually done, in confining "all religious knowing to the sensible historical world," is to relegate all religions to differing symbolic expressions of some one deeper and all encompassing philosophical truth. Thus all religions lose their integrity, for no deference is given to their own unique religious character and theological distinctiveness. THE SYMBOLICTHEOLOGYOF ROGER HAIGHT 127 Haight can similarly deny that the Holy Spirit is a distinct subject within the Trinity. As with the Son, the early church and the subsequent Christian tradition hypostatized the New Testament understanding of Spirit as if it possessed an objective knowledge of God's inner being. Rather, "the metaphorical symbol of God as Spirit expresses the experience of God's power and energy in creation .... God's Spirit is not so much a distinct agent of creation but the creative power itself of God" (448). Lastly, Haight can deny the entire doctrine of the Trinity as defined by the early councils and developed and taught within the Christian tradition, because they were again not sensitive to the symbolic nature of religious language. They falsely believed that they were actually speaking about how God truly exists, and were unaware that, because of God's transcendence, "such language, therefore, is not objectively representational, or immediately referential, or propositionally descriptive, or ostensive in its reference" (471). The one God is not then the ontological communion of three distinct subjects, the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit; rather, "Father/Mother," "Son/Word," and "Spirit" are symbols of God's immanence within the world (see 467-91). 12 I have delineated Haight's denials in some detail for if his use of his negative hermeneutical axiom concerning the symbolic nature of religious language is correct it strikes a death blow to Christianity as it has been proclaimed, understood, professed, and 12 Haight argues that his understanding of the Trinity is a form of modalism, though now properly and legitimately set within a symbolic context. This means that "God as Word" and "God as Spirit" are symbolic expressions of the manner in which God is experienced within the world (see 4 76-79, 488). Haight is correct that his conception of the Trinity does possess a modalistic flavor, but because he has placed it within a symbolic framework it is not modalistic at all. Traditional modalism had the one God actually acting in time and history under various modes. But Haight's God is not actually acting in time and history under various modes. The "modes" are merely our symbolic expressions of how we perceive God's presence and not how he is in fact acting. Moreover, for Haight, because religious symbolic language does not convey objective knowledge of God, "there is no logical connection that demands a correlation of an internal differentiation within God and God's actual selfcommunication to human existence" (488). The immanent expression of God, as humanly conceived symbolically, bears no correspondence to his transcendent reality. This would appear to be a major quandary within Haight's whole theological enterprise, and it will be examined shortly. 128 THOMAS WEINANDY, O.F.M.CAP. lived since its conception. So thorough is Haight's denial of traditional Christian doctrine that whatever he may propose as its replacement it will not be a fine-tuning or development of doctrine but a mutation into an entirely new and different religion. The meaning of the "Christian" words will now assume an utterly disparate definition. For Haight though such a mutation is not impossible or even undesirable. Since religious symbolic language does not lock one into objective or factual truth about God, it not only sanctions one to reinterpret religious symbols but also actively encourages one to create new symbols in a manner that best accords with the prevailing intellectual and cultural milieu. At this point I also want to make a more specific and substantive criticism. Haight believes that, in insisting that one cannot possess objective and factual knowledge of God, he is but protecting the very mystery of God's transcendence. He is merely preserving the venerable tradition concerning the apophatic character of theology, whereby God can never be fully comprehended. As seen above, those who formulated the classic doctrines of the Christian faith labored under the misconception that one could obtain factual and objective knowledge of God; in so doing they shattered the very mystery of God. "God is a mystery, doctrines are not" (480). Now God is indeed a mystery and all that pertains to him shares in that mystery, but the doctrines of the Christian faith, though considered to be true, were never thought to be comprehensive statements about God and his actions. The doctrines were definitions of what the mystery of God is and what he has done, and they were historically formulated precisely to protect the mystery of God from those who would make God and his revelation comprehensible. The conciliar doctrines concerning the persons of the Trinity state precisely what the mystery of the Trinity is and are not statements that make the Trinity comprehensible. The Chalcedonian definition that Jesus is the eternal Son of God existing as an authentic man is a statement that articulates the very mystery of the Incarnation. What it definitely does not do is make the mystery of the THE SYMBOLICTHEOLOGY OF ROGER HAIGHT 129 Incarnation comprehensible. Ironically, while Haight remains, throughout his book, scrupulously agnostic about the "mystery" of who God is, his symbolic understanding of "Christianity" becomes very comprehensible, for no longer do disconcerting and embarrassing mysteries loiter within his symbolic understanding of Jesus and the gospel. Ill. AN AMBIGUOUS HERMENEUTIC OF AFFIRMATION In tandem with his denials Haight presents his symbolic affirmation of the Christian gospel. He argues that his reconstruction is in conformity with Scripture and even with the Christian tradition if such are understood according to their proper intent and authentic purpose, that is, symbolically, though his symbolic interpretation may not concur with their actual former reading or belief. What is ultimately decisive in assessing Haight's book is not merely a critique of the specifics of what he wants to affirm about God, Jesus, salvation and Christianity's relationship with other religions, etc., but an evaluation of the premises upon which he wants to affirm such assertions. If the premises are flawed, then the affirmations become utterly problematic. It is these premises that I want now critically to examine. Haight is correct when he states that, since God is wholly transcendent and thus not a member of the this-worldly order, we cannot have any direct experience and knowledge of him. Because of this, as is evident from the above, Haight reduces all theological language to the symbolic. He insists that this symbolic language does not arise from a manner of knowing that differs in kind from all other human knowing. It arises out of "religious questioning," that is, from such human experiences as the presence of evil and death and the desire for happiness and wellbeing (see 192-93, 254-55). But from where do the answers for such questions come? At this point one encounters much ambiguity and even a dilemma within Haight's presentation. He consistently states, as seen above, that "religious symbols . . . point to and mediate transcendent realities." We become 130 THOMAS WEINANDY, O.F.M.CAP. "existentially and experientially" conscious "of that which is mediated by the symbol." Symbols "draw" and "lead" us to "deeper and higher truth." Religious symbols "draw human consciousness and life into a deeper world of encounter with transcendent reality" and so symbols allow us to be "engaged in participatory knowledge" with the transcendent object. As Haight states in his second positive axiom: "the symbolic assertions of theology communicate through the engaged participatory experience which they invite and actively engender." Notice that, for Haight, it is not the case that some religious experience of a transcendent reality gives rise to its being expressed in a symbolic manner. Rather, it is the religious symbol itself, such as Jesus, or the symbolic expression itself, such as Scripture, that "draws," "engenders," "leads," or "invites" one into a symbolic experience of the transcendent reality. As he states: "The world of religious symbolism, the world of language about God, is not one of facts and digital information; it is a world of religious experience; it is based on a narrative of a symbolic encounter with God in history" (472). Haight is not talking about a religious experience that is expressed symbolically, but is rather saying that "the religious experience" itself, the encounter with God, is symbolic for it is "based on a narrative of a symbolic encounter with God in history." The question and problem that now arises is: If religious symbolic language solely and completely emerges from within historical and cultural experiences of the this-worldly order, what founds the truth and validity of the symbol and its symbolic expression? Religious experience does not found the truth of the symbol because it is the symbol itself or its symbolic expression that gives rise to the symbolic experience. Even if one did allow an experience of something that transcended worldly historical reality, it would mean that one's experience and knowledge exceeded the normal manner of human knowing. Equally, one would then possess, in some sense, a factual or objective knowledge of the transcendent reality. Both of these possibilities Haight intentionally and repeatedly rejects. Moreover, the symbol THE SYMBOLICTHEOLOGY OF ROGER HAIGHT 131 and its symbolic expression cannot, obviously, be due to a specific "interventionist" action on the part of God within history and the world by which he reveals something about himself and so is responsible for its meaning. Haight's negative hermeneutic concerning symbolic knowledge is purposely designed to eliminate such a view. Thus within Haight's account there appears to be no epistemological connection between the symbol or the symbolic language and the transcendent reality that is meant to be experienced symbolically. For Haight the symbol arises exclusively from within the culture in which it was formed, or from within "the present-day experience of the community." In so arising it thus fosters a symbolic experience of "the transcendent" in keeping with that culture or community, but this merely informs one as to how a particular culture or community conceives and symbolically experiences the transcendent reality (God). It does not validate as true that cultural or communal religious symbol or symbolic experience. The symbol is purely the seemingly arbitrary conception of a particular culture or community within its historical setting-what it holds to be of transcendent value. Within a Christian culture it may be that God is symbolized as personal and loving. Within another religious culture God may be symbolized in a pantheistic manner. However, there is no way, within Haight's theory, for religious symbols and their symbolic expression to leap beyond their historical and cultural bounds from which they were engendered and so make contact with a transcendent reality that exceeds these bounds. Thus, while Haight wishes to hold a "symbolic realism," there is actually no realism to the symbol, for there is no authentic epistemological basis upon which this realism is founded. Its referent is not actually the "real" God, but only the real historical culture or community from which it arises. Moreover, while Haight continually argues that religious symbolic knowledge does put one in contact with transcendent reality, there is no basis for such a claim since one's symbolic religious knowledge arises out of and 132 THOMAS WEINANDY, O.F.M.CAP. is completely confined within the this-worldly order. 13 The truth of this objection is seen in Haight's own insistence that religious symbolic knowledge, by its very symbolic nature, is not an objective or factual knowledge of the transcendent reality. Thus Haight's book is fraught with ambiguity. On one level Haight makes numerous affirmations founded upon his understanding of symbol and symbolic language that give the impression that one is actually saying something that is meaningful, objective, factual, and true about God. For example, he constantly states that Christian religious symbolism "reveals," especially through Jesus, and so allows one to encounter a personal God who is loving, kind, compassionate, just, and forgiving (see 11318).14 Or, most importantly, he argues that Jesus is the Christian symbol of God, that is, in his concrete historical human personhood, he was "the parable of God" (112-13). 15 He not only symbolized what God is like, but through his words and actions manifested symbolically what God has always been doing and continues to do throughout the world to ensure humankind's salvation. This includes what God is salvifically doing within 13 In defence of his "symbolic realism" Haight argues that it would be erroneous to relegate his understanding of symbol to that of being "merely a symbol," "for a symbol as it is understood here truly reveals and makes present what it symbolizes" (197). Even if this were true, it would still mean that what is revealed and made present is only present in a symbolic manner, and not present as it actually is, and thus its presence would still be merely symbolic. 14 The term "revelation," for Haight, does not refer to some specific action of God, but arises out of a human engagement with the world and is "a form of human experience" whereby "God works within human subjects in a way that corresponds to the structure of human experience itself" (194). But the way "God works" which "corresponds to the structure of human experience" is not actually a work of God at all. Rather, revelation simply "occurs in human experience through symbolic mediation" (198-99), namely, through humanly manufactured symbols and symbolic language that are symbolically termed "revelation" and "the works of God." 15 Haight is very selective in his use of the New Testament. He limits his Christology almost entirely to the Synoptic Gospels, for the obvious reason that they seem to uphold more unmistakably Jesus' humanity with little or no reference to his possible divine status. Haight omits almost the whole of the Johannine literature (all references are by way of critique) and the Pauline corpus. There is no mention of any of the other New Testament documents. Moreover, while Haight emphasizes the plurality of New Testament Christologies (see 425-31), once these Christologies are filtered through his symbolic prism they lose their uniquely vibrant Christological hue and are all homogenized. THE SYMBOLIC THEOLOGY OF ROGER HAIGHr 133 other religions, though such religions may symbolize God's salvific action in a manner that is in conformity with its own historical and cultural milieu. He tirelessly argues that the religious symbol of "God as Spirit" is the symbolic expression of God's "work, as activity, and as power, energy or force that accomplishes something" (447). 16 "God as Spirit," for Haight, is thus the symbol of God's continual activity and power within the world since creation and is manifested in Jesus in a supreme manner. The symbol of the Spirit more forthrightly makes the claim that God, God's very self, acted in and through Jesus ... the symbol of God as Spirit is not a personification of God, but refers more directly to God so that it is clear from the beginning that nothing less than God was at work in Jesus .... This should also be construed as more than a thin functional or "adverbial" presence of God to Jesus, and truly an ontological presence, because where God acts, God is. In this empowerment christology Jesus is the reality of God. (451, 455) 17 At another level, one must always bear in mind that such and similar affirmations, despite the impression they may initially give, are not making objective or factual statements about the true nature of God and his manner of acting. They are but symbolic statements that draw one into symbolic experiences founded upon one's historical, religious, and cultural milieu, and have no objective reference to God and his actions at all. They are entirely culturally, historically, and religiously relative. 16 To speak of "God as Spirit" as "indicating God's work, as activity, and as power, energy or force that accomplishes something" is to mislead the reader at best, for such terms do not refer to the way God actually is and acts. Again, they are merely symbolic expressions arising out of a particular historical, religious culture that symbolically designate the symbolic presence of the transcendent. Their frame of reference is contained solely within the historical worldly order. 17 In "The Case for Spirit Christology," Haight speaks of God being "adverbially" present within Jesus. Within his book he strengthens his claim by saying that God is "ontologically" present in Jesus-though how we would know this, given that we are laboring within the constraints of symbolic knowledge, remains ambiguous at best. In any case, this ontology of "presence" is far removed from saying, as Nicaea and Chalcedon do, that, objectively and factually, Jesus is ontologically the eternal Son of God, one in being with the Father. For a full critique of Haight's interpretation of the councils and the validity of his "Spirit Christology," see my article cited in note 3. 134 THOMAS WEINANDY, O.F.M.CAP. In the end, as Haight would ultimately agree, despite all of his affirmations, we do not actually know God and thus we do not know whether or not God is actually "loving, kind, compassionate and forgiving," for such words do not convey any objective or factual knowledge of God. 18 While Haight wants us, through religious symbols and their linguistic expression, to be in touch with the incomprehensible transcendent reality of God, yet neither the symbols nor their expression allow us anything more than to be in touch with the mystery and transcendent reality that resides solely and exclusively within this cosmic order. Haight does argue that the epistemological connection is founded upon the Creator/creature relationship. "Among other things, the doctrine of creation out of nothing means that God is immediately present to all finite reality and thus to human beings" (392 n. 52). This Creator/creature relationship is the exclusive relationship upon which Haight founds his symbolic knowledge and language. All religious symbols, including Jesus and salvation, are but the various and diverse symbols through which the religious implications of this relationship are manifested. 19 Thus, the ontological Creator/creature relationship provides the epistemological window by which religious symbols, such as Jesus, and religious symbolic language, such as Scripture, acquire their meaning and validity. However, for Haight, while this relationship allows one to be led and drawn into the incomprehensible mystery of transcendent reality through these valid symbols and meaningful symbolic language, yet one never actually knows, objectively and factually, the transcendent reality itself. The obvious question remains, how is it possible for symbols to be valid and for symbolic language to be meaningful, if the 18 What Haight has in effect attempted to do in his symbolic reinterpretation of the gospel is to affirm such of its parts as that God is personal, loving, and kind. However, he would have no basis for affirming these, as the Scriptures make unmistakably evident, if God had not actually intervened in the world and so historically revealed that he is indeed a personal God who is kind and loving. 19 For the relationship between creation and salvation, see pp. 350-54; between creation and Christology and eschatology seep. 392 n. 52; and between creation and revelation and grace, seep. 453. THE SYMBOLICTHEOLOGY OF ROGER HAIGHT 135 symbols do not convey valid truth and the symbolic language does not articulate meaningful knowledge. In the light of the book as a whole, the above argument is nonetheless fascinating. Haight is adamant that all religious knowledge and language is symbolic, but here we now profess that God-the wholly mysterious, incomprehensible, and transcendent God-is indeed factually and objectively the Creator. The term "Creator" is not symbolic.20 Moreover, having ruled out of court an "interventionist" view of God acting within history and the world, we have here the literally primordial intervention. If there ever was a "supernatural" act, one that only God can perform and for which neither history, nor culture, nor the this-worldly order's causality can give account, since they exist not, it is the act of creatio ex nihilo. Here we see dearly the ambiguity and the dilemma within Haight's position. Religious symbols and their symbolic expression are entirely embedded within this world of history and culture, but he wants them nonetheless to have some ontological and so epistemological connection with transcendent reality, though not an epistemologically objective and factual connection. He calls into play the notion that God is Creator in order to establish such an ontological and so epistemological connection. However, if the term "Creator" becomes a symbol and if "creation out of nothing" becomes symbolic, which they rightly should be so as to conform to Haight's own premises, then the whole religious symbolic system becomes ensnared within this historical, cultural world order. Religious symbols, such as Jesus, and their symbolic expression, such as the sacred texts of all religions, merely provide symbolic knowledge of a transcendence that refers not to a wholly transcendent other called "God" but only to the "mystery" that lies completely within this cosmic order. Moreover, the term "God," for Haight, must now be construed symbolically as well, for it does not refer to an existing being distinct from the historical, cosmic order, but is merely the 20 On one occasion Haight does speak of "the symbol of creation," but that hardly accords with his notion of "creation out of nothing" (453). 136 THOMAS WEINANDY, O.F.M.CAP. symbolic expression of the "mystery" that lies within the historical, cosmic order. One wonders whether Haight himself is not unaware of this. When speaking more philosophically rather than theologically, he often seems to prefer the phrase "transcendent reality" over the term "God," for "God" implies a being distinct from the historical cosmic order, whereas "transcendent reality" does not necessarily do so. The reality that is transcendent could very well be within the historic cosmic order. If such be the case, then one would have, in Haight's account, a form of atheism that is merely couched in religious symbolism. IV. CONCLUSION I have not assessed to any great degree the specifics of Haight's theological program, having done so in my previous article. What I have done here is address what I consider to be the important issues and critical ramifications that ensue from Haight's philosophical and theological premises-his understanding of religious symbols, religious symbolic knowledge with its religious symbolic language and the religious symbolic experiences to which they give rise. Haight argues that a radical redefinition of Christianity is necessary in order to make it credible to the contemporary educated person of postmodernity, and he has offered his version of what that redefinition should be.21 It must be forthrightly acknowledged that Haight's reinterpretative enterprise is a form of philosophical and theological colonialism, for it does not arise from within the gospel itself but is the importation of a foreign hermeneutic. 21 While some have hailed Haight's book as theologically "innovative" and "pioneering," it is but one more example of a theological genre that goes back, at least, to the Enlightenment. Haight himself affiliates his Christological enterprise with that of Schleiermacher (see 304-9 and 445-46). Moreover, anyone who has kept abreast with contemporary Christology will recognize that Haight's book bears a striking resemblance to such books as The Myth of God Incarnate (ed. John Hick}, The Metaphor of God Incarnate Uohn Hick), The Humanity and Divinity of Jesus Uohn Knox), Jesus Christ in Modem Christian Thought Uohn Macquarrie), Christology Revisited Uohn Macquarrie), The Human Face of God U.A.T. Robinson), and many more contemporary works. BOOK REVIEWS Le thomisme et /es thomistes. By ROMANUSCESSARIO,O.P. Trans. Simone Wyn Griffith-Meister. Paris: Les Editions du Cerf, 1999. Pp. 125. 120 F. ISBN 2-204-06252-9 (paper). In this French translation of a book originally written in English, Fr. Romanus Cessario, O.P., provides a brief, but impressive, survey of the formation of Thomism and its development over the more than seven centuries since Aquinas's death. Relying on some of the most recent historical and critical work done over the past decade, Fr. Cessario's book is not aimed at making a contribution to be read by specialists, something that the volume on Jean Capreolus (Jean Capreolus en son temps [Paris, 1997]) by himself, Guy Bedouelle, and Kevin White already accomplishes. Rather the present work is aimed at giving the general reader a thumbnail sketch of the history of Thomism, which history is overlooked by Thomists more often than not. In this regard, Cessario's book is a marked success and should be extremely useful to those just beginning to take an interest in exploring the career of Thomism after 1274. The work is divided into two unequal parts: the first, entitled Le Thomisme, gives an overview of Aquinas's life and writings drawn from the extraordinarily fine historical scholarship of Jean-Pierre Torrell, O.P., and discusses the exclusion/inclusion criteria for identifying Thomists over the course of the centuries; the second, entitled Les Thomistes, recounts briefly the history of Thomistic thought from the thirteenth century to the twentieth century, emphasizing the relationship between Thomism and the wider context of European political and social history. In the first part, Cessario sketches out Aquinas's life, noting in the process that Aquinas's relationship to his predecessors may rightly be considered, as noted by Alasdair Macintyre, both a theoretical articulation of the rationality of tradition and a concrete living instance of the continuity of the rationality of tradition. Such a dear example of setting one's own thinking within a dearly defined and consciously recognized ongoing tradition is something that could 137 138 BOOK REVIEWS be well imitated, Cessario hints, by those claiming adherence to Aquinas's tenets. Among the works of outstanding importance for understanding Thomas's own Thomism are the two Summae as well as the Scriptum on the Sentences (20-21). Before launching into the history of Thomism, Cessario considers the various ways that the historians of Thomism have organized the school's history. The most common approach is to divide Thomism into first Thomism (roughly from the thirteenth to the fifteenth, though in some cases to the sixteenth, centuries), second Thomism (the Thomism of the later Spanish Scholastics and the Catholic Reformers), and neo-Thomism (the Thomism of the nineteenth and twentienth centuries). Since the precise points of chronological division are by no means agreed upon by the specialists who have written on the history of Thomism, Cessario elects to organize his treatment (46-53) not by neatly dividing the school's history into periods but by narrating the history of the school continuously and by relating the ebb and flow of the school's prominence to the general course of European history. As to the identity of those called Thomists, Cessario proposes, following Fr. James Weisheipl's classification, a distinction between Thomism in a broad sense and eclectic Thomism (26-27). The latter is characterized by the desire on a given thinker's part to include elements of a distinctively non-Thomistic philosophical or theological system within a framework inspired by, or dominated by, the teaching of St. Thomas. Eclectic Thomism would number among its members historical figures such as Molina, Vasquez, and Suarez, while some of its more recent representatives would include Marechal, Rabner, and Lonergan. In the main, Cessario focuses on narrating the history of the Thomism of the Thomists in the broad sense, though he does occasionally mention the more distinguished eclectic Thomists. The primitive origins of Thomism lie, according to the narrative developed in this book, in the debates of the 1270s and early 1280s concerning a cluster of doctrinal issues, chief among which was Thomas's doctrine of the unicity of substantial form. Among the earliest defenders of Aquinas are included such figures as Giles of Lessines and Peter of Conflans, the latter of whom explicitly called into question the reasoning of critics such as Robert Kilwardby-under whose aegis, as archbishop of Canterbury, Thomas's views on substantial forms were condemned at Oxford in 1277. The Thomistic school at Oxford, however, flourished despite the condemnation, resulting in the thought of such early English Thomists as Richard Knapwell, Robert Orford, and Thomas Sutton (62-63). Meanwhile, the French school of Thomism was developing under the leadership of such figures as Bernard de Trilla, Peter of Auvergne, BOOK REVIEWS 139 Bernard of Auvergne, Jean Quidort, and Hervaeus Natalis. As Cessario notes, these Thomists were often engaged in opposing the key theses of the leading Parisian theologian of the late thirteenth century, Henry of Ghent, whose work, notwithstanding their opposition, left marks on their manner of presentation and argumentation (67). Turning his attention to Italy and Germany, Cessario discusses such early Thomists of the Italian school as Romanos de Roma and John of Naples, while early figures of Germany included are Ioannes and Gerard of Sterngassen. Curiously enough, also mentioned as belonging to the early German Thomistic school, albeit as Thomists of the eclectic type, are figures such as Ulrich of Strasbourg, Dietrich of Frei burg, Berthold of Moosburg, and Meister Eckhart. Clearly Ulrich, Dietrich, and Berthold belong to the quite distinct school of Albertism, though, equally clearly, they exercised considerable independence of mind even in regard to Albert's teaching. As for Meister Eckhart, though he certainly borrows from Thomas and is in accord with him regarding many doctrinal points, his genius should probably, as Cessario hints, earn him a status all his own (72). The linkage between the figures of the late thirteenth and early fourteenth centuries within the Thomistic school and those of the fifteenth century, such as Capreolus, is provided by the thinkers associated with the Avignon Papacy. Prominent among such Thomists were those who functioned as advisors and experts to Pope John XXII during the Poverty Controversy: Armand de Bello Visu, Petrus de Palude, and especially William Peter Godinus. Godinus's unpublished Lectura Thomasina on the Sentences was doubtless one of the standard presentations of Thomistic thought until the advent of Capreolus and its publication remains one of the great desideratafor scholarship devoted to the history of fourteenth-century philosophy. Naturally, a place of pride is assigned to Jean Capreolus whose Defensiones marks a highpoint in late medieval Thomism (77-81 ), but some attention is also given to the little remembered Byzantine Thomism, which developed out of Greek translations of the Summa Theologiaeand Summa contra Gentiles (75). Cessario emphasizes the effect that the Black Death had upon European life during the late fourteenth century and the growth of humanism as a distinct intellectual current providing some of the setting for the work of Capreolus. Renaissance Thomism was something of a syncretic affair, often drawing upon the philosophical ideas of Aquinas but synthesizing those ideas with materials drawn from elsewhere. If Renaissance Thomism could be charged with unevenly appropriating some of Thomas's philosophical insights without any recognition or interest in the theological framework into which they were 140 BOOK REVIEWS meant to fit, the opposite point could be made, Cessario rightly remarks (9293), about Thomism during the Reformation. Thomism during this period became increasingly focused on the theology of grace and merit and less and less concerned to buttress the philosophical positions upon which much of the theology of the sacraments was based. The Thomism that flourished after the Council of Trent did return to philosophical speculation in such figures from the Iberian peninsula as Melchior Cano, Dominic de Soto, and Dominic Banes. But undoubtedly the most innovative and creative of the Thomists of this golden age of late Scholasticism was Jean Poinsot whose reflections on signs are probably the most enduring legacy of this period. The period of modern philosophy saw a decline in the number of Thomists and a tendency for their studies to remain confined to the area of moral theology. The outcome of this tendency was the gradual drift toward replacing Thomistic philosophy with Cartesian manuals in Catholic universities and seminaries. As Cessario remarks, elimination of such manuals and their replacement with genuinely Thomistic guides to philosophy was among the first acts of Leo XIII upon assuming the papal office (108). Cessario does not attempt to enter into the controversial history of Thomism in the twentieth century nor into its internecine conflicts. Rather he prefers to mention briefly some of its leading proponents in Europe such as Etienne Gilson, Jacques Maritain, M-D. Chenu, and R. Garrigou-Lagrange, while apropos of American Thomistic circles, he cites the River Forest School Thomists as a distinctive group with their characteristic emphasis on the importance of the study of natural philosophy for understanding Thomistic metaphysics and theology. On balance, the book is as accurate as such a brief survey and introduction could hope to be, compressing as it does some 700 years of doctrinal history into such a short space. Still, one might wish for a little more sophistication regarding the distinction between Thomists and non-Thomists. To account figures such as Ulrich of Strasbourg as Thomists seems to stretch the term "Thomist" beyond its proper bounds and to fail to recognize the legitimacy and independence of Albertism, a distinctive school of philosophical and theological thought both within and outside of the Dominican order. Of course, my quarrel here is not so much with Cessario's work as with the historians upon whom he depends and, in particular, their penchant for classifying later Dominican thought as Thomistic whether it genuinely is or is not. And, while the importance of non-Thomistic currents of Catholic thought is recognized by Cessario as at least that of alternative expressions of the philosophiaperennis (47-48), he could have placed greater emphasis upon the point that earnest BOOK REVIEWS 141 dialogue with such alternative expressions, especially ones that attempt to use philosophy with a view to engaging the problems of Catholic theology, is a steady feature of Thomistic thought through the centuries and one that Thomists would find to be worth emulating in the contemporary pluralistic context. TIMOTiiYB. NOONE The Catholic Univeristy of America Washington, D.C. Measure of a Different Greatness: The Intensive Infinite, 1250-1650. By ANNE ASHLEY DAVENPORT. Leiden: E.J. Brill, 1999. Pp. 435 ISBN 90-0411481-5 (cloth). The purpose of Anne Ashley Davenport's Measure of a Different Greatness: The Intensive Infinite, 1250-1650 is threefold: to analyze medieval texts pertaining to the concept of the intensive infinite; to identify the cultural and political factors that shaped the Scholastic discussion of this concept; and to explore the synergy between medieval spirituality and early modern science (xii). The book's title may be slightly misleading in that the study focuses on the concept of divine infinity and only peripherally considers the more general concept of intensive infinity. The study is encyclopedic in the range and variety of its material, if not always in the command of it. Extensive footnotes provide the subtexts of Davenport's commentary. In chapter 1, Davenport presents the sudden interest of such thirteenthcentury Catholics as Alexander Nequam and Robert Fishacre in the intensive infinite as a response to the dualism advocated by the Cathars to explain the existence of evil. Both men sought to combat the rational arguments of the Cathars, "to wield Reason in support of Catholic doctrine," so as to obtain a universal consensus in matters of faith which Scripture alone does not seem to provide (18). Davenport credits Nequam with having identified three important properties of divine infinity: that it cannot be increased, cannot be reached by finite means, and cannot be expressed in ordinary quantificational terms. Fishacre goes on to develop the notion in terms of "a state of maximal reduction that corresponds to universal relatedness" (40). Davenport credits Fishacre with capitalizing on Augustine's distinction between an extensive and 142 BOOK REVIEWS an intensive measure of greatness, quantitas molis and quantitas virtutis. She herself gives no independent consideration to the Augustinian, scriptural, and philosophical sources she alludes to in the chapter, although she acknowledges in a footnote that the whole Greco-Arabic Neoplatonic tradition must be taken into account to study the evolution and transmission of the concept of "spiritual quantity." Instead, for an introductory discussion of the infinite Davenport refers the reader several times to Bertrand Russell's Our Knowledge of the External World. Chapter 2 pits the Aristotelian scientific "theodicy" of Thomas Aquinas against the Augustinian/Anselmian mystical "theodicy" of Bonaventure. Why Davenport speaks of "theodicy" rather than "theology" is unclear. In any case, her contrast between the theodicies of Aquinas and Bonaventure is done in broad and unpersuasive strokes. She seems unaware of the twentieth-century studies on Aquinas's Neoplatonic heritage. Even though she states that all the Scholastics acknowledge that Aristotle restricted the sense of "infinite" to extensive quantity, she nevertheless attributes Aquinas's concept of intensive infinity to his commitment to Aristotelian natural science. The heart of her argument is quickly sketched in footnote 33 of page 60, in which she traces Aquinas's argument for God's infinity in question 7 of the Prima Pars back to his proof in question 2 for a First Mover. Davenport also attributes to Aquinas the position that natural investigation culminates with the discovery that God is infinite and therefore beyond human knowledge, leaving man dependent on Scripture and the magisterium's "cadres of professional exegetes" for positive quidditative knowledge of God (56). On the one hand, Davenport is apparently unaware that Thomas argues that no knowledge of God in this life can be quidditative, either natural or revealed. On the other hand, she attributes to Aquinas an "apophatic" doctrine that all natural knowledge of God is negative, apparently unaware of his polemic against Maimonides. She moreover ascribes to Aristotle the primacy that Thomas assigns to existence (64), and later in the book suggests that latent in Thomas was the intellectualist notion that intelligereis in fact prior to esse in God. In a word, a command of Thomistic sources is not in evidence here. Davenport argues that whereas Aquinas looks outward to cosmic phenomena to demonstrate the necessary existence of a first cause that is unrestricted being, Augustine turns inward to ascend by degrees to a necessary first truth that is spiritually infinite. "Augustine's spiritual theodicy, conducted as a private communion between the soul and its Creator, precludes discovering infinite Being without a conversion of the heart. In contrast, Thomas' supremely objective scientific theodicy inspires public consensus and BOOK REVIEWS 143 awe-precisely what is needed to maintain Peter's ship in the high sea" (69). Davenport argues that Bonaventure's discussion of divine infinity is distinguished from Aquinas's by two Augustinian features: first, that the human soul is constitutionally suited to find its rest only in infinite being; and second, that theological truth is not grasped when the mind is convinced, but rather when the will is moved, so that "Francis of Assisi, praying like Josaphat, 'in forests and solitary places,' grasped the truth of divine infinity better than professional theologians" (75). Davenport goes on to analyze Bonaventure's description in his ltinerarium of the Holy Spirit's mystical purgation and illumination of the soul that culminates in its "contuition" of God's infinite being. In notable contrast to her lyrical descriptions of Bonaventure's Franciscan mysticism is her quotation of the following passage from the ltinerarium: "Since non-being is the privation of being ... non-being cannot be grasped except through being, and if being in potency cannot be understood except through being in act, and if being signifies the pure act of being, then being is what first comes into the intellect and this being is what is pure act. But this being is not particular being, which is a limited being because mixed with potentiality; nor is it analogous being, for that has the least of act because it least exists. It remains that the being in question must be divine being" (82). With all due respect to St. Francis, this passage suggests a far greater debt to Greek metaphysics in general and to Aristotle in particular than to Christian scriptures or saints. In chapter 3, Davenport offers a close reading of Henry of Ghent's arguments for "infinite totality" as the supreme metaphysical description of God's quiddity and the supreme metaphysical reduction philosophy seeks but fails to achieve. Special divine illumination is necessary to grasp the infinity of God, completing natural knowledge with certainty rather than supplanting or invalidating it. Davenport offers in particular a translation of article 44 of Henry's De infinitate Dei followed by the Latin text. Moving on to Peter John Olivi's assault on Aristotle's "militant pagan theodicy," Davenport sees as the centerpiece of the "crisp 'user-friendly' theodicy" that Olivi offers a notion of superexcessive abstractions that positively exclude all imperfection through negations and rise above creatures to supreme superexcessivenss. Assimilating both Cathar and Provem;al motifs, Olivi finds in the concept of superexcessive being a way both to discredit the immutable divine nature of pagan philosophy and a means to convert the will to a Franciscan imitatio Christi: "Just as the mind, by quodam superexcessu intellectualis operationis rationally grasps the existence of God as summe abstractum and summe infinitum, so the will voluntarily pledges itself to the 144 BOOK REVIEWS practice of evangelical poverty, by a symmetric act of 'superexcessive' love" (237). Chapter 5 is devoted to John Duns Scotus. In his metaphysical proof for the intensive infinity of the divine essence, Scotus treats essential Being as a pure perfection and creatures as metaphysical quanta univocal with God (248). He proffers an Anselmian scheme in which a univocal intensive magnitude is increased continuously to an inaugmentably intense term. Scotus holds that the being that divides into finite and infinite before dividing into the ten categories is indeterminate and susceptible to quantification, the divine mode of "infinity" being such a metaphysical quantity. This quantitative metaphysics embraces God and creatures in a single latitude of perfection. Davenport suggests that an achievement of Scotus's "homogenized, quantitative ontology" is that it provides a positive scheme to admit infinite elements. In chapter 6, Davenport celebrates Ockham's semiotic treatment of divine infinity for disentangling all semiotic entities from the extramental things they denote (356). Davenport prefaces her study of Ockham with a semiotic analysis of the illusionistic methods of Giotto's art and the spiritual treatise of Marguerite Porete on the love of an absent God (308). Perhaps more helpful for analyzing Ockham is Davenport's only analysis in the book of an Augustinian source, De trinitate 13.1, employed by Ockham to disentangle semiotics from metaphysics. "[R]ecognizing that to know something 'in a concept' is simply to have a distinct sign for it, Ockham provides both a coherent and theologically safe way to extend finite domains of discourse by instituting signs to stand for infinite elements that are and remain essentially inaccessible" (359). To think and speak of an actual infinite is not to know it, but simply to have a semiotic device with which to designate it. This semiotic designation suffices for loving the thing because it is possible to love something more distinctly than it is comprehended. Although man's intellect in this life can only contemplate signs of the divine, his will is able to transcend the signs and rest in God. "What he proves, based on a 'modern' analysis of signs, is that the soul is 'irreducibly' better able in this lifetime to love God than to know God" (363). In the final chapter, Davenport seeks to show how Ockham's nominalist treatment of the infinite opened the way for a deontologized and secularized notion of the infinite in early modern science. She considers how the notion of inaccessible ideal elements at infinity was appropriated by men like John Buridan, Nicole Oresme, Piero della Francesca, Johannes Kepler, Girard Desargues, Blaise Pascal, and Rene Descartes. The thirst for God becomes a taste for geometry: "Descartes inherited from scholastic theology the axiom BOOK REVIEWS 145 that rational souls are capaces Dei, which means, equivalently, that they are capacesinfiniti. Already in this lifetime, there is therefore something uniquely satisfying and uniquely rational about imagining absolute domains endowed with infinite endpoints" (411). In this final chapter, Davenport cites Ockham's opinion that only through faith is a supreme actual infinite admitted into metaphysics, a concept never claimed, proved, or even suspected by philosophers. It is all well and good that Ockham and others thought so, but it belongs to the intellectual historian to test such claims and in general I do not find Davenport's evaluations philosophically astute. For example, she notes in passing that the term "infinite" does not appear in Scripture, but she seems unfamiliar with such research as that of Norris Clarke which indicates that the term is first applied to God by the Jewish Neoplatonist Philo of Alexandria, that early Fathers of the Church took the Platonic position that "infinite" signified a lack of perfection and should not be said of God, and that the first Christian text to call God infinite is apparently a liturgical text ca. A.D. 300. Plotinus seems to be the first architect of a full-blown concept of intensive infinity. To attribute this technical philosophical concept to the Psalmist when he says that "God is great" or to St. Francis when he strips himself naked in the square of Assisi is a bit of a stretch. Likewise, granted that both Aristotle and Aquinas conclude to a prime mover who is pure act, the former means by this name pure form and the latter infinite being. Such a difference at the very least merits notice, if not analysis. Although Davenport notes that Augustine's distinction between material and spiritual quantity is decisive, when she compares the joys claimed by the modern geometer to those claimed by the medieval mystic (411), or appeals to David Hilbert's remark to a congregation of mathematicians that no concept "has stirred men's emotions more than the infinite" (417), one wonders whether she effectively loses sight of the pivotal distinction of her own study. JOHN TO MARCHIO Villanova University Villanova, Pennsylvania 146 BOOK REVIEWS Augustine's "City of God": A Reader's Guide. By GERARD O'DALY. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1999. Pp. 323. $85.00 (cloth). ISBN 0-19-826354-6. Gerard O'Daly, professor of Latin at University College London and a member of the editorial board of the Augustinus Lexicon, has written a brief and thoughtful introduction to Augustine's magnum opus et arduum. Aptly subtitled, in just under three hundred pages this book not only offers a helpful overview of the lengthy work, but (perhaps more importantly) also defines the context within which the text is to be understood. The first several chapters are helpful in establishing context, and the first and third could stand alone as essays in their own right. The first treats the theme of the "city" of Rome in late antiquity, as a means of gauging Augustine's use of this idea. This chapter serves incidentally as a bibliographical essay on more recent trends and approaches in the field of late antique history. In particular, O'Daly examines the topos of city in four writers: Ammianus, Symmachus, Claudian, and Prudentius. He demonstrates both how each exploited the understanding of Rome shared among members of late antique culture and how each author shaped the contours of this topos for his own literary, political, or theological purposes. While this endeavor involves some "reconstruction," O'Daly is convincing, at least insofar as he offers a glimpse at how the sensibilities of the age operated; it is out of this common set of assumptions about the "city" that Augustine would offer his own vision. O'Daly's analysis (24-26) of Augustine's correspondence with Nectarius, which antedates the writing of De civitate Dei by several years, shows the degree to which Augustine could engage these assumptions-and, at the same time, transform them. The second chapter offers a brief overview of the circumstances that elicited a work such as De civitate Dei from Augustine, noting that it is undeniable that the sack of Rome by Alaric in 410 provided the impetus for its composition (31). However, as O'Daly points out, as psychologically arresting as the sack of 410 was, the stability of Roma aeterna was in question prior to that date. Alaric had been in Italy since around 400, and there were calls to renew the pagan cult prior to the fall of Rome. Christians like Jerome were terrified by the events of 410, largely, O'Daly contends, due to their Eusebian sensibilities. They had so tied the spread of Christianity to the success of the Empire that the fall of Rome itself raised fears about the continued stability of the faith. Thus O'Daly wisely asserts that "Augustine's overriding aim is to dissociate Rome's historical destiny from that of Christianity, or any religion" (29). He does a fine job of demonstrating how Augustine's sermons of 410-11 reflect these and similar concerns, and equally how Augustine himself was in the BOOK REVIEWS 147 process of modifying his earlier optimism about the possibilities of a Christian Empire. Further, in terms of the intended audience, O'Daly is careful to point out that, while the work is certainly apologetic, its scope was not simply the refutation of pagan opponents of Christianity. In fact, its principal audience seems to have been Christians-and those on the fringes of Christianity (such as Volusianus)-who might have found themselves somewhat "unhinged" by recent events and the response these events elicited from their pagan contemporaries. Thus, there is more to the work than simply apology contra paganos. De civitate Dei was written as much to bolster Augustine's fellow Christians as to challenge their pagan critics. O'Daly notes that the depth and range of topics treated in the work reveal its hortatory and catechetical dimensions, though he later suggests the perils of trying to separate the catechetical and apologetic purposes of the work (271). The range and theological vision are what distinguish De civitate Dei and signal its lasting importance. O'Daly concludes his second chapter by addressing the possibility (based on an inference from one of the Divjak letters) that Augustine had revised the text, perhaps repeatedly. He concludes that the evidence renders such a conclusion speculative. The third chapter offers a summary of the Latin Apologetic tradition in Christian North Africa. O'Daly's summary of the principal authors-Tertullian, Minucius Felix, Arnobius, and Lactantius-is concise and informative, reflecting the best in recent scholarship. He characterizes the apologetic project of each of these authors, noting shared emphases as well as differences. He observes that while Augustine may have known and utilized the work of his apologetic forebears, his own contribution is, nonetheless, quite original, particularly in terms of its scope. This may simply reflect differences theologically between Augustine and his predecessors (certainly true in the case of Lactantius), but it is more probable that Augustine is up to something quite different from them. In short, O'Daly can conclude that "no one of his precursors has either a dominant or a profound influence on his apologetic concerns and strategies" (52). Chapter 4 deals with the notion of the "two cities" and seeks to locate Augustine's use of this idiom within the history of ideas. After probing similarities in Jewish apocalyptic, the Greek philosophical tradition, and other possible Christian influences, O'Daly locates in Tyconius "a likely major source" of Augustine's views (57). However, he concludes that while Tyconius anticipates Augustine, particularly in his use of the language of the corpus bipertitum (Augustine, of course, preferring the term corpus permixtum) in reference to the Church and in his insistence that the corpus diaboli is not the reflection of an evil nature but of an evil will, one must be circumspect in 148 BOOK REVIEWS drawing significant conclusions about this influence. This reticence is due largely to the fact that the fragmentary evidence found in Beatus of Liebana may in fact have been subtly shaped by his own Augustinian sensibilities. Further, following]. Van Oort, O'Daly is chary of the view that the two cities simply reflect a dependence upon Manichean dualism; it is more likely that Augustine's dualism is biblical in origin. Again, he sees Augustine as undertaking something quite original, particularly in utilizing language of the two cities within the context of salvation history. Chapter 5 treats the structure of the work. Rather than viewing De civitate Dei as an occasional work that, over a dozen or so years, took on a life of its own, becoming longer and more unwieldy as Augustine pounded it out, O'Daly sees in preface to book 1 Augustine's plan for the work as a whole; there is a reprise of this plan, with greater detail, at 1.35-36. The central themes, antitheses, and characteristic language of the later books are found in nuce at the very beginning. While O'Daly acknowledges that the work's digressions and "often distracting wealth of detail" (71) might obfuscate the plan or direction of the work as a whole, he marks clearly the signposts Augustine himself placed along the way, concurring with J. J. O'Donnell that "the conception of the work was unified and complete before Augustine set pen to paper." The following five chapters offer O'Daly's reading of the text itself. In about 160 pages, he discusses the work and its elements and, with careful attention to the subtleties of the text, helps one to appreciate the structural unity he had presented in chapter 5. Chapter 11 discusses the "influences and sources" upon which Augustine drew in composing De civitate Dei. O'Daly treats three categories of authors: secular Latin writers, Greek writers, whom Augustine would have encountered in Latin translation, and the Jewish and Christian writers who exercised at least a probable (though not undisputed) influence on him. In the case of each possible influence, O'Daly's notes reflect the various positions in scholarly debate, and he is judicious in his assessment of the possibilities. The final chapter tries to place De civitate Dei in the context of Augustine's literary enterprise as a whole. O'Daly shrewdly observes that "Augustine does not, for the most part, write works on self-contained topics" (265), reminding us of the dangers inherent in trying to read Augustine as a systematic theologian in the modern sense. O'Daly singles out and discusses two earlier works that anticipate what Augustine accomplishes in De civitate Dei, De vera religione (390-91), and De catecheumdis rudibus (400/404-5) (266-72). The book contains several short appendices, dealing with (a) the original title of the work (contra paganos is a later accretion); (b) the manuscript BOOK REVIEWS 149 tradition as well as the genealogy of printed editions; {c) the distinction between the breviculus appended to the letter to Firmus {authentic, but not intended as chapter headings) and the canon found in the Corbie MS (probably inauthentic), which offered chapter headings; and {d) a problem with the chronology in 18.54. Augustine's "City of God": A Reader's Guide is a helpful and thoughtful introduction to one of Augustine's greatest and most complex works. It is important contribution to the vast sea of secondary literature on Augustine, not least because it offers in one volume the information and insight which will enable readers to approach De civitate Dei with intelligence and sensitivity. It is to be hoped that this volume will be made available in a much less expensive paperback, since it would serve well as a secondary text at the graduate level. MICHAEL HEINTZ University of Notre Dame Notre Dame, Indiana Kant's Ethical Thought. By ALLENB.WOOD. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1999. Pp. 436. $54.95 {cloth), $19.95 {paper). ISBN 0-52164056-3 {cloth), 0-521-64836-X (paper). Allen Wood's book presents a comprehensive account of Kant's ethics. At the origin of the project was the realization "that Hegel's criticisms of the Kantian principle of morality do not entirely succeed because, like most of Kant's readers, Hegel attended exclusively to the Formula of Universal Law, ignoring the other formulations, which are more adequate statements of the principle" {xiii). Wood also understood that on the deeper issues that separate Kant and Hegel the former's position is grounded on a distinctive theory of human nature and history, whose importance for Kant's ethics has seldom been appreciated (ibid.). Kant's theory of human nature anticipates, according to Wood, Hegel's philosophy of history, "but it also provides a compelling explanation for Kant's notorious view that natural inclinations are a 'counterweight' to moral reason ... rather than being (as Hegel thinks) an expression of reason" (ibid.). Wood begins his investigation by recognizing a deep affinity between Kant and the Enlightenment. He goes as far as to call Kant's ethical thought "both 150 BOOK REVIEWS the finest and the most characteristic product of the Enlightenment" (1). He invites the reader to keep in mind that the Enlightenment "still exists today, since many people throughout the world still struggle for the expansion of liberty in human thought and action, equality in the social, politic, and economic spheres, tolerance regarding religious and cultural diversity" (ibid.). This tribute to Kant as an Enlightenment philosopher is contrasted, however, by Wood's almost complete lack of interest in Kant's most strikingly "enlightened" writings, namely his precritical ethical writings, which are dealt with in less than a page of the introduction (l lf.). The book is structured in two parts. There is first an exposition of Kant's "metaphysical foundations," followed by an exposition of Kant's "anthropological applications." One might as well speak of Kant's "first ethics" and then of his "second ethics," the former constituted by the Groundwork and the Critique of Practical Reason, the latter by all his other ethical writings-but apparently Wood does not like this way of talking about Kant's ethics. The first chapter investigates reciprocally equivalent versions of the formula of morality by means of which Kant appealed to moral common sense for motivating a more rigorous account of the commitments of common sense in terms of philosophic moral cognition (17). The concepts of good will, acting from duty, moral worth, and respect for the law are briefly introduced in the pages that follow. An entire chapter is dedicated to the various kinds of moral imperatives (50-75), while the formula of universal law, "Act only in accordance with that maxim through which you can at the same time will that it becomes a universal law," together with Kant's famous case-studies (suicide, lying, working hard, being charitable) are the object of the following chapter (75-110). Wood gives the same kind of treatment to the formula of humanity as end in itself, "So act that you use humanity, whether in your own person or that of another, always at the same time as an end, never merely as a means" (111-55), and to the formula of autonomy, "Choose only in such a way that the maxims of your choice are also included as universal law in the same volition" (156-90). Whatever we may or may not hold about the compatibility of freedom and natural causality, Wood says, we must presuppose our own freedom, as the capacity to act under norms of reason, in order to represent ourselves as competent to decide on rational grounds whether fatalism or compatibilism is true (178). In an endnote to this problem, which could also be seen as interpretation of the antithesis of the third antinomy of pure reason (viz., "There is no freedom; everything in the world takes place solely according to laws of nature" and there is no such thing as another causality besides that of nature [Critique of Pure Reason, A445/B473]), Wood makes clear that BOOK REVIEWS 151 it is not necessary to assert that we ate free .... merely in order to consider theoretical questions or to make judgments according to normative laws of thinking and judging. Nothing in the process of raising the question of freedom and coming to a fatalist conclusion about it would necessatily require us to assert the contradictory of fatalism ... then fatalism itself, once its implications ate understood, won't appeal to anyone who is faint-hearted about adopting desperate measures. (381) Wood remarks further (ibid.) that he is defending Kant's defense of freedom in a way that is very close to the conceptions of "pragmatism" and "ultimate grounding" (Letztbegriindung) advocated by Karl-Otto Apel and his followers (see especially Karl-Otto Apel, "The a priori of the Communication Community and the Foundation of Ethics: The Problem of the Rational Foundation of Ethics in the Scientific Age," in idem, Selected Essays, vol. 2 [Totowa, N.J.: Humanities Press, 1996], 1-67). It is appropriate to repeat, says Wood, that to represent freedom as a presupposition of rational judgment is by no means to provide a theoretical proof that we are free. For all such arguments show, there might even be strong evidence or arguments that we are not free and that freedom is an illusion. What Kant shows is that we would face an insuperable difficulty if we were confronted with such proofs or evidence. For even to represent ourselves as considering such proofs on their merits is to presuppose that we have the capacity to judge according to norms of reasoning, hence to presuppose that what such proofs are trying to show is false (178). Concluding this argument, Wood points out that Kant's argument on fatalism attacks skepticism about morality by showing that the skeptical doubts undermine the very conditions of their own intelligibility (ibid.). Kant's thought, argues Wood, is grounded on the typically Enlightenment appeal to critical self-confidence in reason without which it would be impossible even to acknowledge on good grounds the limits and fallibility of reason (ibid.). This remark enables us to shift to the second part of Wood's book, the one dedicated to Kant's anthropological applications. Wood concedes that in the Groundwork (where Kant first spoke of the distinction between metaphysics of morals and practical anthropology) it remains extremely unclear what either a metaphysics of morals or a practical anthropology would look like. Kant seems to want to have little to do in the Groundwork with practical anthropology, since he appears to cast himself for the purpose of that work as someone better suited to the metaphysical side of moral philosophy than the empirical or anthropological side (193). In fact, it is difficult to see how on Kantian principles empirical anthropology might play an indispensable role in practical philosophy. However, it obviously requires empirical knowledge of 152 BOOK REVIEWS human nature to determine which ends suitably honor the rational nature of human beings and which ends are contrary to the respect we owe to human dignity. Besides, no attempt to determine the laws that unite the ends of rational beings into a realm can afford to ignore what ends such beings are empirically disposed to adopt (195). By shifting the content of a metaphysics of morals toward the empirical, Kant, says Wood, is in no way abandoning or modifying his fundamental thesis that the supreme principle of morality is wholly a priori and borrows nothing from the empirical nature of human beings. Kant is rather simply withdrawing his earlier claim that a metaphysics of morals can concern only the idea and the principle of a possible pure will and not the actions and conditions of human volition generally. In other words, Kant no longer regards a metaphysics of morals as constituted solely by a set of pure moral principles. It is instead the system of duties that results when the pure moral principle is applied to the empirical nature of human beings in general (196). In what follows, Wood delves into Kant's presentation of empirical psychology, pragmatic anthropology, human history, natural teleology, natural and social passions, sympathy, love, charity, friendship, and eventually into the idea of an ethical community. His conclusion is that Kant's moral principles and his theory of human nature are designed only to add to our discontent with ourselves. Kant thinks that as rational creatures our condition must be one of dissatisfaction, selfalienation, and endless striving. Philosophy should not try to transcend that condition, but only to help us live with its inevitability, and more important, to make progress in the painful tasks it sets us. To some this aim may seem unhealthy, perhaps even dangerous. From a Kantian standpoint, however, any other way of representing our condition appears complacent, cowardly, and dishonest. (334) This is a very well balanced book that adds significantly to the understanding of Kant's philosophy. Wood's arguments are sound and the goals he sets to himself are legitimate. He presents us with a new and important interpretation of Kant's ethical thought. RICCARDO Pozzo The Catholic University of America Washington, D.C. BOOK REVIEWS 153 Feminist Reconstructions of Christian Doctrine: Narrative Analysis and Appraisal. By KATHRYN GREENE-MCCREIGHT. New York: Oxford University Press, 2000. Pp. 175. $29.95 (cloth). ISBN 0-19-512862-1. In this book Kathryn Greene-McCreight undertakes to evaluate the truth and adequacy of certain feminist reconstructions of Christian doctrine. It concerns her that feminist theologians wield so much influence today in seminaries and churches when the reconstructions they propose often seem novel and even alien. She worries that the backlash they invite will destroy the gains that women have made in the Church's life. She recognizes that her evaluation must take into account more than feminist reformulations of the "primary" Christian doctrines; she must first stake out a position from which to assess their "governing" doctrines, namely, the principles and rules that characterize feminist theology. The latter is the really daunting task. The strength of the book lies in the careful attention Greene-McCreight gives to setting out such a position. She identifies a standard of evaluation, and then uses this standard (1) to examine feminist biblical hermeneutics and (2) to analyze and appraise selected feminist reconstructions of the doctrines of sin, Christ, and the Trinity. In chapter 1 Greene-McCreight brings the resources of the "Yale School" (the work of William A. Christian, in addition to that of Hans Frei, and George Lindbeck) to bear on the questions before her. She takes from this school her standard of orthodoxy, "the biblical narrative identification of God," and a series of important distinctions related to method (e.g., between the narrative and nonnarrative interpretations of Scripture, between dogmatics and apologetics, and between authentic doctrines and alien claims). By means of these tools, she lays out for comparison two different (and opposed) patterns by which religious communities respond to novel claims. For GreeneMcCreight, feminist claims can be properly assessedonly by a narrative reading of Scripture (i.e., one that incorporates the present reality into the biblical world) that gives primacy to dogmatics (the logic of belief) and uses the community's authentic doctrine as a test of what is true and right. She points out that in feminist theologies, by contrast, the interpretive flow is "nonnarrative," primacy is given to apologetics (the logic of coming to belief), and an "alien claim" regarding what is true and right is used to judge the authenticity of the community's doctrine. By noticing the way theological inquiry proceeds according to these two patterns, she develops a helpful scheme to use in her analysis. Greene-McCreight recognizes the strategic importance of clarifying not only what a religious community holds to be true ("primary doctrines") but also 154 BOOK REVIEWS how it determines what counts as true and who has the authority to decide ("governing doctrines"). In chapter 2 she discusses the "governing doctrines" of feminist theology: its intellectual families of origin (modern theology and the feminist movements), its explicit and implicit commitments and principles of interpretation, and its implicit commitments borne out in practice. "The full humanity of women" is a governing doctrine because it functions as the norm. "Women's interpreted experience" (interpreted, that is, by their "feminist consciousness,"their experience of and stance toward oppression) functions as the authority, or ultimate court of appeal when it comes to determining what is true and right in Christian doctrine and practice. This authority takes precedence over text, tradition, or reason. In mainline feminist theology, then, feminist claims supplant biblical authority and are "elevated to the status ... of governing doctrines" (55). The feminist critique of Christian doctrine serves as a critical principle for rendering judgments on primary doctrines and even on their biblical source. Like Francis Martin's pioneering work, The Feminist Question: Feminist Theologyin the Light of ChristianTradition (1994), Greene-McCreight' s study spends considerable time examining feminist biblical hermeneutics. In this analysis-perhaps the highlight of the book-she cites telling examples to challenge those feminists who regard the biblical text itself as an enemy, a dangerous "vehicle for the furtherance of patriarchy." Those who take this view, she asserts, reverse the proper "flow" of interpretation, judging the revelatory value of the text by the "authority" of their own experience; they "pull the rug out from under the classical hermeneutic" (68). Their "nonnarrative" reading allows alien claims to trump the authority of the biblical text. The fundamental criterion of Christian orthodoxy, the biblicalnarrative identification of God, is then replaced by feminist reconstructions. The author asks whether all the claims of feminism are indeed "authentic doctrines," and whether they cohere with the authentic doctrine of the community. In her opinion, feminist reconstructions must be tested to determine their coherence with the biblical-narrative identification of God. When they do not meet this standard, and, by the force of their own logic, begin to reshape "the web of belief," they constitute a serious threat to doctrinal orthodoxy. On the basis of this analysis, Greene-McCreight proceeds in the subsequent chapters to apply her standard to selected feminist reconstructions of three primary doctrines: sin, Christ, and the Trinity. Of these chapters, the one on sin and victimization is the most successful. The analysis is carefully constructed. The author identifies the hermeneutical problem (the canon is already infected by sin) and names the standard feminist "doctrines" regarding original sin (patriarchy, or sexism) and women's sin (self-denial and sub- BOOK REVIEWS 155 missiveness). Then she points out two difficulties that arise from this nonnarrative reading of Scripture. The philosophical difficulty lies in their totalizing assumptions about women. (I regret that she chose not to examine the question of "essentialism.") The theological difficulty arises from the fact that some feminists use an anthropology constructed without reference to the biblical drama to critique the biblical doctrines. In a very insightful next step, Greene-McCreight presents an alternative interpretation. Drawing on Barth, she illuminates the relationship between pride (the male sin) and sloth (the female sin), showing that both are forms of rebellion, opposed to Christ whose humble obedience is the source of his exaltation. It seems to her that the feminist reconstruction makes self-assertion the goal in a way that contradicts the Reformed doctrine of justification by grace through faith alone. The first of two chapters on feminist Christologies deals with the Incarnation (and the theological significance of maleness), the Cross, and the Resurrection. These complex topics are difficult to negotiate on any terms, so it is not surprising that Greene-McCreight's analysis here is less successful. Her identification of three models of feminist reconstruction of the doctrine of Christ-internal apology, doctrinal relocation, and allegorical reconstructionhas considerable merit, and many specific judgments and comments are judicious and insightful. The chapter as a whole, however, is marred by the fact that she accepts at face value the feminist arguments in favor of the ordination of women to the priesthood (71£., 107-10). For lack of acquaintance with the terms of the intra-Catholic debate, she is unable to evaluate it correctly. The chapter also reveals the deficiency (from a Roman Catholic point of view) of her criterion, the biblical narrative identification of God, for the adjudication of these questions. Let me offer some further comment on these two deficiencies. As to the first, my complaint is that feminist theologians often misrepresent Catholic teaching as asserting that women are excluded from the ministerial priesthood because they cannot image Jesus Christ who is male. From this, they move to an exploration of the significance (or lack of it) of maleness in his case and in relation to the Godhead and of its relevance to the salvation of women. The feminist critique, at this point, is built on a mistake. The Catholic Church, in fact, gives as its reason for this exclusion the choice made by the Lord when he called the Twelve and carefully maintained by the apostolic Church and in subsequent tradition. Feminist failure to consider this rationale often reveals ambivalence around Catholic teaching regarding the sacrament of holy orders and its difference (in kind, not just in degree) from the sacrament of baptism (the point at which salvation is relevant). It also represents and even generates an unwillingness to grant sacramental significance to sexuality. As to the second, the "biblical narrative identification of God" does not suffice as a BOOK REVIEWS 156 criterion to answer questions of Church order in a communion that understands the Church and its essential structures to have been given by Christ. (Could Greene-McCreight acknowledge in the "biblical narrative" the significance of Jesus' choice of twelve men? Not, it seems, apart from the tradition which interprets this choice as normative for ordained ministry [see 161 n. 90], and not on the basis of a Reformed view of that ministry.) Avery Dulles recently proposed fifteen criteria of Catholic theology (see Communio 22 [1995]: 303-15). Clearly, Roman Catholics have been in the business of articulating their governing doctrines longer than Protestants. The second chapter on feminist Christologies is superior to the first. The author's critique of Sophia Christology is often very cogent, and she offers some suggestive leads for further inquiry into feminist uses of the dichotomy between the Jesus of history and the Christ of faith. Overall, however, she is unable at times to spot the flaws in Christological doctrine manifest in many feminist reconstructions-for example, the failure to distinguish nature from person in Christ, to affirm the personal preexistence of the Word, or to find a redemptive value in the sacrifice of the Cross. On balance, she is perhaps too ambitious to attempt in such brief compass an evaluation of feminist Christologies as diverse as those of Mary Grey and Anita Nakashima Brock. The chapter on feminist Trinitarian reconstructions focuses on the problem of naming God; here Greene-McCreight's standard serves very well. Her comments on and judgment of feminist reconstructions of the baptismal formula are very astute. She suggests that popular misunderstandings be corrected by catechesis rather than by altering the biblical language and thereby the story it tells about God. In her conclusion, Greene-McCreight weighs up feminist reconstructions in terms of her original scheme and finds many of them erroneous. She urges others to join her in a scholarly critique of these constructions, lest the gains made by the feminist movement be rejected wholesale. While she acknowledges the validity of many feminist claims, she warns that "if we do not respect the holistic narratival depiction of the biblical God, there is no compelling reason for us to claim as true or even as noteworthy any of the remnant details presented to us in that depiction" (133). Anyone who grasps the urgent necessity of engaging Christian feminist theology in a serious dialogue will be grateful to the author for providing this helpful and provocative study. SARA BUTLER, M.S.B.T. Mundelein Seminary Mundelein, Illinois BOOK REVIEWS 157 Liberty, Dominion, and the Two Swords: On the Origins of Western Political Theology (180-398). By LFSTERL. FIELD, JR. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. 1998. Pp. 542. $95.00 (cloth). ISBN 0-268-01304-7. Perhaps the best way to introduce this book on early Christian political theology would be to cite a passage from Aidan Nichols's recent book, Christendom Awake! (Grand Rapids, Mich.: Eerdmans, 1999), in which he remarks: I have said so far that the embodiment of the shared aims of a Christendom society cannot be separated from the need to enact the fundamental norms of such a society in the civil law, for the re-creation of Christendom as State. Whereas in traditionally republican polities, a supreme court might be regarded as the appropriate institution for testing proposed legislation against the public criterion of the JudaeoChristian revelation, I wish to concentrate in conclusion on the possible role of a revived (national and also international) monarchical institution in this regard. (83-84) The plausibility of Nichols's "revived monarchical institution" cannot be understood without some reference to that long history of politics and theology in the West wherein politics, while being politics, still did not exempt itself from the sources of revelation and its effect on the public order. Professor Field's erudite study of late-second-to-fourth-century efforts to understand the relation between the emperor and the God of revelation provides some of the historic background of the relation between political structures and theological principles. This learned book contains 264 pages of text, with almost the same amount of space devoted to endnotes, bibliography, and index. The book is divided into three general parts: "The Church of the Martyrs" (180-312), "The 'ConstantinianRevolution'" (312-74), and "The Age of Ambrose" (374-98). The first part is divided into three chapters that discuss, in order, "Liberty," "Ecclesiastical Dominion," and "Imperial Dominion and the Two Swords: Images and Reflections." The second part contains six chapters: "Freedom of Religion," "The Emergence of a Christian Empire," "Donatism: The Church in Africa or Heretical Conventicle?" "After Nicea: Western Reactions to Arianism," "Lucifer of Cagliari and the Luciferians," and "Hilary of Poitiers." The third part has four chapters: "Freedom by Birth, Faith, and Priestly Right," "How Was an Empire Christian," "The Christian Empire," and "The Papacy: Ancient Denouement or Medieval Prelude?" This content outline alone gives some indication of the scope of this fine study. The book begins and ends as a study of liberty in its many nuances. Field is aware that Christianity introduced itself into the world not under the rubric of 158 BOOK REVIEWS necessity or coercion but of liberty. "Ancient Christians regarded liberty as humanity's greatest gift and highest goal," Field writes in his introduction. This view survived antiquity. Yet it survived differently in the East, where Christians continued to express themselves in Greek, and in the West, where after the second century they increasingly or generally expressed themselves in Latin. Hence the designation "Eastern" and "Western"came to indicate considerably more and less than a location in the Roman empire. From a historical and theological standpoint, these regional labels gradually signaled two distinct self-understandings. (xiii) No doubt, Field notes, with some irony, liberty is not considered to be antithetical to revelation, but is precisely a "gift" and a "goal." It is something we do not yet possess; it is not something acquired solely by our own powers. He does not think that, at bottom, there is a difference of principle between Eastern and Western Christianity on this point, however different their external political manifestation may be. Liberty, no doubt, needs to be ordered for it to be what it is. The classical enemy to liberty, as Aristotle had already implied in his definition of democracy, was liberty itself, that is, a form of liberty that had no end or purpose. This is the liberty that is identified with license, doing whatever one wants, whatever it is one wants, a principle that has reappeared as near, if not at, the heart of "modern" political philosophy since Machiavelli. Freedom rather was to be a result of the virtues, not of their lack. Will depended on intelligence to specify its end and hence the status in good or evil of what is chosen or rejected. But Christians came to learn more about will from the first books of Genesis than from Aristotle, however insightful the latter was. We can catch some of the importance of this understanding in Field's discussion of the antecedents of the expression "freedom of religion": As used by the Fathers and Constantine, the "freedom" to choose a religion falls nowhere within these modern, or early modern, boundaries. It meant neither "disapproval" nor "forbearance." Nor did it legitimate, or prompt respect for other religion. For Tertullian who coined the expression, libertasreligioniswas simply a theological and psychological fact. God bestowed such freedom when He bestowed freedom of choice, that is, when He made humans according to His own image. . . . This argument was aprioristic: it argued a "fact" concerning human nature from theological first principles. Put differently, the very validity of "freedom of religion" resided in the superiority of the Christian truth over pagan error .... Free choice BOOK REVIEWS 159 pertained to the simplicitasof human substance, of which no one could deprive another. (67-68) The theological grounding of free will, allied as it was later in Aquinas to Aristotle's discussion of the double syllogism, of the examination of how we do good or how we err, does not by itself determine the social and political sorts of institutions conducive to the flourishing of this freedom. But it does emphasize that man's relation to God, from the side of revelation itself, does depend on this metaphysical and theological grounding of freedom. In his chapter on "Hilary of Poitiers," Field writes, "Nicenes drew from ancient and common font. Although Hilary coined the politically pregnant formula libertasecclesiae,Christian freedom had always uniquely pertained to the Church" (164). The martyrs themselves were killed after all in the name of their freedom from their persecutors. The freedom of the Church was precisely its being what it was within the saeculum; within it was the true circle of freedom to be what we are. Nothing could stand against it; hence it was free. It is the primary concern of this book to trace out the ways, granted the legal and economic structure of the Roman Empire in the light of traditions and philosophies from the Greeks, in which freedom is manifested within the Church in the relation of clergy to bishops, and bishops to the pope, with this broad freedom of the Church seen as accepting of and stimulating to a proper and limited political freedom within the public order. In the Church, however, as Ambrose saw it, they (David and Nathan, pope and emperor) were to one another accountable, all the more so through Peter and his successors of Rome. "Freedom" remained eschatological. Temporarily, however, papal decree, confirmation, and anathema circumscribed it-at least by papal self-understanding-for "all the churche!'." By a primacy-at once martyrological, christological, and petrine-the spiritual sword belonged preeminently to Rome. The lack of "freedom to be silent," which Ambrose claimed with respect to the emperor, Pope Siricius had already claimed with respect to the episcopacy. (252) The famous language of the "two swords" developed through Gelasius and worked to establish what came to be the medieval problematic. The one society had two proper authorities, one spiritual and one political or secular. This understanding was already foreshadowed by St. Ambrose's confrontation with Theodosius. Whenever there was a problem of doctrine or living that jeopardized the authenticity of the freedom of revelation in the public world, the bishop and the pope were not allowed simply to remain silent. Their duty to speak, to stand for what the tradition held, was the basis of a limitation of 160 BOOK REVIEWS the emperor's own power, as well as a definition of the rightful but limited authority of bishops within the Church itself. Field's book, though restricted in time frame to 180-398, does recognize that the theological reflections of the early Church did have political consequences, oftentimes tending to heretical consequences. Thus, the intricate argumentation of some of the greatest of the early Church bishops and fathers, against these positions, would have lasting effects on the precise form of political order in the West during medieval and indeed in modern times. Fields concludes with these perceptive sentences: Whatever its institutional consequences, Gregory VII's libertasecclesiae still meant libertas christiana, libertas christianae fidei-in short, libertas aeterna. Formally, that is, theologically, the "freedom of the Church" still entailed the single "political" agendum of preserving the catholic faith. For all its other political implications, even in the minds of the eleventh century reformers, the "freedom of the Church" retained its eschatological meaning. (264) This "freedom of the Church" is Field's way of accounting for a continuity of principle throughout the early centuries of the Church in its dealings with the political power and with its own organs designed to preserve what it was. One can look on this negatively, say, from the point of view of the martyrs (of which we have more in the twentieth century than they did during these years of which Field writes). That is, certain demands of the state, whatever its form (democratic, totalitarian, or in between), cannot be accepted in this world, and the martyr stands for something that is rejected in the public order. Or it can be looked on positively, that is to say, that just as the individual soul can be redirected, even healed by grace, so there are public orders more conducive to encouraging the eschatological purpose of the Church in its wayfaring in the world. In either case, as Field's conclusion implies, what concerns the "freedom" of the Church is that eschatological purpose or end according to which it finds itself in this world. That purpose or end is that what is "given" for our freedom remain in the world, under all its political configurations. JAMES V. SCHALL, S. J. Georgetown University Washington, D.C.