The Thomist 65 (2001): 327-59 CONGAR'S DEVELOPING UNDERSTANDING OF THE LAITY AND THEIR MISSION RAMIRO PELLITERO Universidadde Navarra Pamplona, Spain I t is the task of theology in the twentieth century to announce to the world the mystery of the Church in all her depth and to define the real canonical status of the laity in the Church." 1 When Congar wrote these words he was plotting what would constitute a good part of his theological project and work. Today we can say that his theology of the laity already belongs, in its substance, to the deposit of the Church's self-reflection and what the Church, by means of her theological work, has said about her own essence and life. INTRODUCTION: THE HISTORICAL-THEOLOGICAL CONTEXT At the beginning of the third millennium, Catholics feel the need to return to the Second Vatican Council in order to understand the Church and the Christian mission. For this reason it is opportune to reflect on Yves Congar's contribution to an Y. Congar, "Bulletin de theologie," Revue des sciencesphilosophiqueset theologiques24 (1935): 731. An abstract of this work was presented, as a talk, at the "Congar Ecumenical Colloquium" during the Fifty-fifth Annual Convention of the Catholic Theological Society of America ("Catholicism and Public Life", San Jose, Calif., 8-11 June 2000). Professors Paul Waisanen, of the St. Herman Orthodox Church (Oxnard, Calif.), and Richard K. Eckley, of Houghton College, responded to my presentation from Orthodox and Protestant perspectives, respectively. I thank the convener of the colloquium, Professor Marc Ginter, of the Saint Meinrad School of Theology, for his suggestions on improving the English text. 1 327 RAMIRO PELLITERO 328 understanding of the lay faithful, an understanding that 1s theological and not merely sociological. 2 Congar began his theological journey in the 1930s, years that witnessed the ascendancy of the de-Christianization that had been progressing in Central Europe since the end of the nineteenth century. As a theologian and a man of the Church, Congar drew upon his Thomistic education, formed in the theological school of Le Sau/choir, in his search for answers to the pastoral La teologfade/ laicado e11 la obra de Yves Co11gar (Pamplona: Servicio de Publicaciones de la Universidad de Navarra/Navarra Grafica de Ediciones, 1996). Besides the specific bibliography on our work of Congar (see below), see on themes related to ours (app. chronological order): B. Mondin, La &clesiologia di Yves Co11gar, Eu11tes Docete 32 (1979): 409-32; T. I. MacDonald, The &clesiology of Yves Co11gar: Foundatio11a/Themes (Milwaukee: Marquette University, 1981); D . .Jagdeo, Holinessand Reform of the Churchin the Writingso(Yves Congar, 0. P. (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America, 1986); M. Meini,Lo Spiritonell'ecclesiologiadiYvesCongar(Siena:Cantagalli, 1988); idem, I riferimenti fondamentalidel pensieroteologicodi Yves Congar, Vivens Homo 1 (1990): 79100; A. Nichols, 0. P., From Newman to Congar: The Idea of DoctrinalDevelopment from the Victoriansto the SecondVatican Council (Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark, 1990); A. Galeano, La Iglesia y su reforma seg1'n Y. Congar: Una eclesio/ogia precursora del Vaticano II (Bogota:Un. de S. Buenaventura, 1991); J. Fameree, L'ecclesiologied"Yves Congar, avant Vatican II. Histoire et Eglise. A11alyse et reprise critique (Louvain: Press. Univ., 1992); S. Brown, Faith and History: The Perspectiveof Yves Congar (Ph.D. diss., St Michael's College, Toronto, 1994); C. Van Vliet, "Communio sacramentalis":Das /(jrchenverstiindnisvon Yves Congar: genetisch und systematish betrachtet (Mainz: Matthias-Griinewald-Verl., 1995); idem, Die &clesiologie Yves CongarO.P. und das Zweite VaticanischeKonzil, Theologieund Glaube 86 (1996): 27-38; C. Caltagirone, 'Tutto" e "parte":IlcontributodiYvesCongaral/o sviluppo della teologiadella Chiesa locale, RicercheTeologiche8 (1997): 5-39; R. Pellitero, Yves Congar(1904-1995), "in memoriam," inAnales de Historiade la Iglesia 6 (1997): 44346; E. Groppe-Sniegocki, The Pneumatology of Yves Congar (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1997); D. M. Doyle, Journet, Congar, and the Roots of Communion &clesiology, Theological Studies 58 (1997): 461-79; N. Gaczynsky, L'ecclesiologia eucaristicadi Yves Congar, di Joseph Ratzingere di Bruno Forte (Rome: Pont. Un. Greg., 1998); W. Kohler, Rezeption in der /(jrche: BegriffsgeschichlichtlicheStudien bei Sohm, Afanafev, Dombois und Congar, (Gottingen: Vandenhoek & Ruprechet, 1998); P. G. Gianazza, Lo Spirito Santo: "Summa pneumatologica"di Yves Congar (Rome: LAS, 1998); J. Riga!, Trois approchesde l'ecclesiologiede communion: Congar, Zizioulas, Mo/tmann, Nouvelle revue theologique 120 (1998): 605-19; J.-P. Torrell, Yves Congaret l'ecclesiologie de saint Thomas d'Aquin, Revue des sciences philosophiqueet tbeologique 82 (1998): 20142;Th. F. O'Meara, "Reflections On Yves Congar and Theology in the United States," U.S. Catholic Historian 17 (Spring 1999): 91-105; A. Dobrzynski, La pneumatologia en la eclesiologfaecumenicadel CardenalYves Congar, Excerpta e dissert. in S. T. (Fac. de T ., Un. de Navarra) 38 (2000): 143-224. 2 See R. Pellitero, CONGAR ON THE LAITY 329 challenges of the time. During these years, Congar figured among the driving forces in the re-evaluation of the role of the laity, within the context of the French Catholic Action movement. In these same years, he was responsible for introducing into France the great ecclesiology of Tiibingen, centered in the works of Johann Adam Mohler, in which the Church appears as a living organism extending herself through history under the impetus of the Holy Spirit. Theology and pastoral preoccupations intersected in the thought of the celebrated Dominican, enriching one another and offering fruits that translated into intellectual enterprises, publications, and in the "ecumenical vocation" of Fr. Congar. Then the Second World War broke out. The war was a catalyst for new experiences and encounters. In the dawn that followed this tragic night, the awareness of the necessity of a renewal of the apostolate sharpened. Public religiosity, pilgrimages, and popular devotions increased, as did the desire to reach the most difficult environments, especially the working masses. All of this led to a profound reconsideration of the Church's mission and, within that mission, of the role of the laity. Congar, in his encounters with the laity (and within the context of the Catholic Action movement), spoke of the personal spiritual life and the Christian transformation of society. In order to provide a foundation for the ecclesial vision of the laity, he turned to the theology of the Mystical Body, then at the height of its popularity, 3 and to the vision of the common priesthood of the faithful: Insofar as one is (in a Christian sense) alive and active, he makes an offering of his own life; in this sense, each person is the priest of his own existence; it is the spiritual worship, the spiritual priesthood of every baptized Christian. This discovery in the first years of my study constitutes the background of my entire theology of the laity. 4 3 See S. Jaki, Les tendances nouvelles de la ecclesiologie (Rome: Herder, 1957); J. E. Scully, "The Theology of the Mystical Body of Christ in the French Language Theology, 1930-1950," Irish Theological Quarterly 58 (1992): 58-74. 4 Y. Congar, in]. Puyo interroge le Pere Congar: "Une vie pour la veritC" (Paris: Le Centurion, 1975), 165£. 330 RAMIRO PELLITERO The beginnings of his theological journey must be situated in the context of the mid-century renewal of biblical studies, patristics, theology, liturgy, etc. Within the methodological possibilities offered by this presentation, I have chosen the one that seems to me to be the clearest: a theological-narrative description of the evolution of Congar's thought regarding the laity, following his writings chronologically in order to see the changes that are, in my opinion, evident in his journey. Before examining Congar's theological journey, however, we must remind ourselves that we are not talking about a straight linear evolution but rather of pathbreaking, at times traveling along previously unexplored trails, which requires great effort and corrections en route. Having said this, we must also add that it is possible to follow a guiding line. We may identify the following phases in Congar's thinking about the figure of the layperson and his mission: (1) a primary stage marked by the theology of the Mystical Body during the 1930s and 1940s; (2) his book ]alons pour une theologie du laicat (1953), which remains Congar's best-known approach to the topic; (3) a stage which may be considered his most glorious, coinciding with the years of the Second Vatican Council in the 1960s; (4) a period, during the years immediately following the council, of reconsideration of his positions, with regard to the so-called "theology of ministries"; (5) a final stage, which we could call a period of simplification and return to the core of his thought, during the 1980s. There is a hermeneutical thesis in our exposition of Congar's theology, which we state now in order to focus our discussion in the debate with other interpreters of Congar's works. The route of Congar'sthought about the person and the responsibilityof lay Christiansmay be understoodin light of a doublesource:his vision of the relation between the Church and the world and his deepeningsense of the threefoldstructureof the Church (ordained ministers, laity, and religious). In this presentation we will try to CONGAR ON THE LAITY 331 show these two sources and the way in which they nourish one another within each stage in Congar's thought. 5 l. THE BEGINNINGS OF CONGAR'S REFLECTION ON THE LAITY Congar's reflection on the laity began with his "theological conclusion" to an inquiry about the contemporary lack of faith in 1935. The framework is intentionally ecclesiological: the Church is "Christ living within and saving the world," and at the same time "the universe as transformed by grace into the image of God. " 6 Congar emphasizes the Christo logical dimension of the 5 On the theology of laity in Congar's writings see A. Rudoni, Fondamenti de/la teologia del laicato in Y. M.-J Congar: '1alons pour une theologie du lalcat" (Rome: Pontificia Universita Lateranense, 1970); J. R. Ceschi, El apostolado de los laicos en la teologia de Yves Congar (Rome and Vicenza: LIEF, 1973); D. Bonifazi, "Sacerdozio-laicato nell'ecclesiologia di Y. Congar: Evoluzione e prospettive," in Popolo di Dio e sacerdozio (Padua, 1983), 30720; M.A. Gibaud, Sacerdocio comun y sacerdocio ministerial en Yves Congary en el Vaticano II (Rome: Pont. Un. de Sto. Tomas, 1983); R. McBrien, "Church and Ministry: The Achievement of Yves Congar," Theology Digest 32 (1985): 203-11; G. Colombo, "La 'teologia de! laicato': Bilancio di una vicenda storica," in I laici nella Chiesa (Turin: LDC, 1986), 9-27; R. Beauchesne, Laity and Ministry in Yves M.-Congar, 0. P.: Evolution, Evaluation and Ecumenical Perspectives (Boston University, 1974); idem, "Worship as Life, Priesthood and Sacrifice in Yves Congar," Eglise et Theologie 21(1990):79-100; R. Pellitero, "La eficacia temporal de! mensaje evangelico segtin Yves Congar," Scripta Theologica 24 (1992): 1031-47; S. Fuster, "Aportaci6n de! padre Congar a la teologfa de! seglar" Ciencia Tomista 123 (1996): 77-98; Pellitero, La teologia del laicado; Th. F. O'Meara, "Beyond 'Hierarchology': Johann Adam Mohler and Yves Congar," in D. ]. Dietrich and M.J. Himes, eds., The Legacy of the Tubingen School: The Relevance of Nineteenth-Century Theology for the Twenty-First Century (New York: Crossroad, 1997), 173-91. E. Vilanova, "La teologia del lakat segons el pare Congar," Revista Catalana de Teologia 23 (1998): 443-51; A. Vauchez, "Yves Congar et la place des !ales clans l'ecclesiologie medievale," in Cardinal Yves Congar (1904-1995) (Paris: Cerf, 1999), 165-82. On the relationship between the Church and the world according to Congar see A. de Nicholas, "Yves-M. ]. Congar," in Teologia de/ progreso (Salamanca: Sfgueme, 1972), LSl66; K. E. Untener, The Church-World Relationship according to the Writings of Yves Congar, O.P. (Rome: Gregorian University, 1976); Ch. MacDonald, Church and World in the Plan of God: Aspects of History and Eschatology in the Thought of Pere Yves Congar, 0. P. (Frankfurt am Main: Verlag Peter Lang, 1982); D. Okashoko Nkoy Mukanga, La dynamique de la catholicite dans l'ecclesiologie du P. Yves Congar (Un. Louvain-La-Neuve, 1994). 6 Y. Congar, "Une conclusion theologique a l'enquete sur les raisons actuelles de l'incroyance," La vie intelectuelle 37 (1935): 214-49, at 242. According to E. Fouilloux this text develops ideas from Congar's lectorat thesis, prepared beginning in 1929, about the 332 RAMIRO PELLITERO Church from a perspective rooted in patristic theology, along the lines of the "ongoing Incarnation," as it was understood by J. A. Mohler. In an expression with an Augustinian flavor, he also indicates that the Church is "the world transformed and sanctified by the active presence within her of the Holy Spirit; that is to say, the entire human and cosmic mass fermented by the leaven of the Faith." 7 In this same work, he also sees the world-from a phenomenological perspective-as "the modern-cultural world," in contrast to the ecclesiastical "world. " 8 Congar places lay Christians in this context. As members of the Mystical Body of Christ, they are called, within their "particular human condition," theme of unity in the Church (see Fouilloux, "Friar Yves, Cardinal Congar," 68). In this thesis, still influenced by a Bellarminian ecclesiology, the young Congar applied a Thomistic analysis to the Church-society, highlighting its institutional dimension; on the other hand he understood that the cause of much of the disaffection with the Church was the "disfigured" face presented by the institution. This "disfigured" face is also a consequence of the breakdown of unity. Congar's "ecumenical journey" had already commenced. 7 Congar, "Une conclusion theologique," 233. 8 In Congar's writings, the concept of a mundus as a union of realities that historically had been conceived as differing from the reality of the Church ought to be distinguished from the world of the cosmos as fruit of creation. One of the keys to his theology of the laity is the connection between these two concepts, which involves the recognition of the autonomy of temporal realities and their inclusion in God's plan. To this end, Congar wrote the following in 1948: The problems proper to our generation ... all point to this: the exact nature of the relationship between the Church and the world (the world in the sense of mundus) supposes a criticism of medieval Christianity (/a chretiente sacrale) and the feeling of historically different states; the problem of the relationship of earthly values with the Kingdom of God, which is to say, of the Church with the cosmosworld demands an historical perspective. Faced with Marxism and its seduction because it integrates its explanation of things and its practical revolutionary program in an overall vision of evolution, Christianity will not have an effective answer if it does not examine more closely what its own nature really is: the realization of a plan in history, a movement which runs from its beginning to its consummation, through a development. (Y. Congar, "Ten dances actuelles de la pensee religieuse en France," Cahiers du monde nouveau [4 March 1948], 49f.) CONGAR ON THE LAilY 333 to assume the created world (and especially human act1v1ties, languages, cultures, etc.) into the redeeming love of Christ, so that the universe might be summed up to the glory of God. 9 A decade later the celebrated theologian began his outlines of a theology of the laity. He maintains that the laity form a part, not of the "structure" (hierarchy) of the Church, but rather of its "communion of life." 10 He understands the laity as possessing the "triple power" of Christ (priesthood, royalty, and prophecy) in a "form" different from that of the hierarchy. 11 He situates the theology of the laity within the context of a "total ecclesiology," built around two essential points: the Church in herself, and the Church in her relationship with the rest of the world. 12 In the "duality" that exists between the Church and the "world," 13 the mission of the laity is not determined in an 9 See Y. Congar, L'Eglise et son unite, ecumenical text prepared for the Second Conference on Practical Christianity ("Life and Work" Movement, Oxford, 1937). I have worked with the French version of the text (Y. Congar, Esquisses du mystere de l'Eglise [Paris, 1941], 11-57). 10 Y. Con gar, "Sacerdoce etlaicat dans l'Eglise," La vie intellectuelle12 ( 1946): 6-3 9. This text constituted Congar's first specific contribution to the theology of the laity. He explains that, to the degree that the People of God already possesses its inheritance (the communion of life in Christ), Christians are therefore kings, priests, and prophets. But to the degree that it is still journeying and has still not internalized the life of Christ, the Church has "the quality and the form of an earthly society" and for this reason requires a hierarchical organization, with "exterior" teaching, rites, laws, and precepts: it has a hierarchicalstructure. 11 With regard to the priesthood which today we call "common," see, before Jalons, Y. Congar, "Structure du sacerdoce chretien," Maison Dieu 27 (1951): 51-85; "Un essai de theologie sur le sacerdoce catholique: La these de l'abbe Long-Hasselmans," Revue des sciences religieuses25 (1951): 187-88, 288-304; "Notes sur notre sacerdoce," Cahiers de l'aumoniercatholique(May 1953): 7-18. In the first of these texts Congar distinguishes three titles of Christian priesthood: interior priesthood(corresponding to the Christian existence shaped by grace and the virtues), baptismal priesthood(which makes one able to participate in the liturgy), and hierarchicalpriesthood (which carries the power to consecrate the Eucharist). This distinction disappears infalons with the combining of the first two categories into a "spiritual-royal priesthood" of the faithful. iz See Y. Congar, "Pour une theologie du lalcat," Etudes Oanuary 1948): 42-54; (February 1948): 194-218 (the expression "total ecclesiology" will become a classic phrase after Jalons). u For Congar this duality (which is not "dualism," because everything comes from God) between the Church and the world, between what comes directly from grace and what comes from creation, was almost identical in the 1950s with the duality between the Church and civil society. It speaks of a distinction that will end in the definitive Kingdom of God which will be inaugurated by the Parousia. Nevertheless, beforefalons Congar held that these two 334 RAMIRO PELLITERO immediate fashion by the institution of Christ, but rather by the ex spiritu testimony they give in temporal realities, owing to their baptismal consecration. With respect to the temporal, they must necessarily act as Christians (en chretiens);in addition, they can bring into play values that are valid for every man. 14 Thus Congar introduces anthropological elements to describe the proprium of the laity. Faced with those who had thought of the laity as mere collaborators in the mission of priests, Congar affirms already in this period that the layperson is a Christian who participates in the apostolic mission of the Church as "part of the apostolic body of the Church" and a co-subject of pastoral theology. 15 The layperson exercises his apostolate by means of his work and his Christian influence in the world 16 according to the gifts and the opportunities the Holy Spirit grants him, and in the "providential" circumstances of his life. In this way, Congar concludes, "his profane work is, in various ways, a service to the Kingdom of God." 17 II. THE LAYPERSONIN "JALONS POUR UNE THEOLOGIE DU LAICAT" (1953) The beginning of the 1950s witnessed intense activity in the life of the French priest, not without difficulties. As a result of misunderstandings and suspicions on the part of those who did not look upon "la nouvelle theologie" with sympathetic eyes, Congar moved, beginning in 1954, first to Jerusalem, later to "spheres" were already connected in the salvific plan of God and, since the Incarnation, have been related to one another. The authors who criticized Congar's vision as if it were a juxtaposition of orders during history did not perhaps understand this Christological root, which led Congar to affirm that since the Incarnation nothing may be considered "profane" (for a discussion of the sacred and the profane, see Pellitero, La teologfa de/ laicado, 323ff.). 14 Cf. Congar, "Pour une theologie du laicat," 195ff. 1·1 See R. Pellitero, "La evoluci6n del concepto 'Teologfa pastoral,'" ScriptaTheologica32 (2000): 471-508. 16 See also Y. Congar, "Efficacite temporelle et message evangelique," Revue nouvelle 17 (1953): 32-49. 17 Congar, "Pour une theologie du laicat," 216£. CONGAR ON THE LAITY 335 Cambridge, and finally to Strasbourg, where he remained until 1968. The beginning of the 1950s also coincided with the dramatic experiment of the "worker priests." Their apostolic zeal for recovering for the Church those milieux where the deChristianization had penetrated most deeply did not know how to measure the difficulties, practical and theological, this effort implied. 18 The experiment was halted in 1954 and the "eldest daughter of the Church" staggered. Only a few months before Congar had published ]alons pour une theologie du lai'cat, the book that he always considered a foundation for a reflection on the laity within his ecclesiological project. 19 A) The Church-WorldRelationshipin '1alons" Besides possessing Christological and anthropological dimensions, the Church-world distinction in ]alons also has ascetic, soteriological, cosmic, and eschatological connotations as well as marked cultural and jurisdictional perspectives. Moreover, it also contains an important development with regard to two questions that continue to be debated today: the theology of history and the theology of work. Christologicaland anthropologicaldimensions.The Church is distinguished from the world in that she proceeds from the redemption worked by Christ, while the world proceeds from the creation. The Church makes her pilgrimage in history together with the world, between the fullness of the Resurrection and the 18 On the "worker priests" and their situation, see, for example, H. Godin, France pays de mission? (Paris, 1943); R. Voillaume, Au coeur des masses (Paris, 1950); A. Dansette, Destin du catholicisme fraw;ais, 1926-1956 (Paris, 1957); E. Poulat, Naissancedes pretres ouvriers(Paris, 1959); J. Loew, Rencontres:]ournald'unemission ouvriere1941-1959 (Paris, 1961); L. Augros, De l'Eglised, bier al'Eglisede demain: L 'aventurede la mission de France (Paris, 1980); D. Perrot, Les fondations de la mission de France (Paris, 1987). Congar,]alons pour une theologie du laicat (Paris: Editions du Cerf, 1953). I have used the second French edition, published in 1954. English translation: Lay People in the Church:A Study for a Theology of the Laity, trans. Donald Attwater (London: Bloomsbury Publishing Co., 1957). The third edition, from 1964, revised by Congar, was first published in the United States by Newman Press (Westminster, Md.) in 1965. 336 RAMIRO PELLITERO fullness of the Parousia. The Church's time is the entre-deux, which immediately raises questions about the value of human efforts in temporal activities and, in a larger horizon, the value of a Christian culture and of a Christian humanism. Ascetic,soteriological,cosmic,and eschatologicalconnotations. According to Congar, Christ is sovereign of the universe (both of the cosmos and of the Church) not only because of his role in the creation of the world as the Word, but by "right of conquest," his redemptive work, which has made him worthy of a place of honor at the right hand of the Father. As a result of his victory over sin on the Cross, the world is already reconciled to the Father, though still not fully. This reconciliation remains to be freely internalized by humanity, in its effort to overcome sin. The Parousia will bring with it the subjection "to the Divine Justice" of those who refused to submit themselves, in the Church, "to the order of His love." It will also bring about the reconciliation, in the Kingdom, of the cosmic order and the order of the "free grace of God." 20 Cultural and jurisdictionalperspectives.Although the sovereignity of Christ extends itself by right over all temporal realities, Congar affirms that in fact "He has established a clear distinction between l'Eglise, spiritual kingdom of the Faith, and le monde natural of humanity and history. "21 Congar's interest is, above all, to criticize medieval clericalism and its undervaluing of the "temporal order" (human work, the family, political life, etc.). True religious rapport remains situated, not on the side of the world, but rather on the side of the spiritual order. (Congar also tends to defend the "monastic ideal" as the goal of every Christian.) This vision in ]alons also shapes the Church-worldKingdom framework: a spiritual kingdom and a natural world 20 It is noteworthy that Congar places the world in a perspective that is partly theological and partly jurisdictional, and that the jurisdictional dimension carries special weight. The Church-world distinction appears situated in a phenomenological perspective (which was already dominant in 1935), which tends to distinguish, on the one hand, the Church and, on the other, the world which does not recognize Christ: the world of sin, but also the modern world which has allowed itself to be deceived by the myth of technological progress, the world of laicism which does not want to know anything about the Church. 21 Congar,Jalons, 111£. CON GAR ON THE LAITY 337 that journey together throughout history without finding one another until the advent of the definitive eschatological Kingdom. The diverse interpretations of authors who have studied the French Dominican's book lead one to think that Congar was unable to achieve in ]alons a complete explanation of the relationship and distinction between the Church and the world. But it is understood that his approach remained open to a further deepening on this point. In any case, for the Congar of ]alons, as he himself expresses it, the Kingdom is continually "maturing" in history to the degree in which it begins to exist in some way in the Church: that is to say, as the fruit of both the action of grace and human cooperation. This last point would be central in understanding the theological meaning of human work, in keeping with what Maritain called an "Integral Humanism. "22 The theology of history and the theology of work. These two theological perspectives in]alons focus on the context which was then called the "theology of earthly realities" (G. Thils). 23 The question at the time was: what meaning does temporal effort have with respect to the building of the Kingdom? Is it important that by this very effort the entrance of the Kingdom into history is brought about, or is the latter, on the contrary, a pure gift of God? 24 In the face of this disjunction, Congar maintains a middle 22 In ]alons Congar confronted both a naturalism or temporalism (an attempt to dissolve the Church in history), and a clerical spiritualism (an attempt to separate the Church from temporal and earthly realities). For this reason he emphasized the distinction between the Church and the world. But he lacked a theology of mission which could resolve the impression, which remained in the minds of his readers, of a separation of these two realities. What was needed was a better explanation of the relationship between the work of creation and the work of redemption. n G. Thils, Tbeologiedes realitesterrestres,2 vols. (Bruges, 1946-49; Paris, 194 7-49). For other studies of that time seeJ. Danielou, "Christianisme et histoire," Etudes (1947): 166-84; R. Aubert, "Discussions recentes autour de la Theologie de l'Histoire," Collectanae Mechliniensa (Mar. 1948) 129-49; and especially L. Malevez, "La vision chretienne de l'histoire: I. Dans la theologie de Karl Barth," Nouvelle revuetheologique71 (1949): 113-34; idem,"La vision chretienne de l'histoire: II. Dans la theologie catholique," Nouvelle revue theologique71 (1949): 244-64; idem, "Deux theologies catholiques de l'histoire," Biidragen 10 (1949): 225-40. l 4 These were, respectively, the positions of the "Incarnationists" (Th. de Chardin, G. Thils, M. Montudard, D. Dubarle, M.-D. Chenu) and the "Eschatologists" (represented by L. Bouyer), in the controversy that arose in France in the years immediately precedingJalons. 338 RAMIRO PELLITERO position,25 similar to the one that Gaudium et spes would later adopt, 26 and that may be synthesized in the following way: temporal efforts have meaning, for God will not annihilate any authentically human achievements. At the same time, the definitive Kingdom will come as a divine and gratuitous solution of that which humanity has tried without success to achieve: the harmony, integration, and reconciliation of all creation. We have already seen that, according to Congar, the world will not form an integral part of the Church until the end of time. But the "outlines" of the Kingdom are already visible in the world thanks to the mission of the laity. The world is not autonomous with respect to God, neither by its origin nor by its destiny. Nevertheless, throughout history, it enjoys a certain autonomy with respect to the ecclesiastical; it has a "natural" consistency that comes from its being the fruit of creation. There is an echo of this perspective in the affirmations of the Second Vatican Council with regard to the autonomy of earthly realities. 27 B) The "Approximations" to a Definition of the Laity According to Congar, the laity do not belong to the "structure" of the Church, but they do belong to the "permanent type" this structure takes in history. 28 In ]alons, the layperson See G. Colombo, "Escatologismo e incarnationismo; le due posizioni," La scuolacattolica87 (1959): 366-69. l5 Congar's point of departure is the unified plan of God. Between the world and the Kingdom there is a unity of end, of agent, and, at least partially, of subject or material cause. There is a certain material presence and activity of the Kingdom in the world. The Church and the world have the same ultimate end, but they do not share the same immediate end; they serve the end by different means and plans (see Pellitero, La teologiadel laicado, 168ff.). 26 Cf. Gaudium et spes 39. 27 Cf. Gaudium et spes 36. With respect to the notion of "nature" in]alons, see Pellitero, La teologiadel laicado, 465-71. 28 Congar here refers to the hierarchical structure of the Church, composed of the pairing of Christian faithful-sacred ministers. Laypersons as such certainly do not belong to this structure, nor do religious. With regard to the distinction between life and structure that appears in]alons, see H. Desroche's review in Revue de l'historie des religions 145 (1954): 245-52; and above all M. Meini, "II mistero complesso della Chiesa secondo Y. Congar," Rivistadi asceticae mistica 12 (1987): 129-45, esp. 143ff. CONGAR ON THE LAITY 339 emerges as, above all else, a member of the People of God, that is to say, as a Christian. At the same time Congar refers to the threefold distinction of the modes of being a Christian: sacred ministers, laity, and religious. This distinction is in accord with a terminology that goes back to the third century, reflecting a "permanent" structure in the Church. It is with these terms that Congar formally proposes his theology of the laity29 within the framework of a renewed ecclesiology. He offers what he calls "two approximations" to a definition of the layperson. First approximation: The laity, Christians who sanctify themselves in the world. Following an historical study of the sources, he concludes by saying that the laity are the "Christians who sanctify themselves in the life of this saeculum. "30 In other words, "the laity are called to the same end as the clergy and religious," but they achieve this end "without sparing themselves the commitment to the movement of this world, in the realities of the first creation, in the periods, stages and movements of history. "31 Even more precisely, he adds that the laity are called to do "the work of God in this world," emphasizing "to the same degree which it ought to be carried out in and by the work of the world." 32 Second approximation: The layperson values things "in themselves." Congar does not stop here, but goes a step further. He writes that the layperson must be "the one for whom, in the same work which God has entrusted to him, the substance of things in themselves exists and is interesting. " 33 For the cleric, and even more for the religious, explains Congar, worldly things are of Pellitero, La teologiadel laicado, chap. 3, pp. 14 lff . ]alons, 22 . .ll Ibid., 38. Commitment in the world means, for Congar, primarily marriage and professional work: "What characterizes the commitment of the laity in the world, in the profane, is marriage and professional labor (metier)" (Y. Congar, "Jalons pour une theologie du lai'cat d'Eglise," Masses ouvrieres(Dec. 1953): 27ff.). It is appropriate here to raise the question of celibacy and virginity: are these charisms incompatible with the lay condition? I do not think that they are (see Pellitero, La teologiadel laicado, 439ff.). Nor did Congar develop the relationship of "other Christians" (priests and religious) with the world. 32 Congar,Jalons, 38. 33 Ibid., 39. 29 .1o Congar, RAMIRO PELLITERO 340 interest not so much in or for themselves, or because of the demands of their nature, as for their reference to God, for their significance. Congar bases himself in St. Thomas in order to distinguish between the philosophicalpoint of view and that of the faithful, respectively assigning them the mission of the layperson and the cleric: The philosopher, we could say the wise man, concerns himself with what is proper to the nature of things, the faithful are interested in their transcendental reference. The philosopher looks for an explanation of things; the faithful, their meaning. One could still continue these reflections searching history for representative types or currents of the attitude of the faithful and the attitude of the philosopher respectively; in short, of the cleric and the layman.34 Congar denounces clericalism, from Charlemagne down to the present, for having lost "the internal truth of the second causes" (the proper demands of natural realities). This, he maintains, is the reason why laicism and the modern world have risen in protest against this tendency. What can be said about this "second approximation"? In the first place, this approach gives the impression of elevating a sociological and historical situation (the necessity of compensating for clericalism) to the level of a theological principle, with the risk of creating obstacles to the unity of the Christian conscience, perhaps excessively separating reason from faith, philosophy from theology. 35 Second, it is understandable that Congar might want to concede everything possible to modern laicism, but perhaps he goes too far, or his expression of the idea is ambiguous. He gives the impression that he leaves the layperson in the "territory" of laicism, without emphasizing sufficiently his condition as a Christian. 34 Ibid. 3-' On this and other points of ]alons, J. Danielou saw a concession to historical naturalism (see Dieu Vivant 25 [1953]: 150£.). See Pellitero, La teologfa del laicado, 465££. See also P. Guilmot, Fin d'une eglise clbicale? Le debat en France de 1945 a nos ;ours (Paris: Cerf, 1969), 209-21. CONGAR ON THE LAITY 341 In any case, what seems to be behind his ideas is that the "modern world" has brought with it the rediscovery of the active role of the laity in the Church, a role that, before all else, coincides with their "place" in the world as Christians. What is behind these judgments is, in all likelihood, an appraisal of the process of secularization which, beginning in the Middle Ages, survives today in a double and ambiguous sense: positively, it is the affirmation of the autonomy of earthly realities; negatively, it is the negation of God, or at least of his relevance in the world. Congar's somewhat rigid understanding of history and of the world influences this second approximation to the definition of the laity, diffusing the first somewhat. This concept of the world sometimes tends to shift the appraisal of the process of secularization from first sense to the second, 36 for lack of an adequate theological perspective (Christological, ecclesiological, Trinitarian, etc.)-a perspective that would only unfold with Vatican II. It is understandable that the council would pick up Congar's first approximation while remaining silent about the second. 37 III. THE LAYPERSON IN AN ANTHROPOLOGICAL-THEOLOGICAL PERSPECTIVE (CONCILIAR PERIOD) As the council drew closer, Congar saw the Church-world duality in terms of mission, juridical terminology giving way to a primarily theological approximation. This theology would also help him to avoid a spiritualism or supernaturalism that might 36 "To be secular is to use all the resources within us in that pursuit of justice and truth for which we hunger, the very stuff of human history." This is not a question, as Congar points out, of defining the laity in the sense of laicism (although in a certain sense this is the case), but of distinguishing between "laicism" and "laicity" (lai"cite), the latter being the positive and valid nucleus of the former. In any case, he understands that the characteristic of "laicality" (lai"calite)is respect for the nature of things, their laws, their needs; and that all of this is the condition of the road which God has willed for the majority of human beings (cf. ibid., 43). Regarding the lay condition, see Pellitero, La teo/ogfade/ laicado, 462ff. 37 The importance and the limitations of Jalons became clear with the later evolution of the theology of the laity (from Vatican II to Christifideleslaici),whose central insights were already operative through the pastoral phenomena aroused in the Church by the Spirit (e.g., Opus Dei), although Congar was not aware of some of them at the time he wrote his book. 342 RAMIRO PELLITERO disconnect the mission of the Church from the actual history of humanity and the world. At the same time, his vision of the laity is situated within the framework of the sacramentality of the Church. If the entire Church is "sacrament" (the sign and instrument of salvation) for the world, the layperson is the same within the temporal order. A) The World as the Object of the Church's Mission Beginning already at the end of the 1950s, Congar speaks of the apostolic activity of the laity in relation to the healing action of grace, with a view to consecrating the world to God (consecratio mundi). This "sanctification of the profane" affects the entire Church and every member of the Church according to his capacities in an organic way. The hierarchy exercises it above all by its magisterium, while "the laity exercise it directly and effectively, being like the yeast in the dough. "38 The anthropological and theological suppositions of this way of thinking are, according to Congar, the recognition of a certain autonomy in earthly realities, pluralism, the development of anthropological questions and the human sciences, and the difficulty of establishing a clear division between the Church and the world, especially "if one focuses on the existence or the concrete condition of the individuals who form one or the other." Congar particularly criticizes a theory that would reduce the Church to its visible dimensions or to that portion of the world which recognizes the sovereignity of Christ. 39 His perspective embraces a wider vision and is more self-critical with respect to ]alons. It embraces the vision of the Church as the People of God and as sacrament (sign and instrument) of salvation for the world ·18 Y. Congar, "Lare," in Encyclopediede la foi, IT, ed. H. Fries (Paris: Cerf, 1965). This text appeared for the first time in the HandbuchTheologischerGrundbefriffe(Munich: KoselVerlag, 1962), 436-56, with the citation on 453. 39 Cf. Y. Congar, "Eglise et monde dans la perspective de Vatican II," in Vatican II: L 'Eglisedans le monde de ce temps; Const. Pastorale"Gaudium et spes," ed. Y. M.-J. Congar and M. Peuchmaurd (Paris: Editions du Cerf, 1967), 15-41, esp. 19-22. CONGAR ON THE LAITY 343 with the anthropological dimensions of its mission.40 The Church appears as a sign and instrument of salvation (in Christ) and of a faith that coincides with humanity's deepest yearnings. The time has come, insists Congar, to give the sacramental priority over the juridical, and to move beyond the "perspective of powers." 41 During this period Congar also deepens his reflection on the way in which grace acts in the world. His ideas on this point can be synthesized in the following way: grace acts within the heart of each person, in the horizon of the Kingdom, which assumes earthly efforts and ends and gives them a new meaning. This metahistorical perspective is achieved, from both the cognitive and the existential point of view, to the degree that the person cooperates with grace. While in]alons the kingship of Christ does not manifest itself where it is not recognized, this kingship now extends to created or temporal structures. Here also the Church, the entire Church (not just the hierarchy), influences the transformation of the world, whether it be through the "pastoral word" of the Magisterium or through the holiness of the laity. The council expressed a sense for these same developments in considering the ordering of temporal realities (from within) toward salvation as the proper mission of the laity (cf. Lumen gentium 31 ). B) The Layperson Seen from the "Ontology of the Christian" In the years immediately following Jalons, Congar used the insights of Karl Rahner to define the layperson as "a Christian who embraces the conditions of his natural insertion in the world." 42 Congar was attracted by this formula because it helped 40 Regarding the sacramentality of the Church in Congar's writings on the laity, see Pellitero, La teologia del laicado, 456ff. On the theme in the ensemble of Congar's ecclesiology, see A. Galeano, "La eclesiologia de Yves Congar," Franciscanum 22 (1980): 141-204, esp. 170ff.; Mondin, "La ecclesiologia di Y. Congar," 424ff. 41 Congar, "Eglise et monde dans la perspective de Vatican II," 19-22; see also Y. Congar, "L'Eglise, sacrement universe! du salut," in Cette Eglise que j'aime (Paris: Cerf, 1968), 41-63. 42 Y. Congar, "Esquisse d'une theologie de I' Action catholique," text of 19 57 collected in his book Sacerdoce et laicat devant leurs t/Jches d'evangelisation et de civilisation (Paris: Edition du Cerf, 1962), 329-56. He places himself in dialogue with K. Rahner: the question 344 RAMIRO PELLITERO him to understand the lay condition in a way that was positive rather than negative, by means of an "internal characterization" intrinsic to the same lay condition: the force of the temporal commitment. But from the beginning, Congar had already pointed out that a positive characterization of the laity should be understood not so much "from the perspective of the world," as above all from the perspective of the Church and the mission she has with respect to the world. For this reason, he says that the laity embrace the world in the way that spouses embrace one another in the Lord. 43 In this period Congar defended a theological characterization of the laity on the basis of their situation in the structure of the Church, a structure that exists for mission. This "structure" is no longer reduced to the hierarchical structure of ]alons. Instead, it is the one reflected in Lumen gentium: the hierarchy, the laity, and the religious are situated within the very heart of the People of God (that is, of the Christian faithful). 44 In 1962, Congar described the laity in a way that recalled the "first approximation" of]alons: the layperson "seeks to serve God consisted in discerning whether the laity of Catholic Action were truly laypersons or not. For Rahner they were not, because the apostolate of the laity is based on being Christian and determined, not by a particular mission received from above, but rather by their existence in the world: "the plan of his Christian influence is the same as that of his relations in the world"; from this Rahner deduced that "participating in the hierarchical apostolate ... is to cease being a layperson" (K. Rahner, "L'apostolat des laics," Nouvelle revue theologique78 [1956]: 3-32, esp. 15-22). For similar reasons, years earlier, he had denied the lay character of the members of secular institutes, while for Hans Urs von Balthasar the best apostolic consecration of the laity would be the religious life in the world (cf. Hans Urs von Balthasar, Der Laie und der Ordensstand [Einsiedeln, 1949]); this "monastic" perspective would accompany Balthasar's theological work. 43 Cf. Congar, "Esquisse d'una theologie de I'Action catholique," 331-50. 44 See Pellitero, La teologia de/ laicado, 279-87. Congar was especially happy that the schema De ecclesia might include the figure of the laity "in the very heart of its dogmatic theology" (Y. Congar, "Debats sur !es laks," in Le Concile au ;our le ;our, III ses. [Paris, 1965], 74; see also "Vers une ecclesiologie totale: Pas d'ecclesiologie sans anthropologie: une theologie du laicat," in Le Concileau ;our le ;our, II ses. [Paris, 1964], 107ff.). The threefold structure "hierarchy, laity, religious life" has been developed in the perspective of the "fundamental structure of the Church," by P. Rodriguez, "El concepto fundamental de la Iglesia," in Veritati Catholicae. Festschrift {Ur Leo Scheffczyk zum 6S. Geburtstag (Aschaffenburg, 1985), 237-46. CON GAR ON THE LAITY 345 . . . in the course of human history, without evading an active compromise in temporal structures as such: simply exerting himself to use these structures according to the will of God and in a way which makes God their ultimate end. "45 This is his way of participating in the evangelizing mission of the Church and the consecratio mundi. One notes that the reference to the "things in themselves" has disappeared. It is also worthwhile to note that Congar is in line with Lumen gentium 31: if every Christian has a mission with regard to the Kingdom of God (a Kingdom in which history itself and the world are included by implication), to the layperson corresponds the mission of ordering temporal realities toward the Kingdom from within themselves, velut ab intra. In the addenda to the third edition of ]alons (1964 ), Congar issues a fundamental warning: it is not enough to refer to the laity as "the faithful," because a faithful-laity distinction "affects the orientation of all of ecclesiology."46 Concerning his "definition" of the layperson, he acknowledges the criticisms that had been made with regard to a rigid distribution of roles: to the laity, the temporal; to the clergy, the spiritual. 47 According to Congar, in 1953 he was not trying to create a purely canonical definition, but rather a definition-better still, a description-that was He insists, "The laity is that which refers to God the very reality of the elements of this world." This does not refer to any occupation whatsoever, undertaken with a spiritual intention, 48 but rather to an activity capable of being "intrinsically spiritual." The meaning of these words can be found shortly afterwards, in another text from 1967: the laity look for "the holiness of earthly existence itself," a life that possesses an 45 Congar, "Laic," 449. 46 Congar, jalons, 3d ed., 647 ff. On the distinction and the relationship between the "faithful" and the "laity," A. de! Portillo's study continues to be key: A. de! Portillo, Fie/es y laicos en la Iglesia: Bases de sus respectivosestatutos juridicos, 3d ed. (Pamplona: Eunsa, 1991; the first edition is from 1969). English ed.: Faithfuland Laity in the Church:The Bases of Their Legal Status, trans. L. Hickey (Shannon, Ireland: Ecclesia Press, 1972). 47 See P. Crespin, Qu'est-ce qu'un lai"t:?, text of 1962 quoted infalons, 3d ed., 648. 48 Such was the formulation of the Ecumenical Council of Churches at the time, which seemed insufficient to Congar. 346 RAMIRO PELLITERO "intrinsically secular character," and that, for this reason, must be oriented toward God according to its nature, laws, and proper ends, without regarding it as "sacred." This for Congar is what the council understands by sanctificatio mundi. 49 In reality, as Congar explains with reference to the baptism of adults, they continue to be what they were and to do what they had done before, but now all of this is given back to them as a mission. IV. THE LAYPERSON IN THE "THEOLOGY OF THE MINISTRIES" (IMMEDIATE POSTCONCILIAR PERIOD) Following the council, and most clearly in the 1970s, Congar introduced the question of the "ministries" in his theology of the laity. This choice signals a point of inflection in his journey. The result will be to accentuate the functional aspect of the lay 49 Y. Congar, "Situation du sacre en regime chretien," in La liturgie apres Vatican II: Bi/ans, etudes, prospective,Unam Sanctam 66, ed. J. P. Jossua and Y. Congar (Paris: Editions du Cerf, 1967), 385-403, esp. 400£. G. Philips had expressed himself in the same line as Congar before the council in "L'etat actuel de la pensee theologique au sujet de l'Apostolat des !arcs," Ephemeridestheologicaelovanienses35 (1959): 899. See also Y. Congar, "Dos factores de sacralizaci6n en la vida social de la Edad Media (occidente)," Concilium 47 (1969): 56-70. These "two factors" must have been (1) having taken the Old Testament as a model for the Christian life and (2) having shaped it according to sacred norms and paradigms taken from a "heavenly" sphere. Regarding the distinction "sacred/profane" in the Christian economy, see Pellitero, La teologia del laicado, 323-28. The transition Congar makes from ]alons to the council years may be summarized in the following way: the layperson is no longer, for Congar, the Christian of the "profane" world opposed to the Church. He is the Christian of a world that, although it continues to be profane in the sense of secular, or not sacred (in this sense the world continues to distinguish itself from the Church, a reality in itself ontologically holy or sacred), is profoundly related to the Church, as the recipient and collaborator in this salvation. The layperson embraces the conditions of his natural insertion in the world. but embraces it as a Christian (this is what Congar failed to explain before!). In ]alons he tries to overcome the idea that the laity are "sent" to the world by the hierarchy. In the council period he says clearly that it is Christ who "sends" them by baptism, with the mission of being the leaven of the salvation of the world "from within." From this period onwards, the perspective of liberation (understood as the promoting of justice, derived from the radical liberation from sin and its consequences) is introduced into the theology of the Church's mission. Congar shares this vision, and at the same time assigns the work of this liberation directly or immediately to the laity, that is to say, at the level of socio-political commitment and action (see esp. Y. Congar, "Place et vision du lalcat clans la formation des pretres apres le Concile Vatican 11," Seminarium 28 [1976]: 59-75). CONGAR ON THE LAITY 347 vocation and the interweaving of the different tasks that exist in the Church. Some people have seen in this a diffusion of the mission and the vocation of the laity in favor of the work of the entire Church. For this reason we are interested in pointing out certain nuances in Congar's texts. A) An Entirely Ministerial Church at the Service of the World The idea of a completely ministerial Church can be found, as we have already said, in Congar' s thinking at the time of Vatican II.5° Congar had observed that there exists in the People of God a double mediation or ministry: "a ministry in the heart of the Church, with the entire Church exercising a ministry with respect to the world. "51 His writings on the ministries in some way represent, and perhaps even inaugurate, the current that is called "the theology of the ministries. "52 This perspective contributed to overcoming a juridicist interpretation of the Church's mission, 53 and helped to create an understanding of the "secular dimension" of the entire Church 54 as a community organically structured for a single mission, with a diversity of ministries, vocations, and charisms (cf. Lumen gentium 11, Apostolicam actuositatem 2). "What is true in the Church," Congar would emphasize years 50 The council used the word "ministries" in the broad sense of functions, offices, or works, without abandoning the strict use of the term "minister" to refer to the office of the bearers of the ministerial priesthood. 51 Y. Congar, "Ministeres et lai'cat dans les recherches actuelles de la theologie catholique romaine," Verbum Caro 18 (1964): 127-48, at 139. 52 As factors that contributed to the formulation of the theology of the ministries, Congar indicates: (1) the historical study of Christian antiquity and the New Testament, (2) the renewed ecclesiology of Vatican II, (3) ecumenical dialogue, and (4) a new understanding of authority (cf. Y. Congar, "Ministeres et structuration de l'Eglise," La Maison-Dieu 102 [1970]: 7-20, at 7-9). 5·1 As G. Thils points out, Congar helped in the recovery of the idea of an ecclesial communion as "spiritual ferment" in the world, in the horizon of God's Kingdom (G. Thils, "Vingt ans apres Vatican II," Nouvelle revue theologique 107 [1985]: 22-42, at 24££.). 54 The expression is from Paul VI, "Discurso a los miembros de los lnstitutos seculares," Ecclesia 1581 (1972): 11. According to Congar, it is the People of God, doubly structured in its interior, which is, as a whole, "bearer of the mission, of the sign of the Gospel before the eyes of the world" (Congar, "Ministeres et lai:cat," 139). 348 RAMIRO PELLITERO later, "is that everyone does everything, though not in the same way or with the same title. " 55 Nevertheless, in my judgment, the perspective of "the ministries" involved certain risks,56 which may be summarized as two: on the one hand, undervaluing of the Church-world distinction and reducing the Church's mission to a socio-political liberation; 57 on the other hand, understanding the variety of functions as a result of a merely sociological distribution of jobs. Neither of these objections concerned Congar. He continued to defend the duality (never separation nor confusion) of the Church and the world. 58 He also maintained the distinction between the common priesthood of the faithful, as a fruit of "Christian ontology," and the ministerial priesthood, as regards the construction of the Christian community. As early as 1967, he had said that the danger of the postconciliar period consisted in losing sight of the transcendental character of the Church, dissolving her mission in the world as if it were of a "supplementary human value. "59 In Congar, then, the arrival of the 1970s does not signal a rupture of perspective in his ecclesiological thought, but rather a deepening in thought about the functional aspects of the Church. Among them stands out the relationship between the community and its ministers. B) The Figure of the Layperson in the Perspective of "Ministries" In this framework of a Church entirely in a mission of service to the world with a diversity of roles, Congar wrote one of his 55 Y. Congar, in B. Mondin, "Problemi e compiti della Chiesa oggi, secondo Ratzinger, Congar, Moltmann e Cullmann," Euntes Docete 33 (1980): 281. 56 See Pellitero, La teologfa del laicado, 389ff. 57 This occurred with liberationist theology, which implied an historical/ecclesiological monism and fell into a mix of secularism and a new clericalism. See ibid., 383ff., 480ff. 58 For this reason he was criticized by authors such as G. Gutierrez, A. Acerbi, P. Gilmot, D. Bonifazi, A. Manaranche, J. P. Jossua, L. Boff, F. Malmberg, T. I. MacDonald, D. Jagdeo, G. Angelini, P. Nonnard, and M. A. Chevalllier (these last two being Protestant exegetes). These critiques, of a very diverse character, are not, in my judgment, completely conclusive, above all if one keeps in mind Congar's entire itinerary. 59 Y. Congar, "L'apostolat des !ales d'apres le Decret du Concile," inA mes freres (Paris: Editions du Cerf, 1968), 47. CON GAR ON THE LAITY 349 most celebrated and important texts, included as a chapter in his book Ministries and Ecclesial Communion. The text is titled "My Path-Findings in the Theology of Laity and Ministries" 60 and here Congar undertakes a review of his journey in the style of the "retractions" of St. Augustine. He begins by reaffirming the idea he had in]alons: "I consider that the definition or rather the description of the layman proposed there (it is taken up by Lumen gentium, no. 31) had abiding value," that is, the positive characterization of the layperson first as a member of the People of God, as a Christian. In a second dimension, "I characterised the layman in positive fashion, by his secularity [laicalite]." The layperson "is the Christian who serves God and his Kingdom in and by his natural engagement in this-worldly activities." 61 Following this, Congar synthesizes his theological journey from the formulation of]alons, through the incorporation of a Rahnerian perspective, to the time of the council and the postconciliar period: The layman is properly that Christian whose service of God is exercised from within his insertion into the structures and the activity of the world, a service which the ministerial priest carries out in another manner as a consecrated minister of the positive means of salvation. 62 Let us keep these two points of Congar' s understanding of the laity in mind: (a) Christian identity and (b) ecclesial service from temporal structures as the proper form of their Christian mission. Congar acknowledges his interest, from the beginning of his ecclesiological work, in determining "the part that the layman may rightfully take in the internal life of the Church insofar as it is a positive, divine institution. "63 In this phrase can be found the explanation for the frequent reduction of the discussion on the 60 Y. Congar, "Mon cheminement dans la theologie du larcat et des ministeres," in Ministereset communion ecclesiale(Paris: Editions du Cerf, 1971). This text appeared in English as "My Path-Findings in the Theology of the Laity and Ministries," The Jurist 32 (1972): 169-88. See the analysis in Pellitero, La teologfadel laicado, 371-91. 61 Congar, "My Path-Findings," 172-73. 62 Ibid., 173. 63 Ibid. (emphasis added). 350 RAMIRO PELLITERO Church as mystery of communion to that of the Church as an institution, as well as the dependence of his reflection on the laity with respect to the clergy. 64 But let Congar speak for himself. He regards his vision of the Church in ]alons as suffering from a certain rigidity: "The inappropriate element in my procedure of 19 5 3 was perhaps to distinguish too nicely."65 We might add that he also gave the impression of dividing the mission of the Church into watertight compartments: the "priests" (hierarchy) as the keepers of the "structure" and the laity as those responsible for the temporal dimension. Now he tries to make it clear that these two "missions" are not so absolutely distinct. He proposes changing the structure-community binomial 66 to that of ministers-community. He explains that "the Church of God is not built up solely by the actions of the official presbyteral ministry"; 67 it does not depend solely on the action of Christ, but also on that of the Holy Spirit. The Church is also constructed, for this reason, by many services more or less occasional or stable, or eventually recognized by a consecration that is not sacramental-modes of service that "relate, if not to the upbuilding of 64 Congar recognized this explicitly some time afterward: "we have thought ... of the status and the activities of the laity in dependence on those of the priests in an exaggerated way. P. Danielou helped us to realize this then" (Congar, "Place et vision du lalcat," 61). 65 Congar, "My Path-Findings," 174. 66 In this duality "structure-community," explains Congar, the minister remains in some way situated before and outside of the community, as a "separate instrumental cause" of the Church, so that it was possible to place him between Christ and the Church, following the scheme Christ-Hierarchy-Church. 67 In another text from the previous year he specifies that the ministries ought to be focused on as a "structuration in the heart of a thoroughly alive Christian community. The ministry does not create the community from without and above. He is situated within it by the Lord in order to sustain and build it." At the same time, Congar adds, it is also impossible to say that the ministers derive from the community, "at least one cannot say this purely and simply, but there is a sense according to which not only do the ministers come from the Church, but also the ministers are made up by the Church, representing and personifying the community" (Congar, "Ministeres et structuration," 10-12). The ministers are raised up by God, by the Holy Spirit, in a community (up to this point is what was accepted by the Protestants); but certain ministries depend directly upon the Christ of history (a Catholic perspective). This means, in short, a balance "between a pneumatological point of view and a Christological point of view." "The sense of the hierarchicalact would be in representing Christ as the Head and Leader in the community, as much in an authoritative or superior aspect as in an aspect of animation and invigoration" (cf. ibid., 13-15). CON GAR ON THE LAITY 351 the Church itself, then to its diakonia." This refers explicitly to the nonhierarchical "ministries" (services), interpreting them in a charismatic perspective. He adds that "to move on to this double recognition . . . is extremely important for any just vision of things, for any satisfactory theology of the laity. "68 In the end, concludes Congar, "the decisive coupling is not the 'priesthood/laity' as I used it in]alons but rather 'ministries/modes of community service. "' 69 What follows from all of this for the understanding of the laity? If one tries to define the laity "entering by the door of the hierarchical priesthood," says Congar, one will conceive of them as participating in the apostolate of the hierarchy or as collaborators in the "priesthood." If, on the other hand, one enters "by the door of the community" one can begin to see the Church, invigorated by Christ and the Holy Spirit, as the bearer of the mission and the sign of Christ in the world. 7°From this it 68 Congar, "My Path-Findings," 176 (emphasis added). With regard to those ministries that would later be called "lay ministries" (beginning with the motu propio Ministeria quaedam, of 1972), Congar in 1976 clearly conceives of them as nonordained ministries, "whose sacramental foundation is Baptism." According to Congar, the nonordained ministries, whose reality is carried further than in Ministeriaquaedam,emphasize the activity of the faithful "each one according to their charisms" ("Place et vision du laicat," 62-64). 69 Congar, "My Path-Findings," 176. In another text from the same year Congar reels off the factors that, in his understanding, contributed first to the development of a theology of the ministerial priesthood "in itself," and later to the change of direction since Vatican II in the line of a Church toute entieresacerdotale(cf. Y. Congar, "Quelques problemes touchant Jes ministeres," Nouvelle revue theologique 93 [1971]: 785-800). See also Pellitero, La teologiadel laicado, 377££. 70 He proposes to substitute for the linear scheme Christ-Priesthood-Faithfultwo concentric circles "where the community appears as an enveloping reality within which the ministries ... are placed as modes of serviceof what the community is called to be and do." In this new scheme Congar situates pointers which point from the community to the ministries, expressing at the same time his desire to avoid "a democratic model of the modern political type" (Congar, "My Path-Findings," 178-79). He also rejects the idea that, from a Catholic perspective, the Church may be understood as a community that is first constituted and afterward creates its ministries as "presidents of the assembly," an idea which would be more in accord with a Protestant explanation. According to Congar in 1964, it is the People of God previouslystructured by the sacraments that is the bearer of the mission (" Ministeres et lalcat," 139££.). RAMIRO PELLITERO 352 can be understood that "it is no longer the layman who stands in need of definition but the priest. "71 Cougar's approach could, perhaps, have been translated as follows: "Therefore, the medieval divisions and restrictions are not absolutely adequate." As a result, the exaggerated emphasizing of the community in the structuring of the Church resulted in a nominalistic and functionalistic interpretation of the modes of being and living as Christians. Consequently, it no longer remained clear what was the identity and the role of each Christian. What remains then of secularity? This is the theme that confronted Congar in the final part of the description of his cheminement. He distinguishes three terms: secularism (a pejorative term that implies the exclusion in principle of religious affirmations); secularization(a term that is at least ambiguous); and secularity.This last notion, says Congar, "is the equivalent of what in ]alons I termed 'laicality,"' and "is simply a matter of recognizing the autonomy of created and this-wordly things in their own order." 72 The theology of ministries in Congar's writings supposes, above all, an accentuation of the coresponsibility of all the members of the Church. But it could be misinterpreted along the lines indicated here. Congar again raises the question, without resolving it, of how clergy and religious relate to the world. He does not, let us say, achieve the desired clarity and systemization necessary because he focuses excessively on the problematic "ministerial" dimension, without developing several conceptually previous perspectives, such as the spiritual and Christological dimensions of the theme. 73 On the other hand, his intuitions Congar, "My Path-Findings," 182. This expression, made at the time of an "identity crisis" for the priest, pointed, according to Congar himself, to the necessity of reaffirming more "effectively" the peculiarity of the priestly ministry (as had been proposed by the Synod of 1971). 7l Ibid., 184. 73 Above all, one misses a greater reflection as to what is proper to the priestly ministry and the religious life, and also about the temporal works of women with regard to the mission of the Church (see Pellitero, La teologfadef laicado, 397ff., 444ff.). On the relationship of the presbyters with the world, see R. Pellitero, Sacerdotesseculares, hoy: Planteamientos, reflexionesy [Jropuestassobre la "secularidad"de los [Jresbfteros(Madrid: Palabra, 1997). 71 CONGAR ON THE LAITY 353 about the charisms as complementary with the institutional aspects of the Church in line with Vatican II are very interesting. 74 For him the figure of the layperson has not changed, nor is his theology of the laity replaced by a theology of the ministries. But the secular nature of the laity as a distinctive feature remains diffused. C) The Layperson,a Christian "sine addito"? Perhaps it was the emphasis on the functional and ministerial dimension of the Church that, in 1976, moved Congar to write the following in a text about lay spirituality: "The layperson is a Christian sine addito; his spirituality is nothing more than the Christian life," proposing that "there is nothing more than one Christianity." 75 At the same time Congar affirms that "the lay condition has its donnees propres, against the ordained ministry or the religious state. For this reason it implies modalites that mark it as such." For this reason, too, it is worthwhile, according to Congar, to speak of lay spirituality as discerning "the values of a Christian life characterized by the full exercise of the activities of the secular city." The question of the "simple Christian" gave way to a discussion prior to the synod on the laity in 1987. Two tendencies were evident in the studies that preceded the synod. On the one hand there were those who supported the theological notion of Regarding this point, see R. Pellitero, "El Espiritu Santoy la misi6n de los cristianos: Los carismas, unidad y diversidad," XIX Simposio Internacional de T eologi'a,Universidad de Navarra (Pamplona, 1998), 505-40. 75 Y. Congar, "Laic etla"icat," in Dictionnairede spiritualite(Paris: Beauchesne, 197 6), vol. 9, cols. 79-108, the citation being in column 103. Up to the years of the council, the expression "Christian sine addito" meant for Congar the "Christian existence," that which was common to all Christians-that is to say, the condition of the faithful Christian. In 1969 he uses it in the sense of the "simple Christian," contrasted with the religious or clergy. (For a careful analysis of the theme, see Pellitero, La teologiade/ laicado, 397ff., 444ff.) Here the context is the same as the beginning of the chapter about the spirituality of the laity in ]alons: granting to the word all of its theological weight, there is really only one spirituality, the Christian. But on the descriptive and concrete level (existential) one can speak of diverse modalities of this spirituality, which may be distinguished from one another by their conditions, their works, and their proper resources. 74 354 RAMIRO PELLITERO the laity as characterized by secularity (indoles saecularis), along the lines of Lumen gentium 31. On the other hand there were those who preferred to speak of the laity as "simple Christians," as Christians sine addito, or as "Christians and nothing more." Concerned about secularism, the latter proposed a "theology of the Christian," and there were some who even wanted to abolish the very terminology of "laity. "76 Congar did not take part in this debate; instead, he substantially maintained his position until the end of his life. V. SECULARITYAS A CHARACTERISTICOF THE LAY FAITHFUL Beginning in the second half of the 1970s, Congar emphasized the Christological and pneumatological dimensions of the ecclesiology of Vatican 11.77 His reflection on the laity is, during these years, almost always indirect, and is centered in the action of the Spirit as the principal protagonist of the mission. 76 Among the defenders of the theological reflection on the layperson (in the line of Congar) can be numbered G. Lazzari, P. Rodriguez, J. L. Illanes, G. Chantraine, and E. Corecco. (In a more general perspective may be added W. Kasper, and among the Spanish ecclesiologists, J. M. Rovira Belloso and R. Blazquez.) Among the supporters of the "theology of the Christian" are G. Colombo (see esp. Colombo, "La 'teologia de! laicato,"' 9-27) and other Italian authors such as G. Angelini, A. Scola, G. Ambrosio, and I. Biffi. See J. L. Illanes, "La discusi6n teol6gica sobre la noci6n de laico," Scripta Theologica 22 (1990): 771-89. The "theology of the Christian" was supported by the fact that the laity form the majority of Christians, who do not need the sacrament of Orders or the religious "profession" in order fully to develop their Christian lives. This theology in addition has other "practical advantages" (see Pellitero, La teologia del laicado, 445-47). Nevertheless, in my judgment, there are three disadvantages in this way of describing the laity: (1) it is rather negative (the layperson is not ordained and not religious), (2) it ignores the distinction between "faithful" (the common denominator of all Christians, expressed in an abstract notion) and "layperson" (existential condition of a type of Christians), and (3) it doesn't explain the fact that the lay condition does not remain in the priest or the religious. To Pedro Rodriguez must go the credit for having raised the question of the proprium theologicum of the lay faithful: for this author secularity is a "structural" charism that qualifies theologically the position of the laity in the Church (cf. P. Rodriguez, "La identidad teol6gica de! laico," in La misi6n de/ laico en la Iglesia yen el mundo, ed. A. Sarmiento et al. [Pamplona: Eunsa, 1987], 71-111). 77 Y. Congar, Le Concile de Vatican II: Son Eglise, Peuple de Dieu et Corps du Christ (Paris: Beauchesne, 1984). CON GAR ON THE LAITY 355 A) Pneumatology and Mission of the Church Let us highlight, in this double perspective of the pneumatology and the mission of the Church, the aspects developed by Congar with regard to the laity. The spirituality of the laity. In 1976, he gathered his most important points from ]alons, indicating that the spirituality of the laity means "cooperating in the 'recapitulation' of all things in Christ." Their natural involvement in life and in the fabric of the world is precisely "the note of secularity by which the lay condition is characterized. " 78 The laity and cosmic pneumatology. In 198 0, at the root of his reflection on the Holy Spirit, 79 Congar points out two consequences by way of "rediscoveries" with relation to the laity: the complementarity of functions in the Church, and the theology of work in relation to eschatology. 80 Liturgy, ministries, and earthly life. In his final texts on the laity, Congar applauds the proclamation Vatican II made with 78 In the laity and for them, as Congar indicates, the Church "can be fully sign and instrument, the sacrament of the salvation of Jesus Christ for the world, so that their Christian life does not imply only the being of the Church in herself, but rather her mission in and for the world" ("Lale et laicat," col. 105). As the conditions of this Christian service to the world, he points out the necessity of specifically religious activities and of a life which is theological in its exercise, and the redisco\•ery of the place and role of the Cross. He sees the Cross in the purified use of temporal goods, in the value of sacrifice (above all in union with the Eucharist) and the understanding of one's failures, and, finally, as an indispensable element for the full communion with Christ. 79 Y. Congar,Je crois en /'EspritSaint (Paris: Editions du Cerf, 1980) (Spanish translation: El EspirituSanto [Barcelona: Herder, 1983]; English translation: I Believein the Holy Spirit, trans. D. Smith [New York: Seabury Press; London: G. Chapman, 1983]). In this work he develops the pneumatological dimension of ecclesiology, and also the relation of the Spirit with humanity and with the world; in this way he completes the markedly Christian vision of his earliest writings. 80 "Work seen as creation makes reference to the Father; seen in its redemptive value, it makes reference to the Son; in its reference to the completion which to eschatology, reference to the Holy Spirit" (cf. Y. Congar, La Parole et le Souffle [Paris: Desclee, 1984], 425-30). Regarding the secular nature of Christifideles laici, see R. Lanzetti, "L'indolc seculare propria dei fedeli laici secondo l'esortazione apostolica post-sinodale 'Christifideles laici,"' Alma/es theologici 3 (1989): 35-51. In relation to human work, see J. L. Illanes, Ante Dios y ante el mundo: Apuntes para una teologfadel trabajo (Pamplona: Eunsa, 1997). 356 RAMIRO PELLITERO regard to the dignity of lay Christians, together with the distinction of ecclesial functions. He sees this dignity expressing itself above all in the celebration of the liturgy and considers the possibility of lay collaboration in some ministerial tasks ("ministries"). 81 B) The Presentationof "Christifideleslaici" (1989) Without a doubt the most important text in this last period is Congar's introduction to the French edition of the post-synodal apostolic exhortation Christifideles laici.82 Congar praises the richness of its content, its structure and unity, and its connection to Vatican II and the Scriptures. In the context of the documentthe Church as mystery, communion, and mission-Congar emphasizes that the perspective of mission is bound to the Church's reflection on her own identity (Lumen gentium) and her relationship with the world (Gaudium et spes). He emphasizes three points: (1) the responsibility of the laity as active subjects in the Church and human history, (2) the value of the "spontaneous ministries" (nonordained) together with the ordained ministers and the charisms, and (3) the anthropological and theological foundation of the distinction between men and women and the contribution of women in society and in the Church. His two suggestions for reading the exhortation are particularly interesting, because they demonstrate clearly what Congar, once he had presented the document's fundamental features, considered most important in it. First, "the laity," says Congar, "are called in Latin fide/es laici in order to indicate those Christians living a lay condition, characterized as the Council says, by secularity." He adds, 81 Y. Congar, "Les hues ont part afaire l'Eglise, n in Les quatre fleuves (Paris: Beauchesne, 1983), 111-20. The following year, in an interview on the current situation of Vatican II, he insists on the role of the laity as "witnesses of the Gospel, but a Gospel which develops its demands ad extra, in the temporal life of menn (Y. Congar, "Vaticano II, un concilio vivente," Rivistade/ clero italiano 65 (1984): 402-8, at 407). 82 Y. Congar, "Introduction, n in Les fide/es lai"cs: Exhortation apostoliquede Jean-Pa11lII (Paris: Editions du Cerf, 1989), i-iv. CONGAR ON THE LAITY 357 parenthetically, "this word 'secularity', which evidently does not have to be identified with secularism, means that those laity have as their proper mission living the Christian and apostolic life in the life of the secular world and its structures." 83 It is worth noting that this notion of the laity is practically that of 1957 (in dialogue with Rabner), although Congar did not employ the term "secularity" then, as well as the one which in 1971 he regarded as the substance of]alons: the theological characterization of the laity by their secularity. 84 Second, Congar announces what we could call the "principle of totality" in the hermeneutic of magisterial texts. The document, he says, must be understood in its entirety, avoiding partial readings. Even more is this required when we are speaking, as is the case here, of "a text that is highly structured in its form and profoundly unified." The introduction concludes with a reference to the Virgin Mary. 85 • 3 Cf. ibid., iii. It is worth transcribing here the literal tone of the document, especially one of the paragraphs of no. 15: "The 'world' is converted into the sphere and the means of the Christian vocation of the lay faithful." By placing the term "world" in quotation marks, John Paul II refers to temporal realities, but at the same time he marks a distinction between the world and temporal, or earthly, realities. Note that Congar reserves the term secularity for the laity, which leaves open the theme of the "secular dimension" of the entire Church and the Christians within it. See Pellitero, Sacerdotesseculareshoy, esp. 105ff. 84 It is significant that Congar relates this idea to the vision of Vatican II. The absence of all references to the "sine addito" is also notable. Lastly, I would also point out that Congar speaks of secularity as a characteristic of the laity and not as an aspect of the Church. It seems to me that the document "completes" Congar's thinking when it says that "the vocation to holiness of the lay faithful implies that life in the Spirit expresses itself particularly in their insertion into temporal realities and in their participation in earthly activities" (no. 17). The indoles saecularisof the lay faithful is thus understood as an expressive sign, in the sense of sacramentality, of the life of the Spirit, and therefore of the action of grace in the world, and, more precisely, in the realities that arise from the first creation. 85 Congar, "Introduction," iii-iv. In this way, Congar is witness to the option taken by Christifide/es laici, clearly emphasizing the Christian dignity of the laity, but at the same time decisively assuming secularity as the theological characteristic of the layperson. With respect to this point, see P. Eyt, "La VII assemblee ordinaire du Synode des eveques," Nouvelle revue theologique 110 (1988): 3-15. 358 RAMIRO PELLITERO CONCLUSION As we have seen, in ]a Ions pour une theologiedu laicat Congar tried to define the position of the laity in relation to the priest, and saw the lay mission as developing within earthly realities. But the lay faithful remained too "lay" and not "faithful" enough. At the beginning of the 1970s he emphasized the ministerial dimension of the Church. As a result, he accentuated the coresponsibility of all Christians in the Church's mission. Nevertheless, in the so-called theology of ministries, some problems remained to be discussed (for example, the relationship of both the priest and the religious with the world). Besides these and other limitations indicated in my investigation, 86 one should remember the horizons opened by Congar, especially the provision of an ecclesiological status of Christian secularity from the "sacramental" perspective of the Church, with a single mission and a diversity of forms in its exercise.87 From the point of view of fundamental theology, Congar emphasizes what the lives of lay Christians bring to the credibility of revelation. The theology of the laity is presented today as a basic instrument for the new evangelization. Shortly before his death, Congar already saw a new Pentecost dawning, especially through the commitment and efforts of many of the lay faithful. 88 I believe 86 In particular, a certain confusion between the structure of the Church and the hierarchical structure in Congar's earliest writings; there are also some initial vacillations in a context which might be jurisdictional or monastic; some epistemological problems (above all in Jalons) when he tries to assess traditional perspectives about the value of earthly realities. In reference to ]alons, Page pointed out that "an overly-strict and uncritical utilization of Congar's first vision has been the source of distinctions which culminated in oppositions; the laity were confined to the 'consecration of the world' (which frequently degenerated into pure humanization), and it was only with reluctance, that their work in more intraecclesial fieldswas accepted" O. G. Page, "La theologie du laicat de 1945 a 1962," Communio 4, no. 2 [1979]: 17-26, at 21). 87 The Catechism of the Catholic Church describes the undertaking of the Church's mission under the corresponding section which, in my notes, I have considered the "fundamental structure" of the Church: "Christ's Faithful: The Hierarchy, the Laity, the Consecrated Life" (see nn. 871-73). 88 Cf. Y. Congar, interview given to Denise S. Blakebrough, ABC (19 November 1994), 75. CONGAR ON THE LAITY 359 that the decisive point lies in valuing what the sanctifying work of the laity represents in the economy of salvation history. 89 In the framework of the relationship and distinction between the Church and the world, through the vocation and mission of the lay faithful, and by their participation in the life of the Trinity, this life can become the life of every human being and the life of the world. As Pedro Rodrfguez wrote, The great effort of men which caused the fermentation of the Church's doctrine on the laity-from Congar to canon Cardijn and Blessed Josemarfa Escriva, a great precursor of the conciliar doctrine on the laity-was not to create a "theology of the laity" distinct from the rest of ecclesiology, or a "lay movement" or a "lay spirituality" contrasted with that of the rest of the Church, but precisely the contrary: these pioneers "restored" the laity to full status in the Church .... Today we could say that the rediscovery of the laity in the "century of the Church" has been, simply, an aspect of the rediscovery of the Church as communion. 90 teologfa de/ laicado, 486ff. "Prologue," in Pellitero, La teologiade/ laicado, 14. 89 See Pellitero, La 90 P. Rodriguez, The Thomist 65 (2001): 361-83 A RECENT CONTRIBUTION ON THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN MONOPHYSITISM AND CHALCEDONIANISM RICHARD CROSS Oriel College Oxford, England I n his recent work, Does God Suffer?, 1 Thomas G. Weinandy offers a powerful restatement of the Cyrilline and Chalcedonian insight that the Incarnation is to be understood in terms of a personal or hypostatic union, according to which divine and human natures are united in the person of the Word. According to Weinandy, this understanding of the Incarnation allows the Word to exhibit in his human nature, or as man, an attribute the contradictory of which is exhibited by that person in his divine nature, or as God. For example, the Word is impassible in his divine nature, or as God; but he truly suffers in his human nature, or as man. Weinandy contrasts this understanding with a monophysite one that sees the Incarnation as involving a union of natures. He argues that in such an understanding conflicts are bound to arise . between divine and human attributes. He spells this out by examining the body-soul analogy beloved of Chalcedonians and monophysites alike.2 For Chalcedonians, the body-soul analogy is used to highlight the fact of the union (182). For monophysites, however, the analogy is used to clarify the manner of the union: two natures united together form a tertium quid. As Weinandy understands it, this new nature will exhibit either predominantly 1 Thomas G. Weinandy, Does God Suffer? (Edinburgh: T. and T. Clark, 2000). All references in the text are to this work, unless stated otherwise. l Even Nestorians use the analogy, though they presuppose a very different anthropology (see ibid., 186-7). 361 362 RICHARD CROSS divine attributes (early-Church Eutychianism) or predominantly human attributes (post-Reformation kenoticism). According to Weinandy, then, the significant difference between Chalcedonian and monophysite Christologies lies in their respective capacities for accommodating putative contradictions. Supposing that the list of necessary divine attributes conflicts with the list of necessary human attributes, Chalcedonianism can, and monophysitism cannot, allow that the incarnate divine person is truly God and man, with all the attributes entailed by each nature. In this paper, I shall argue that Weinandy's position is false, and suggest that there is a far more rigorous way of distinguishing Chalcedonianism from monophysitism. I shall look at the issue more from a conceptual point of view than an historical one, though I will draw on insights of John of Damascus. Thus, I shall refer to the debate as one between Chalcedonianism and monophysitism, rather than between particular Chalcedonians and particular monophysites. I begin with an exposition of Weinandy's view, following this with a critique and then an account of my proposed alternative way of distinguishing between monophysitism and Chalcedonianism. The substantive contribution that I wish to make to the general debate between Chalcedonians and monophysites can be found in this third section. 3 I Weinandy's crucial Chalcedonian insight, from which all else is developed, is that two natures-divine and human-are united in one person, in such a way that they do not form some new, third sort of thing (a union of the two natures, in Weinandy's Chalcedonian language), but rather are possessed by one and the same person. According to Weinandy, a nature is a "manner of existence," and a person a "who" that exists in such-and-such a manner (197). Using this understanding of person and nature, Weinandy proposes the following summary of what I am labeling "Chalcedonianism": "Jesus is one ontological entity, and the one 3 Generally, my target is not Weinandy himself. He is a particularly lucid and persuasive representative of a Christological tradition that goes back to Cyril of Alexandria. MONOPHYSIDSM AND CHALCEDONIANISM 363 ontological entity that is Jesus is the one person of the divine Son of God existing as a complete and authentic man" (174). According to Chalcedonianism, there is one ontological entity, one who; this entity has two manners of existence-divine and human. Weinandy makes it dear that what I am labeling Chalcedonianism entails that all (concrete} predicates can be ascribed to the person. 4 He sees the fault of non-Chalcedonian positions as lying in their propensity to ascribe predicates to natures: more precisely, in their propensity to ascribe the predicates of one nature to the other nature. According to Weinandy, this is as true for Nestorianism as it is for monophysitism (177-81 [Nestorianism], 184-90 [monophysitism and its offshoots]}. He analyzes all monophysite Christologies in terms of an underlying model: the union of body and soul to constitute a human being. The basic analysis is worth quoting at some length: If one conceives the soul-body relationship as forming an ontological union, this gives rise to a new and third reality called man. To apply this model to the Incarnation necessitates that the divine and the human natures are ontologically united so as to form a new composite nature-a tertium quid-neither fully God nor fully man. Jesus may be one, but he becomes a hybrid, for the divinity and the humanity, like the body and the soul, are seen as constitutive components whose ontological fusion gives rise to a new kind of being. Moreover, because the incarnational union is modelled after the soul-body, and so conceived as a compositional union of natures, then the divine and the human attributes necessarily are predicated to the different natures. Thus the Son would be passible and so suffer and die within his own nature, and the humanity itself would directly assume the attributes of the Son's nature. Thus, an unworkable and intolerable tension results. Either the divinity is diminished or the humanity is mutated. Both are unacceptable for a proper understanding of the Incarnation. (184) At least two different criticisms are being made in this passage. The first is that monophysitism entails that the nature of Christ 4 We should exclude from this list of predicates trivial ones such as 'being predicable of a substance', or 'being a part of a substance', which can clearly be properties of a nature but not of a person. I shall assume this exclusion in what follows. I use single inverted commas when mentioning words, and double inverted commas when mentioning properties or attributes. 364 RICHARD CROSS is a different sort of thing from either divine or human nature, such that the whole Christ has neither divine nor human natures. In fact, this assertion would be denied by moderate monophysites,5 but this does not make much difference to the conceptions involved here. A moderate monophysite would claim that Christ's human nature is a part of some unified nature (perhaps "Christness") in a way analogous to that in which my soul is a part of my human nature. 6 A more extreme monophysite might claim that Christ is (fully) human while lacking human nature (i.e., Christ is human in virtue of the composite nature [perhaps "Christness"] that is proper to him). Weinandy's point is that one nature-however conceived-cannot be the locus for contradictory properties. If any version of monophysitism is true, the lists of divine and human attributes have to be trimmed so that there are no contradictory properties in the two lists; and this will result in the compromise either of the integrity of the divine nature (kenoticism) or of the human nature (Eutychianism). Weinandy's second criticism develops this line of thought further. Since, for example, being human entails being passible, it follows in the monophysite view that the divine nature does not include the property of impassibility. Weinandy infers that the Son would suffer "within his own [i.e. divine] nature." Again, the thought here is that monophysitism does not allow the different attributes to be parcelled off from each other in such a way as to allow them to retain any sort of independence. This second criticism presupposes that the features of a person that are had in virtue of a certain property will-unless there exist ways of dividing the properties into different groups-necessarily 5 By far the best account of monophysitism in the years after Chalcedon is still Joseph Lebon, "La christologie du monophysisme syrien," in A. Grillmeier and H. Bacht, eds., Das Konzi/von Chalkedon:Geschichteund Gegenwart.3 vols. (Wiirzburg: Echter-Verlag, 1954), 425-580. On more extreme monophysites such as Sergius Scholasticus, see Iain R. Torrance, ChristologyafterChalcedon:SeverusofAntioch and Sergiusthe Monophysite(Norwich: The Canterbury Press, 1988). Torrance's volume includes translations of the correspondence between Sergius and Severus as well as a very useful commentary. 6 Severus of Antioch, for example, would argue, roughly, that all human attributes can be found in Christ, and that they can be seen in abstraction from the divine ones without in any sense being really separable from the divine ones. MONOPHYSIDSM AND CHALCEDONIANISM 365 somehow affect all other properties of that person. This is on the face of it false, largely because we would not expect the features of a person had in virtue of one property to make any difference to the other properties of that person (though of course they make a difference to the person), whether or not the properties can be divided into different groups. 7 The first criticism is much more important, because it is in this way that theologians from the time of Chalcedon onwards have distinguished Chalcedonianism from monophysitism. Because in Chalcedonianism the attributes can be divided into two different groups (i.e., according to the different natures) Chalcedonianism can avoid Christological contradictions. There are no incompatible properties as it were battling for existence in the same logical space. Rather, what is true of the Word as God is not true of the Word as man. The two natures thus allow for semantic qualifiers that we can exploit in Christological predications. This insight is used by W einandy to criticize thinkers who both accept Chalcedon and yet feel the need to argue explicitly that contradictory attributes cannot be had by one and the same subject in the Christological context. Thus, he criticizes Thomas Morris and Richard Swinburne in this way: Both ... conceive the incarnational act as a union of natures similar to that of the soul-body, and it is for this reason that the conflict between incompatible or mutually exclusive attributes arises. Their solution is to offer a form of adoptionism, that is, the divine Son of God does not come to exist as a man and so is conscious of himself and thinks in a human manner, but rather the Son adopts or acquires the mind of the human Jesus. (189)8 The fact that Weinandy makes this criticism here seems to confirm the basic reading that I am offering: that on Weinandy's analysis someone (such as Morris or Swinburne) who worries 7 Nevertheless, Weinandy is right to think that even moderate monophysites-professedly following Cyril of Alexandria-talk in the way he criticizes here: see Severus's first letter to Sergius, translated in Torrance, Christologyafter Chalcedon,151, quoting Cyril's third tome against Nestorius, ch. 3 (PG, 76:137BC). 8 For Morris, see his The Logicof God Incarnate(Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1986); for Swinburne, see his The ChristianGod (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994), 192-238. RICHARD CROSS 366 about contradictory attributes has not really understood Chalcedon at all.9 As presented thus far, Weinandy' s view is that all attributes can be predicated of the person, or at least, of the person under certain descriptions. I shall return to this insight shortly. But first I want to deal with an ambiguity in Weinandy's presentation that might be thought to be more damaging than it in fact is. W einandy supposes, and I shall do so with him, that there is a sense in which we can think of the natures as subjects of predication: we predicate divine attributes of the divine nature and human attributes of the human nature. 10 The crucial contrast of Weinandy's view with monophysitism, given this concession, is that in the former attributes of the human nature are never made to be attributes of the divine nature, nor are attributes of the divine nature made to be attributes of the human nature. Equally, in Chalcedonian Christology, the attributes of both natures are never made to be attributes of a new composite nature. The point is important, since, as I will outline, Weinandy's interpretation of Chalcedon-once certain ambiguities in the account have been tidied up-actually requires that the natures can be in some sense be subjects not only of their own component properties but also (in the case of the human nature) of certain accidental properties. This insight might appear damaging, because an obvious way of distinguishing Chalcedonianism from 9 For a similar observation made of another contemporary Christologist, see Weinandy, Does God Suffer?, 198-99 n. 49, referring to T. W. Bartel, "Why the Philosophical Problems of Chalcedonian Christology Have Not Gone Away," HeythropJournal 36 (1995): 153-72. A criticism of Morris very close to that proposed by Weinandy can be found in Eleonore Stump's review of The Logic of God Incarnate(Faith and Philosophy6 (1989]: 218-23); for example. "If the only constituents of the human nature Christ takes on are those properties essential to human beings but not incompatible with any divine properties, what I share with Christ as regards human nature seems rather meager" (ibid., 220). 1 For example, Weinandy thinks of the human nature as the subject of human attributes (in contrast to the monophysites, who make it the subject of divine attributes): thus, monophysites make the divine attributes "wash ... into the human nature, making it omniscient and omnipotent, and thus not authentically human" (p. 186), and I shall consider more evidence for this claim in a moment when I examine Weinandy's treatment of qualifiers such as "as God," "as man." ° MONOPHYSITISM AND CHALCEDONIANISM 367 monophysitism is by arguing that Chalcedonianism never ascribes properties to natures, whether the divine nature, the human nature, or some composite nature (e.g, "Christness"). But in fact, we do not need to distinguish Chalcedonian from nonChalcedonian theories in this way, as I shall show. 11 Suppose that the divine nature is impassible, and the human nature passible. These two attributes-impassibility and passibility-are not as such straightforwardly attributes of the person, on pain of contradiction. But, according to Weinandy, they can be made to be attributes of the person undera certaindescription: the person is impassible as God and passible as man. How does Weinandy understand these as-qualifiers ("as God" and "as man")? The answer is not exactly clear. Sometimes, Weinandy speak in ways that suggest that he sees as-qualifiers as shifting the reference of the subject term of propositions that contain such qualifiers. Thus, sometimes asqualifiers specify that a nature is a subject. For example, according to Weinandy, for some contemporary theologians, it is not enough to say that the Son of God grieved, suffered, and died only as man, but remained unaffected as God. They wish to exploit the communication of idioms so as to establish the premise that God, even within the Incarnation, does indeed grieve and suffer as God. Even the death of Jesus affects his divinity." (175-76, emphasis added) Equally, Luther according to Weinandy interprets the communication of idioms as "the predicating of the divine and human 11 As a matter of historical fact, this hardly does justice to the position of moderate monophysites such as Severus. Such thinkers the basis of a notorious passage in the Tome of Leo canonized at Chalcedon (viz., "each nature performs what is proper to it in communion with the other")-that the error of the Chalcedonians was to ascribe properties (in this case, actions) to the two natures respectively, and thus, by treating the two natures as independent subjects of attribution, to subscribe covertly to Nestorianism. For the quotation from Leo, see his Epistola 28.4. The view that the natures can have attributes is odd, because we would probably want to think of attributes as much as of natures merely as manners of existing. So the natures do not themselves have further manners of existing; they just are manners of existing. Equally, to say that a nature has such-and-such an attribute is on the face of it just a way of saying that anything that has that nature has the attribute. If the divine nature is impassible, for example, then any person that has that nature-any divine person-is impassible. I will return to this below. 368 RICHARD CROSS attributes directly of the other nature, thus creating an impossible tension, for it is not God as God who suffers and it is not man as man who creates" (185, emphasis added). Another example is even clearer: "God as God cannot eat carrots for he does not have teeth, a mouth, a stomach, etc.... Suffering does not affect his divinity" (205, emphasis added). In all of these examples, the asqualifiers are taken as shifting the reference of the subject term from the person to a nature-or at any rate, allowing the subject term to refer indifferently to person or nature. Elsewhere, the issue is more complex. In the passages just quoted, it is clear that attributes of one nature are ascribed also to the other nature. The passages might be taken as suggesting the further move that it is in virtue of the ascription of properties to a nature that they can be ascribed also to the person. This sort of strategy is open to more orthodox forms of Christology too. In a passage that Weinandy cites from Cyril, this implication is made explicit: When it is said that the Son of God suffered and died, it is not meant "that God the Word suffered blow, nail-piercings or other wounds in his own nature (the divine nature is impassible because it is incorporeal) but what is said is that since his own created body suffered these things he himself 'suffered' for our sake, the point being that within the suffering body was the impassible." (201) 12 Here, the idea is that we can predicate suffering of the person on the grounds that the person's body suffered. The body is the immediate subject of the suffering, and the person derivatively the subject of the suffering. Weinandy's Cyrilline idea is that, while we cannot say that the divine person suffered straightforwardly, we can claim that the divine person suffered in virtue of his body's being the immediate subject of the suffering. Thus, the appeal to as-qualifiers, open to the Chalcedonian but not to the monophysite, allows the Chalcedonian to affirm that the Word in the Incarnation is fully God, with all the attributes traditionally necessary for being God, and fully ·man, with all the attributes 12 The quotation is from Cyril's second letter to Nestorius, 5 (Greek text in Cyril of Alexandria, Select Letters, ed. Lionel R. Wickham [Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983], 6). MONOPHYSITISMAND CHALCEDONIANISM 369 traditionally necessary for being human. More precisely, the use of as-qualifiers, open to the Chalcedonian but not to the monophysite, allows contradictory attributes to be ascribed, in different respects, to one and the same person. The Chalcedonian insight, according to Weinandy, is in effect that the only way in which attributes can be ascribed in differentrespects (divine and human) to one and the same person is if that person has two different natures, divine and human. II Weinandy's argument moves rather too quickly here. To see why, I would like to consider the use of as-qualifiers more closely, because it seems to me that they are susceptible of two quite different interpretations. Clearly, as-qualifiers are ways of pointing out that an attribute is had by a subject in virtue of some further feature of that subject. There are two different sorts of further feature that might be relevant here. First, the relevant explanatory feature could be a part of the thing that is the subject of the attribute; or, secondly, the explanatory feature could be a (further) attribute of the thing that is the subject. The distinction between parts and attributes or properties is not easy to explain, but I take it that parts are like substances in the sense that they are not the sorts of thing that can be exemplified. Parts themselves exemplify properties: my heart is a part of the substance that I am, and it exemplifies certain primary qualities of its own, some of which are also properties of me.13 It is important to understand that any first-order property that is not a property of the part of a substance is eo ipso a property of the whole of the substance, tertium non datur: there is no other sort of object (other than wholes and parts) that exemplifies first-order properties. 14 13 I examine all of this in much more detail in my "Parts and Properties in Christology," forthcoming. I consider too in this article how we should distinguish parts from properties on the assumption that properties are tropes. 14 First-order properties here are properties of things; second-order properties are properties of properties. Things are such that they cannot be exemplified, and the only nonexemplifiable objects available here are wholes and parts. 370 RICHARD CROSS In line with this, we can understand as-qualifiers in correspondingly two different ways (and only two different ways), and these different ways follow rather different linguistic rules. For those attributes that are had by me in virtue of a part of me, there is always a sense in which they are properties of the whole of me. 15 But they are not always straightforwardly properties of the whole of me. It is in virtue of my body's being bodily that I am bodily. But we would not want to say unqualifiedly that I am bodily, lest this assertion be thought to exclude the possibility of my being non-bodily too. To use a rather different example, a house that is made of bricks and glass is certainly made of bricks; but it is not straightforwardly made of bricks, because it is made of glass too. The second case is rather different. Suppose that there are some attributes of me for which it is not the case that they are had by me in virtue of a part of me. In some such cases, it is true that the possession of one attribute might be dependent upon the possession of some explanatorily prior attribute. I am in this sense derivatively the subject of the first attribute. In others, the attribute is had by me in the most basic way possible-that is, not in virtue of any other attribute. In both cases, our linguistic customs allow that the attribute is had straightforwardly by the subject, and as we will see there is a good reason for this. An example might make the matter a little clearer. Suppose it is true of Socrates that, as man, he is passible. His being human explains his being passible: being human is sufficient for being passible. We would not claim that Socrates as wise is passible, because wisdom is not sufficient for passibility. Socrates is unqualifiedly or straightforwardly human, and he is unqualifiedly or straightforwardly passible too. The reason that undergirds this linguistic rule is simply that there is no obvious sense in which Socrates is not passible, or in which he is impassible-even though it is not the case that he is passible in virtue of his 15 "In virtue of" is important here; there are some first-order properties of my parts that are not had by me--for example, the weight of my hand, which is a property of my hand but not of me. MONOPHYSmSM AND CHALCEDONIANISM 371 wisdom. 16 On this understanding of as-qualifiers, they cannot be used to sanction contradictory predicates, because all the predicates on this analysis apply to the subject straightforwardly. Given this distinction, we are in a better position to assess Weinandy's argument about the correct differentia of Chalcedonianism. Weinandy's argument relies on the claim that only Chalcedonians are in a position to use as-qualifiers. But I think that we have already seen enough to understand why this argument is flawed. The monophysite's body-soul analogy is in effect a part-whole analogy: humanity and divinity are parts of Christ in a way analogous to that in which body and soul are parts of a human person. And as I have pointed out, as-qualifiers can be applied in the case of part-whole relationships as well as in the sort of contexts in which Chalcedonians usually apply them. In fact, the situation is more complex than this simple refutation of W einandy supposes, although even this refutation alone is sufficient to show that Weinandy's analysis of Christological doctrine is inadequate. As I have just suggested, the only context in which as-qualifiers can be used to sanction the predication of otherwise contradictory predicates is when applied to part-whole relations. This conclusion is ironic, given Weinandy's assertion that the weakness of monophysite Christologies lies in their utilization of the body-soul analogy-and thus of a part-whole analogy. Let me apply this analysis more specifically to Christology, focusing first on the "attribute" analysis of as-qualifiers (the second sense just outlined), and then on the "part" analysis of as16 We can contrast this with the case of the house make of bricks and glass. In this case, there is a sense in which the house is both made of glass and made of not-glass (i.e., because it is made of bricks too, and thus not straighdorwardly made of glass). We simply do not say of Socrates that he is impassible, even though his passibility is had by him derivatively-that is, in virtue of his being human. For an attempt to argue that in effect these derivative attributes are had in such a way as to licence the predication of contradictory attributes in different respects, see John Haldane, "lncarnational Anthropology," in David Cockburn, ed., Human Beings, Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 29 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 191-211. An account of Haldane's sophisticated argument requires too much space to be given here. I provide a detailed discussion and critique in chapter 9 of my The Metaphysics of the Incarnation: Thomas Aquinas to Duns Scotus (Oxford: Oxford University Press, forthcoming). 372 RICHARD CROSS qualifiers (the first sense outlined above). Consider the two following propositions: "Christ is passible as man" and "Christ is impassible as God." Suppose we understand the as-qualifiers in the second of the two senses outlined above, namely, such that 'God' and 'man' pick out attributes of Christ (viz., "being God" and "being man"), and such that these attributes are not had in virtue of any parts of Christ. In this case, given the rules just proposed (rules that reflect our common-sense intuitions), "Christ is passible" is straightforwardly true, and "Christ is impassible" is straightforwardly true. So this understanding of as-qualifiers generates contradictions, and the as-qualifiers understood in this sense cannot be used to block contradictions. If we understand the as-qualifiers in the first sense, picking out a part of the subject, however, the situation is somewhat different. In this case, as I argued above, the as-qualifiers do not allow us to infer that the relevant predicate can be ascribed to the subject straightforwardly. So this use of as-qualifiers is of great help to the Christologist who believes that some essential divine attributes are contradictories of certain essential human attributes. Just as I am bodily and non-bodily in virtue of my parts (body and soul), so Christ can be passible and impassible in virtue of his parts (human nature and divine nature). But in neither case are any of these predicates applicable without qualification. Weinandy never explains how he understands as-qualifiers in the Christo logical context. To that extent a commentator is free to infer from what Weinandy says just what he might have in mind. It readily becomes apparent that he treats these qualifiers as though they draw attention to part-whole relationships. This makes his objection to monophysitism very hard to assent to. We should understand Weinandy's account of as-qualifiers to be drawing implicitly on the part-whole model simply because he supposes that as-qualifiers can allow us to predicate passibility and impassibility of Christ. For example, consider Weinandy's treatment of the correct logical form of the negations of propositions that involve asqualifiers. Weinandy holds that the proposition "It is not the case that Christ is passible as God" is equivalent to "It is the case that MONOPHYSIDSM AND CHALCEDONIANISM 373 Christ is impassible as God. " 17 On the attribute model, the asqualifier merely gives the reason why the Word is impassible.18 If the as-qualifier is understood in this way, then the two propositions ("It is not the case that Christ is passible as God" and "It is the case that Christ is impassible as God") are not equivalent. The first of these claims asserts merely that there is nothing about the divine nature that requires the possibility of suffering. 19 The second, however, asserts that there is something about the divine nature that precludes the possibility of suffering. The first of these is Christologically harmless. The second, however, generates a contradiction, because it asserts that it is unqualifiedly impossible for a divine person to suffer-and hence that it is impossible for an incarnate divine person such as Christ to suffer. On the parts model, however, it is clear enough that contradictory attributes can be genuinely predicated of one and the same subject, as Weinandy proposes. In this case, the two propositions "Christ is passible as man" and "Christ is impassible as God" are both true; the first asserts that Christ has a part that is passible, and the second that Christ has a part that is impassible. But these two assertions do not allow us to infer that Christ is straightforwardly passible, or straightforwardly impassible, and thus do not entail contradictions. As an interpretation of Weinandy's view, it must be admitted that this is problematic, because part of Weinandy's worry about the body-soul analogy (i.e., a parts analogy) is that it leads far 17 Thus, he cites with approval the Papal International Theological Commission's Theology, Christology, Anthropology to the effect that "the Church does not allow us to affirm formally that Jesus Christ could suffer according to his divine nature" (Weinandy, Does God Suffer? 202 n. 57), but clearly understands this to support his claim that God as God is impassible ("He who is impassible as God actually is passible as man"; ibid. 202). 18 The reason is that the attribute model, as I have sketched it, ascribes properties to the subject straightforwardly. If the subject is a man, such that "being man" is not an attribute had in virtue of a part of the subject, and if as man the subject is passible, then the subject is straightforwardly passible. 19 I do not here want to adjudicate on the sense intended by the Theological Commission, but merely to use the statement quoted by Weinandy as an example of his conceptual ambiguity at this point. If the ambiguity can be found in the tradition, it is no less an ambiguity for that. 374 RICHARD CROSS more naturally to either Nestorianism or monophysitism than it does to Chalcedonianism. There is in fact a good reason for this, though Weinandy never states it. The reason is that the most obvious part-whole relations are aggregation and constitution. In the first case, the Christological correlate is Nestorianism-two parts of a new whole that is not held together by any substantial ties. In the second case, the most obvious (though not the only) Christological correlate is monophysitism, the constitution of a nature from its parts. It may be that a Chalcedonian Christology could be developed along part-whole lines. The constraint on such an account is that the parts would have to be such as to compose a substance, one "ontological entity" in Weinandy's language. And in this case, Weinandy is right that Chalcedonianism (thus understood) is sufficient to allow the use of asqualifiers to block potential Christological contradictions. Butand this is the point at which I dissent from WeinandyChalcedonianism is not necessary for this. In so far as the monophysite Christologist uses the body-soul analogy for the hypostatic union, he will be in at least as good a position as the Chalcedonian to deal with putative Christological contradictions. It is simply not true that contradictory attributes cannot be had in virtue of one and the same nature, provided that the attributes are had in virtue of different parts of that nature. (Consider my being both bodily and non-bodily in virtue of my having body and soul as parts.) Thus Weinandy's fundamental account of the differentia of monophysitism cannot be right. Indeed, to the extent that monophysites have a way of spelling out the relevant sort of part-whole relations (i.e., parts of a nature), they are in a stronger position than Chalcedonians. It is worth noting, too, that Weinandy's use of as-qualifiers is ultimately too ambiguous to be of any help to the Chalcedonian. On the one hand, Weinandy accepts that as-qualifiers can be used to block potential contradictions, thus suggesting a part-whole Christological model; on the other hand he apparently rejects such a model as inconsistent with Chalcedon. In the next section, I will try to show why there are conceptual reasons for supposing that monophysitism is false, irrespective of MONOPHYSITISM AND CHALCEDONIANISM 375 any commitment to a part-whole Christology. I will use these reasons to try to propose an alternative account to Weinandy's of the difference between monophysitism and Chalcedonianism. III According to Weinandy, Chalcedonianism is sufficient in general for dealing with the possibility of putative Christological contradictions (such that, whatever the relevant attributes, the qualifier 'as' will deal with them). Weinandy uses this insight to argue that concerns about putative contradictions are-in effect-forms of rnonophysitism, such that Chalcedonianism is distinguished from monophysitism precisely in terms of the capacity of Chalcedonianism, but not of monophysitism, to deal with these sorts of putative contradictions. I have tried to argue that Chalcedonianism is no better placed than monophysitism to deal with these contradictions, and hence that this strategy cannot be used to provide a principled distinction between Chalcedonianism and monophysitism. How then should we go about distinguishing them? In what follows, I shall draw on an insight of John of Damascus to show that there is a principled way of making the distinction even if we suppose that the list of divine and human attributes of Christ cannot contain contradictory pairs, with or without the qualifying 'as.' On the face of it, John is an odd choice, since his standard way of distinguishing his Chalcedonian view from the monop hysi tism of his opponent Severus is exactly that proposed by Weinandy-namely, to assert that contradictory attributes cannot be had by just one and the same nature. 20 If my argument is right, John should not argue in this way. Sometimes, however, he proposes a far more fruitful line of reasoning. His proposal is that monophysitism is false because there simply is not a natural-kind "Christness" available for the second person of the Trinity to instantiate. 21 The idea is that we can carve the world up into 20 John of Damascus, Expositio fidei 47 (ed. Bonifatius Kotter [Berlin and New York: De Gruyter, 1973], 112, 11. 29-32). 21 Ibid., 47 (p. 113, I. 50). 376 RICHARD CROSS certain sorts or kinds: for example, human being, cat, dog, and so on. According to John, there is no kind "Christness" (i.e., "Godman ") just as there is no kind "wise-man" or "foolish-man." There may indeed be wise men and foolish men, but that is because there are men who are wise, and men who are foolish, not because wise men and foolish men are as different from each other as men and cats. There is a vast range of philosophical issues at stake here, but we need not discuss these now. Anyone who interprets Chalcedon in a realist sense is likely (and just as likely as a monophysite) to accept that there are natural-kinds. So all sides are going to agree here. The argument that there is no natural-kind "Christness" is effective against both stronger and more moderate forms of monophysitism. According to stronger forms of monophysitism, there is no sense in which Christ has divine and human natures; according to weaker forms of monophysitism, there is a sense in which Christ's one nature includes divine and human natures. If there is no natural-kind "Christness," then monophysitism is false in a way that does not entail the falsity of Chalcedonianism: and this is sufficient to distinguish these two Christologies. How does John know that there is no natural-kind "Christness"? His basic argument is that it is not possible for there to be more than one God-man, and John believes (reasonably enough) that anything that is a natural-kind must admit of more than one instance. 22 There are, however, two obvious objections to this line of reasoning. The first is that there is no reason to suppose that the claim that there cannot be more than one Christ is true-indeed, it was a standard medieval claim not only that more than one divine person could become human, but even that more than one divine person could become this human being, Jesus Christ. 23 So if we are to reject the claim that "Christness" is a natural-kind, it must be for a reason different from that suggested by John. 22 lbid., 47 {p. 113, II. 51-53). 23 On these, see my Metaphysicsof the Incarnation,ch. 7 and excursus 2, respectively. MONOPHYSITISM AND CHALCEDONIANISM 377 The second objection is this: why cannot "Christness" be something sufficiently like a natural-kind to count as nature even if there cannot be more than one instance of it? John hints at an answer to this. But, as we shall see, the answer is effective only against strong forms of monophysitism, not against more moderate forms. In effect, the thrust of John's argument is that strong forms of monophysitism are false in a way that does not entail the falsity of Chalcedonianism. So we can distinguish strong monophysitism from Chalcedonianism in this way. I will return later to weaker forms of monophysitism. John's insight is simply that something belongs to a kind if it has all the properties necessary for belonging to that kind. In the case of the Incarnation, Christ has all the properties necessary for being man, and all the properties necessary for being God. So Christ has human nature and divine nature, and monophysitism is false.24 Let me develop this thought a little further using the analogy of substance and accident. A black horse and a dappled horse are both horses since they have all the properties necessary for belonging to the kind "horse." A mule has some, but not all, the properties necessary for being a horse, and, crucially, it has some properties incompatible with being a horse. So a mule, although it has a horse as one of its parents, is a different kind of thing from a horse. A mule has a composite nature, in the sense of being a third sort of thing, different in kind from its parents. A dappled horse, contrariwise, has all the properties necessary for being a horse. In the case of the Incarnation, "man" is a naturalkind, and "God" is something close enough to such a kind to allow us to talk about it as a natural-kind. 25 The simultaneous instantiation of more than one natural-kind is not something that we find in our usual experience. But the case cannot be unlike 24 This argument is suggested by things John says in De naturacompositacontraacephalos 1 (Liber de haeresibus.Opera polemica, ed. Bonifatius Kotter (Berlin and New York: De Gruyter, 1981), 409, 1. 12). 2.; There are lots of reasons for supposing that "God" is not exactly a natural-kind. But these make no difference to my argument, and I shall ignore them for now. After all, even the most traditionally minded theist claims that God has (or perhaps is) a nature. 378 RICHARD CROSS that of a dappled horse. A dappled horse has all the properties necessary for being a horse, and all the properties necessary for being dappled. 26 The God-man has all the properties necessary for being God and all the properties necessary for being man. This line of reasoning is sufficient to allow us reject strong forms of monophysitism without this rejection entailing the 26 My examples here are not quite parallel to the case of the hypostatic union, since, for example, the dappling on a horse is in some sense an accident of the horse, whereas Christ's human nature is not an accident because human nature is a natural-kind. The analogy is close enough, however, for my purposes. Oddly, Weinandy objects to the use of the substanceaccident analogy in Christology. He criticizes a reading of Cyril of Alexandria according to which Cyril understands the union in person along the lines of the relation between substance and accident. It is easy enough to show that Cyril does speak in this kind of way (Weinandy's target is specifically Ruth M. Siddals, "Logic and Christology in Cyril of Alexandria," Journal o(Theological Studies n.s. 38 [1987]: 341-67, though it seems to me that Weinandy says nothing to rebut the reading of Cyril found in this excellent article). Weinandy's criticism is that Cyril elsewhere makes it clear that "the Son is God, and in the Incarnation, he actually comes to be man, and so equally is man" (Weinandy, Does God Suffer? 201 n. 53). This is hardly a criticism of the use of the substance-accident analogy; if someone gains a new accidental feature-say wisdom-then that person actually comes to be wise, and so equally is wise. Weinandy's difficulties are caused by an apparent misconception that if the humanity is acquired as an accident, then this would entail that the accident is "something that [Christ] substantially and existentially was not, but only a new characteristic attached to his divine nature" (ibid., emphasis added). I do not understand why Weinandy should accept the obviously false claim that, if the humanity were an accident, it would attach to the divine nature rather than to the person. (It should hardly need saying that Socrates's wisdom attaches to Socrates, not to his human nature.) But there is a substantive point being made by Weinandy too. If the human nature is an accident, then the Word is not "substantially and existentially" man. There is a sense in which the Word is not substantially and existentially man: he is not necessarily man but only contingently man. There is another sense in which the Word is substantially and existentially man: human nature, unlike wisdom or whiteness, is a natural-kind. But in this case the simple lesson is spelled out clearly by Thomas Morris: the orthodox Christian "will reject the view that every nature is an essential property of every individual who exists in that nature" (The Logic of God Incarnate, 172). Interestingly, some monophysites of the sixth century were motivated to deny that the humanity of Christ can count as a nature precisely because they accepted that natures are essential properties of those individuals who have that nature, and that there is no sense in which the human nature is an essential property of the Word: see for example the passages from Timothy Aelurus quoted in Lebon, "Christologie," 463 n. 28. We might reasonably claim something analogous to this: Christ has two natures (divine and human), but only one essence (divine), since the human nature is not essential to him. But this modern usage of 'essence' does not correspond straightforwardly to the Patristic ousia, either in Chalcedonian or in monophysite theologians. MONOPHYSITISM AND CHALCEDONIANISM 379 rejection of Chalcedonianism, and thus is sufficient to differentiate monophysitism from Chalcedonianism. The reason why "Christness" cannot be a natural-kind is precisely that if it were, we would have to accept that something could have all the properties necessary for being a man and yet not have human nature, and all the properties necessary for being God and yet not have divine nature. But human nature is just the conjunction of all the properties necessary for being human, and divine nature just (in some sense) the conjunction of all the properties necessary for being divine. And I have argued that possession of all the properties necessary for belonging to a kind is itself sufficient for belonging to that kind. If this insight from John of Damascus is right, it will be sufficient to show that monophysitism in its stronger forms (i.e., in so far as it is understood to deny that Christ has two natures in the sense just outlined) is contradictory, claiming both that Christ has all the properties required for being human, and that Christ lacks human nature. 27 . Can John's insight be used against weaker forms of monophysitism too-those that claim that Christ has a human nature, but that it is an inseparable part of a new composite nature (perhaps of Christness)? 28 Clearly, John's argument that there are no natures that can only be instantiated by only one hypostasis has a bearing here. But I do not know a way of showing that this argument is convincing. It may be that the difference between these weaker forms of monophysitism and Chalcedonianism are really little more than verbal. Both sides acknowledge that Christ has divine and human natures; they disagree ultimately about the sense in which these two natures are united, monophysites affirming, and Chalcedonians denying, that 27 In so far as having human nature is just a circumlocution for being man, stronger forms of monophysitism look straightforwardly incoherent; what could be the sense of claiming that something is man and yet lacks human nature? 28 Referring to the nature posited by monophysites as 'composite' was a strategy largely adopted by their opponents. I do not think that anything turns on this, and greater accuracy here would involve considerably more complexity in my account. 380 RICHARD CROSS the two natures combine to form a third nature that inseparably includes both of its component natures. 29 In evaluating this monophysite proposal much depends on the theoretical function that natures are supposed to play in the constitution of hypostases. For example, let us consider a robust account of nature-assuming perhaps in Aristotelian style that all natures are principles of action and operation. On this sort of view of nature, the monophysite will have two options. First, he could argue that the only nature in this sense in the incarnate Christ is the composite nature of "Christness," and thus that monothelitism and monergism are true. Historically, of course, this is precisely how moderate monophysites did argue. 30 But this means that the monophysite account does indeed ultimately compromise the integrity of the divine and human natures in Christ, which are no longer natures in the way that they are in other persons, divine or human. They are, after all, not principles of action and operation in the way that they are in other persons. In this sense, more moderate forms of monophysitism will turn out to be closer to stronger forms of monophysitism than their adherents admit. And in any case, monothelitism and monergism look to be undesirable positions from the point of view of soteriology. 29 Strictly speaking, moderate monophysites hold that the two natures are separable only 'in thought'. Coupling this with the principle that only discrete items can be counted, it is easy to see how they should have regarded the Chalcedonians' two-nature formula to amount to an assertion of two discrete items, and thus of two persons: see, e.g., Philoxenus of Mabbug, Tractatus de Trinitate et lncarnatione, ed. and trans. A. Vaschelde, Corpus Scriptorum Christianorum Orientalium, Scriptores Syri, series 2, vol. 27 (Rome: De Luigi; Paris: Carolus Poussielgue Bibliopola; Leipzig: Otto Harrassowitz, 1907), 43. Clearly, this criterion for counting is too restrictive: we can count non-discrete entities under a certain description (e.g., natures, sets of properties, etc.). Philoxenus clearly does not understand how Chalcedonians want to use nature language. He understands the Chalcedonians' two natures as parts--a sort of Christology that he believes to be Nestorian (see e.g. Tractatus, 4344)-and thus infers that the Chalcedonian view is that the natures, rather than the person, are consubstantial with, respectively, the Father and the human race (ibid., 44). The manifold forms of both monophysitism and Chalcedonianism would repay very deep further study. 30 See for example Severus's first letter to Sergius, in Torrance, Christology after Chalcedon, 153-56. MONOPHYSIDSM AND CHALCEDONIANISM 381 The monophysite could argue that the divine and human natures in Christ include principles of action and operation. But this argument would lead-intolerably-to three such principles in Christ, corresponding to each nature (divine, human, and Christ-like). And this would place strains on the unity of Christ that would be unacceptable even to a Chalcedonian. This robust account of natures looks to be true, because we would expect the set of properties necessary for kind-membership in the case of intellectual beings such as God and man to include principles of action and operation. Even were a monophysite simply to deny this we can still find ways of distinguishing Chalcedonianism from monophysitism, and in this case the reasons will indeed take John of Damascus's insight as their starting point. John's view is that the possession of all properties necessary for kind-membership is also sufficient for kindmembership. So something possessing all the properties necessary for membership of humankind will be a human being; something possessing all the properties necessary for being God will be God; and something possessing all the properties necessary for being both God and man will be both God and man. Can we develop this insight to show that it would not be possible for something that is both God and man to belong to a further, higher species such as "Christness"? Again, I would like to argue from more standard cases, since it seems to me that there is no point making the hypostatic union more unlike the sorts of union that we see in the created realm than it need be. (Mysteries, as it were, should not be multiplied unnecessarily.) It is clear that we never encounter cases in the created order where one hypostasis has more than one nature. A fortiori we never encounter cases in the created order where a creature has more than one nature such that these two natures are themselves the determinables (i.e., genera) for some higher, composite determinate (i.e., species or nature). Ultimate natural kinds such as "dog" or "cat" are not such that they could be genera for a further nature. The reason for this is that a genus is not the sort of thing that something can be unqualifiedly-nothing is just an animal without being either a dog, or a cat, or whatever. But species are not like this: things 382 RICHARD CROSS are just dogs, or cats, or whatever, in this way, without any further qualification. It is dear that a hypostasis can have two natures without these natures themselves being parts of some higher, composite nature; it is clear in other words that a twonatures Christology does not (as moderate monophysites hold) have to be reducible to a one-nature Christo logy. If we do not need this composite nature to explain unity, then we should not posit it. Chalcedonianism is distinguished from monophysitism in this case by its (perfectly understandable) refusal to allow ultimate species to function as genera. But in any case, this less robust account of natures-according to which a nature is not understood as necessarily including principles of action and operation-is probably false. IV On the face of it Chalcedonianism is no better placed than monophysitism to deal with putative Christological contradictions. It is misleading to claim, as Weinandy does, that a Christologist who argues that it is necessary to trim the list of divine and human attributes in such a way as to exclude any attributes the contradictories of which are had by the other nature has failed to understand Chalcedon. I have tried to show by way of prolegomenon that monophysitism, at least in the various simple forms I have been considering, is probably an incoherent position, and thus that Chalcedonianism is preferable to monophysitism. If my argument in section II above is correct (according to which the only way to allow the use of as-qualifiers as a way of avoiding contradiction is in the context of part-whole relationships), then there are two possible ways forward for constructive Chalcedonian Christo logy. One is to develop an appropriate part-whole Christology that can be distinguished from monophysitism. The other is to abandon the attempt to ascribe contradictory predicates to one and the same person. Which of these strategies we adopt will depend on how committed we are to the ascription to God of certain attributes that are incompatible with human attributes. If we are MONOPHYSITISMAND CHALCEDONIANISM 383 committed to this, then our best Christological efforts will be spent on developing appropriate part-whole models for the hypostatic union. For example, Weinandy's claims about divine impassibility are made in the context of a large-scale argument to show on the basis of Scripture, tradition, and reason that God is impassible. This explains his worries about the Incarnation. 31 Developing a suitable part-whole Christology will turn out to be very difficult, just because of the difficulty of finding ways in which a nature could be a part of any other substance. It seems to me that, to preserve Chalcedon, it is necessary to develop some theory of the divine nature, and some theological anthropology, that would jointly allow the instantiation of both divine and human natures in one person without the natures thereby being parts of that person. 32 This would involve doing more of the sort of careful work undertaken by the likes of Thomas Morris (though doubtless informed with a more developed historical sense than his), summarily (and wrongly) dismissed by Weinandy as ultimately monophysite. 33 31 How committed we are to divine impassibility might depend on how convinced we are by Weinandy's general argument in favor of divine impassibility. It seems to me that there is little reason to be so, and I have argued as much elsewhere (see my review of Weinandy's book in Reviews in Religionand Theology 7 (2000]: 420-22). Perhaps we should interpret conciliar pronouncements about divine impassibility as meaning that it is not in virtue of his divine nature that a divine person is passible; or that nothing can happen to God contrary to his will-that nothing external to God can cause an effect in God unless God allow it to. 32 Swinburne comes to a similar conclusion, presupposing a parts Christology to be unworkable: "Qua divine, Christ was impassible. There seems to be one dear correct point here. Suffering is something, pain, happening to you. A divine individual as the cause of all does not have things happen to him, unless he allows them to happen to him. So only if he puts himself in a special position, e.g. by taking on a human nature, can he suffer. But the denial that Christ, qua God, suffered cannot be read as a denial that God suffered. For a very dearly advocated patristic doctrine-and one to my mind dearly implied by the Chalcedonian definition-was the doctrine later called communicatio idiomatum ... , the doctrine that the human and divine attributes are predicable of the same individual" (The Christian God, 197). Ironically, then, Weinandy's treatment of the communicatio entails denying the very principle he wants to affirm. 33 I wish to thank Richard Swinburne and Tom Weinandy for discussing some of these issues with me. The Thomist 65 (2001): 385-407 OF WHAT BENEFIT TO HIMSELF WAS CHRIST'S SUFFERING? MERIT IN AQUINAS'S THEOLOGY OF THE PASSION W. JEROME BRACKEN, C.P. Immaculate Conception Monastery Seton Hall University South Orange, New Jersey R omanus Cessario, in his study Christian Satisfaction in Aquinas, rightly sees Thomas moving from a juridic to a personalist understanding of Christ's suffering. While it is true that Christ's suffering and death pay the penalty for original and personal sins, it is His personal act of love and obedience that satisfies for the original disobedience and lack of love of Adam. Consequently, by Christ acting in "solidarity with suffering humanity, penal suffering becomes 'once and for all' truly restorative and rectifies human willing." It is the rectification of human willing that enables us to join with Christ and enter into full communion with God, which is itself a triune communion. Thus Christ's satisfaction restores us to the image of God, which had been damaged by sin, and Christ's merit perfects that image so that we attain full communion with God in beatific vision. 1 This, we understand, is how Christ saves us. But what about Christ Himself, whose human image needed no restoration? Was His suffering only for us? Thomas contends that it was not. In fact, he seems to assume that Christ's suffering was for His own salvation when he writes, "Consequently, Christ by His Passion 1 Romanus Cessario, Christian Satisfaction in Aquinas: Towards .a Personalist Understanding (Washington, D.C.: University Press of America, Inc., 1982), 255; 260; 257; 166-67, 207. 385 386 W. JEROME BRACKEN, C.P. merited salvation, not only for Himself, but likewise for all His members." 2 How is this possible? He certainly did not merit the salvation of His soul, which is union with God, since, Thomas contends, from the moment of His conception Christ had sanctifying grace and was intellectually united with the very essence of God,3 the source of beatitude. 4 The only thing Christ could merit was the "glory of His body" and "whatever ... [pertains] to His outward excellence, as His Ascension, veneration, and the rest." 5 However, Thomas says that Christ already merited "the glory of immortality . . . in the first instant of His conception. "6 This would make Christ's Passion but another cause of this glory. But why accomplish the same thing in another way, when one way is enough? Furthermore, in what meaningful way does Christ's Passion contribute to His salvation when the ultimate salvation is beatific vision, and Christ had this vision from the moment of His conception? It will be the task of this paper to develop answers to these questions. Cessario gives us a clue as to how to do this. Aquinas, he says, lays out his programmatic investigation of Christ's Passion in the first three articles of question 46. 7 Shifting from the viewpoint according to which God and His justice required Christ's Passion, Thomas points to three ends for which Christ's Passion was willed: (1) that we be "delivered by His Passion" so that we might attain "life everlasting," (2) that Christ might merit "the glory of being exalted," and (3) that God's own "determination regarding the Passion of Christ" would "be fulfilled." 8 God's purpose, therefore, is much broader than the fulfillment of His justice. Furthermore, Thomas envisions the Passion as involving "various concurring means" which "are themselves helpful to such an 2 Thomas Aquinas, Summa TheologicaIII, q. 48, a. 1. Translations from the Summa are from the Benziger edition (New York: Benziger Brothers, Inc., 1947). 3 STh III, q. 34, a. 4 4 STh Ill, q. 34, aa. 1, 4; III, q.19, a. 3 5 STh Ill, q. 19, a. 3. 6 STh Ill, q. 34, a. 3, ad 3 7 Cessario, Satisfactionin Aquinas, 190. 8 STh III, q. 46, a. I MERIT IN THE THEOLOGY OF THE PASSION 387 end." These means involve human acts of love and the virtues, the merit of sanctifying grace and the glory of bliss, our being "more bound to refrain from sin" and the attainment of "man's greater dignity. " 9 Consequently, we can expect that Thomas will spell out in the rest of his articles how all these factors concur not just for our deliverance but also for Christ's exaltation and beatific vision. In other words, Thomas envisions Christ's Passion as an act of God's providence, which is fundamentally prudential. 10 God seeks to attain multiple ends, such as sanctifying grace and the resurrection of the body, with multiple means, such as the human act of Christ's Passion and our own acts. The view that Christ's Passion is an exercise of God's providence to produce these ontological effects is manifest in questions 46-4 9. Thus, Thomas writes that he will consider what God willed (the Passion itself [q. 46]), His willing it (its efficient cause [q. 47]), and the effect of what He willed (its fruits [qq. 48 and 49]). Article 1 of question 48 deals with what is first in Christ's intention (i.e., merit), and article 6 in question 49 deals with what is last in the execution of Christ's act (i.e., His exaltation). The notion that God acts providentially, that is, prudentially, through the human acts of Christ and ourselves to save us is what Lonergan describes as the upper blade by which the lower blade of data, from Scripture and Tradition, is organized in order to cut through to an understanding of Christ's Passion. Recognizing this structure can help guide one's understanding of Aquinas and thus answer the question, "Of what benefit was it to Christ to suffer and die, especially in regards His own beatific vision?" 11 SI'h III, q. 46, a. 3. SI'h I, q. 22, pro!.: "For in the science of morals, after the moral virtues themselves, comes the consideration of prudence, to which providence would seem to belong." By envisioning God's providence in terms of prudence acting for certain goals rather than in terms of God's justice, Thomas significantly departs from Anselm's satisfaction theory. The Passion makes sense not because it was necessary to preserve the order of justice in the world but because through it God could bring together many things that would contribute to and enhance Christ's and our salvation. 11 Bernard Lonergan, Insight;A Study of Human Understanding(New York: Longmans, 1967), 36; 577-578 9 10 W. JEROME BRACKEN, C.P. 388 I will capitalize on Thomas's notion that the intentions of the human act produce corresponding dispositions in the actor to explain how Christ produces salvific effects for Himself in His resurrection and beatific vision. I will consider first Christ's intention of merit (q. 48, a. 1) and then its corresponding effects (q. 49, a. 6). I. SUFFERING AS A PRINCIPLE OF MERIT (STh III, q. 48, a. 1) When Aquinas considers the meritorious role Christ's sufferings play in our redemption, his question is "whether Christ's Passion brought about our salvation by way of merit." The objections are as follows. Merit has to come from the person who acts, yet suffering is something inflicted upon a person, so suffering cannot be a source of merit. Charity is a source of merit, yet, as the objection correctly states, Christ's charity was not increased by His sufferings. In fact, as far as merit is concerned, it would seem that Christ's Passion is superfluous, since without suffering and in His very first act of charity, Aquinas contends, Christ merited salvation for Himself and for us. 12 In the sed contra Thomas cites Philippians 2:9 (the "lowliness of the Passion merited glory") and John 17: 10 (His glory was "not merely in Himself , but likewise in His faithful ones"). He then sets himself to show that Christ's Passion merits salvation. The theoretical reason Christ can merit for Himself as well as for us is the grace of headship. Grace establishes a proportion between the natural activity of suffering and the supernatural reward of salvation. By the particular grace of headship, Christ joins us to Himself so that we can share in both His act and its reward. The Gospel of Matthew states that suffering does play a role in this merit: "Blessed are they that suffer persecution for justice's sake." 13 "Consequently," Aquinas concludes, "Christ by 12 SI'h III, q. 48, a. 1, obj 1; ibid., obj. 3; ibid., ad 2. 13 This statement seems to imply the connection between voluntary suffering and salvation that Lonergan refers to in his Law of the Cross about the intrinsic connection that God establishes between sin, punishment, satisfaction, and salvation (Bernard F. Lonergan, De Verba Incarnato,thesisdecimaquinta ad decimam septimam.Ad usum auditorumeditiotertia MERIT IN THE THEOLOGY OF THE PASSION 389 His Passion merited salvation, not only for Himself, but likewise for all His members." The more important issue, however, is not whether Christ's Passion merits salvation, but how. It is with this issue that Aquinas grapples when he answers the objections. He addresses three important points: first, how suffering can be a source or principle of merit; second, how it merits our salvation; and third, how it merits Christ's. Aquinas states that Christ's Passion merited not on account of a greater charity, but because of the nature of the work, which produced a special effect.14 The description of the Passion as a work tempts one to think that Aquinas is referring to a previous definition of merit: "As it is an act of justice to give a just price for anything received from another, so also is it an act of justice to make a return for work or toil. " 15 In this view, Christ's suffering merits the way a worker earns his pay. In return for His work of suffering, God pays Christ by exalting Him and by removing the barriers that prevent us from enjoying Christ's previously acquired merits. This seems to be the view of Reginald Garrigou-Lagrange. Suffering is a principle of merit by being an object of the will. Although Christ offered Himself and merited man's salvation from the moment of His conception, His acceptance of death supplied an objective value His other meritorious acts did not have. 16 This interpretation raises a problem. If Christ offered His human nature to the Father from the moment He was conceived, how could the destruction of His human integrity add something of value to His original gift? Since the object chosen specifies the act, would not the choice of self-destruction specify Christ's act as evil? To see Christ's death as a valuable object to be chosen betrays what the Scriptures say about Christ being repulsed by His (Rome: Pontificia Universitas Gregoriana, 1964), 556. 14 STh III, q. 48, a. 1, ad 3. 15 STh 1-11, q.114, a. 1. 16 Reginald Garrigou-Lagrange, O.P., Christ the Savior:A Commentary on the Third Part of Thomas' TheologicalSumma (St. Louis: B. Herder, 1950), 565-66, 603. W. JEROME BRACKEN, C.P. 390 own death as well as one's God-given inclination to preserve one's life. There is, however, another way to explain merit. Aquinas writes that as "natural things by their proper movements and operations obtain that to which they were ordained by God," so Christ's dying becomes part of His movement to the Father and to eternal life. Since "the rational creature moves itself to act by its free will," Christ's "action has the character of merit," and what is obtained has the character of a reward. 17 Similarly, it is by the actions of our free will and under the power of the Holy Spirit that we merit (i.e., attain) eternal life. One obtains the reward of eternal life the way a runner reaches the finish line (1 Cor 9:24-27) or the way a vine obtains its grapes Un 15:1-10). The reward is intrinsically caused. Thus Aquinas calls the results of Christ's Passion "fruits. " 18 In the Passion Christ's merit arises from an inward principle, does a special work, and produces a special effect.19 Christ's death, therefore, is not a principle of merit in the sense of being an object of His will, as if His death were some good eliciting His will's movement. It is a principle of merit by being part of the will's command. Christ is faced with a choice between saving His own life or accepting His Father's bitter cup. He makes that choice out of obedience to the Father and out of charity, just as He made every other choice in His life. Thus there is no need for any increase in charity to perform such an act. 20 However, in order to execute this act Christ must command His body to be separated from His soul, so that He might hand His soul over to the Father. It is not only by His will and charity and other virtues that Christ lays down His life for the Father, but even by the process of His death. That is, "Christ received a command from the Father to suffer. For it is written Uohn 10:18): 'I have power to lay down My life, and I have power to STh I-II, q. 114, a. 1. Compare STh Ill, q. 46, pro!. where the results of Christ's Passion are seen as "fruits," with STh Ill, q. 48, pro!., where they are seen as an "effect." 19 STh Ill, q. 48, a. 1, ad 1-3. 20 STh Ill, q. 47, a. 2, ad 2; Ill, q. 48, a. l, ad 3; III, q. 49, a. 6; ibid., obj 2, ad 2. 17 18 MERIT IN THE THEOLOGY OF THE PASSION 391 take it up again: [and] this commandment have I received of My Father."' Accordingly the "Passion inflicted by violence did not take away His life, ... [rather] He preserved the strength of His bodily nature, so that at the last moment He was able to cry out with a loud voice: and hence His death should be computed among His other miracles." Like other miracles, it is done in the power of His own divine person. 21 Because of the power of His own person, Jesus' command touches not only His human mind and will, not only His interior and exterior senses along with their feelings and emotions, but even His very soul. Consequently, "Christ's Passion has a special effect, which His preceding merits did not possess, not on account of greater charity, but because of the nature of the work, which was suitable for such an effect."22 But what is this effect, and how exactly is it caused? II. THE EFFECT OF CHRIST'S MERITORIOUS SUFFERINGS: HIS EXALTATION (STh III, q. 49, a. 6) The traditional way for explaining how Christ's Passion produces its effect is to say that Aquinas connects the moral causalities of Christ's acts with the instrumental causality of His humanity. 23 So where the first five articles of question 48 speak of the moral causalities of Christ's Passion as meritorious, satisfactory, etc., the sixth article speaks of Christ's humanity as the efficient instrumental causality of God's grace. Thus Aquinas writes, "Christ's Passion, although corporeal, has yet a spiritual effect from the Godhead united: and therefore it secures its efficacy by spiritual contact-namely by faith and the sacraments of faith." 24 In question 49, as Cessario describes it, Aquinas speaks of Christ removing us from the evil of sin, Satan, and punishment and promoting us to the good of being reconciled with God and of having the gates of heaven opened for us. All the while Christ q. 47, a. 2, ad 1; III, q. 47, a. 1, ad 2 III, q. 48, a. 1, ad 3 23 Cessario, Christian Satisfaction in Aquinas, 201. 24 STh III, q. 48, a. 6, ad 2. 21 STh III, 22 STh W. JEROME BRACKEN, C.P. 392 acts through the instrumentality of His humanity and the sacraments. What is communicated, in Cessario's words, "is ordered ... to the accomplishment of the work of satisfaction, namely, image-restoration, and the perfection of the soul for the worship of God. " 25 This could mean that grace is bestowed upon us both to restore and to perfect us for the worship of God. 26 In this case the restorative effects would come from the efficient causality of the sacraments giving grace rather than from any acts that Christians perform. Moreover, the principal cause would not be Christ, the human instrument, but the triune God. But since Thomas says that Christ's Passion causes His own as well as our salvation, we are left with trying to explain how Christ in His humanity is both the instrument of salvation and that upon which the instrument operates to bring about His salvation. There must be another way to explain these texts. The texts in question point to two distinct activities. The first concerns the effect His act has upon Himself. The second concerns what the new effect in Christ enables Him to effect in us. We have already established, in examining article 1 of question 48, that Christ made the process of his dying part of his voluntary, virtuous, and charitable movement to the Father. In article 6 of question 49, Aquinas attests that the result of this movement is Christ's exaltation. That is, even though His sufferings added nothing to His charity, Christ "by His Passion ... merited to be exalted. "27 Again, it is God's word that gives Aquinas this conviction. "On the contrary," he writes, "it is written (Phil. 2:8): He became obedient unto death, even the death of the cross; for which cause God also exalted Him. "28 However, it is Aquinas's notion that human acts produce effects upon the actor that enables him to explain how this happens. His ChristianSatisfactioninAip4inas,209-18, 234-38; 236. The full text reads: "thus Saint Thomas has no difficulty in describing the effects of the sacramental system in the pattern of Christian life as satisfactory, and at the same time, expressive, both within formal liturgical structures and outside of them, of the worship owed by man to God" (ibid., 236). 27 See STh III, q. 49, a. 1, obj. 1, 2, 4. 28 STh III, q. 49, a. 6, sed contra. 15 Cessario, 26 MERIT IN THE THEOLOGY OF THE PASSION 393 working principle is, "A human virtue is one which renders a human act and man himself 'good. "' 29 Human acts produce habits in the actor: good ones produce virtues; bad ones produce vices. What needs to be shown is how Christ's Passion produces a good habit not in His powers of acting but in His own soul so as to bring about His exaltation and salvation. A) The Nature and Possibilityof Christ's Exaltation Aquinas begins by considering how the end result of Christ's Passion-His exaltation-is possible, since the very first objection to saying that Christ merited His exaltation is to deny its possibility. To be exalted is to be raised to a higher rank. At the highest rank is God. He has that rank because of His perfections, both in being and in knowledge. Thus, one is exalted to the degree one attains a perfection in being or in knowledge. While it is true that Christ from the moment of his conception was exalted in the perfection of His human nature by hypostatic union and in the perfection of His knowledge by beatific vision, He still lacked perfection in His soul's relationship to the body. Having taken on the punishment of original sin in which one is deprived of the gift of original justice,30 the soul's life-giving function was not sufficient to prevent Christ from suffering and dying. Of course, Christ would not have died if the glory of His soul from His beatific vision had flooded His body with glory, as it did in His transfiguration. 31 But this did not happen. Christ did die. Consequently, one has proof that Christ's soul as a formal principle of the body had not the power to communicate an immortality and impassibility to it. This means that Christ's soul lacked a certain perfection in this area. Being capable of receiving a further perfection, therefore, Christ's soul was indeed capable of being exalted, that is, brought closer to God in perfection. STh 11-11, q. 58, a. 3. STh III, q. 14, a. 1. 31 In Matt., c. 17 (1424-26; 1432 [Marrietti edition]). 29 30 394 W. JEROME BRACKEN, C.P. B) God•s justice and Christ•s Exaltation Having established the possibility of Christ's exaltation, Aquinas argues that it takes place through His sufferings, according to the law of justice.32 Reward, he says, follows the same order as punishment. But in explaining this order, Aquinas uses the testimony of the Scriptures and so refers to the order that God has established. Exodus 22: 1 states that if a person steals one sheep he should pay back four and that if a person deprives himself of what is his due he should receive it back and more besides. Aquinas cites this to indicate that God's order of justice is not simply a matter of rebalancing the scales. It is rather an order of growth and dedine--in terms not of goods that are restored but of a person's being. So, according to Philippians, Christ gains far more than He surrendered. Deprived of life, Christ gains a better life, a resurrected life. Placed in a grave in the earth, Christ ascends to heaven. Humiliated and made subject to others, Christ is raised to God's right hand to become judge of all.33 In this way, "by the union of the body and soul, the body was uplifted to a higher condition of nature, but not a higher personal state. "34 C) The Intrinsic Cause of Exaltation: Christ's Humanity In the second objection of article 6 of question 49 it is argued that there is no increase in charity and therefore there is no intrinsic principle in Christ's act of merit that could account for His exaltation. In reply Aquinas writes: Christ by his previous merits did merit exaltation on behalf of His soul, whose will was animated with charity and the other virtues; but in the Passion He merited His exaltation by way of recompense even on behalf of His body: since it is only just that the body, which from charity was subjected to the Passion, should receive recompense in glory. (Emphasis added) 32 STh III, q. 49, a. 6. Referring to Rom 4:4, Thomas writes, "Merit implies a certain equality of justice." 33 STh III, q. 49, a. 6. 34 STh III, q. 53, a. 1, ad 2. MERIT IN THE THEOLOGY OF THE PASSION 395 The italicized phrase defines in what way Christ's exaltation was "a recompense ... on behalf of His body." Thomas is not saying that Christ's exaltation is the Father's reward for His suffering and death, as if His Father valued His Son's destruction. As we have seen, Aquinas considers Christ's death not as the object chosen but as a principle of His meritorious act. Thus, Aquinas takes the concluding statement of the objection, " ... since charity is the principle of merit," and proceeds to show in his response that there are other principles, besides charity, that are involved in Christ's act of merit. On their account it is possible for Christ to merit His exaltation by His Passion and not by His other acts.35 D) The Meritorious Principles of Exaltation Since whatever is in control of Christ's will can be a principle of merit, 36 the fact that Christ's body "from charity was subjected to the Passion" is a cause of merit. It brought about His exaltation. Thus, because of the special power that Christ claimed to lay down His life and take it up again Uohn 10:18), His voluntary assent to the movement of His soul away from His body "merited His exaltation." To understand this one must consider Aquinas's answer to the third objection of article 6 of question 49. The glory of Christ's body, Aquinas indicates, comes from the glory of His soul. The soul acts as an intrinsic principle of Christ's exaltation. That is, the soul, as form to the body, is able to become the formal principle of Christ's exaltation. Moreover, Aquinas argues that Christ procured His bodily glory with greater honor. Since honor is based on excellence, greater honor implies a greater excellence.37 Indeed, Christ's body attains an excellence greater than it had before He died. He attained a resurrected STh III, q. 49, a. 6, obj. 2 and ad 2. See SI'h III, q. 48, a. 1, ad. 1 Of the relationship of the will and other powers see SI'h 1-11, q. 56, a. 4. Of merit and these powers see SI'h 1-11, q. 114, a. 4. 37 SI'h III, q. 49, a. 6, ad 2. See also "For honor is given to man on account of some excellence in him ••.. Now a man's excellence is in man's perfect good" (SI'h 1-11, q. 2, a. 2). Thomas Gilby in the McGraw-Hill edition comments on this phrase: "Man's perfect good, in the concrete, is not isolated in an apex animae, but comprehends his whole well-being or consistentianaturalis. Cf. STh 1-2. 10. 1." 35 36 396 W. JEROME BRACKEN, C.P. condition that was immune to death, He ascended bodily to the Father, and He is able to exercise judiciary power through His exalted humanity. Aquinas does not make explicit how Christ's meritorious act of dying could bring about this greater excellence of his soul, but a clue comes by connecting the previous article, in which he says that Christ's redemptive work overcomes original sin, with this article in which he says that Christ merited His exaltation. Out of pride Adam and Eve disobeyed God, arrogating to themselves the power to make their own judgment as to what is good and evil, even in the face of God's threatened punishment of death. Aquinas's describes Jesus' act as the reverse of theirs. Jesus humbled himself; He allowed Himself to be under the power of men, to be mocked in His person, to be subject to a "death to which he was not bound" and to have His body cast into a grave and His soul into hell. Because of this voluntary action, Christ, Aquinas says, "merited a fourfold exaltation from His Passion": the Resurrection, the Ascension, "the sitting on the right hand of the Father and the showing forth of His Godhead," and "His judiciary power. "38 By performing an act contrary to Adam and Eve's, Christ produced effects that not only remedied the defects of original sin but raised His human nature to a higher state. His act can do so for two reasons: the structure of the human act and its special power that comes from Christ's hypostatic union. Every human act is made of active and passive principles, with the active powers disposing the passive ones for future actions. Thus when one makes a choice, one inclines these powers to the object of that choice. That is, "human acts produce an inclination to like acts."39 When sin is involved, which is a choice between two contraries, one inclines one's self to that which is evil and opposed to that which is good. In so doing, one disposes one's self to do similar sinful acts in the future. Adam and Eve, however, did more than incline themselves to evil. For them the stakes were higher. They had at hand not only 38 STh III, q. 49, a. 6. 39 STh 1-11, q. 85, a. 1. MERIT IN THE THEOLOGY OF THE PASSION 397 the gifts of divine grace to attain eternal life but also the gift of original justice to withstand a temporal death. This gift of original justice kept their souls' apprehensive and appetitive powers in harmony, and it enabled their souls to hold their bodies in subjection. 40 When they confronted the choice to do their will or God's, they chose their own will. Instead of going to the infinite God to whom they were naturally and supernaturally inclined, they chose what was less than God. Consequently, they not only lost God and His gifts, they also disoriented the very powers by which they could have been united with God. Not going to their due end, their apprehensive and appetitive powers lost the harmony to which they were ordained and the gift of original justice which preserved that harmony. Consequently, with their sensitive powers rebelling against the control of reason and directing the will with its infinite desire to what is finite, their souls themselves became weakened. So indisposed, they could not for long carry out their purpose of giving life to the body. Consequently Adam and Eve and their posterity became subject not only to sin, but also to suffering and death. 41 Christ came to reverse this process. He could do so because He shared in the human condition. Even though His grace preserved His powers from any inclination to sin,42 it did not preserve His soul from the punishment of death incurred by Adam and Eve.43 Having neither original justice to keep the contrary powers of his bodily nature in check44 nor the overflowing influence from divine grace in His soul protecting Him from death, 45 Christ was subject to this punishment of original sin. For Christ to overcome this effect of original sin in Himself, He needed not only to direct His powers to their proper acts and ends by the power of His grace but also to affect the essence of His soul as it was the lifeform of His body. It is an axiom of Aquinas that one should STh 1-11, q. 82, a. 1; 1-11, 85, a. 5. STh 1-11, q. 83, aa. 2-3; 1-11, q. 82, a. 1, ad 1; 1-11, q. 85, a. 5; 11-11, q. 164, a. 1. 42 STh III, q. 14, a. 4; III, q. 15, a. 1. 43 STh III, q. 14, a. 1. 44 STh III, q. 14, a. 3, ad 2. 45 STh III, q. 14, a. 1, obj 2 and ad 2. 40 41 W. JEROME BRACKEN, C.P. 398 remove evil by setting up what is good. 46 Thus, since the evil was in Christ's body making Him subject to death, Christ had to give His soul a new disposition, one that would act as an irremovable life principle for His body. Christ gives this new disposition to His soul in the same way that Adam and Eve indisposed their souls-by a choice. His choice between two contraries is for the good. But it is a choice that is so deep and so powerful that it can affect not only the apprehensive and appetitive powers of His soul, but His soul itself. And it must do so precisely as it is the form of His body, for there is where the natural contraries of one's body which are causative of death can be overcome and where the indisposition from original sin lies in us who die. 47 E) The Act and Habit of Christ's Dying As we have already seen, Christ did make a choice between His own will and that of His Father. Moreover because Christ's act of dying is to be computed as a miracle, the effects of that act should be miraculous. They are in His Resurrection, Ascension, and sitting at the right hand of the Father. Consequently, Christ's soul can be affected, because he makes his choice through the power of His person. It not only affects the active and passive powers by which he operates but also the active and passive principles that constitute His humanity. When Christ chooses to do His Father's will rather than His own, Christ's will, with the supernatural powers of charity and His divine person, engages His soul as it is separating from His body and directs it to the Father. In so doing Christ confers a new power and a new direction upon His soul, just as an act of the will affects one's passive powers of apprehension and appetite, makes them active, and directs them to the object chosen. As an act of the will is the suppl. q. 12, a. 3, ad 2. I-II, q. 83, a. 2. "Now the origin reaches the soul as the term of generation, according as it is the form of the body: and this belongs to the soul in respect of its essence, as was proved in the First Part (Q. 76, A. 6). Therefore the soul, in respect of its essence, is the primary subject of original sin." 46 STh 47 SI'h MERIT IN THE THEOLOGY OF THE PASSION 399 means by which operative habits such as justice or fortitude are formed, so Christ's act of will, with its additional divine powers, is the means by which an entitative habit in Christ's soul is formed. As a result Christ's act of dying not only removes a weakness from His soul, but so strengthens His soul that it becomes the formal principle of His Resurrection. The good that Christ's choice causes in His soul is a habit, an entitative habit, similar to, but different from, the entitative habit of sanctifying grace. It is "the habit of glory. "48 The production of this habit follows the principles of merit and virtue, which Aquinas lays down in other parts of the Summa Theologica. First, one merits by bringing oneself to the term of merit. Second, the term or object of an act can be an effect.49 This is especially so in an act of virtue, since "A human virtue is one which renders a human act and man himself 'good.'" When one says, therefore, that Christ's act of merit in the Passion does a "special work," one can mean that Christ's act of dying is like a virtuous act; namely, not only is it a good act, but it makes Christ Himself good by conferring a habit upon His soul. This is possible, for although man cannot cause any entitative habits in his soul, God can.50 God causes sanctifying grace in man's soul and the divine person of the Son causes this new entitative habit in His soul through His human act of suffering and dying.51 On this basis, therefore, one can explain what Aquinas means when 48 STh suppl., q. 95, a. 5, ad 3. "But comprehension, or fruition as denoting comprehension, does not signify a habit distinct from those two (faith and charity), but the removal of the obstacles which made it impossible for the mind to be united to God by actual vision. This is brought about by the habit of glory freeing the soul from all defects; for instance by making it capable of knowledge without phantasms, of complete control over the body, and so forth, thus removing the obstacles which result in our being pilgrims from the Lord." That is a habit of soul, rather than a habit of intellect and will. • 9 STh 1-11, q. 18, a. 2, ad 3. 50 STh 1-11, q. 50, a. 2. "If therefore we take habit as having a relation to nature, it cannot be in the soul, that is if we speak of human nature: for the soul itself is the form completing the human nature .••• But if we speak of a higher nature, of which man may become partaker •.. nothing hinders some habit, namely, grace, .from being in the soul in respect of its essence." .<1 Compare STh III, q. 48, a. 1; ad 2-3 with STh III, q. 49, a. 6, ad 3; and with STh suppl., q. 95, a 5, ad 3. 400 W. JEROME BRACKEN, C.P. he says that "Christ's Passion has a special effect, which His preceding merits did not possess, not on account of greater charity, but because of the nature of the work, which was suitable for such an effect."52 The work that Christ did was to remove "some obstacles whereby we were hindered from securing the effect of His preceding merits."53 "For the removal of the obstacles which made it impossible for the mind to be united to God by actual vision (the goal of merit)," Christ brought about "the habit of glory freeing the soul from all defects ... making it capable of knowledge without phantasms ... [and] of complete control over the body." 54 The qualities of this habit are like the qualities of any habit that perfects the subject in which it resides.55 In Christ's act of dying, the subject perfected is His soul. Its specific perfections reflect the nature of the act that causes the habit. Since this act has reference to Christ's own divine hypostasis, to His body, and to His Father, the perfection bestowed upon Christ's soul reflects these references. F) The Qualities of Christ'sHabit Constitutionally, Christ's choice affects His soul in its relation to His divine hypostasis. Just as a virtue not only inclines the power in which it resides to the object of choice but also strengthens that power, 56 so Christ's choice strengthens His soul. By separating His soul from His body, Christ attaches it more strongly to His divine hypostasis, which confers on it a greater perfection of being. For this reason Christ's soul reaches a state of perfection that surpasses even that of the angels.57 52 Sfh III, q. 48, 3. 1, ad 3. 53 SI'h Ill, q. 48, a. 1, ad 2. SI'h suppl., q. 95, a. 5, ad 3. SI'h I-II, q. 56; II-II, q. 58, a. 3. 56 SI'h I-II, q. 55, a. l; 1-11, q. 49, a. 2. s7 See In Heb., c. 2, lect. 2-3. 54 55 MERIT IN THE THEOLOGYOF THE PASSION 401 Constitutionally, also, Christ's choice affects His soul's relationship to the body. Since His soul has been given a perfection which makes it more perfect than that of the angels, Christ can infuse His body with new perfections of being also.58 He can confer upon His body the perfections of impassibility, immortality, subtlety, and clarity. These are the very same qualities that are conferred on the just at their resurrection. They all come from the human spirit fully controlling its material counterpart. Consequently "by the union of body and soul, the body was uplifted to a higher condition of nature, but not to a higher personal state. "59 Such an explanation is a way of expounding what Aquinas writes so cryptically: It was owing to a special dispensation in Christ that before the Passion the glory of His soul did not shine out in His body, in order that He might procure His bodily glory with greater honor, when He had merited it by His Passion.60 Just as Christ's soul would have been the formal principle of His body's glory because of His hypostatic union and beatific vision, so it becomes the formal principle of a greater glory because of the entitative habit and greater perfection it acquires from His dying. Finally, since Christ consciously chooses the Father and His will rather than what He humanly and naturally desires for His body, He orients His soul more to His Father than to His own body. Consequently, Christ's dying perfects His soul in its constitutional references to His Father. Christ merits His own excellence, therefore, by the intrinsic efficacy of His act of dying and the intrinsic efficacy of His soul as form to His body. The glory He manifests at His Resurrection comes not just from His beatific vision and hypostatic union but also from His soul gaining a new and permanent perfection. 61 ss Ibid. Aquinas gives the sign of Christ's exaltation over the angels. It is His attainment of immortality, the lack of which was the one thing that made His soul, with its hypostatic union and beatific vision, less than the angels. 59 SI'h III, q. 53, a. 1, ad 2. 60 ST'h ID, q. 49, a. 6, ad 3. 61 STh Ill, q. 45, a. 2 402 W. JEROME BRACKEN, C.P. G) Christ's Exaltation and the Goal of His Merit: BeatificVision If the Passion contributed to Christ's salvation, should we not expect that, in saving Him from the punishments of sin, it saved him for beatific vision? Aquinas does not ask this question, perhaps because he holds that Christ enjoyed beatific vision from the moment of His conception. Still, the question is worth asking. Would God have deliberately suspended the effects of Christ's beatific vision so He could suffer to redeem us and not have this suffering contribute to His Son's own beatific vision? Surely not. In fact, the happiness of Christ in beatific vision increased not just in extent but in intensity as well because of His Passion. Christ's happiness in the beatific vision increased in extent in so far as the happiness He experienced at the apex of His soul, from the moment of His conception, was extended to every part of His soul and body at the Resurrection. However, this increase in joy had little to do with His Passion but with God's ordination. As God had ordained that the joy of beatific vision be limited to the apex of Christ's soul so that He could redeem us through suffering, so, upon Christ's completion of this task, God ordained that this joy now be allowed to spill over into every part of His human nature. Instead of being a reason for an increase of joy, Christ's Passion was the reason for its suspension. This was not the case regarding the intensity of Christ's joy, however. The intensity of love is due not to the object loved, which Jesus completely possessed in beatific vision, but to the power and disposition of the one loving. 62 These were affected by Christ's Passion, both on the part of his knowing and on the part of His willing. That Christ's happiness increases on the part of His knowing can be seen on the basis of the principle that the more perfect the nature, the more perfect the operation. Beatific vision is due, on 62 m 11-11, q. 26, a. 7. Every act should be proportionate both to its object and to the agent. But from its object it talces its species, while from the power of the agent it talces the mode of its intensity: thus movement has its species from the term to which it tends, while the intensity of its speed arises from the disposition of the thing moved and the power of the mover. MERIT IN THE THEOLOGY OF THE PASSION 403 our part, to an operation of the intellect. The more perfect the nature that sustains this operation, the more perfect will the operation be. Christ's soul has the perfection of being that is due to its union with His divine hypostasis. However, His soul, as we have established, received a further perfection, namely, the habit of divine glory, from His act of dying. When certain saints gain this glory by dying in union with Christ, Aquinas says, they can have a vision of God clearer than that of some angels. Consequently, Christ, who was exalted above all creation as a result of His dying, should have the clearest vision of all.63 Christ's happiness in His beatific vision can increase on the side of His will as well. This increase, however, is of a unique kind. It is not due to Christ's charity having a greater power so as to reach some greater goal. From the moment of His conception Christ had attained the goal of happiness, an intellectual union with the very essence of God. That knowledge brought with it, as all knowledge of the good does, an immediate movement of love. Because God in His goodness was immediately attained in that intellectual union, the outflowing love turned into joy, which is the fulfillment of love. Since the attainment of God's essence involves an immense power of intellect and will and since the intensity of love is proportionate to that power as well as to the one loving, the joy that Christ experiences is one of great intensity. However, such a joy was experienced at His conception64 and was not brought about by His dying. The increase in intensity of Christ's joy comes from the changes wrought by the paschal mystery in his human nature and its powers of knowing and loving. All these changes make Christ more disposed to the God He contemplates in beatific vision. The more one is disposed to the beloved the more intense is one's love for the beloved. And when one is united with the beloved, the more intense is the corresponding joy. First one is disposed to the beloved in that one's knowledge of the beloved specifies the movement of one's love to what is good. One can become more disposed to the beloved when one 63 STh 1-11, q. 4, a. 5; ibid, ad 2; ibid., ad 6 64 ITh III, q. 7, a. 12. 404 W. JEROME BRACKEN, C.P. recognizes that there is a likeness between the two. If the likeness is that between what the lover has potentially and the beloved has actually, one moves to the beloved not simply because of the beloved's goodness but also because it means one's own completion. So the love is more intense. Christ already has this completion in beatific vision itself. The other kind of likeness, however, is one that Christ acquires through His dying and rising. It is the likeness between what the lover has actually and what the beloved has actually. In this movement of love one wishes to the other what one wishes to one's self. It is a friendship love. The friendship love that arises as a result of His Passion and Resurrection does not arise from charity. Rather, it arises from Christ's new likeness to the Godhead. It comes from the new knowledge He acquires in His dying, the new perfections that His dying produces, and His knowledge of these. This knowledge is new in that it is added to Christ's beatific vision, his natural intelligence, and His other gifts of knowledge. It is a knowledge that Christ gains through experience-the kind of knowledge to which Luke refers when he says that Jesus grew in wisdom before God and men (Luke 2:40) and Hebrews refers when it says that "Although he was a Son, he learned obedience through what he suffered"(Heb 5:8-9). 65 Furthermore, the experiential knowledge that comes from Christ's paschal mystery is primarily subjective. Christ does not come to have God as a new object of knowledge; rather, He comes to a new subjective awareness of Himself. This is possible, since whenever one has knowledge of an object one also has an awareness of one's self as knowing the object.66 Accordingly, with this new subjective awareness, Christ can assess the goodness of God as being more in accord with Himself. This makes Him all the more wish to God, in friendship love, what He wishes to 65 STh III, q. 9, a. 4; III, q. 12, a. 2. "Christ as Subject: A Reply," in Collection: Papers by Bernard Lonergan, S.J., ed. F. E. Crowe, S.J. (New York: Herder and Herder, 1967),176-79: 66 Bernard Lonergan, "Further, I should say that one and the same act is at once the act of the object and the act of the subject; inasmuch as there is a sensibileactu or intelligibileactu, an object is known; inasmuch as there is a sensus actu or an intellectus actu, the subject in act and his act are constituted and known." MERIT IN THE THEOLOGY OF THE PASSION 405 Himself. This occurs, however, not because God changes to be more like Christ in His humanity but because Christ changes in His humanity to be more like God in His divinity. When this change is complete, Christ's friendship love turns to joy. The first new awareness of Himself comes from His dying. When Christ surrenders to His Father's will and feels His soul sustained in that surrender, even as it is being sundered from His body, He is aware that His action is coming from the Father and is being sustained by something deeper in Himself than the union of His body and soul. In this differentiating moment, Christ experiences His own personhood as coming from the Father and as sustaining His very soul as He is dying. This gives Christ a new subjective awareness of Himself, similar to the subjective awareness that the Son has of His person in His divine nature. 67 In place of having an awareness of being sustained, the Son has an awareness of Himself as subsisting in divine nature; 68 in place of His action coming from the Father, the Son is aware of His nature coming from and being directed to the Father. 69 On the other hand, since human experience cannot in one moment mirror the rich experience of God, Christ next comes to experience not His person, but His human nature in a way that is similar to the way the Son experiences His divine nature. As a result of His habit of glory, Christ's human nature is inclined to the Father, and He experiences this inclination in a way similar to that in which the Son experiences His "habitude" to the Father in His divine nature. The differences in these experiences are twofold. The new human inclination that Christ experiences is qualitative; the divine inclination the Son experiences is substantial. 70 In God the 67 STh I, q. 32, a. 3: "Now the divine persons are multiplied by reason of their origin; and origin includes the idea of someone from whom another comes, and of some one that comes from another, and by these two modes a person can be known." 68 STh I, q. 29, a. 4: "Therefore a divine person signifies a relation as subsisting." 69 STh I, q. 28, a. 4: "and the relation of the one proceeding from the principle is called filiation." 70 STh I, q. 28, a. 1: "Such regard to another exists sometimes in the nature of things, as in those things which by their own very nature are ordered to each other, and have a mutual inclination; and such relations are real relations." STh I, q. 28, a. 4: "it follows that a real 406 W. JEROME BRACKEN, C.P. experience of His person and of His divine nature are identical, whereas in Christ's humanity they are two distinct experiences. So in Christ two entitative habits are operating, each making Him like God. The habit of sanctifying grace relates Christ's humanity to the divine nature of the Godhead. The "habit of glory" relates Christ's humanity to the divine Son. Whereas grace affects the soul as it performs operations regarding God as the object of knowledge and love,71 the "habit of glory" affects the soul as it is the subject of these operations. Consequently, while contemplating God in the beatific vision after His death and Resurrection, Christ, with this new subjective awareness of His person and His human nature, can perceive that there is a deeper accord between Himself in His humanity and the divinity as a result of His paschal mystery. With this recognition there is a more intense love. Since this accord between His humanity and divinity reaches a new completion at each stage of His exaltation, the intensity of Christ's joy increases at each new stage. It will be consummated when Jesus comes to exercise His judiciary and saving power on the last day. Since Christ's beatific vision includes the vision of ourselves, we need to say one more thing. In the past-as shown in His agony in the Garden-what God willed as comporting with Himself was very different from what Christ willed as comporting with Himself as human. 72 God willed a love that involved the human death of His Son and Christ willed a love that involved His human survival. But with the change in His awareness of His person and of His human nature, there now are things that God relation in God can be based only on action .... Hence, it follows that real relations in God can be understood only in regard to those actions according to which there are internal, and not external, processions in God. ..• In respect of each of these processions two opposite relations arise; one of which is the relation of the person proceeding from the principle; the other is the relation of the principle Himself. " 71 STh1-11, q. 5, a. 7. For grace is not a term of movement, as happiness is; rather is it the principle of the movement that tends towards happiness. n STh 11-11, q. 26, a. 7, ad 2. Charity conforms man to God proportionately, by making man comport himself towards what is his, as God does towards what is His. For we may, out of charity, will certain things as becoming to us which God does not will, because it becomes Him not to will them. MERIT IN THE THEOLOGY OF THE PASSION 407 willed and wills that comport with Christ in His humanity that did not comport before. No longer are the wounds in His hands and His side signs of being forsaken by His Father. They have become signs of His being sent by the Father to bring peace, joy, and forgiveness Uohn 20:19-23). Christ's sufferings and death, therefore, are not superfluous. They bring about the exaltation of His humanity and with each of its stages a more intense joy in the contemplation of the Triune God and of ourselves in beatific vision. The Thomist 65 (2001): 409-39 AQUINAS'S THEOLOGY OF THE INCARNATION IN LIGHT OF LOMBARD'S SUBSISTENCETHEORY MICHAEL B. RASCHKO Seattle University Seattle, Washington Therefore it is plain that the second of the three opinions, mentioned by the Master (Sent. iii, D, 6), which holds one hypostasis of God and man, is not to be called an opinion, but an article of Catholic faith. So likewise the first opinion which holds two hypostases, and the third which holds an accidental union, are not to be styled opinions, but heresies condemned by the Church in Councils. 1 H ere in the Tertia Pars of the Summa TheologiaeThomas gives his final judgment on the three opinions outlined by Peter Lombard on the mode of union in the Incarnation. Thomas condemns the first and the third as heresies and accepts the second not as an opinion but as the correct statement of the Catholic faith. As Walter Principe points out, Thomas and most of his contemporaries approached the theology of the Incarnation through a dialogue with these three opinions, in which Lombard had summarized the work of early Scholasticism.2 Thomas's adoption of the second opinion, then, is key to his theology of the person of Christ and sets the tone for his discussions regarding the Incarnation. Thomas's statement is a product of both the development of his own thought and the history of the discussion of the Incarnation in Christian theology. This article will therefore 1 Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae III, q. 2, a. 6 (New York: Benziger Brothers, 194 7). Principe, "St. Thomas on the Habitus-Theory of the Incarnation," St. Thomas Aquinas, 1274-1974, Commemorative Studies (foronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1974), 1:381. 2 Walter 409 MICHAEL B. RASCHKO 410 discuss the history of the theological discussion of the issue as Thomas perceived it, his presentation of his theology of the Incarnation in the light of his acceptance of the second opinion, the development of his thought on the Incarnation in four of his works that deal with the issue (the Commentary on the Sentences, the Summa contra Gentiles, the Quaestio Disputata de Unione Verbi Incarnati, and the Summa Theologiae), 3 and his discussion of certain issues having to do with the Incarnation in the light of his presentation of the second opinion. I. HISTORICAL BACKGROUND The history of the theology of the Incarnation as it is reflected in Thomas's writings may be divided into three parts: the boundaries established by the Fathers of the Church in their condemnations of various Christological heresies, the three opinions outlined by Lombard and the issues they raise, and the issues that arose in the late twelfth and early thirteenth centuries. A) The Patristic Boundaries Thomas's clearest exposition of the boundaries set by the rejection of the Christo logical heresies of the patristic era is found in book IV of the Summa contra Gentiles. This part of his work is the fruit of the time he spent in Orvieto under the patronage of Urban IV. In Orvieto Thomas had the time and the bibliographical resources to become familiar with the early councils of the Church. 4 When he presents this material in the Summa contra Gentiles he has the positions of ancient Greek and medieval Islamic thinkers in mind. Therefore, he follows something of the historical and genetic order of nine erroneous 3 Thomas Aquinas, OrdinisPraedicatorumCommentum in Quatuor LibrasSententiarum Magistri Petri Lombardi (New York: Musurgia Publishers, 1948); Summa contra Gentiles, trans. Charles J. O'Neil (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1975); Quaestio Disputatade UnioneVerbi Incarnati,in QuaestionesDisputatae(Rome: Marietti, 1949), vol. 2, pp. 419-35; Summa Theologiae(New York: McGraw-Hill, 1974). 4 Thomas F. O'Meara, O.P., Thomas Aquinas, Theologian (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1997), 23. AQUINAS AND LOMBARD ON THE INCARNATION 411 positions whose condemnations set the boundaries for Christian reflection on the Incarnation. He refutes them not by quoting the decrees of the councils that condemned them (the non-Christians for whom the work is written would not find these convincing) but through Scripture and philosophical arguments. He is not trying to prove the Christian belief in the Incarnation; he is establishing that these heresies do not represent the truth revealed in that mystery and that the proper statement of that truth is not contrary to reason. In his later Christo logical work Thomas refers directly to the decrees of the early councils, but he does not deal with their results in as systematic a way as he does in the Summa contra Gentiles. Thomas begins with the error of Photinus, the Ebionites, and Paul of Samosata, who held that Christ had only a human nature and that he merited by his death an outstanding participation in the divine glory. Here God did not become man; rather, an earthly man became God. This error is trying to protect the divine nature from any hint of change and to show the salvific movement of the human toward participation in the divine. However, as Thomas points out, the Scriptures claim that the Word became human. In refuting this error Thomas establishes the principle that from the beginning of his life Christ is divine and possesses a divine nature. 5 Thomas then deals with three positions that deny in various ways that Christ had a truly human body. The first, that of the Manicheans, held that Christ had no more than an imaginary body. Thomas rejects this position on the grounds that it reduces the incarnation to a fiction and denies Jesus' humanity. The second position, that of the Valentinians, claimed that Christ had a heavenly not an earthly body. It held that all matter is evil and that for Christ to have had a natural human body he would have had to participate in evil. Aquinas argues that Christ came to exalt our nature, not degrade it by comparing it to a heavenly body. He assumed a material body so that through his mediation it might be made incorruptible and heavenly. If Christ did not have a truly 5 ScG IV, c. 28. 412 MICHAELB. RASCHKO human body, he would not have shared human nature with us and so would not have redeemed us. Further, Christianity holds that it was God who came down from heaven, not a body. The third position is that of Apollinaris, who held that Christ's body was not assumed from the Virgin but was a product of the process in which the Word was made into flesh. Thomas holds that such an opinion implies that the divine immutable Word has changed, which is impossible, and that things that do not share matter and a common genus cannot be converted into one another. Thus the Incarnation cannot be understood to mean that the Word was changed into flesh; it means that the Word assumed flesh. In rejecting these three positions Thomas defends the Christian belief that Christ possessed a truly human body. 6 Thomas next turns to two positions that denied that Christ possessed a fully human soul. The first is that of Arius, who denied the human soul in Christ altogether and claimed that the Word served as the soul for the human flesh it had assumed. Arius could hold such a position and yet maintain the immutability of the divine nature because he held that the Word is a creature. Thomas holds that the Word is God and cannot act as the form of a body, lest the divine nature become mutable. He argues that if there is no human soul in Christ there is no true humanity, for the form of humanity is lacking. Thus the position of Arius denies that Christ shares the human species with us. Second, Apollinaris held that the soul of Christ was merely sensitive and that the intellective element was provided by the Word. Thomas replies that Christ would then lack true humanity, for a soul that lacks reason belongs to some other species. Thus Christ would not be of the same species as we.7 Thomas points out that the rejection of the first six positions has established that Christ is divine and that he has a true human body and soul. The last three heretical positions concern the union of these three substances. The first position is that of Theodore of Mopsuestia and Nestorius. Thomas states that both men held that the human body and soul formed a man, Jesus, 6 ScG IV, cc. 29-31. 7 ScG IV, cc. 32-33. AQUINAS AND LOMBARD ON THE INCARNATION 413 who shared a common nature with humanity and who was joined to God by God's indwelling in him through grace and through an affective union of his will with the will of God. While this union of grace and will surpasses that in any other human being, there yet remain in Christ two distinct natures and two distinct persons. What is said of one cannot properly be applied to the other for they share no common supposit. Thus it was the man and only the man Jesus who was born, suffered, and died. Thomas maintains that this denies the truth of the Incarnation, which says the Word of God was made flesh. He also claims that the union envisaged by Theodore and Nestorius does not differ except by degree from God's indwelling in all holy men and women (and it is not said that the Word became Moses or Abraham). Thomas uses many examples from the Scriptures to show how what is said of one nature is also said of the other and that therefore there must be a common supposit of both natures. Further, the pronouns used for Christ in the Scriptures are used with predicates appropriate to both natures. Thomas thus concludes there must be a unity in Christ and that unity is of supposit or hypostasis or person. 8 The second position is that of Eutyches, who in opposition to Nestorius sought to preserve the unity of Christ, but in doing so found himself in an error of the opposite extreme. He taught that in Christ the human and the divine natures combined to form a single common nature. For him the person of Christ is from two natures, but it does not subsist in two natures. Thomas refutes this position in several ways which will be seen later in his discussion of his own position on the union of the Incarnation. 9 The final error to be rejected is that of Macarius, who held that in Christ there is only one operation and will. Thomas argues that each nature has its proper form or principle of operation. Christ in possessing the perfection of both divine and human natures must then possess the principle of operation of each and the type of will that is appropriate to each. 10 ScG N, c. 34. ScG N, c. 35. 10 ScG N, c. 36. 8 9 414 MICHAEL B. RASCHKO By Thomas's account, the early Christological struggles of the Church established the following principles of orthodox Christology to which any subsequent Christology must adhere. Christ is divine and possesses the divine nature. He has both a human body and a human soul and these are joined to form a fully human nature. The divine and the human nature are united not accidentally or by indwelling or by personal relationship but in such a way that what is said of each nature is said of a common supposit or hypostasis. This union does not produce a union of the two natures into one common nature, for such a union of natures is impossible. Each nature maintains the fullness of its perfection and each retains its proper principle of operation and its will. 11 B) The MedievalFrameworkSummarizedby Peter Lombard The second area of the history of Christological thought that shapes Thomas's work is Peter Lombard's outline of the three opinions on the mode of the union in the Incarnation. Principe comments that these "were not three uniform positions but rather general groupings or tendencies, each with certain common presuppositions and each with general agreement on answers to the various questions proposed. " 12 The central problem in each of the three opinions stems from the Boethian definition of the term "person" as an individual substance of a rational nature. Given the duality of natures and the unity of person in Christ, the issue centers on the identity of person and substance which the definition implies. The first opinion is commonly referred to as the assumptus homo theory. It is a theory struggling to find a language adequate to its insights. As Lombard presents it, the proponents of this position held that in the Incarnation of the Word of God a certain man, made up of a rational soul and a human body, which constituted a true and fully human being, began to be God not 11 ScG IV, c. 39. The Theology of the Hypostatic Union in the E.arlyThirteenth Century (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1963-75), 1:65. 12 Walter Principe, AQUINAS AND LOMBARD ON THE INCARNATION 415 through the nature of God but through the person of the Word. This man was assumed by the Word, is united to the Word, and is the Word. This line of reasoning led its proponents to say that God became man, or is man, and that that human substance was made, or began to be, God. They were able to say this because God was made or began to be a certain substance subsisting in a rational soul and human flesh. This did not take place by the abandoning of one nature for another but by each nature being preserved so that it can be said that God has been made man and man has been made God and that God is man and man is God. The proponents of the opinion also held that the man subsists in a rational soul and a human body so that Christ the man is not held to be composed of two natures, divine and human. The two natures cannot be considered parts of that person; rather the body and soul are his components. 13 The assumptus homo theory seeks to preserve the full humanity of Christ. Given the Boethian definition of person, its proponents found themselves in the position of having to affirm a human person in Christ because Christ was fully a human substance with a rational nature. For them to deny that the assumed man was a person was to deny that human nature was assumed by the Word of God. They held for a personal union oriented toward the person, that is, a union that makes a thing to be a person. They looked to the union of body and soul as an analogy of this personal union. Thus Hugh of St. Victor held that just as in human nature only the soul is truly personal and that the body becomes the same person through union with the person of the soul, so in the Incarnation the Word is a person and the assumed man becomes one and the same person by union to the person of the Word, yet the human nature can still be said to be a human person. 14 Robert of Melun used a similar analogy: in Christ two substances become one person just as body and soul are one person yet remain two distinct separate substances. l.l 14 III Sent., d. 6. N. M. Haring, "The Case of Gilbert de la Porree Bishop of Poitiers," Mediaeval Studies 13 (1951): 29-30. MICHAELB. RASCHKO 416 Robert's analogy failed to convince those who held that a human being is a single substance, a totum. 15 The proponents of this position sought to be orthodox. They emphasized the full human nature to avoid the error of Eutyches. However, they lacked the clear terminology needed to state their case. One can hear them struggling with language as they affirmed that Christ is both humanus aliquis and humanum aliquid. Yet they also maintained that the result of the union was both an unus and an unum or totum. 16 While maintaining the full humanity and thus a human person in Christ, they yet wanted to hold for the product of the union as a single substance and so maintain a unity of person in the light of the Boethian definition of person as an individual substance. They seemed to have avoided the heresy of Eutyches only to have their opponents accuse them both of Nestorianism and of introducing a fourth person into the Trinity. 17 The second opinion summarized by Lombard is called the subsistence theory. Those whose theologies were within the parameters of this opinion held that the man Jesus was not only made up of a rational soul and a body but also of divine and human natures. He is of three substances: divinity, body, and soul. Jesus Christ is only one person, totally simple before the Incarnation, but in the Incarnation a composite person made up of divinity and humanity. Thus there is no other person than that of the Word. This person, which was previously only the person of the divine nature of the Word, has also become the person of a man in the Incarnation. There are not two persons, but one and the same person of the Word and of a man. The person who previously was simple and existed only in one nature now subsists in and through two natures. The person who was only divine has become a truly human subsisting being. This person subsists not only through the soul and the body but also through the divinity. The notion of person does not apply to the human nature standing in and by itself. It is the person of the divine who now 15 Ibid., 31. 1' Ibid., 29-30. 17 Ibid., 32. AQUINAS AND LOMBARD ON THE INCARNATION 417 subsists through a human nature as well as through its divine nature. That person can be said to have come to be insofar as it subsists in a human body and soul; but neither a person nor a substance nor a nature came to be. Insofar as it is that thing subsisting, the person is composite; insofar as it is the Word, it is simple.18 This opinion strongly emphasizes the divine element in Christ and clearly denies not only a created human person in Christ but also a human nature as a reality on its own. Its proponents could acknowledge a formula such as Augustine's "aliud est Verbum Dei, aliud homo" as applying to the natures, yet they would so emphasize Christ as "unum et idem" that they would not be willing to apply the "aliud et aliud" formula to Christ in the sense of distinct substances. They acknowledge one person and therefore, given the Boethian definition of person, they could acknowledge only one substance.19 The great advocate of this theory was Gilbert of Porree. He applied to the Incarnation his metaphysics which was built in large part on the Boethian distinction of the id quod and the id quo of any nomen. The id quod is the concrete subsisting reality; the id quo is the quality that enables that reality to be. Thus the noun "man" refers both to a concrete existing substance and to the quality of humanity through which that reality exists. Gilbert held that Christ is one id quod who exists through a dual id quo, divinity and humanity. Gilbert and others who held this opinion were attacked for denying the humanity of Christ as a concrete reality, an aliquid. They felt they must deny this in order to maintain the unity of the person of Christ, given the identification of person and substance in the Boethian definition of person. 20 Lombard's third opinion, the habitus theory, went further than the second in denying any possibility of a duality of person in Christ. Its adherents denied both that there is any union of Christ's body and soul that would form a substance before the Incarnation and that the human nature is a substance in which the 18 III Sent., d. 6. 19 Haring, "The Case of Gilbert de la Porree," 20 Ibid., 33-34. 32. 418 MICHAEL B. RASCHKO person of the Word subsists. They chose the category of habitus to describe the linion of the human nature to the person of the Word. 21 According to Lombard the proponents of the position denied not only that the person of Christ is composed of natures, but also that there is any substance in Christ composed of body and soul. The body and soul are united to the person of the Word in such a way that they do not form a substance or a person. Rather, the Word is vested in them like clothing so that he might appear in a manner suitable to human eyes. Christ is said to be true man because he has accepted a body and a soul. In his receiving of them, or something composed from them, they do not form one person alongside the Word, nor are they the Word, nor is the number of persons in the Word augmented so that there would be a quaternity in place of the Trinity. The person of the Word is not divided or changed by his assumption of those vestments. He remains one and the same, immutable. It is because God has accepted humanity as a habitus that it can be said that God is human; and it is because God assumed humanity that it can be said that a man is God. 22 Those who held versions of this opinion moved beyond those who held the second opinion in their refusal to speak of the person of Christ as facta or composita. They eliminated Christ's humanity as a substantial component of the union. For the sake of the unity of the person of Christ, understood within the limits of the Boethian definition of person, they refused to use the category of substance at all in dealing with the humanity of Christ. They chose instead the category of habitus.As habitus,the humanity remains extrinsic to the divine substance and is not itself an aliquid or an aliquis. They did not intend to deny the substantiality of the body or the soul, but they had to deny any union of them that would form a substance independent of the Word. Such a human substance would have to be a person, given their definition of person. Divinity is here totally protected from mutability. Christ's humanity contributes nothing to the constitution of his substance or person. In this the proponents of 21 Ibid., 34. iz III Sent., d. 6. AQUINAS AND LOMBARD ON THE INCARNATION 419 this opinion differ radically from those who held the second opinion and saw the person of Christ as a composite substance. They agreed with those who held the second opinion in denying a human aliquid. Like those who held the second opinion, they were attacked for denying the humanity of Christ. Because of their use of the category of habitus in the place of substance in describing the union, they were also accused of a tendency to deny a true human body and soul in Christ. 23 C) The Issues in Thomas's Own Time The third area of the history of Christological thought of which Thomas is very much aware in his own writings is the subsequent discussion and development of Lombard's three opinions. The most important development in the discussion had to do with the aliquidissue. In 1163 a conciliar debate was held at Tours in the presence of Pope Alexander III. The proponents of the second and third opinions attacked two propositions: that in Christ there is a human aliquis and that Christ as man is not an aliquid. The debate itself went unresolved, but in 1170 and 1177 Alexander issued decretals that condemned the proposition "Christus secundum quod homo non est aliquid." Thus he upheld one of the tenets of the first opinion and forced the other two to adapt as best they could to his teaching. He did not, however, give explicit approval to the first opinion nor did he attack the positions of the second and third opinions. 24 Proponents of the third opinion were unable to adapt their position to explain the presence of a human aliquidin Christ. By the thirteenth century this position had lost almost all support. The problem raised for the second opinion was how to differentiate an individual human nature and a human person. 25 This shifted the basic issue of discussion away from the question of the mode of union-which the three opinions had discussed in seeking to explain such statements as "Deus factus est homo" -to 23 Haring, "The Case of Gilbert de la 34-37. Ibid., 37-38. 25 Principe, The Theology of the Hypostatic Union in the Early Thirteenth Century, 1:68. 24 MICHAEL B. RASCHKO 420 the issue of unity and duality in Christ given the fact that there is in Christ a human aliquid.26 By the third and fourth decades of the thirteenth century the interpretation of Lombard's three opinions had been fairly well fixed and systematized.27 The first was presented so dualistically that it appeared more objectionable than in fact it was, and as a result was abandoned. The third opinion had been unable to explain the human aliquid of Christ, and so it too was largely abandoned. Both opinions were commonly attacked for teaching an accidental union. Common theological opinion rejected any idea of a resolution of the two natures into one common nature and any attempt to identify too closely the humanity with the divinity of Christ. 28 The second opinion thus held the field by the mid-thirteenth century. It posited a unity of person in Christ, a communication of the properties of the two natures, and a composite person with two distinct natures. Its problem lay in the differentiation of individualized human nature and human personhood. The dominance of this opinion was also aided by the strong influence of Gilbert of Porree and by its development of a theory of the subject.29 The problems were not all solved, however. Echoes of the first opinion can be heard in some theologians who held for a unity of person but a duality of hypostases, 30 and the union was often spoken of in terms of quasi-accidentality. 31 Terminology remained a problem. II. THOMAS'S CONSTRUCTIVE WORK A) Term.inology One of Thomas' s major contributions to the theology of the Incarnation is his clarification of the terminology that was used 26 Ibid., 1:67-70. 27 Ibid., 4: 194. 28 Ibid., 4: 194-96. 29 Ibid., 4:194-99. 30 Ibid., 4:196-97. 31 Ibid., 4:198. AQUINAS AND LOMBARD ON THE INCARNATION 421 to discuss the union. The Boethian definition of person as an individual substance of a rational nature caused a great deal of confusion for Christological thought because of its tendency to identify such terms as "person," "substance," "hypostasis," and "nature." Before he proceeds with his own thought on the Incarnation in the two Summae or the De Unione, Thomas first clarifies the terminology he will use.32 In these three works Thomas proceeds by way of etymology to define the term "nature." He finds its root in the verb nascor, "to be born," and shows how this root meaning was extended to the principle of the begetting of that which is born. Because this principle is intrinsic to a living thing, "nature" was further extended to include the principle of any motion that is intrinsic to a being. Finally, "since the result of any generative process in what is generated is the essence of the species as expressed by the definition of the species, that essence is accordingly termed a 'nature.'" 33 Thomas thus agrees with the Boethian definition of nature: "Natura est unamquamque rem informans specifica differentia. "34 The Summa contra Gentiles differs here from the other two works in that it quotes the Aristotelian definition "ut sic natura alicuius rei dicatur 'essentia, quam significat definitio.'" 35 However, the basic meaning remains the same: nature is the essence, or the quod quid est, or the quidditas of a thing. 36 It has to do with the integrity of species. Those things that are essential to the makeup of a particular species are made one in the nature of any individual in that species. Thus, for example, body and soul in any human individual are made one in constituting the human species or nature in that and every other individual of the human species.37 Given this definition of nature ScG N, c. 41; De Unione, a. 1; STh III, q. 2, aa. 1-3. STh III, q. 2, a. 1. 34 STh III, q. 2, a. 1, quoting Boethius, De Duabus Naturis I (PL 64: 1342). Note that the quotation is slightly different in the De Unione, where it reads, "Natura est unumquodque informans specifica differentia." 35 ScG N, c. 35; quoting Aristotle's Physics 2.1 (193a30). 36 ScG N, c. 41; STh III, q. 2, a. 2. 37 ScG N, c. 41. 32 33 MICHAELS.RASCHKO 422 it is impossible to add anything extrinsic to the unity of a nature without losing the species.38 In dealing with the term "person" Thomas accepts the Boethian definition but qualifies it in an important way. In the Summae and the De Unione this qualification of the term takes place in the distinction of nature and supposit, which is a wider category to which "person" belongs. A supposit is a whole that has a nature as its formal or standard part. 39 Supposit and nature are identical in those beings in which there is nothing other than the essence of the species. There the essence of the species subsists individually by itself.40 But there are also beings in which there exist things beyond the essence of the species, either accidents or individuating matter. In these cases the supposit is not entirely identical with the nature, but has additions to the nature. Thus while the nature is a species that is realized in many individuals, a supposit is an individual realization of the nature that may include more than that which.makes up the nature. 41 In the Summa contra Gentiles Thomas calls the individual in the genus of substance an "hypostasis. "42 In the Summa Theologiae he defines the supposit as something subsisting.43 The terms "supposit" and "hypostasis" are products of the same line of reasoning and thus Thomas uses them interchangeably. One can see this in articles 2 and 3 of question 2 of the Tertia Pars, where "person" is derived first from the concept of supposit and second from the concept of hypostasis in separate reiterations of the same argument. "Person" is then defined within the wider concept of supposit or hypostasis, as an hypostasis that has a rational nature. Thus the Boethian definition of "person" as an individual substance of a rational nature is preserved, but a nuance has been added so that 38 Ibid. 39 40 STb III, q. 2, a. 3. De Unione, a. 1. 41 Ibid. 42 ScG IV, c. 41. 43 STb III, q. 2, a. 2. AQUINAS AND LOMBARD ON THE INCARNATION 423 it is now clear that a person can include other elements in its being beyond its nature. Thomas makes this qualification of the Boethian definition in Summa TheologiaeI, q. 29, a. 1, where he discusses "person" in the light of "substance." There he defines "substance" as an individual by itself. He distinguishes substance from accidents that are individual only through their subject, which is itself a substance. A substance as a subject is also called an "hypostasis" or "first substance." Rational substances are more perfectly individual and particular because they can act on their own initiative and so have control over their own actions. Such rational substances are called "persons." Thus in the Boethian definition the term "individual substance" points to a singularity of being in the category of substance, and the term "rational nature" points to that singularity of being in the genus of rational substances.44 In article 2 of question 29 the notion of substance is further clarified. Thomas follows Aristotle in pointing out two ways the term is used. First, it can stand for the quiddity of a thing. In this sense it means the same as essence or nature. In the second sense substance is the subject or supposit that subsists in the category of substance. This latter meaning is the sense in which substance was defined in the previous article and the sense Thomas finds in the Boethian definition of person. Within this latter meaning of the word other terms may be used that correspond to it. It is a "subsistence," meaning that it exists in itself and not in something else. It is "a thing of nature," which means it is an individual realization of a particular species. It is an "hypostasis" in that it is an individual reality that can support accidents in its being.45 B) The Nature of the Union Given this clarification of terminology, Thomas is quickly able to develop his position on the nature of the union in the Incarnation. He does so most succinctly in the De Unione: 44 STh I, q. 29, a. 1. l, q. 29, a. 2. 45 STh 424 MICHAEL B. RASCHKO It is therefore possible that nothing prohibits things from being united in person that are not united in nature. For it is possible for an individual substance of a rational nature to have something that does not belong to the nature of the species, and this is united to it personally, not through its nature. This therefore is to be accepted as the mode by which the human nature is united to the Word of God, in the person not the nature. For if it does not belong to the divine nature, it does, however, belong to his person in so far as the person of the Word takes to himself human nature as an addition. 46 In both of the Summae Thomas deals first with the "non naturaliter" element of his position. This hinges on the fact that according to Thomas's metaphysics a nature cannot be added to or subtracted from without changing the species or nature. He is bound here by this concept of nature and by the fact that in the Incarnation Christ must be one and yet must possess the perfection of both divine and human natures in an unmixed manner. He is seeking to avoid the error of Eutyches. In both Summae Thomas seeks a possible mode of union in which two or more natures can be joined so that they form one reality without losing the independence and fullness of each. The arguments in each work are virtually the same. In the Summa contra Gentiles Thomas merely lists the possible modes of union and rejects them one by one. In the Summa Theologiae he organizes them into three types of union and deals with them under those three headings. The first type of union is that in which the several united natures each remain intact. Such unions consist in juxtaposition, rank, or shape. Examples may be found in a haphazard pile of stones or in the many parts that come together in the construction of a house. Such a union would imply an order with or without a planned composition. This mode of union is rejected for three reasons. It is accidental, not substantial; it results in one thing 46 De Unione, a. 1: "Sic ergo patet quod nihil prohibet aliqua uniri in persona quae non sunt unita in natura; potest enim individua substantia rationalis naturae habere aliquid quod non pertinet ad naturam speciei, et hoc unitur ei personaliter, non naturaliter. Hoc igitur modo accipiendum est quod natura humana unita est Verbo Dei in persona, non in natura: quia si non pertinet ad naturam divinam, pertinet autem ad personam ipsius, in quantum persona Verbi assumendo, adiunxit sibi humanam naturam." AQUINAS AND LOMBARD ON THE INCARNATION 425 only in a qualified sense, for the parts remain intact and actual; and the form is artificial and not natural. The second type of union is that in which the things united are changed in the process of unification. Here both the product and the parts that went to make it up differ from the original parts, as they existed on their own. This mode of union cannot be applied to the Incarnation because the divine nature cannot change, because Christ would no longer have divine and human natures, and because the two natures in the Incarnation are so different that the greater-the divine-would simply consume the lesser. The third mode of union is that which results from realities that are not changed though they themselves no longer remain complete things. Examples are the union of the body and soul in human nature and the union of many parts of a body. This cannot be applied to the Incarnation, again for three reasons: in the Incarnation each of the two natures has its own complete and independent meaning, the divine and human natures cannot be parts of a body for the divine is incorporeal, and Christ could not exist in either nature for something added to either nature would change the species of the nature. 47 Thomas, then, finds that the union of the Incarnation is "personaliter non naturaliter." 48 This mode of hypostatic union follows quite simply given Thomas's reworking of the Boethian definition of person. "Person" for Thomas includes not only the nature of a subsistent rational being, but also whatever else is joined to him as a subsisting individual. Thus he can say, "All that is present in any person, whether belonging to nature or not, is united to him in person. "49 The person of the Word has possessed divine nature from eternity and yet can also assume to his person a human nature without mixing it with his divine nature or in any way diminishing the perfection of either nature. This line of thought is basic to all three of Thomas's constructive works. It is clearly developed in the Summa 47 STh III, q. 2, a. 1. 48 De Unione, a. 1. 49 STh III, q. 2, a. 2. MICHAEL B. RASCHKO 426 Theologiae, 50 as summarized above, and is given in a similar manner in the De Unione. 51 In the Summa contra Gentiles, however, it is presented in a more disparate manner. After analyzing of the term "person" Thomas merely says, "Nothing prevents some things not united in nature from being united in hypostasis or person. "52 He does not explicitly apply his insight to the union of the two natures, although that is the topic he is discussing. In an earlier chapter he clearly gives the dogmatic formula that the two natures are united in Christ in one hypostasis and one supposit. He applies this basic line of thought in his response to objections against faith in the Incarnation when he says that the human nature is drawn into the subsistence of the personality of the Word and does not have a subsistence of its own. Thus the line of thought is present, but it is not drawn together in the way it is in the later works. 53 C) Thomas's Dependence on Lombard's Formulation Thomas's identification of his own theology of the Incarnation with that of the subsistence theory can be clearly seen in the Summa Theologiae when he deals with the question of whether the person of Christ is composite. First, the very term used by Thomas, "persona composita," can be found twice in Lombard's short summary paragraph and a number of times in his supporting quotations. Second, the phrase "subsistit in duabus naturis" reflects a threefold usage by Lombard: "in duabus et ex duabus subsistit naturis," "persona quae tantum erat Deus, facta est etiam verus homo subsistens," and "Facta est igitur illa persona, quidam subsistens ex anima et came ... et in quantum est illud subsistens, composita est." The mode of union in each case is one in which one and the same person, already subsisting in a divine nature, comes to subsist also in human nature. Third, the presentation of the argument in both Thomas's article and JO srh III, q. 2, aa. 2-4. JI See above, n. 46. nScGIV,c.41. 53 ScG IV, cc. 39, 49. AQUINAS AND LOMBARD ON THE INCARNATION 427 Lombard's summary emphasizes a comparison of the person of the Word in its simplicity and complexity. Lombard does so in an historical sequence (i.e., before and after the Incarnation). Thomas does so from two speculative points of view, that of the person of the Word as it is in itself, in which case it is simple, and that of the person considered as subsisting in some nature, in which case it is complex because of its subsisting in two natures. Fourth, both men use a common quotation from John Damascene. Finally, Thomas's phrasing "licet sit ibi unum subsistens est tamen ibi alia ratio subsistendi," echoes the metaphysical language of Gilbert, the champion of the second opinion, who described the Incarnation as a single id quod subsisting through a dual id quo. Thus one can see not only a dear dependence of Thomas's thought on the second opinion as it is presented by Lombard, but one also finds in this article of the Summa Theologiae a strong literary dependence on Lombard's presentation of that opinion. 54 D) Thomas's Rejectionof the First and Third Opinions Having developed his own position in the first four articles of question 2 of the Tertia Pars, in the following two articles Thomas rejects the first and third opinions. He first rejects the habitus theory in article 5 because in denying the union of the body and soul in Christ it denies the hylomorphic union that constitutes the human species. The term "man" is applied univocally to Christ and to all other human beings by Thomas. Thus Christ must share in a nature constituted by the union of body and soul. Thomas also rejects both opinions in article 6 on the grounds that both claim that the union of Christ's human nature to the Word is accidental. If the human nature has the status of an accident, substantiality is not predicated of it. Thus there would be no human aliquid, a position condemned by the decretals of Alexander III. Thomas notes that the motivation in each of these opinions was sincere, for both sought to avoid the heresies of Eutyches and Nestorius. However, both have fallen H Sfh III, q. 2, a. 4; III Sent., d. 4. 428 MICHAELB.RASCHKO into Nestorianism by different routes, for both propose an accidental union, whether that accident be by indwelling or by habitus. Thomas condemns both by bringing against them the ancient Christo logical norms of the Church. Finally, he claims explicitly that the subsistence theory is the teaching of the Church. ss Thus the ancient Christo logical decisions of the Church serve Thomas as the measure of orthodoxy as he deals with the three opinions in the light of two issues that were raised in the late twelfth and early thirteenth centuries: the issues of an accidental union in the Incarnation and of the human aliquid of Christ. E) Development within Thomas's Position Both Principe and H. F. Dondaine comment on the development of Thomas's treatment of the assumptus homo and habitus theories of the Incarnation. Dondaine in particular comments regarding the treatment of the former: Without returning to the basics of the question, we simply want to list the dogmatic qualifications given by St. Thomas to this opinion over the course of his writings: their sequence reveals a coherent progression. 56 The progress he sees in Thomas's treatment is divided into three periods: The preceding texts can be arranged well enough in three stages, given by the three major works: Commentary on the Sentences III, Summa contra Gentiles IV, and Summa Theologiae III. From one to the next the dogmatic notes become graver.H Sfh III, q. 2, aa. 5-6. "Sans revenir sur le fond de la question, nous voulons simplement recenser Jes qualifications dogmatiques donnees par S. Thomas au cette opinion, a cours de ses oeuvres: leur suite revele un progres coherent" (H. Dondaine, "Qualifications dogmatiques de la theorie de l'asssumptus homo dans Jes oeuvres de S. Thomas," Les Sciences Philosophiques et Theoloqiques [Paris: Vrin, 1941-42], 163). 57 "Les textes qui precedent s'ordonnent assez bien en trois etapes, donnees par Jes trois grand ouvrages: Comm. in Sent III, Contra Gentiles IV, Summa theol., Illa p. De l'un a l'autre, la note dogmatique s'aggrave" (ibid., 165). 55 56 AQUINAS AND LOMBARD ON THE INCARNATION 429 The first stage of Thomas's thinking merely abandons the opinion; the second sees it leading to the errors of Nestorius condemned at Ephesus, and the third stage sees the opinion itself as condemned in 553 at Constantinople. 58 One can see a similar progression of Thomas's treatment of the habitus theory, according to Principe's survey. The Commentary on the Sentences finds erroneous tendencies in the theory's treatment of the aliquid question and in the lack of a human nature (since there is no union of body and soul in Christ). The Summa contra Gentiles condemns it vehemently for several heresies that it appears to hold, but the identification with the heresies is tenuous to say the least. The De Unione equates it with Nestorianism because both see the union as accidental. The Summa Theologiae calls the opinion itself a heresy, condemned at the Second Council of Constantinople. The charges thus become more pointed and direct until finally a conciliar decree is applied directly to the opinion. Principe also points out a progression in the development, compression, and linking of the arguments against the opinion. 59 One can find something of a similar development in Thomas's approach to the subsistence theory. We have noted that Thomas calls it the statement of the Catholic faith in the Summa Theologiae and that his presentation of the union in question 2, article 4 of the Tertia Pars shows great affinity with Lombard's presentation of the opinion. While he does not discuss this opinion in the De Unione, the line of argument regarding the union in articles 1 and 2 of the quaestio is similar to that in the Summa Theologiae. The language does not reflect that of Lombard. The De Unione is more concise and is not as explicitly identifiable with the second opinion as presented by Lombard. 60 Again Thomas does not discuss the second opinion explicitly in the Summa contra Gentiles. The same line of argument that is found in the later two works is found there but in a more disparate manner. Thomas had yet to systematize and compress Ibid., 165-67. Principe, "St. Thomas on the Habitus-Theory of the Incarnation," 381-98. 60 De Unione, aa. 1-2. 58 -'9 430 MICHAELB. RASCHKO his thought. His statement that nothing prevents some things not united in nature from being united in person does not have the same force as his later statements that the union is hypostatic. 61 It is in the Commentary on the Sentences, which like the Summa Theologiae explicitly discusses the second opinion, that one finds interesting comparisons to the Christology of the Summa Theologiae. There the terminological clarifications and the mode of rejection of a union in nature are already present in the forms in which they can be found in the later works. 62 Thomas holds for a unity of person in Christ and denies that a person is assumed in the Incarnation. 63 He agrees with the second opinion's stance that in Christ there is one hypostasis, one supposit, and two individuals only one of which subsists in itself. (Here individuality means indivisibility.64 ) Most importantly, Thomas agrees with the second opinion that there is a composite person in the Incarnation. 65 He thus accepts the basic lines of the second opinion and we find here the elements of his own line of thought about the Incarnation. However, he does have a problem with the second opinion's denial of a human aliquid in Christ. Thomas states: Thus according to the second opinion, with which we are dealing, that aliguid which is assumed by nature is not predicated of Christ because he does not have the rationality of an individuated man, but of human nature. 66 This, however, does not stop Thomas from accepting the second opinion. He does so by investigating what it means by aliquid: Aliquid therefore as it is predicated of Christ does not so much signify nature, but rather the supposit of the nature. And because the plural is the double of the singular, it is not possible to attribute the plural aliqua to Christ unless 61 Compare ScG IV, c. 41 with De Unione, a. 1. 62 III Sent., d. 5, q. 1, aa. 2-3. q. 3, a. 3. III Sent., d. 6, q. 1, a. 1. 65 III Sent., d. 6, q. 2, a. 3. 66 III Sent., d. 6, q. 2, a. 1: "Secundum igitur secundam opinionem, de qua agitur, illud aliquid quod est natura assumpta, non praedicatur de Christo; quia non habet rationem hominis, sed humanitatis." 63 III Sent., d. 5, 64 AQUINAS AND LOMBARD ON THE INCARNATION 431 there are in him two supposits of the natures. The second opinion denies this, as the third opinion does in a similar way. For each opinion says that Christ is one. But the second says that he is one in himself; the third says that he is one through accidents, like saying a man is white. 67 Given this understanding of aliquid, Thomas is able to accept the opinion. Thus we find that Thomas is consistent throughout his works in following a basic line of thought that is rooted in the second opinion summarized by Peter Lombard. The elements of his own position are present from the beginning. Through the course of his work his position is further systematized and more strongly affirmed. In accepting the second opinion he was not unaware of its problems. He had to qualify the definition of "person" and work out his own position on the question of the human aliquid. The aliquid issue was not the only one raised in this debate. A look at the first twenty-six questions of the Tertia Pars reveals many of the problems that had to be commented on in the development of a theology of the Incarnation in the thirteenth century. In the development of the second opinion Thomas found a key for the systematic resolution of most of those issues. In the first place, Thomas's theology of the Incarnation protects the immutability of the divine nature. This had been a concern of both the first and the third opinions. According to Thomas, all change that occurs in the union of a human nature to the person of the Word takes place in the human nature, which is drawn into union with the already subsisting divine person of the Word. 68 The objection had been made that because the person of the Word is totally identical with his divine nature the union could not just be brought about in the person but must also be brought about in the divine nature. Thomas recognizes that in God nature and person are not really distinct, yet they do differ 67 Ibid.: "Aliquid ergo, secundum quod praedicatur de Christo, non significat tantum naturam, sed suppositum naturae. Et quia plurale est geminatum singulare, ideo Christus non posset dici aliqua, nisi essent in eo duo supposita naturarum; quod negat secunda opinio, et similiter tertia. Et ideo utraque opinio dicit, quod Christus est unum; sed secunda dicit, quod est unum per se; tertia vero, quod est unum per accidens, sicut albus homo." 68 ScG IV, c. 49. 432 MICHAEL B. RASCHKO in what they signify, for person signifies something subsistent. The nature thus remains unaffected when the person as the subsistent assumes another mode of subsisting, that of human nature. 69 The dignity of the human nature is also saved by Thomas's theology. Those who held the first opinion sought to save the fullness of humanity in Christ. Objections had been made that those who held the other two opinions denied the fullness and the dignity of Christ's humanity because that humanity did not have its proper personality. Thomas notes that it has the personality of the Word which bestows greater dignity and fullness than it would have had if the humanity had existed in itself.70 The difficulties caused by the Boethian definition are also solved. The issue here centered on the contention that an individual substance of a rational nature by definition constitutes a person. Because Christ possessed a perfect human nature, some argued, he must have possessed human personhood. Thomas replies that to be a person does not belong to every individual substance of a rational nature but only to those that exist in themselves. In Christ the human substance does not exist separately in itself but in something more noble and perfect. In Christ human nature is a substance but not an individual substance, which is a reality that exists in itself and cannot be assumed by a higher being.71 By identifying "person" with the genus of hypostasis or supposit, Thomas resolved the confusion that had resulted in the theory that in Christ there were two hypostases or supposits and one person. Given Thomas's definition of "person," there is no difference in a subsisting rational nature between the hypostasis and the person. Thomas rejects the theory of two hypostases on two grounds. First, if anything more were added to the idea of hypostasis by the notion of person than the qualification that it has a rational nature, the addition would have to be one of 69 STh III, q. 2, a. 3, ad 1. 10 STh III, q. 2, a. 3, ad 2. 71 STh l, q. 29, a. 1, ad 1-2. AQIBNAS AND LOMBARD ON THE INCARNATION 433 dignity or excellence. This would reduce the union to one of moral excellence, a theory that was condemned with Nestorianism. Second, the operations and properties of a nature are attributed to the supposit in any predication. If there is another supposit than the Word in Christ's human nature, the actions of the human nature cannot be attributed to the Word. This too Thomas identifies with Nestorianism. 72 The unity of person in two distinct natures allows Thomas to develop his answers to the questions regarding the knowledge, will, and actions of Christ and the question regarding the communication of idioms. The Word possesses the fullness and perfection of each nature and therefore has the principle of operation and faculties of each nature. Therefore, Christ has a distinct knowledge, will, and principle of action in both his humanity and his divinity. In the case of knowledge, Christ is omniscient as divine; yet he also possesses the perfection of human knowledge. Therefore, Christ must have a knowledge of all being by infused knowledge, for that is the end and perfection of the passive intellect. 73 He must also possess the beatific vision for that too is a capacity of human nature as a rational being.74 Because he has an active intellect, Christ must also have acquired knowledge through abstraction from the phantasms. 75 However, though his humanity has reached its created perfection, it has no intellectual perfection beyond its natural limits. It is not able to comprehend the Word, nor does it know the infinite. The human soul is finite; it is oriented to the knowledge of being and there is a limited number of entities that have being. Therefore, the humanity of Christ does not share the modes of knowledge proper to the divine nature. 76 Thomas deals with the wills and principles of action of the two natures in the same way. The distinction of natures in a unity of person also enables Thomas to preserve the communication of idioms. The mode of III, q. 2, a. 3. III, q. 9, a. 3. 74 STh III, q. 9, a. 2. 75 STh III, q. 9, a. 4. 76 STh III, q. 10, a. 1. 72 STh 73 STh MICHAELB.RASCHKO 434 operation appropriate to a nature is predicated of the person of the Word as it subsists in that nature. This allows Thomas to make three important moves. First, it saves the scriptural accounts of Jesus' activity without introducing passivity and mutability into the divine nature. Human actions and emotions are attributed to the divine person as he subsists in a human nature. 77 Second, actions appropriate to God take place in one and the same person who also possesses human nature. Thus the person of the man Jesus is able to effect salvation through his humanity. 78 Third, Thomas is also able to deal with such statements as "man is God" and "God is man" by discussing them in the light of the hypostatic union. Both terms are predicated of the common sup posit of both natures. 79 F) The Problem in the De Unione The second article of the De Unione raises the issue of exactly what can be said of the human nature of Christ if it does not subsist through itself and so does not have its own supposit separate from that of the divine nature. In the article Thomas surveys those terms which pertain to individuation, whether they belong to the first order, such as persona and "hypostasis," which signify the thing in itself, or to the second order, such as "supposit" and "individual," which signify individuality in the intention of a mind as it thinks or speaks about a thing. He divides these into those that pertain solely to the category of substance (supposit, hypostasis, person, and res natura) and those that pertain either to substance or to accidents (individual, particular, singular). He uses the word "substance" here in the second sense developed in Prima Pars question 29, article 2: substance is that which subsists in and of itself. In the De Unione he uses the term "partial substance" for that which subsists in another. Thus the term "substance" may be used only in its partial sense when one speaks of the human nature of Christ, for it does 77 ScG N, cc. 34, 38. 78 Ibid. 79 STh III, q. 16. AQUINAS AND LOMBARD ON THE INCARNATION 435 not subsist in itself. Thomas concludes that one can use such words as "particular," "singular," and "individual" in speaking of the humanity of Christ, but not "supposit," "person," or "hypostasis." He is also very careful to note that while the human nature subsists in something other than itself, it is not an accident or part of a larger totality. In noting this he is very much conscious of the rejection of the first and third opinions because they held that the union of the humanity of Christ to the Word was accidental. Thus in no way dare he say that the union is accidental. 80 The difficulty regarding the use of the term "substance" is dealt with in the Summa Theologiae. There Thomas says that "hypostasis" refers to a substance that is complete in itself. The human nature of Christ can be called a particular substance but not an hypostasis for it is in union with something more complete, the whole of Christ as God and man. Thus the humanity of Christ is not a substance that exists in and by itself.81 Thomas is consistent in the positions he takes on most of the Christological issues raised by the discussion of the three opinions. However, in his discussion of whether there is but one esse in Christ his thinking shows a marked shift. The point at issue is this: if there are two distinct natures each with its own proper principle of action, are there two esse (two acts of being) or does the single person have one esse in and through two natures? The De Unione favors the former option. There Thomas states that Christ is one simply through the unity of his supposit, but two secundum quid because of the two natures. Thus he has one esse simply because of the one esse of the eternal supposit. He has another esse, however, not insofar as he is eternal but insofar as he was made human in time. That esse is not an accident, which is a logical possibility (accidents can be said to have an esse insofar as they subsist in another being). The esse of Christ's humanity is not accidental for that is not the mode of the union. 80 De Unione, a. 2. 81 STh III, q. 2, a. 3, ad 2; De Unione, a. 2. 436 MICHAEL B. RASCHKO The esse of Christ's humanity is secondary. Thus Christ has two esse.82 In the Summa Theologiae Thomas distinguishes that which has esse (id quod) and that by which it has esse (id quo). The former is the subsisting subject; the latter is a nature. There are in a person, however, things that are not necessities of the nature but are a part of the individual person (e.g., accidents). These have a type of esse which is said to be in the person and can be multiplied in the person but do not multiply the single esse of the person. In Christ, however, the union of nature is not by accident but by a common hypostasis. The union does not produce a new act of esse in the person of the Word. Rather the one person in one esse now subsists in a second nature. 83 There is an obvious difference here. James Weisheipl holds that it is a vast difference and that there is a definite development of doctrine. 84 Colman O'Neill claims that Thomas's opinions are not contradictory but rather that the De Unione looks at the personal existence of Christ from two unique points of view.85 A. Patfoort plays with the possibilities of an explanation in terms of problems in transcription, Thomas's mood at the time he wrote the De Unione, or Thomas's trying an intellectual adventure in the De Unione. 86 The question concerns the De Unione, for the treatment in the Summa Theologiae agrees with that given years earlier in the Commentary on the Sentences. 87 It seems to me that the treatment of the issue in the Summa Theologiae is more consistent with Thomas's general position. A comparison with Thomas's final position on thealiquid question, as understood by Principe, is useful. The aliquid question is not treated in the Summa Theologiae, but Principe believes he has 82 83 De Unione, a. 4. SI'h III, q. 17, a. 2. 84 James A. Weisheipl, Friar Thomas D'Aquino: His Life, Thouqht, and Work (Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday, 1974), 311. 85 Colman E. O'Neill, in the second appendix of the Summa Theologiae (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1974), 227. 86 A. Patfoort, L'unite d'etre dans le Christd'apresS. Thomas (Paris: Desclee, 1964), 18386. 87 III Sent., d. 6, q. 2, a. 2. AQUINAS AND LOMBARD ON THE INCARNATION 437 found the line of a solution in Thomas's treatment of the questions as to whether Christ as human is person, God, and creature. As we saw earlier, in treating the second opinion Thomas had noted its denial of a human aliquid, but he understood that by aliquid the opinion meant a subsistent being. But given the decretals of Alexander III, Thomas had to find a way to view the human nature as an aliquid and not merely an abstract id quo. In III Sentences,d. 10, and Summa TheoloqiaeIII, q. 16, aa. 10-12, Thomas says that Christ as man is aliquid, individual, person, God, and creature only by reference to the supposit in which those predicates subsist. These statements are not true in the abstract. One cannot simply say Christ as human is aliquid, or person or individual. They are true only in the concrete, that is, that Christ as this human being is aliquid, because this human being is the one in which the person of the Word subsists.88 The same pattern of thought can be applied to the question of the unicity of esse in Christ. If one can say Christ as man has esse, it must be in the same manner that one says Christ as man is person. This can be done only by reference to the one supposit of both predicates, the person of the Word. Thus one can no more speak of a duality of esse in Christ than one can speak of a duality of person. There is a person, an esse, an aliquid in the human nature of Christ, but it is that person, esse, and aliquid of the divine person subsisting in human nature. III. CONCLUSION The qualification of the use of language in this issue of the unicity of esse in Christ, the discussion of language in the De Unione, and the careful definition and use of the central terms in his theology of the Incarnation all betray an awareness on Thomas's part that language is the key to the discussion of this mystery. In the Summa contra Gentiles, attempting to explain how the Incarnation should be understood, Thomas introduces one metaphor of the union by saying, "And although to explain 88 Principe, "St. Thomas on the Habitus-Theory of the Incarnation," 412-18; STh III, q. 16, aa. 10-12; III Sent., d. 10, q. 1, a. 2. 438 MICHAEL B. RASCHKO this union perfectly is beyond human strength, nonetheless ... ". 89 All of his theology of the hypostatic union must be viewed in the shadow of this concessive clause. At times he uses metaphors such as the instrumental relationship of the body and the soul or the relationship of the hand as part to the totality of the body, 90 but each of these is rejected as an inadequate description of the Incarnation. 91 Such metaphors will not work because there is no created example of the kind of union we find in the Incarnation. In the De Unione, after rejecting the model of accidental union or that of the part in the whole, Thomas finds himself reduced to saying that the union is "per ineffabilem assumptionem. " 92 In the last analysis it is ineffable because the Incarnation is a revealed truth of the type that cannot be known by the human mind unless it is revealed by God. Nevertheless Thomas is careful to find a systematic language that through analogy can express the incomprehensible mystery that has been revealed. He is seeking to reject erroneous language and options, to show that this belief is not contrary to reason, and to find a way of expressing the union of the Incarnation that is adequate to the needs of the Christian community. The theology of the Incarnation must serve the same purpose as that of sacred doctrine in general: it is a necessary mode of appropriation of those truths revealed by God which enable the Christian to return to God. 93 Clearly Thomas's theology of the Incarnation fits his larger system and serves it well. He deals with the Incarnation in a way that is clear, precise in its terminology, and internally consistent. His modification and acceptance of the second opinion enables him to resolve the basic problems that had plagued the issue in the late twelfth and early thirteenth centuries. It also fit well with other themes of his theology, his anthropology, and his view of God and revelation. It served the larger theological system well because it enabled Thomas to view Christ as the mediator who ScG IV, c. 41. SI'h III, q. 2, a. 3, ad 2; ScG IV, c. 41. 91 SI'h III, q. 2, a. 1. 92 De Unione, a. 2. 93 SI'h l, q. 1, a. 1. 89 90 AQUINAS AND LOMBARD ON THE INCARNATION 439 opens for humankind the possibility of a return to God. The question of salvation and the view of Christ as mediator are central not only to Thomas's theology but to the Middle Ages in general. That Thomas has his eye on the fact that Christ must be a mediator between God and the human race cannot be doubted. One is struck in reading the Summa contra Gentiles how often Thomas rejects various false opinions because they do not maintain that Christ is one species with us. He must be one with God and one with us so that he might truly mediate between the two. The true end of Thomas's development of his theology of the Incarnation can be seen in the last question of that part of the Summa Theologiae in which he deals with the Incarnation. In question 26 of the Tertia Pars he asks whether Christ is the mediator of God and human beings. There Thomas reaps the benefit of his long work on the mode of the union of the Incarnation in statements that are possible only in the light of that theology of the union: The distinctive function of a mediator is to bring together those between whom he acts as mediator; for extremities are united in the middle point. Now to unite men with God in the manner of a self-sufficient agent is the office of Christ, through whom men are reconciled with God: God was in Christ reconciling the world with himself. It follows that Christ is the self-sufficient mediator of God and men by reason of his having reconciled, through his death, the human race with God. 94 Now the fact of being an intermediary implies being set apart from both extremes; while, in order to bring these together, the mediator bears what belongs to one over to the other. Neither of these elements is realized in Christ in so far as he is God, but exclusively in so far as he is man. For as God he is not distinct in nature and lordship from the Father and the Holy Spirit; nor do the Father and the Holy Spirit possess anything which the Son does not possess and which, as belonging to them and not to himself, he might bear to others. But both elements are realized in Christ as man. For as man he is set apart from God in nature and from man in the eminence of his grace and glory. Likewise as man his office is to unite men with God, which he does by setting before men the divine commandments and gifts and by atoning and interceding for men with God. 95 94 STh III, q. 26, a. 1. 95 STh III, q. 2, a. 2. The Thomist 65 (2001): 441-63 SCIENCE AND RELIGION IN THE THOMISTIC TRADITION 1 WILLIAMA. WALLACE, 0.P. Universityof Maryland CollegePark, Maryland T he topic "Science and Religion" continues to be much discussed in the present day, particularly in the context of an opposition or warfare between the two. 2 It is a commonplace that in the past those interested in such discussions have inclined more to the side of science than they have to the side of religion. On the religion side, it seems that Catholics rarely get excited about the subject, whereas for Protestants it is a topic of ongoing, and in some cases intense, interest. Indeed, among historians of science it is not unusual to find persons who turned away from a career in science, to which they had first aspired, to study history-to set the record straight, as it were, on the relationship between science and religion. The fruits of labors of this type are now apparent in a volume that has just appeared bearing the title The History of Scienceand Religionin the Western Tradition:An Encyclopedia.3 It may seem odd that a topic such as this should have a history, but if it has been around for a century or so it seems inevitable that it would 1 This essay is based on a lecture given at St. John's University, Jamaica, New York, on 16 October 1996, as part of a series on Science and Religion. 2 The best-known exposition of the warfare thesis is that of Andrew Dickson White, A History of the Warfareof Sciencewith Theology, 2 vols. (New York: Appleton, 1897). This was preceded by the also well-known work of John William Draper, History of the Conflict BetweenReligionand Science (London: 1874; reprint, New York: Appleton, 1928). 3 Gary B. Ferngren, ed., The History of Science·andReligionin the Western Tradition:An Encyclopedia(New York and London: Garland Publishing, Inc., 2000). 441 442 WILLIAM A. WALLACE, O.P. take on a life of its own and so become deserving of historical treatment. It is not our intention here to review this multifaceted work. Suffice it to note that there are some serious omissions in the essays, over a hundred in number, that make up the volume. With regard to the two main terms, there is no clear-cut definition of what constitutes a religion and how one religion is differentiated from another, nor is there any serious treatment of the term "science" and the various meanings it has taken on from Aristotle to the present day. 4 Perhaps more serious, there is no essay on faith, and there are only seven references to that term in the almost six hundred pages that make up the volume. Again, there is no essay on theology, nor is the term even mentioned in the index. 5 Among Catholics, as suggested above, the general attitude toward this topic seems to be lack of interest. 6 This is especially true of those who identify in some way or other with the Thomistic tradition. If they are knowledgeable about the origins of Thomism in the works of Albert the Great and those of Thomas Aquinas, they see a complementary relationship between science and what now passes under the name of religion. At the same time they are aware that there are important differences between scientia and fides.7 Among contemporary philosophers 4 There is an essay entitled "The Demarcation of Science and Religion" (ibid., 17-23), but this is essentially a reworking of arguments for and against a demarcation between science and metaphysics, or between science and non-science, which for positivists degenerated into their distinction between science and nonsense. 5 There is. however, an entry for a book entitled The Theology of Electricity, by Ernst Benz (trans. Wolfgang Taraba [Allison Park., Penn.: Pickwick, 1989]), which explores seventeenth and eighteenth century debates on electricity. This is not the sense of theology that is here intended 6 Perhaps this serves to explain why there is a minimal Catholic presence in the volume. Only two Catholic priests are among the contributors, Stanley L. Jaki, who wrote an essay on "God, Nature, and Science" (Science and Religionin the Western TTadition, 45-52), and William A. Wallace, O.P., who wrote on "Thomas Aquinas and Thomism" (ibid., 137-49). Among Catholic laymen the most notable from Catholic institutions are Richard J. Blackwell, who authored the article on "Galileo Galilei" (ibid., 85-89), and Michael J. Crowe, who wrote on "The Plurality of Worlds and Extraterrestrial Life" (ibid., 342-43). 7 This theme has gained importance for Catholics from the promulgation of Pope John Paul H's encyclical Fides et Ratio in September 1998. On that encyclical in the present context, see William A. Wallace, O.P., "Fides et Ratio: The Compatibility of Science and SCIENCE AND RELIGION 443 of science, of course, there are those who think of science in terms of belief, as when they refer to science as "justified true belief." But then one has to consider what they mean by the qualifiers "justified" and "true"-and when that is done, it is evident that there is no connection whatever between their usage of the term "belief" and its meaning in a theological context. 8 In light of this situation, our essay begins with St. Thomas's thought on the differences between scientia and religio, and then discusses the development of Thomism in a general way as it relates to the history and philosophy of science. After that it goes into fuller detail on two themes directly related to the Thomistic tradition, namely, the efforts of Galileo and others to demonstrate the motion of the earth, and the prospects for a renewed interest in Thomism as a philosophy of science in the present day. A) Science and Religion The juxtaposition of science and religion in the modern mind, with the connotation that the two must be either opposed or linked in some way, does not resonate significantly with Aquinas's thought. Much of what is now discussed under the category of science and religion he would have seen as part of a larger problem of the relationship between faith and reason. Once the respective spheres of these two types of knowing are made clear, most of the difficulties arising in debates over science and religion may be seen to disappear. In brief, faith is taken by Thomas to mean belief in God and acceptance of divine revelation as true. 9 He would differentiate it from reason on the basis of the fact that reason refers to the way Religion," forthcoming in the Proceedings of the National Catholic Bioethics Center's Eighteenth Workshop for Bishops, Dallas, Texas, 5 February 2001. 8 "Justification" is usually understood by such philosophers in terms of hypotheticodeductive methodology, which may be capable of arriving at some degree of probability but is incapable of attaining certitude. Then truth is for the "truth value" of a formal deductive system, or in terms of a coherence theory of truth, as opposed to a correspondence theory-in the sense of an adaequatio rei et intellectus, which is required for knowing epistemically or in a strictly scientific way. 9 On faith as a theological virtue see Aquinas, Summa TheologiaeII-II, qq. 1-7. 444 WILLIAMA. WALLACE, O.P. humans acquire knowledge through their natural powers of sense and intellect alone, without relying on God or supernatural revelation. His distinction focuses more on the mode of acquisition of knowledge than on the knowledge acquired. A person whose reason is complemented by faith would, for him, be capable of knowing more truths than one who knows through reason unaided. But if contradictory truths seem to derive from the two sources, then the competing claims of faith and reason have to be resolved, and we are faced with what even he would recognize as a "science vs. religion" controversy. To be more precise, faith for Aquinas is a supernatural virtue (along with charity and hope) that accompanies grace in the souls of Christians and disposes them to believe in truths revealed by God. Such truths are not self-evident to human reason, and assent to them must be determined by a voluntary choice. If such a choice is made tentatively it is called opinion; if it is made with certainty and without doubt it is called faith. The objects of divine faith are formulated in creeds that are made up of articles, that is, of connected parts. Believing in such articles means putting faith in them, and this resembles knowing in its giving firm assent; it also resembles doubting or holding an opinion in that it does not entail a complete vision of the truth. Faith's assent is an act of the mind that is voluntary-it is determined not by reason but by the will. But since its object is truth, which is the proper object of the intellect, it is more proximately an act of the intellect and so is regarded as an intellectual virtue. 10 Religion, like faith, is a virtue for Aquinas, but it resides not in the intellect but in the will. 11 It is allied to the virtue of justice, which disposes a person to render to others their due. Since humans owe their entire being to God they owe him a special kind of honor. Obviously they can never repay him for what he has given them, nor can they give him as much honor as they ought, but only as much as is possible for them and is deemed acceptable to him. Those who are sensitive to this obligation are in fact religious persons. Being religious in this sense does not 10 STh 11-11, q. 2, a. 1. 11 STh 11-11, q. 81. SCIENCE AND RELIGION 445 involve having any special scientific knowledge and thus does not bear directly on "science vs. religion" controversies.12 Science or scientia is also a virtue for Aquinas, but it is a natural virtue of the human intellect. 13 It was characterized by Aristotle as a type of perfect knowing wherein one understands an object in terms of the causes that make it be what it is. It is attained by the type of reasoning called demonstration that meets the norms of Aristotle's PosteriorAnalytics and as such is certain and not revisable. 14 In no way dependent on divine faith, it falls completely outside the sphere of religious assent. Most of what passes under the name of "science" in the present day, of course, is fallible and revisable, and as such would be classified as opinion and not as science in the strict sense. This raises the question whether there is anything in modern science that is certain and unrevisable, a question to be addressed in the last part of this essay. B) Thomism and the History of Science With the element of religiosity removed, Thomism-as exemplified in the works of both Aquinas and his followers-can be characterized as an intellectual movement within medieval Aristotelianism. As such its major characteristics may be seen by contrasting it with four other varieties of Aristotelianism that flourished in the medieval period, namely, Augustinian, Averroist, 12 Residing as it does in the will, religion is a moral virtue, not an intellectual virtue, and thus it is not directly concerned with knowing, but rather with how people should act to be virtuous. 13 STh 1-11, q. 57, a. 2. Like faith, science is an intellectual virtue, and so, if there is any opposition between the two, it should be resolved in the intellect. Consequently, the relationship that should be examined critically is that between science and faith, not that between science and religion. For a historical account of the former relationship, see William A. Wallace, O.P., "A History of Science and Faith," in Transfiguration:Elements of Science and ChristianFaith, ed. S. M. Postiglione (St. Louis: !TEST Faith/Science Press, 1993), 1-44. 14 Aristotle, PosteriorAnalytics 1.2; see also Aquinas, I Post. Anal., lect. 4-6, for his exposition of this teaching. For a clear exposition of the sense of the term "demonstration" in this context, see Melvin A. Glutz, C.P., "Demonstration," in New Catholic Encyclopedia, ed. J.P. MacDonald, 15 vols. (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1967), 4:757-60. 446 WILLIAMA. WALLACE, O.P. Scotist, and nominalist. 15 Augustinian Aristotelianism generally rejected any attempts to separate reason from faith and approached the study of nature in an ambience dominated by faith. Averroist Aristotelianism placed the greatest trust in reason and saw all of truth as contained in the writings of Aristotle, thus leaving no room for faith. Steering a middle path between the two, St. Thomas granted autonomy to reason in the study of nature but allowed for reason to be complemented by faith in the realm of supernature. Indeed, so great was his commitment to reason that some of his teachings fell under ecclesiastical condemnation in 1277 at both Paris and Oxford. The remaining two varieties of Aristotelianism developed in reaction to the condemnations. That of John Duns Scotus questioned the primacy Aquinas accorded to the intellect and placed emphasis instead on the will. His synthesis can be seen as articulating a position between Augustinianism and Thomism, though closer to the former. Nominalist Aristotelianism, as seen in the works of William of Ockham, reacted against the Scotistic version and further attenuated its knowledge claims by making singulars the object of the intellect and reducing demonstration to the level of hypothetical reasoning. The medieval mendicant orders institutionalized these teachings, with the Dominicans being the main but not exclusive proponents of Thomism and the Franciscans proponents of Scotism and Ockhamism. Though not a scientist in the modern sense, Aquinas addressed many problems that arose in the medieval Aristotelian, Archimedean, Ptolemaic, and Galenic counterparts of modern physics, astronomy, chemistry, and the life sciences.16 In the study of 15 For a fuller account of the various schools, see William A. Wallace, O.P., "Aristotle in the Middle Ages," in Dictionaryof the Middle Ages, ed. J. R. Strayer, 13 vols. (New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1982), 1:456-69. The same divisions continued throughout the Renaissance; for details, see William A. Wallace, O.P., "Aristotle and Aristotelianism," in Encyclopediaof the Renaissance,ed. Paul Grendler, 6 vols. (New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1999), 1:107-13. See also "Scholasticism" in this encyclopedia by the same author, 5:422-25. 16 For a sketch of these scientific contributions, see William A. Wallace, O.P., "Thomas Aquinas," in the Dictionaryof ScientificBiography,ed. C. C. Gillispie, 16 vols. (New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1970-1980), 1: 196-200. A similar treatment of the scientific work SCIENCE AND RELIGION 447 motion, for example, he held that velocity is a mode of continuous quantity and thus is capable of intensification in the same manner as qualities. He further taught that if, by an impossibility, a vacuum were to exist, motion through it would still take time, since its temporal character does not arise uniquely from external resistance. Both of these teachings influenced fourteenth-century thinkers in their quantitative analyses and speculation about internal resistances to motion, thereby foreshadowing the modern concept of inertia. He regarded gravitation as the natural motion of a heavy object to its natural place but denied that it was caused by an absolute principle such as a vis insita. In this he implicitly rejected the absolute space and attractive forces later proposed by the Newtonians, and opted for relational concepts that have more affinity with those of modern relativity. He took up the problems of the magnet, of tidal variations, and of other occult phenomena, and was intent on reducing them to natural, as opposed to supramundane, causes. His analysis of magnetism was known to William Gilbert and was praised by him. In astronomy he was cognizant of the major mathematical theories of the universe and of Ptolemy's use of eccentrics and epicycles, but he was aware that all are based on hypothetical reasoning. He is often cited for voicing his expectation that Ptolemy's theory would one day be superseded by a simpler explanation. On the structure of matter he introduced a distinctive teaching on how elements are present in compounds, holding that they are not present there actually or potentially, but only virtually. His concept of virtual presence dominated all subsequent medieval teachings on the subject and still has relevance in the present day. In the life sciences he wrote a treatise on the heart in an attempt to trace lines of causality in its motion. And, like his contemporaries, he believed in spontaneous generation and countenanced a qualified type of evolution in the initial formation of creatures. Most of the contributions of his followers, the Tho mists, to the history of science consist in defenses and developments of of Aquinas's teacher, St. Albert the Great, will be found in the entry on "Albertus Magnus" by the same author in ibid., 1:99-103. 448 WILLIAM A. WALLACE., O.P. Thomas's thought on these particular points. They are contained in commentaries on his writings, on the Sentences of Peter Lombard, and on the works of Aristotle. In England the foremost Thomists were William of Hothum, Richard Knapwell, and Thomas Sutton. In France the principal Thomists were Hervaeus Natalis and John Capreolus. Among early Germans one might name John of Sterngasse, Nicholas of Strassburg, and Theodoric of Freiberg; later we might mention John Versor. In Italy the early group included Rambert of Bologna and John of Naples. Fifteenth-century expositors included Dominic of Flanders and T ommaso de Vio Cajetan, the latter important for his disputes with Averroists at the University of Padua over the immortality of the human soul. 17 Much work yet needs to be done to assess the full impact of Thomism on the development of science from the thirteenth through the fifteenth century. By far the most important Dominican for medieval science was Theodoric of Freiberg, whose experimental work in optics is universally acknowledged as its crowning achievement. Theodoric came from Albert the Great's province (of T eutonia) and studied at the University of Paris right after Aquinas's death. 18 He used Thomas's commentaries on the PosteriorAnalytics and his exposition of the rainbow as a plan for his research. To these he added an important insight from St. Albert the Great, namely, that individual raindrops are what cause the rainbow, not clouds, as was otherwise thought in his day. Theodoric's genius is seen in his extensive experimental work, working with crystals and spherical flasks of water to trace the passage of light rays through them, to see how they produced 17 For details, see Frederick J. Roensch, E.arly Thomistic School (Dubuque, Iowa: Priory Press, 1964). There are also entries on many of these authors in the New Catholic Encyclopedia.For an overview, see the entry in that encyclopedia on "Thomism" by James A. Weisheipl; see also William A. Wallace, O.P., "Thomism and Its Opponents," Dictionary of the Middle Ages, 12:38-45. Also relevant is William A. Wallace, O.P., "Thomism and Modern Science: Relationships Past, Present, and Future," The Thomist 32 (1968): 67-83. 18 For an overview of Theodoric's life and· works, see William A. Wallace, O.P., "Theodoric (Dietrich) of Freiberg," New Catholic Encyclopedia,14:22-24; for a synoptic account of his contributions to science, see "Dietrich von Freiberg," Dictionaryof Scientific Biography,4:92-95, by the same author. SCIENCE AND RELIGION 449 the colors of both the primary and the secondary rainbow. This led him to the first essentially correct explanation of that phenomenon, for which credit is usually given to Descartes, though Theodoric anticipated Descartes's work by over three hundred years. 19 Cajetan was largely responsible for a revival of Thomism, sometimes called "Second Thomism," which played a significant role in early modern science (i.e., that of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries). Here the locus of activity shifted to the Iberian peninsula, where the principal Dominicans were Francisco Vittoria, Domingo de Soto, Melchior Cano, and Domingo Banez. Of this group Soto is of particular significance for his questions on the Physics of Aristotle, in which he adumbrated the concept of uniform acceleration in free fall.20 Soto is even more important for the history of science than was Theodoric of Freiberg, for there is indirect evidence that Soto's work may have influenced Galileo Galilei in his famous discovery of the laws of falling bodies. Such evidence is discussed elsewhere, but the following brief account may suffice for purposes of this essay.21 The Jesuit Order newly founded by Ignatius Loyola contributed substantially to the development after Soto, since Loyola's constitution enjoined Thomism on them in their teaching of theology, while allowing them to be eclectic Aristotelians in their work in philosophy. Early professors at the Collegio 19 For a detailed account see William A. Wallace, O.P., The Scientific Methodology of Theodoric of Freiberg: A Case Study of the Relationship Between Science and Philosophy, Studia Friburgensia n.s. 26 (Fribourg: University Press, 1959). Excerpts from Theodoric's explanation of the rainbow, translated into English by the author, may be found in Edward Grant, ed., A Source Book in Medieval Science (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1974), 435-41. 20 For details of Soto's research on falling motion, see William A. Wallace, O.P., "The Enigma of Domingo de Soto: Uniformiter difformis and Falling Motion in Late Medieval Physics," Isis 59 (1968): 384-401; and William A. Wallace, O.P ., "Domingo de Soto's 'Laws' of Motion: Text and Context," in Texts and Contexts in Ancient and Medieval Science, ed. Edith Sylla and Michael McVaugh (Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1997), 271-304. 21 See William A. Wallace, 0.P., "Domingo de Soto and the Iberian Roots of Galileo's Science," in Hispanic Philosophy in the Age of Discovery, ed. Kevin White, Studies in Philosophy and the History of Philosophy 29 (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1997), 113-29. 450 WILLIAM A. WALLACE, O.P. Romano, the principal Jesuit institution of learning founded by Loyola himself, relied heavily on Thomistic authors, but as the order grew it developed its own distinctive teachings. These are seen mainly in the writings of Francisco Suarez and Luis de Molina, who also incorporated Scotistic and nominalist strains in their thought. One of Soto's students at the University of Salamanca who was already a priest, Francisco Toledo, joined the Jesuit Order and was sent almost immediately to the Collegio Romano to serve there as a professor of philosophy. 22 By the end of the sixteenth century the courses he inaugurated in logic and natural philosophy had become highly developed. Some time ago it was discovered that Galileo Galilei obtained lecture notes from this period at the Collegio that are Thomistic in orientation, most notably those of Paulus Vallius.23 Between 1589and1591 Galileo appropriated materials from Vallius's lectures that are still extant in his Latin notebooks, composed when he had just begun teaching at the University of Pisa. The influence of the notebooks dealing with physical questions and with motion on Galileo's later work is gradually being recognized among scholars. 24 More important, it is now generally accepted that his notebook dealing with logical questions, essentially an exposition of the teaching on demonstration in the Posterior Analytics, guided his scientific investigations throughout his life.25 22 For a general account of Toledo's life and works, see William A. Wallace, O.P., "Franciscus Toletus," Encyclopediaof the Renaissance,6:148-49. 23 These discoveries are described in summary fashion in William A. Wallace, O.P., "Galileo's Pisan Studies in Science and Philosophy," in The CambridgeCompanionto Galileo, ed. Peter Machamer (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 27-52. For more details see William A. Wallace, O.P., Galileoand His Sources:The Heritageof the CollegioRomano in Galileo's Science (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984). 24 For an English translation of the physical questions, see William A. Wallace, O.P., Galileo's Early Notebooks: The Physical Questions. A Translation from the Latin, with Historicaland PaleographicalCommentary (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1977). z.; An English translation of the logical questions is now also available. See William A. Wallace, O.P., Galileo's Logical Treatises: A Translation,with Notes and Commentary, of His AppropriatedLatin Questions on Aristotle's "PosteriorAnalytics," Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 138 (Dordrecht-Boston-London: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1992). SCIENCE AND RELIGION 451 Both Jesuits and Dominicans played an important part in Galileo's trial in 1633. Despite their differences both groups subscribed to a Thomistic theory of knowledge and of demonstrative proof. In their eyes it was Galileo's inability to provide a demonstration of the earth's motion that brought about his downfall. 26 Recently records have been discovered showing that the Dominican Benedetto Olivieri recognized by 1820 that empirical proofs of the earth's motion-stellar parallax and the deflection of falling bodies towards the east-had by then been given. By invoking such proofs Olivieri was instrumental in having the Church finally remove its long-standing sanctions against Copernicanism and Galileo. 27 Apart from its role in the early modern period, Thomism entered a third phase of development during the late nineteenth and twentieth centuries in a movement known as the Thomistic Revival or Neo-Thomism. Impetus for this revival came from Pope Leo XIII, whose encyclicalAeterni Patris of 1879 called for a return to the thought of St. Thomas as a means of solving contemporary problems. This papal endorsement stimulated much historical research, including that bearing on the history of science. In the early twentieth century the Catholic Pierre Duhem, though not a Thomist himself, used history to develop a positivist philosophy of science that restricted science's epistemic claims. He did so in order to protect the Church's metaphysics against encroachments from the science of his day, which was very antiA companion volume explaining Galileo's use of these questions in his scientific work is William A. Wallace, O.P., Galileo'sLogicof Discoveryand Proof: The Background,Content, and Use of His AppropriatedQuestionson Aristotle's "PosteriorAnalytics,"Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 137 (Dordrecht-Boston-London: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1992). 26 For an account of the trial and the bearing of demonstration on its outcome, see William A. Wallace, O.P., "Galileo's Science and the Trial of 1633," The Wilson Quarterly 7 (1983): 154-64. On Galileo's science, see William A. Wallace, O.P ., "Galileo's Concept of Science: Recent Manuscript Evidence, in The GalileoAffair:A Meetingof Faith and Science, ed. G. V. Coyne, M. Heller, andj. Zycinski (Vatican City: The Vatican Observatory, 1985), 15-35. 27 For details, see Walter Brandmiiller and Johannes Greipl, Copernico, Galilei, e la Chiesa: Fine della controversia(1820), gli atti del Sant'Ufficio (Florence: Leo S. Olschki Editore, 1992). See note 29 below. 452 WILLIAM A. WALLACE, O.P. clerical and materialist in its orientation. Apart from Duhem, twentieth-century Catholics have shown little interest in science, being concerned mainly with metaphysics and social and political thought. Notable exceptions are Jacques Maritain, Charles de Koninck, and Vincent Edward Smith, all of whom developed philosophies of science.28 All three, in my view, were too much influenced by Duhem and the Critique of Science Movement, and tended to deny to modern science the possibility of attaining demonstrations in the world of nature. A moderate realist position that allows such a possibility seems more in accord with Aquinas's own thought. C) Galileo and Proof of the Earth's Motion Before exploring this possibility, let us return to the problem of demonstration of the earth's motion and how it was finally effected in the early nineteenth century. This will require us to back-track for a moment to see how Galileo attempted to prove that the earth moves and the difficulties he encountered. From this we can then sketch other attempts at a proof that ultimately proved to be successful.29 Galileo's notion of demonstration, which he appropriated from the Jesuits, was actually that of Jacopo Zabarella and the Paduan Aristotelians. 30 It involved what is called the demonstrative regress: a procedure wherein one reasons from effect to 28 The views of Duhem, Maritain, and DeKoninck are sketched in William A. Wallace, O.P., "Toward a Definition of the Philosophy of Science," in Melanges a la memoire de Charles de Koninck (Quebec: Les Presses de l'Universite Laval, 1968), 465-485. This essay has been reprinted as "Defining the Philosophy of Science" in William A. Wallace, O.P., From a Realist Point of View: Essays on the Philosophyof Science (Washington, D.C. and Lanham, Md.: University Press of America. 1979, 1983); see the first essay in both, titled "Defining the Philosophy of Science." Vincent Edward Smith explains his position in his PhilosophicalPhysics (New York: Harpers, 1950). 29 What follows is a synopsis of material contained in William A. Wallace, O.P., "Galileo's Trial and Proof of the Earth's Motion," CatholicDossier 1.2 (1995): 7-13. This in turn relies heavily on the discoveries recounted in Brandmiiller and Greipl, Copernico, Galilei, e la Chiesa. 30 Details are given in William A. Wallace, O.P., "Randall Redivivus: Galileo and the Paduan Aristotelians," Journal of the History of Ideas 49 (1988): 133-49. SCIENCEAND RELIGION 453 cause in a provisional way, and then, after testing and verifying the supposed connection between cause and effect, goes backward (or regresses) to the cause again and sees it as offering the unique and proper explanation of the effect. The technique is most easily applied in the "mixed sciences" first developed by Archimedes, namely, those that use a mix of mathematical and physical premises, for in these one can most readily employ simplifying suppositions, indirect proofs, and rigorous methods of approximation. Throughout most of his early period Galileo subscribed to and taught the Ptolemaic (or earth-centered) system of the universe, although he knew of, and occasionally flirted with, the Copernican (or sun-centered) system.31 His astronomy was contained mainly in his Treatise on the Sphere, written around 1606. This was not a planetary astronomy but one that concerned mainly the motions of the earth, moon, and sun. The problems he addressed involved only relative motion and the demonstrations he offered would be valid in either system. The heavens were not his main interest at this time. His enduring preoccupation was the study of mechanics and motion. He made marvelous progress in both, initially with his provisional insights at Pisa, then with a dogged experimental program at Padua that enabled him to formulate and verify the basic laws of motion. At both universities he employed the demonstrative regress with good effect to move both studies to the level of Aristotelian sciences. But that result paled before his improvement of the telescope as an astronomical instrument and the marvelous discoveries he made with it in late 1609 and 1610. The same regress, now combining refined sense observations with irrefutable projective geometry, yielded "necessary demonstrations" that would electrify Europe and set astronomy on an unsuspected new course. The dividing line between Galileo's first and second periods, paradoxically, was drawn by these demonstrations. To understand this one must appreciate that Galileo's view of science was 31 See William A Wallace, 0.P., "Galileo's Early Arguments for Geocentrism and His Later Rejection of Them," in Novita Celestie Crisi del Sapere, ed. Paolo Galluzzi (Florence: Istituto e Museo di Storia della Scienza, 1983), 31-40. 454 WILLIAM A. WALLACE, O.P. very different from our own. Recent science is identified with theory, with series of conjectures and refutations, one succeeding another without end, with no result final and irrevisable. Galileo's knowledge claims were not of this type. He knew that he had offered more than conjectures, that he had really demonstrated the existence of mountains on the moon, satellites of Jupiter, Venus's orbiting of the sun. 32 With these results, the Ptolemaic system could no longer be entertained, even as a possibility. He jettisoned it without further ado and became an ardent supporter of Copernicus. Galileo's second period, inaugurated by his move to Florence as "mathematician and philosopher to the Grand Duke of Tuscany," saw him dropping all work on motion and mechanics to inaugurate a new crusade. Its aim was unambiguous: to convince the Catholic Church that it is the earth that moves, not the sun, despite statements in the Scriptures to the contrary. The period was one that saw few new discoveries, was filled with polemics and controversy, and came to a tragic end. Only after it was over, in the relative tranquillity of his house arrest at Arcetri during his third and final period, could Galileo turn back to the scientific work of his youth and publish the Two New Sciences, for which he is justly proclaimed the "Father of Modern Science." Predictably, Galileo's difficulties with the Church dominated the second period. Shortly after he began urging the reality of Copernican teaching on the earth's motion and the sun's rest he was denounced to Rome as rejecting the traditional interpretation of the Scriptures on that subject. The situation was exacerbated when a Carmelite theologian in Naples, Paolo Antonio Foscarini, came to Galileo's defense and argued that the Bible could be interpreted in a way that sustained the Copernican teaching. This gave rise to the document we might say started the whole "Galileo Affair": a letter of 12 April 1615 from Cardinal Robert Bellarmine to Foscarini, explicitly directed to Galileo also, warning both that they stood on dangerous ground. 33 Bellarmine is given in Wallace, Galileo's Logic of Discovery and Proof, 194-211. of Bellarmine's letter is in Maurice A. Finocchiaro, The Galileo Affair: A Documentary History (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1989), 67-69. 32 A full account 33 An English translation SCIENCEAND RELIGION 455 commended them for their prudence in speaking "suppositionally," that is, for holding, on the supposition that the sun stands still and the earth moves, that one can save the appearances of the heavenly motions. But that is very different from offering a "true demonstration" that the sun is at the center of the world and the earth is in orbit around it. If there were such a demonstration, Bellarmine admitted, the situation would be quite different. But to his knowledge no demonstration of this type existed, and he had grave doubts about whether it ever could. Much research has been done recently on Bellarmine, Foscarini, and another defender of Galileo, the Dominican Tommaso Campanella, in the context of this letter. 34 While quoting the Council of Trent on the interpretation of Scripture, it seems that Bellarmine went considerably beyond the council in explaining how the motion of the sun and the earth's immobility were a matter of faith. For him, this was not because of the subject matter being treated but because of the one informing us about it, namely, the Holy Spirit. This seems to have been behind Bellarmine's personal conviction that the earth's motion could never be demonstrated, even though he was willing to entertain the possibility of a demonstration. On his reading of Trent, everything in the Bible became a matter of faith simply because it was the word of the Holy Spirit. Alarmed by this and other signs that the Church might condemn Copernicanism, Galileo traveled to Rome late in 1615 to head off such action. We can safely presume that his own views on demonstration, deriving as they did from Jesuit teaching notes, were in general agreement with Bellarmine's, who was a Jesuit and had himself taught at the Collegio Romano. But it should be noted here that there can be ambiguity when applying the expression "suppositionally" (Lat. ex suppositione) to demonstrations in the mixed sciences. These invariably are based on suppositions-not mere hypotheses, as Bellarmineunderstood the expression, but the kind that can be verified in physical situations, a la Archimedes. No doubt Galileo understood what Bellarmine J. Blackwell, Galileo,Bellamiine,and the Bible (Notre Dame.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1991). 34 See Richard 456 WILLIAM A. WALLACE, O.P. meant, but he himself, thinking of the Archimedean usage, resumed work on what he hoped would meet the demand for a "true demonstration" of the earth's motion, the famous argument from the tides.35 The basic idea for the argument had occurred to him many years earlier. As he saw it, a twofold motion of the earth, one of annual revolution around the sun, the other of diurnal rotation on its axis, is probably the primary physical cause of the backand-forth motion of the seas on the earth's surface. To this he proposed to add secondary or concomitant causes to account for the diversity of tidal movements. In a letter to Cardinal Alessandro Orsini dated 8 January 1616 in which he explained this, Galileo concluded on the note that he thus would harmonize the earth's motion and the tides, "taking the former as the cause of the latter, and the latter as a sign of and an argument for the former"-a quite concise description of the demonstrative regress. Seven years later, in 1623, a Florentine cardinal who had befriended Galileo, Maffeo Barberini, was elected to the papacy as Pope Urban VIII. The next year, in an audience with the new pope, Galileo explained his demonstration of the earth's motion from the ebb and flow of the tides and expressed his interest in resuming work on the Copernican system, despite the warning he had received in 1615 from Bellarmine. Urban was not impressed with the tidal argument and discouraged Galileo from using it, but apparently he gave permission for Galileo to do a comparative study of the two chief world systems, the Ptolemaic and the Copernican. Galileo returned to Florence, and by 1630 had completed a draft of the new work on this subject, which he entitled simply the Dialogue. He submitted it for approval to the censor, a Dominican named Niccolo Riccardi, then Master of the Sacred Palace. ·15 On various uses of the term suppositio, see William A. Wallace, O.P., "Aristotle and Galileo: The Uses of Hupothesis(Suppositio)in Scientific Reasoning," in Studiesin Aristotle, ed. D. J. O'Meara, Studies in Philosophy and the History of Philosophy 9 (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1981), 47-77. The ways in which the demonstrative regress is used in Galileo's two formulations of the argument from the tides are given in Wallace, Galileo's Logic of Discoveryand Proof, 212-16 and 228-32. SCIENCE AND RELIGION 457 Riccardi was favorable to Galileo but he was uneasy with the manuscript, for it made use of the argument from the tides, of which he knew the pope did not approve, and it clearly presented the Copernican system as superior to the Ptolemaic. Riccardi nonetheless made suggestions for changes at the beginning and at the end, and, when Galileo had made them, approved it for publication. The Dialogue was printed at Florence early in 1632. It was greeted with enthusiasm by Galileo's friends, but in Rome it provoked a decidedly unfavorable reaction. By summertime the pope was so distressed that he ordered the printer to hold up its distribution and appointed a special commission to bring Galileo to trial for publishing it as he had. Thus came about the famous trial of Galileo in 1633. There are many things one might say about the trial and its aftermath. Here we will address only one small question. Had Galileo actually proved that the earth moves, did he feel he had succeeded in demonstrating the earth's motion, thus holding it as true and certain? If so, he would have lied under oath and perjured himself when he claimed during the trial that he did not hold for the earth's motion. Many people think that he did just that: this was Berthold Brecht's judgment on him, and it is that of recent biographer James Reston in his book Galileo: A Life. But that is hard to believe. The argument from the tides was a very fragile argument and Galileo had been patching it up for years, with little success. The earth's motion, on the other hand, is notoriously hard to prove. A better reading of what happened is that a plea-bargaining tactic with Galileo worked out by the prosecutor (the Dominican Maculano Firenzuola) at the end of the trial worked, and probably in a way he had not dreamt it might. He effectively called Galileo's bluff on the tidal argument, and latter's bravado simply caved in. Galileo knew in his heart that he had not demonstrated the earth's motion; he was too good at logic for that. Once he admitted this to himself, the work of the prosecution was over. For, if Galileo still had doubts, as well he might, about the argument from the tides, the basis for the trial had changed. That left room for his acceding to the Church's teaching (wrong though we now know it was) until such time as 458 WILLIAMA.WALLACE,O.P. conclusive proof became available. And although other evidences began to appear in the eighteenth century, it is generally agreed that the earth's motion was not completely accepted until Friedrich Bessel's measurement of stellar parallax in 1838 and Leon Foucault's experiments with the pendulum in 1851-both of which were still a long way off in 1633. Oddly enough, the recent researches of Pope John Paul Il's Galileo Commission have disclosed that the Church actually removed its prohibition against Copernican teaching in 1820, and this on the basis of demonstrations of the earth's motion earlier than Bessel's and Foucault's. 36 The occasion arose in 1820 when Giuseppe Settele, astronomy professor at the Sapienza (now the University of Rome), requested permission to print the second volume of his Astronomia, which taught, on the basis of new evidence, that the earth moves. Permission was denied by the Master of the Sacred Palace, the Dominican Filippo Anfossi, on the basis of the Church's 1616 decree against Copernicanism. Earlier, Settele had asked his colleague at the Sapienza, yet another Dominican, Benedetto Olivieri-who was professor of Old Testament there but also happened to be Commissary of the Holy Office-whether he could openly teach the earth's motion without running into difficulty with the Church. Olivieri, aware of changing interpretations of Scripture and new scientific evidence, had replied in the affirmative. A controversy thereupon ensued between the two Dominicans, Anfossi and Olivieri, both Thomists-the first of a conservative mold, the second clearly a progressive. The latter, being the more knowledgeable of the two, was able to convince Pope Pius VII and the cardinals of the Holy Office of the correctness of his views. Anfossi was silenced, the imprimatur sought after was granted late in 1820, and the second volume of Settele'sAstronomia came off the press on 10 January 1821. The new scientific proofs advanced by Olivieri in presenting his case to the pope are found in the works of two little-known Italian astronomers, Giovanni Battista Guglielmini and Giuseppe 36 The main discovery here was that of Brandmiiller and Greipl, Copernico, Galilei, e la Chiesa. SCIENCE AND RELIGION 459 Calandrelli. The first was professor of mathematics at the University of Bologna and the second director of the observatory in Rome at the Collegio Romano. Olivieri pointed out that, in experiments performed at Bologna between 1789 and 1792, Guglielmini offered the first physical proof of the earth's rotation. Similarly, Calandrelli had measured the parallax of star Alpha in constellation Lyra and so presented what Olivieri called "a sensible demonstration" (una dimostrazione sensibile) of the earth's annual motion. This he had done in a work published in 1806, which he had in fact dedicated to Pope Pius VII. For our purposes here Guglielmini's demonstration is the more interesting, since it involved the Torre dei Asinelli in Bologna, the same tower the Jesuit Giambattista Riccioli had used in 1640 to verify experimentally Galileo's law of falling bodies. Guglielmini took inspiration from a passage in Galileo's Dialogue where, on the Second Day, he is discussing the fall of an object from the orb of the moon to the earth's surface. Rather than falling to a point directly beneath the point from which it is released, the object should "run ahead of the whirling of the earth" and land at a point farther to the east. This should come about because, at the time of its release, the object would have a greater horizontal component in its motion the more distant it would be from the earth. The effect would not be noticed with objects dropped from a ship's mast or from a low tower, but it might be noticeable with those dropped from a high tower such as the Torre dei Asinelli. Sir Isaac Newton was aware of this possible test, and so was Pierre Simon de Laplace, who suggested it to Joseph Jerome Lalande, director of the Paris observatory, who unfortunately never performed it. Thus it was left for Guglielmini to do so. He made a number of tests from the Torre at a height of 78 .3 meters and measured, on an average, a deviation of 19 mm. to the east. Concerned about atmospheric disturbances at the Torre, he also measured drops from a height of 29 meters in a spiral staircase inside the astronomical observatory at Bologna and found a deviation there of 4 mm. to the east. Guglielmini was in communication with a German astronomer, Johann Friedrich Benzenburg, who dropped objects from the 460 WILLIAMA. WALLACE, O.P. campanile of a church in Hamburg in 1802, at a height of 76.3 meters, and again from within a mine shaft at Schelbusch in 1804, at a depth of 85 .1 meters, and obtained comparable results. Rough confirmation was also obtained by Ferdinand Reich, who performed tests in a mine shaft at Freiberg in Saxony, at a depth of 158.5 meters, in 1831. It turned out that longer falls were not necessarily more accurate indicators, because perturbing factors, both in the open air and within mine shafts, introduced effects much greater than that being measured. Definitive tests were finally made in the United States by Edwin Herbert Hall in 1902, working at Harvard under very controlled conditions, at a latitude close to that of Bologna. With a drop of 23 meters, Hall measured a deviation of 1.50 ± 0.05 mm. to the east, against a predicted value of 1.8 mm. When one considers the problems encountered in demonstrations such as Guglielmini's, and the length of time it took to solve them, one can appreciate the enormous difficulty faced by Galileo with his argument from the tides. Actually his insights were correct: there are mathematical effects in the tides' motions that might be produced by the earth's motion, but these are so minute as to be undetectable by physical measurements. It also turns out that there was nothing wrong with his logic-the demonstrative regress was the proper technique to use in seeking a proof of this type. Galileo simply underestimated the difficulty of his undertaking. For this he surely deserves the greatest sympathy. Perhaps the theologians of 1633 deserve some sympathy also, unless we are to condemn them, as some wish to do, for not being prescient enough to see hundreds of years into science's future. The point of all this is simply that the norms pointed out at the beginning of this essay, stated explicitly to Galileo by Cardinal Bellarmine, and already agreed to by Galileo in his Letter to the Grand Duchess Christina, were still in effect in 1820. As soon as a demonstration of the earth's motion had been achieved, it had become a fact known by reason and its contrary could no longer be held "on faith." The opposition between science and religion ceased at that point, and the Church finally recognized this. It SCIENCE AND RELIGION 461 had taken almost two hundred years to establish the fact, and indeed its factual status had still to be reinforced by the more precise discoveries of Besseland Foucault. But the distinction was valid, and the Church can hardly be condemned for adhering to it as long as it did-although one may well wish that the discoveries had been made a lot sooner. D) Thomism as a Philosophy of Science The demonstration of the earth's motion by empirical science was not expected by many, and yet such a demonstration, when it came, did cause the Church to rethink its position on Copernicanism and ultimately to close the case on Galileo. There is no doubt, then, that demonstration is an important concept for resolving potential conflicts between science and religion. 37 It is even more important for resolving serious problems that have arisen within the last decade or two within the philosophy of science. This thesis has been argued in my book The Modeling of Nature: Philosophy of Science and Philosophy of Nature in Synthesis. 38 The following is a brief summary of the theme of that work and its relevance to the topic of science and religion. Our scientific knowledge of the universe surpasses that of any previous age. Yet, paradoxically, the philosophy of science movement is now in disarray. The collapse of logical empiricism and the rise of historicism and social constructivism have effectively left all of the sciences without an epistemology. The claims of realism have become increasingly difficult to justify, and, for many, the only alternatives are probabilism, pragmatism, and relativism. 37 I have made this point more strongly in William A. Wallace, 0.P., "Dialectics, and Experiments, and Mathematics in Galileo," in Scientific Controversies: Philosophical HistoricalPerspectives,ed. Peter Machamer, Marcello Pera, and Aristides Baltas (New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), 100-124. 38 William A. Wallace, O.P., The Modeling of Nature: Philosophy of Science and Philosophyof Nature in Synthesis (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1996). See Benedict M. Ashley and Eric A. Reitan, "On William A. Wallace, The Modelingof Nature," The Thomist 61 (1997): 625-40. 462 WILLIAM A. WALLACE, O.P. But the case is not hopeless. Human beings have a natural ability to understand the world in which they live. Many have suggested that this understanding requires advanced logic and mathematics. To the contrary, nature can more easily be understood through the use of simple modeling techniques. That explains the title of the book, The Modeling of Nature. In its first part, through the use of iconic and epistemic models a quasiintuitive knowledge of the philosophy of nature is built up. 39 Selected materials from cognitive science are there employed to provide a model of the human mind that illuminates not only the philosophy of nature but also the logic, psychology, and epistemology that are requisite to it. The second part of the book is devoted to renovating the philosophy of science. The purpose of this part is twofold: to provide an epistemic justification of the insights provided in the first part and, in the process, to delve into aspects of logic and epistemology that are treated more by philosophers of science than by natural philosophers. It begins with an overview of the philosophy of science movement as this developed in the twentieth century, mainly in an Anglo-American setting, pointing out how it relates only tangentially to the study of nature. Following this an analysis is given of probable reasoning as it has become canonical for philosophers of science in the United States, showing its similarities with dialectical or topical reasoning in the Aristotelian tradition. The main contribution comes in the chapter entitled "The Epistemic Dimension of Science," where the case is presented for going beyond probable reasoning to restore the notion of epistemeto science, and, through its use, to seeing some science, at least, as providing true and certain knowledge. By way of application, eight conceptual histories are then considered, ranging from medieval to recent science, and detailing how demonstrations were actually arrived at in different fields of science. The concluding chapter takes up various controversial aspects of these demonstrations and explains how disputes were 39 How this is done is explained in William A. Wallace, 0.P., "A Place for Form in Science: The Modeling of Nature," Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 69 (1995): 35-46. SCIENCE AND RELIGION 463 finally resolved, thus supporting the epistemic thesis advanced in the previous two chapters. Implicit in this discussion is a philosophy of science that is based on knowledge of nature rather than on formal logic and that harvests the fruit of science's history as this serves to clarify its philosophy. Thus it is able to bypass the technicalities that burden the literature of the philosophy of science movement and so bring the discipline closer to the commonsense realism by which scientists actually live and operate. One can see from this how important the concept of demonstration is for advancing the cause of realism in modern science. Neither Maritain nor de Koninck nor Smith ever faced up to this problem and they were content to leave all of modern science, as did Pierre Duhem, within the domain of probable knowledge. Demonstration, of course, is not easy to teach.Yet the task is manageable. And demonstration is important, not simply for the philosophy of science, but also for saving the philosophy of nature as a discipline. It should also be understood and preserved as one of our most valuable tools for heading off science-religion conflicts in the future. The Thomist 65 (2001): 465-73 MORAL THEOLOGY IN A SAPIENTIALMODE: VER/TATIS SPLENDOR AND THE RENEWAL OF MORAL THEOLOGY CHRISTOPHER J. THOMPSON Universityof St. Thomas St. Paul, Minnesota T he issuance of Veritatis splendor on the Feast of the Transfiguration in 1993 marked one of the most important catalysts in the renewal of moral theology. Veritatis splendorand the Renewalof MoralTheology,a collection of essays published to mark the five-year anniversary of the encyclical, continues that renewal at least through the next generation of Catholic scholarship. 1 Bringing together some "outstanding" Catholic scholars, the collection provides readers with an excellent analysis of some of the leading themes and insights inaugurated by the Holy Father. It is likely to become a standard resource among seminary students as well as interested laity. Part 1, focusing on "Perspectives," features the reflections of three leading scholars, J. Augustine DiNoia, O.P., Servais Pinckaers, O.P., and Alasdair Macintyre. Part 2 focuses more specifically on certain "issues" in moral theology, featuring reflections by Russell Hittinger (on natural law), Avery Dulles, S.J. (on freedom), Livio Melina (on the desire for happiness), Martin Rhonheimer (on intrinsically evil acts), and Romanus Cessario, O.P. (on moral absolutes). The issues and scholarship displayed here are familiar enough to anyone acquainted with the contemporary shape of the discipline, reinforcing the notion that this J. A. DiNoia, O.P., and Romanus Cessario, O.P ., eds., VeritatisSplendorand the Renewal of Moral Theology: Studies by Ten Outstanding Scholars (Chicago: Midwest Theological 1 Forum, 1999). Pp. x + 287. ISBN 0-87973-739-5. 465 466 CHRISTOPHER]. THOMPSON collection is likely to become a standard supplement to any serious course in moral theology. Part 3 focuses upon the encyclical's "reception" and features efforts by William May and Rhonheimer. In this last section the question of the accuracy of the encyclical's portrayal of dissenting traditions, specifically "proportionalism," is raised-no doubt in an attempt to address the less enthusiastic reception of the encyclical among those who have challenged its accuracy. The essays conclude with an epilogue by Pio Cardinal Laghi, at the time of publication Prefect for the Sacred Congregation for Catholic Education, concerning the reception and impact of Veritatis splendor on Catholic higher education. For anyone familiar with these contributors, it should come as no surprise that the overall tone of the collection is one of enthusiastic support for the encyclical, specifically its overall injection of a spirit of renewal for a more Thomistically oriented ethics. In this sense, the collection follows nicely upon the themes addressed in the encyclical as well as the more recent reflections of the Holy Father in Fides et ratio on the importance of philosophical reflection at the heart of a sound theological method. However, it would be wrong to assume that the essays are simply the reflections of now rather familiar positions, simply one more round in the neverending chorus of recriminations that has marked moral theology for the past few decades. Instead, the collection gives rise to a hope in the new evangelization inaugurated in this pontificate, a hope that the call for renewal in moral theology announced by the Second Vatican Council is beginning to take shape. To get at this issue of a renewal in moral theology, the question may be reasonably asked: what is the advantage of compiling a collection of essays, many of which have previously appeared in well-known Catholic venues? What does the collection do as a whole, in other words, that is not already accomplished in its parts? The first line of response might be simply practical. Compiling leading essays on the questions raised in Veritatis splendor supplies the teacher of moral theology a handy reference toward MORAL THEOLOGY IN A SAPIENTIALMODE 467 which he might direct students interested in the orthodox reception. For whatever else mainstream Catholic academics might be remembered, if at all, in this period of the intellectual history of the Catholic academy, enthusiastic study of the thought of the Holy Father will not be one of them. Students interested in the intellectual history of theology may satisfy some curiosity in this collection on those terms alone. But to frame the collection of essays from the vantage of its place within a "history of the conversation" of moral theology, to see the compendium as merely the necessary, and thus predictable, complement to other, less enthusiastic collections of responses, would be already to miss its spirit. What the compilers of these essays intend is not merely to display, from the vantage of some disinterested desire for comprehensiveness, the range of responses to Veritatis splendor among enthusiasts. They wish rather to give voice to, if only through a chorus line of individual performers, a reformulation of what the task of moral theology ought to be about. To yield to mere historical curiosity in matters of contemporary moral theology would be to run precisely counter to the very point of this book. "Theological discourse today," the editors note in the brief preface, "is often dominated by historicist interests. The question addressed by researchers is not 'What is the truth of the matter?' but 'what did a particular author think about the subject?'" (viii). Though there is no evidence that the editors would prohibit sales to those who are interested in merely finding out "what a particular author thinks about the subject," to receive the collection on these terms alone is to miss the point. The editors note that though many of the essays do take account of the history of moral theology, they do not end there; nor do they confine themselves to a dialectical exchange with previously published assessments of the encyclicals. The ten internationally known scholars . . . are united in their effort to take the encyclical as a source for serious theological thinking. (Ibid., emphasis added) 468 CHRISTOPHER J. THOMPSON "Serious theological thinking," it turns out, will have a multifaceted appearance throughout the collection, but common to all the essays is the consistent hue of a "reformulation of morality in terms of a theology of the moral life" (ix). In other words, what the essays taken together as a whole begin to convey to the careful reader is the overall impression of a change in direction in the mode in which moral theology is to be understood and conducted. By assembling essays whose unifying conviction orbits the question of the truth-not merely of the encyclical, but of the truth of the moral life in Christ- the editors have done more than supply a particular collection driven by a set of academic convictions. They have, instead, supplied a kind of apprenticeship in Christian formation by drawing upon the sapiential character of moral theology. Because of this drawing together of disparate voices into a common chorus of theological reflection, readers are better able to discern the kind of theological reflection the encyclical itself is hoping to renew. Moral theology, in these essays taken as a whole, is to be understood not merely as an exercise in academic reasoning, a kind of scientiadivorced from any practical reasoning. Rather, it is to be understood in its sapiential mode, as an exercise in the wisdom in which the practical living of the life in Christ is to be taken up. In short, what the editors are attempting to accomplish is the very thing Veritatissplendorsought to inaugurate, namely, a reconfiguration of the task of moral theology as precisely the search for the wisdom one finds in a life ordered toward Jesus Christ. All practical reasoning in its Christian mode will either be directed to this aim or it will fail as an authentic expression of moral reasoning. It would be wrong, moreover, to see the encyclical as well as these essays as simply a response to what proportionalist theories have sought to develop after the council. Alasdair Macintyre rightly warns, "One way of missing the point of Veritatissplendor would be to tie its reading too closely to the work of those particular moral theologians whose writings may have been the occasion for its composition" (94). Though the essays by Rhonheimer and May address the question of the fairness of the MORAL THEOLOGY IN A SAPIENTIALMODE 469 encyclical in its criticism of certain strands of theological reasoning, the encyclical's reach is far beyond the parameters of the proportionalist disputes. Servais Pinckaers's essay provides one way by which the reader can begin to appreciate the depth and scope of the encyclical's vision. In a comprehensive and masterful synopsis which itself is worth the price of admission, Pinckaers identifies six guidelines, or points of departure, for the evangelical renewal of moral theology: the relationship between moral theology and Scripture, the question of happiness, the reinterpretation of the decalogue in the light of authentic love, the reintegration of the new law in moral theology, the link between the commandments and the search for perfection, and the necessity of grace (19-34). The comprehensiveness of his analysis should be enough to persuade the reader that the vision of the encyclical, as well as the conversation it seeks to inaugurate, while occasioned by certain recent trends, extends well beyond the horizons of the last few decades. It is a call to renew moral theology, not to reinvigorate a restorationist longing for a preconciliar tradition. This is why the essays cannot fairly be described as "conservative." For those of us who were trained in moral theology within the last decade or so, "conservatives" tended to be those who objected to proportionalist analyses, and because of that conviction were inclined to speak of the moral theology almost exclusively along the fault lines of "intrinsically evil acts," "objective evil," and to speak in terms of the moral "act itself." Such language remains instructive, to be sure, but it is difficult to find undergraduate students or incoming seminarians these days who are energized by the notion that the accomplishment of Veritatis splendor lies in its more or less definitive rejection of proportionalist moral reasoning. To limit one's theological formation, or one's subsequent efforts in teaching, to the charting of these now ossified categories is simply to ensure that the renewal in moral theology will be happening in someone else's seminar. One promising line of inquiry opened up in several of the essays has to do with the Holy Father's remarks that in order to 470 CHRISTOPHER]. THOMPSON enter effectively into the task of moral theology one has to take serious the demand to place oneself "in the perspective of the acting person." The phrase is put to use in several ways throughout many of the essays, though it lacks an entry among the subjects in the index. Among them is the notion that one must shift one's emphasis from that of an abstract consideration of moral acts as such to the concrete context of a deliberative choice on the part of the person. Rhonheimer's reflections in part 2 on "Intrinsically Evil Acts and the Moral Point of View" picks up this line of reasoning and argues on several fronts that such a perspective helps reveal deficiencies in typically proportionalist accounts of moral reasoning. For example, by addressing the question of the natural inclinations from the perspective of the acting person, one is better able to discern the important distinction between the genus naturae of human acts and the genus moris. The proportionalist habit of speaking of "non-moral goods," Rhonheimer suggests, confuses the two orders. It is not the ends of these inclinations which are non-moral, but rather the abstract way of considering them which is non-moral. The problem springs from looking at natural inclinations simply as natural inclinations, inclinations of the "genus naturae" abstracted from the actual human person. (165) There can be, from the perspective of the acting person, no nonmoral goods directing the will in a deliberate choice; the attempt on the part of some proportionalists to deracinate the object of the will from any moral valuation distorts what occurs psychologically in the performance of a properly human act. In his second essay, written in response to Richard McCormick, Rhonheimer returns again to the perspective of the acting person, this time focusing more precisely on the nature of deliberation and the object of the act understood as "a freely chosen kind of behavior." Precisely as a chosen kind of behavior, the object of the moral act carries with it some kind of intentionality. Otherwise, it is not amoral, deliberative act. The failure to recognize any intentionality in a deliberative act (the MORAL THEOLOGY IN A SAPIENTIALMODE 471 object of which is a freely chosen kind of behavior) leads to a kind of physicalism in terms of human action by pushing any consideration of "intentions" whatsoever under the consideration of "ends." Thus while proportionalists might speak of the socalled object of an act, "killing as such," and only then discuss the issues of proportionate intentions, Rhonheimer suggests that "killing as such," is not a proper grasp of the moral object. It fails to include precisely the deliberate intention, the choice, to kill. There is a difference, in other words, between the object of the act, as an "intentional basic action," and further intentions (249). And because of this difference one can reasonably assert that there are certain actions, as deliberate, freely chosen kinds of behavior, that can never be part of one's intentional action, independent of any further intentions on the part of the agent. There are, in other words, objectively evil acts, which in their very object can be said to be "not capable of being ordered toward God." The reason why "killing the innocent" "as such" might be indifferent in its species (and thus taken to be a kind of non-moral or pre-moral evil) is that one can imagine the (albeit rare) instance in which the death of an innocent person is the consequence of a non-moral act, an actus hominis. But from the perspective of the acting person, as opposed to a person who merely happens to cause events, "killing the innocent" is always and everywhere wrong, a species of murder. As a human act (the actus humanus) of an acting person, it is a deliberate, freely chosen kind of behavior. Considered "as such" in this light, it cannot ever be the case that this freely chosen kind of behavior is a kind of nonmoral or pre-moral evil. For as a human act of the acting person it is by definition morally specified. As evil in its species, it cannot ever be performed by one whose deliberative intelligence is also ordered toward God. It is, in other words, evil in its objectregardless of any further intentions. Livia Melina is another of the essayists who takes up this perspective of the acting person and draws upon this vantage point to reintroduce the notion of the desire for happiness and the tradition of the virtues at the center of morality. "The priority of virtue over the commandment is a decisive characteristic of the 472 CHRISTOPHERJ. THOMPSON 'ethics of the agent subject' or 'ethics of the first person' vis-a-vis the 'ethics of the observer' or 'ethics of the third person.'" Melina continues, "For the former, the agent subject is at the center with his aspiration toward happiness; for the latter, an external regulation of behavior by means of norms and precepts is at the center" (149). By beginning its meditation on moral theology from the context of the desire for happiness, Veritatis splendor "reintroduces the desire for happiness as the original experience and foundational principle of morality, within which the Commandments, in their turn find their proper place and significance" (ibid.). In this sense, Melina serves as a nice complement to some of the insights developed at length by Pinckaers. Still, I am less persuaded that further nuances on the distinctions between first and third person accounts of the moral life will yield as much fruit as a more adequate appropriation of St. Thomas's moral psychology. Once the analysis of the deliberative choice is fully grasped, so many of the complementary notions of the Christian moral life can be adequately introduced. In the deliberative choice the intellectual appropriation of the truth is wedded to the vigorous desire for an authentic good. Then the role of the intellectual virtue of faith becomes paramount. The need for the right ordering of the appetites through the moral virtues and the theological virtues of charity and hope emerges. The integral role of prudential reasoning becomes apparent. The essential and elevating role of the gifts of the Holy Spirit becomes manifest and the vocation of the person in the New Law toward beatitude is revealed-not a bad start to begin one's renewal in moral theology. While a more adequate psychology would likely go a long way toward reinvigorating the place of morality in the Christian life, it alone will not be enough to complete the kind of renewal toward which both the encyclical and the editors seem to be pointing. For to turn to "the person" is not merely to turn to a more adequate psychology. Rather, to speak of the person is to enter into the realm of metaphysics.The "person" is the supposit, that "subsistence" in which the intimate dialectic of freedom and truth in the spiritual being is nurtured. "To his people and to his MORAL THEOLOGY IN A SAPIENTIAL MODE 473 faithful ones, to those who put in him their hope," borrowing from the imagery of the Psalmist, "person" is that sanctum where "kindness and truth shall meet, justice and peace shall kiss" (Ps 85). The person is not merely the sum of the performance of actions by a protagonist, nor is "person" to be at all reduced to personality. "Person" is the source of personality and action. It names that impenetrable mystery of the "I," the forge in which the love of the good is purified in the fire of a true conscience. It is that which gives rise to personality, but because it is more than personality, it is also that source, that origin by which personality may be healed of its defects, where one's character is no longer to be confused with lack of character. "Person" discloses the subsistent at the heart of personality, that utterly unique gift of existing by which we are a gift of self. Any moral theologian who wishes to take "the perspective of the acting person" seriously, then, must also be willing to take up the task of helping people "acknowledge their sins, so that [they] can move beyond the state of image-restoration, which entails sorrow and conversion, to that of image-perfection, which is the state of genuine freedom" (Cessario, "Moral Absolutes in the Civilization of Love," 203). Failure to grasp the sequla Christi at the heart of all sound moral theology is ultimately, "fatal to true theology, for it prevents the theologian from developing the habit of systematically understanding the truths of the faith" (viii). More to the point, it prevents the theologian from developing the habit of systematically understanding the faith as true. One can, it seems, master the trade of the academy and thus "manage" the claims of the faith in a manner which is perhaps systematically consistent without ever having to raise the more poignant, the most human question: what is the truth? To do so, though, would be to join the ranks of all of those "rich with intellectual possessions," who have nonetheless gone their own way-sad. BOOK REVIEWS The Philosophy of William of Ockham in the Light of Its Principles. By ARMAND MAURER. Studies and Texts 133. Toronto: PIMS, 1999. Pp. 590. $85.00 (cloth). ISBN 0-88844-133-9. In the last three decades of the twentieth century, students of medieval philosophy witnessed or partook in a widespread enthusiasm for the thought of William of Ockham. That enthusiasm was made possible by a new critical edition of William's philosophical and theological writings (St. Bonaventure, N.Y.: Franciscan Institute, 1967-88). Ideologically, it was fueled by the perception that William's thought, more than that of other medieval thinkers, approximates the linguistic, analytic mode of philosophy that prevails in most American and British universities, and so just might convince contemporary philosophers that medieval philosophy offers something worthwhile. The abundant academic literature has sufficed to establish William as a "major figure" in medieval philosophy, worthy of being called "William Ockham" by analogy with "Thomas Aquinas" (will "Henry Ghent" be next?). By the end of the century, the original fervor had cooled somewhat. After all of the analyses of arguments and single doctrines, the time was ripe for a disinterested, comprehensive assessment of William's thought and its unifying insights. That assessment has now been provided by Armand Maurer in his synthetic study of William's philosophy "in the light of its principles." Maurer's book displays the lucidity of interpretation and style that characterizes all of his scholarly writings on medieval philosophy. In his notes he generously cites the contemporary literature on William's thought and graciously acknowledges those interpretations from which his own has benefitted. The reader will be thankful that he has not cluttered his pages with recitations and refutations of contemporary analyses that oppose his own; rather, he indicates the disagreements in the notes, allowing readers to pursue them as they will. Nor does he indulge the habit of labeling William's thought "nominalist" or "conceptualist" according to some a-historical typology of possible positions. Maurer uses those terms sparingly and interchangeably. In this he is historically justified. William did not call himself a "nominalist" or "conceptualist." Before the fact, Albert the Great's definition of the term 'nominalist' "perfectly fits Ockham's doctrine" (63). Although many in the fifteenth century (guided by Albert's usage) imposed the term nomina/es on 475 476 BOOK REVIEWS William and followers of the "modern way," they understood well that he focused his analysis on concepts and their "mental language"; for them, as for Maurer, the fundamental issue was not the relation between concepts and spoken or written language (the conventional usage of which the requirements of "mental language," de virtute sermonis, must sometimes disrupt), but the relation between thinking and extramental reality. Maurer was a close colleague (and admirer) of Etienne Gilson; his synthetic approach and disposition of topics, indeed, is rather "Gilsonian." As the title of his book suggests, he interprets William's philosophy by means of a reductio ad principia,that is, in terms of key principles that are operative throughout his treatments of medieval topics and questions. He also expounds William's arguments dialectically, in relation to the arguments of his actual logical and theological opponents (notably, Walter Burley, Pseudo-Richard of Campsell, Thomas Aquinas, Henry of Ghent, Duns Scotus, William of Alnwick, Walter Chatton, Peter Aureol). Maurer's "reductive" method is akin to "the spirit of medieval philosophy" itself. Thus, one of William's fourteenth-century disciples, in a work entitled De principiistheologiae,derived 250 of his master's philosophical and theological conclusions from the two principles of divine omnipotence and parsimony (169 and 81, respectively; see 8, 121, 132). So also fifteenth-century opponents of the nominatesidentified their way of thinking according to its ontological and logical first principles (mostly the same ones Maurer identifies). As far as Scholastic thought is concerned, there would seem no better way to discover "the unity of a philosophical experience." According to Maurer, the principles or "primary notions" of William's philosophy are (1) "his belief in the absolute power and freedom of God and the complete contingency of the created world" (and his use of the allied distinction between the "absolute" and "ordered" power of God); (2) the principle of parsimony, whereby "a plurality should not be posited without necessity"; (3) his disjunctive conception of the relation between language and reality and his consequent reliance on the analysis of the "supposition of terms"; (4) his ontological convictions that "only individual things are real" (i.e., exist outside the mind) "and that individuals are such by nature and have no essences in common," so that "each individual is an individual . . . by essence" (7-9). Maurer's extended analysis discloses that these principles are interrelated: (4) depends on (1), and (2) and (3) on both of those. William's logic, in short, which has received so much attention, is a consequence of his theological faith and ontology. At the outset, Maurer emphasizes the historical truth that William "was first and foremost a theologian," whose "main works are professedly theological," who in his philosophical works "never forgets that he is a theologian," who continually introduces the "truth of theologians" into his logical writings and Aristotelian commentaries, who philosophized in order "to provide a finely honed instrument for theological investigation," and who, finally, "would undoubtedly have been surprised to receive the title" philosophus(reserved for BOOK REVIEWS 477 the likes of Aristotle and Averroes [4, 6, 9)). Nevertheless, Maurer devotes his study to William's "philosophy," venturing "into the domain of his theology ... only insofar as this helps to illuminate his philosophy" (9). That venturing turns out to be frequent. Like every other Scholastic theologian, William distinguishes formally between faith and reason, theology and philosophy. Yet, in exercitu, by Maurer's own account, William's reasoning continually subverts any attempt to extract a rationally independent philosophy from his thought. The penetration of "the truth of theologians" into William's logic and natural philosophy accords with his conviction, evident in all of his writings, that human reason is weak and by itself cannot attain sure knowledge of the "way things really are." The soul contacts reality directly through (imperfect) sensible and intellectual intuitions of singular things within its purview. Thence the mind, often misled by the abstract terms of conventional speech, begins to conceptualize and generalize about the things it cogitates. William leaves unclear "how the mind forms universal concepts" (494; see 470-510). By the technique of 'personal supposition' especially (26-28), through the tangle of universal terms and concepts the mind fights its way back to extramental reality, declaring the singularity of the things it apprehends and judges. Logic corrects misconceptions "from below"; faith supplies true propositions "from above." What accounts for this disjunction and natural disproportion between the way things are, on the one hand, and the way we must reason about them, on the other? This is but one "mystery" pertaining to William's theory of cognition in statu isto (208-9 n. 11). Might not recourse to a set of theological doctrines-for example, original sin, the virtue of faith, the beatific vision (for the last, see 266)-clarify the mystery, at least "conditionally"? In William's view, "the mind seldom rises to a strict demonstration"; thus, as a theologian, he felt justified in seeking "other resources to confirm his philosophical conclusions" and "in bringing theological arguments to bear upon philosophical issues" that cannot be demonstrated (134). William's theologizing practice of philosophy, moreover, accords with his understanding of the unity of a science. A science is composed of many parts with many subjects, and is a collection of many propositions and mental habits; consequently, no science has a numerical unity but is an organized collection of cognitive items, no one of which can be said to belong exclusively to any one science. Thus, one may integrate theological habits and propositions into philosophy, and conversely, philosophical habits and propositions into theology (142-44). Like other medieval Scholastic teachers, William philosophized in the terms of Aristotle's writings. For him, however, Aristotle's teaching did not capture the "philosophical truth"; rather, Aristotle's doctrines are probable opinions (even when the Philosopher thought he had made demonstrations), and are often erroneous, in which case they must be corrected in the light of Christian faith and brought into harmony with the orthodox teaching of the Church and the "saints." Maurer concludes that William's commentaries freely interpret Aristotle's texts in the light of his "conceptualist views in logic, physics, and 478 BOOK REVIEWS metaphysics," and consequently "gives us a new version of Aristotle, profoundly different from those of his fellow scholastics" (104). One may wonder, indeed-as Maurer himself sometimes does (e.g., 46)-in what sense William can be called an "Aristotelian," and whether his largelysemantic interpretations did not, in effect (and perhaps by intention), eviscerate the pagan Philosopher's teaching of its "truth-value" in respect of the order of nature. William insisted that students should master logic before delving into the subtleties of the sciences, and judged that many errors in natural philosophy and theology were the result of the lack of such mastery. His logic, indeed, predetermines many of his solutions to philosophical and theological questions (9); for that reason, Maurer rightly begins his study with an analytical survey of its main components (14-102). Yet even at the starting point of logic the theologizing character of William's thought is manifest. (It is telling that he composed his Summa logicae after the Ordinatio.) Materially, for example, he introduces the topic of the Trinity into his treatment of 'relation', the Incarnation into his treatment of 'substance, nature and suppositum', and the Eucharist into his treatments of 'quantity' and 'accident'. The penetration of theology goes even deeper, to the level of first principles. Maurer observes that even though William distinguishes in theory between the realms of logic and metaphysics, his treatment of logic is inseparable from his ontology and his consequent noetic and epistemology. William's conviction that only individual things exist outside the mind is itself dependent on his notions of God's absolute freedom and omnipotence in creation, and those doctrines, according to William himself, are not provable by reason but are articles of faith (see 24565 et passim). Scarcely less than in his theological writings he repeatedly introduces his "favorite revealed principle of the divine omnipotence into philosophical discussions" (4). Aristotle's notion of demonstration, which many thought to be the crowning achievement of human reason, is rooted ultimately in his false doctrine of the eternity of the world and its "necessary beings," and in his ignorance of God's free creation of the world and its radical contingency. Thus, as Maurer shows, "Ockham makes little use of induction and demonstrative reasoning in his philosophy ... his preferred method is dialectic" (121). Maurer's treatment of William's use of dialectical reasoning (112-21) is one of the most valuable contributions of his book. This feature of William's thought reflects a more old-fashioned understanding of how reason can be used in theology, prevalent before medieval Scholastic thinkers became absorbed with the criteriology of the Posterior Analytics (in a way that was sometimes disadvantageous to the cognitive status of theology). While William diminishes the importance and range of demonstration, he elevates the status of dialectic. In his mind, dialectical reasoning produces not only probable conclusions but even conclusions that are "true" and evince a "conditional necessity." The "conditional necessity" of such conclusions can be explained only in relation to another theological principle, God's "ordered power," by which he actually BOOK REVIEWS 479 created the world. The "rules and laws" of the actual physical and moral universe, discoverable by dialectical reasoning, "have only conditional or hypothetical necessity, for they are necessary only on condition that God wills them to be so" (119). Significantly, William's principle of parsimony is a dialectical instrument. Maurer argues that William's "razor has an ontological as well as a methodological bearing," that he "intended the razor to be used in philosophy along with the dictates of reason and experience and not with God's extraordinary workings," and that the principle can produce "conditionally necessary" conclusions that are not "doubtful but highly believable" (126-29). But if William sought other foundations for the principle of parsimony besides the divine omnipotence, it remains that the "conditionally necessary" conclusions that it optimally yields, as all such, rely on the theological principle of God's "ordered power." Fifteenth-century philosophers identified the "modern way" initiated by William by its doctrines on universals and the divine attributes and ideas. Their perception seems acute. Here too a philosophical doctrine is inseparable from theological conclusions. Maurer points out that William's "most extensive and systematic treatment" of universals occurs in the Ordinatio 1, d. 2, qq. 4-8, in conjunction with his treatment of the divine attributes (Ord. 1, d. 2, qq. 1-2), in order "to lay the groundwork for the resolution of theological issues, such as the possibility of predicating univocal concepts of God and creatures, and the knowability of the divine essence" (64). "How could he resolve the problem of the divine attributes," Maurer asks, "without carefully investigating the nature of a universal concept and its relation to reality, the mind, and language?" (184). One might just as well read the problematic the other way round, according to the actual order of questions in the text. William discerned that those who argued, in various ways, that distinct universal concepts of properties or specific essences correspond with something in re, in the constitution of beings existing outside the mind, furthermore argued, however weakly or strongly, that they had also some foundation ante rem, in "the fullness of divine perfection" or in some distinction of reason in the divine mind or by their own formal nature. By denying that distinctions among the divine attributes correspond with anything in the divine essence but only connote diverse perfections in creatures as conceptualized by human reason, and by arguing that the divine ideas are "pure nothings" in God and refer only to the multiplicity of created, individual beings, which God knows by his making them (see 212-28), William eliminated any foundation, natural or divine, for the reality of universals. Here one arrives, in terms of Maurer's interpretation, at the heart of William's theological agenda: by his denials, William sought "to uphold the autonomy and liberty of God against all philosophical threats to these divine prerogatives," which include "the Platonic notion of ideas as models of creation that have some kind of being of their own" and upon which God would depend, and thus "would cease to be the 480 BOOK REVIEWS absolutely free creator in whom Christians believe" (226). In so liberating God from any trace of necessity or dependence, William, it would seem, likewise liberated Latin theology from a defining doctrine of its greatest authority, St. Augustine. The theologizing habit evident in William's logic in some sense compels the subsequent order of Maurer's book. Before turning to William's thinking concerning the physical universe (natural philosophy [375-450]) and the composition and acts (cognitive and volitional) of the human person (451-539), Maurer treats the relations between philosophy and theology, the existence, attributes, knowledge, will, and power of God, his creative causality, human knowledge of God, and the angels (the last is another special contribution of Maurer's book). Throughout, he convincingly explains William's solutions in terms of their governing principles. Maurer remarks that it "might seem out of place to treat the existence and attributes of God" before treating his physical and anthropological doctrines, but it "can be justified from an heuristic point of view," for at "crucial moments in his physics, noetic, and ethics, he presupposes the [undemonstrable] existence of God and especially the attribute of omnipotence" (159). In other words, the nature of William's thought requires, in a synthetic analysis, that it be treated in a theological order-in effect, in the order of Peter Lombard's Sentences and of many theological Summas (excluding the "strictly supernatural truth" of the Trinity). In terms both of its order and of the arguments analyzed in each section, Maurer's book could be titled, alternatively, "The Christian Philosophy of William of Ockham." In light of the evidence of his study, Maurer judges "that the central theme of Ockham's philosophy is the singular or individual thing (res singularis),"the notion of which "undergirds his innovations in logic ... is the centerpiece of his noetic ... dominates his notion of science ... is found in his new concepts in physics ... [and] influences even his social and political thought" (540, 543). And William's ontology is inconceivable except in relation to his faith in the absolute freedom and omnipotence of God in the creation, preservation, and governance of the world, and the radical contingency of all creatures. In protecting God's absolute freedom and omnipotence, William, unlike the theologians whose teachings he disputed, made no compromises with pagan or Muslim philosophers. "Above all," Maurer concludes, "he wanted to safeguard the first article of the Creed: 'I believe in one God, the Father almighty'" (547). Rationalist and positivist scholars have judged that Latin "philosophy" in the Middle Ages was wholly subsumed in Christian theology, and therefore has little relevance to modern philosophy. In response, other scholars have discovered an independent medieval philosophy in the metaphysical speculations of various thinkers, or in the semantic, logical, and exegetical writings of masters in the Arts faculty, or in the autonomous Aristotelian "ethical ideal" (largely influenced by Arabic philosophers) of a small band of "noble minds," or in the doctrine of transcendentals at the peak of metaphysics, BOOK REVIEWS 481 etc. By a "cunning of reason," Gilson's notion of "Christian philosophy" (or "decapitated theology," as Fernand van Steenberghen once called it) obliquely confirms the judgment of the rationalists. Whatever one's judgment about the status of medieval philosophy in general, Armand Maurer's book reveals that William of Ockham's "philosophy," in its first principles and the doctrines that flow from them, is wholly dependent on, and permeated by, Christian faith and "the truth of theologians." As such, William's thought would seem to be an unlikely candidate for success in modern philosophy departments. In light of Armand Maurer's magisterial study, in any event, the burden of proof now rests on those who would say otherwise. KENT EMERY, JR. University of Notre Dame Notre Dame, Indiana Negotiating Identity: Catholic Higher Education since 1960. By ALICE GALLIN, 0.S.U. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 2000. Pp. 269. $32.00 (cloth). ISBN 0-268-01489-2. Alice Gallin is eminently qualified to write on the topic of Catholic higher education in the United States. In the 1980s she served as the executive director for the Association of Catholic Colleges and Universities. More recently, she has been involved with the implementation committee for Ex corde Ecclesiae. Her professional contacts in the world of Catholic higher education are impressive, leaving no doubt that her account of what has happened to Catholic universities in the past forty years is as much the view of an "insider" who has lived this history as it is a dispassionate study by a detached observer. Her mastery of the historical data is thorough and is reason enough to attend to this text, but it is the note of personal involvement in the subject matter that gives this study its punch. The book's title is a clear indication of its message, namely, that Catholic higher education has advanced in the past four decades through a series of "negotiated" adjustments to four main constituencies: (1) civic and governmental officials; (2) the American higher-education community; (3) the Roman Catholic Church; and (4) the internal constituency of faculty, students, administration, and trustees. Gallin correctly identifies, in my view, the sociological and ideological forces that were the primary causes of the changes that swept over Catholic higher education during this period. The cultural revolution of the sixties, the changing demographics of the student population, 482 BOOK REVIEWS the increased emphasis on pluralism and diversity, the heady atmosphere and expectation for change created by Vatican II, the threat of civil action to cut off federal aid to "pervasively sectarian" colleges and universities, and the desire for institutional autonomy from ecclesiastical authority and greater academic freedom in order to join the mainstream of the American educational establishment all contributed to the tectonic movement of Catholic higher education from its relative peace and isolation in the Catholic ghetto out into the rough and tumble mainstream of the secular academic world. Without a doubt, Gallin is correct in her assessment that these various forces all constituted "constituencies" with whom the Catholic university had to contend. Gallin, however, is not content simply to catalogue the process. The question she poses throughout the text is what is the extent to which a Catholic university can accommodate itself to these constantly changing constituencies without losing the flavor and substance of its Catholicity. The neuralgic point, therefore, is the Catholic identity issue and Gallin's text (like James Burtchaell's The Dying of the Light) must be read through the lens of the contemporary debate over Ex corde and its implementation. The issue is not whether we should have a Catholic identity, but rather what is meant by Catholic identity, who defines it, and more importantly who polices its implementation, given the complex constituencies so aptly outlined by Gallin. Gallin seems generally sympathetic to the claim that Catholic higher education has indeed lost some of its identity as Catholic. She views this loss as "growing pains" along the path to the full implementation of Vatican II's radical call to change. Her sympathies lie with Theodore Hesburgh, Call to Action, and Land O'Lakes. By contrast, she portrays the Roman magisterium as the chief obstacle to progress, unable to grasp the unique subtleties of the "American context." The methodology she follows in her analysis of the challenges posed to Catholic universities by the various constituencies follows a clear and consistent pattern: (1) begin with a detailed analysis of the problem, (2) offer voluminous documentation of the various position papers and mission statements sent to Rome by the university presidents, (3) catalogue the nature and gravity of the Roman rejection of these efforts, and (4) comment on the disappointment felt by "many" over Rome's apparent ignorance of the American context. This "American context" is framed primarily by the peculiar American constitutional arrangement regarding matters of church and state, as well as the understanding of tenure and academic freedom in the secular American academy. Gallin understands the nature of the challenge posed by these realities, but seems to accept the secularist biases that animate them. She is unable to see the extent to which the simple importation of these models into a Catholic context, without significant modification or critique, may be inimical to the Catholic identity of the university. For example, she defines academic freedom along the typical secularist lines as a pursuit of one's discipline unhindered by anything except the pursuit of the truth. It is BOOK REVIEWS 483 pertinent to ask whether "truth" here means a pursuit of value-neutral facts to be passed on to our students as bits of disconnected data, or is rather contextualized in its relation to a notion of the good. The fact that Gallin has high praise for curricula that are integrated around an awareness of social justice is an indication that she does accept the contextualized nature of the pursuit of truth. It follows that in a Catholic university the pursuit of truth must always take place within the context of the living faith of the Church. But if this is the case, it is not clear why there should not be some kind of juridical relationship with that Church as part of the very mission of the university. Should not the Catholic university, precisely through a greater immersion in its own intellectual tradition, proceed to a prophetic critique of the many pathologies inherent in our culture's notions of the true and the good? It is not evident why the pursuit of secular status, enshrined in the secular notion of academic freedom, is desirable. This may have been somewhat understandable forty years ago, but times have changed and it is no longer so apparent that the secular model for education is the Camelot it once appeared to be to an earlier generation (a generation beset with feelings of Catholic inferiority). The irony here is that it is precisely through a closer relationship with the Church that the university will be freed from its slavery to secular totalisms. Gallin acknowledges that elsewhere in the world it is desirable for a university to have a juridical relationship with Rome in order to protect itself against despotic forms of government. In America, by contrast, we have no such fears and therefore, apparently, no such needs. Gallin is strangely irenic toward the American cultural challenges that she so ably outlines in her book. Even though she acknowledges that these cultural realities pose a real threat to the Catholic identity of the university she in no way opposes "negotiating" an accommodation to them. Gallin argues that there is another reason for being careful about juridical relationships with the Church-the issue of the loss of federal aid to Catholic universities if they are deemed to be "pervasively sectarian." This is in fact a widespread misconception. Time and again the courts have ruled in favor of faith-based institutions and their right to the same federal aid as any other institution of higher learning. The court's message has been consistent now for almost 45 years: through a variety of legal challenges the fundamental right of faith-based institutions to receive governmental funding has been upheld. Even institutions as pervasively religious as BYU have passed the muster. Gallin's use of this issue to explain the wholesale retreat of Catholic universities in the sixties and seventies from their ecclesiastical moorings is one of the weakest treatments in the whole book. It is at this juncture that one notices a theological flaw in Gallin's approach relating to the relationship between the pastoral and the juridical aspects of the Church. In her resistance to any sort of ·ecclesiastical jurisdiction over the university and any contextualizing of academic freedom within that jurisdiction, Gallin routinely pits the "juridical" against the "pastoral," the atmosphere 484 BOOK REVIEWS of "mutual trust and dialogue" established by university presidents against the "juridicism" of Rome. One searches in vain for any acknowledgement that there are genuine theological and pastoral principles that animate canon law. It is the very juridicism of the Church that preserves many of our "spiritual rights" as members of the mystical body of Christ-it protects us from abuses both clerical and lay and provides for the common good of the people of God by regulating the proper administration of the sacraments and so forth. Likewise, canon law can play a role in the maintenance of "Catholic identity" on an American university campus for the sake of the faithful-do Catholic parents not have a right to expect a certain minimum Catholicity when they send their children to Catholic colleges and universities? Gallin notes on several occasions that the current Roman magisterium seems intent on curbing or even rolling back some of the "openness" of the council on these matters. She fears that Ex corde is the Pope's attempt to bring all Catholic institutions of higher learning, not just those with ecclesiastical mandates, under the juridical control of Rome. It is a shame that she chooses to frame the debate in this manner. Gallin's obvious grasp of the history of Catholic higher education since 1960 gives her voice on these matters a gravitas that is deserved. Unfortunately, the book is constrained by its effort to justify the accommodation of American Catholic universities to the dominant culture. It is a shame to see a text with so much promise fail due to the weaknesses of its underlying assumptions. Gallin gets the history right, but seems not fully to grasp its lessons. LARRY S. CHAPP DeSales University Center Valley, Pennsylvania Words of the Living God: Place and Function of Holy Scripture in the Theology of St. Thomas Aquinas. By WILHELMUS G. B. M. VALKENBURG. Leuven: Peeters, 2000. Pp. 253. 1200 BEF (paper). ISBN 90-429-0818-1. In an era when the Summa Theologiaelargely served as the sole Dominican textbook, a well-intentioned novice master habitually encouraged his charges to read the Bible because it is "chock full of Scripture." Wilhelmus Valkenberg helps us to see that St. Thomas, biblical theologian, might be read for much the same reason. This study states its aim at the outset: to investigate St. Thomas's use of Scripture in his systematic-theological works, and more precisely, to demonstrate the biblical character of the Summa Theologiae in light of his exegetical works. Valkenberg's thesis, ecumenically conscious, is defined BOOK REVIEWS 485 against the Reformation portrait of a gospel-compromising Thomas, the progressive assessment of a thinker ignorant of the passionate God of Scripture, and the conservative reading of a philosopher fitting theology into metaphysics. The thesis, simple in its overall design and complex in the details, uncovers the biblical character of Thomas's systematic theology in intricate analyses. The quantitative inquiries ("place") present comparative analyses of the number and kinds of scriptural quotations in different theological works and tracts. The qualitative inquiries ("function") probe the distinct uses of Scripture in such varied tasks as determining the quaestio, elucidating the argument, and confirming the conclusion, and in such various modes as the clearly cited, the generally presupposed, and the cross referenced. Chapter 1 contains the thesis in miniature by presenting the theory, which is tested in the following chapters against what Thomas actually does. It introduces the three major issues associated with place and function: defining the relationship between Scripture and theology (sacra doctrina), developing a methodology for distinguishing kinds of references and tabulating them, and providing a "heuristic framework" for undertaking the virtually unprecedented task of studying Thomas's actual use of Scripture in his systematic theology. First, sacra doctrina is identified alternatively with Scripture and theology because theology is intimately grounded in divine revelation-this in contrast to contemporary theology which approaches Scripture more critically and less confidently. Even in Thomas, however, the precise relationship between Scripture and theology requires clarification. A brief presentation lays out the Summa's architectonic vision of rooting all of theology in its scriptural source. This leads to Valkenburg's central insight that Scripture is at work in the text long before it is cited because theology based on faith ultimately rests on God's revealing word. Scripture's other two major functions are quite secondary: as an identifiable source in scholarly argument and as a confirmation for weighing theological conclusions against divine revelation. Second, Valkenburg proposes a methodology for a quantitative analysis of Thomas's use of Scripture by focusing primarily on two texts concerning Christ's resurrection, taken from the very early Sentences commentary and the very late Summa. Valkenburg chooses the resurrection as the thematic instrument because of its theological centrality, its relative neglect, and its copious references to explicit and implicit scriptural citations. The first assignment is simply one of counting explicit and implicit quotations in the In Sent. and the Summa as well as in their respective tracts on Christ, which reveal a higher number of citations. References are then assigned to four categories: Scripture, the Fathers, the philosophers, and "interlocutors" (glosses and contemporary theologians). Here and throughout the text Valkenburg offers a wealth of statistics on Thomas's use of Scripture, handily compressed in a table (209-10). The next task is to tally the relative number of scriptural quotations in the main parts of the Christology tracts on Christ in the In Sent. and the Summa. Scriptural quotations are found to be more heavily 486 BOOK REVIEWS represented in the so-called "soteriological" parts of the Christology tracts (which chapter 2 will confirm). The conclusions drawn are that the mature Thomas became increasingly aware of revelation and its basis in Scripture, and that a heightened use of Scripture accompanied his later accent on the soteriological-and thus theological-value of the events of Christ's life. Finally, distinguishing the various types of references in terms of explicit and implicit, direct and indirect, and literal and free not only offers new tools for analyzing the deployment of quotations, but also leads to important hermeneutical observations. For example, medieval theology's superior familiarity with Scripture gave it greater liberty with implicit and free quotations. Valkenburg gives attention to Thomas's rational theological language which avoids the exhortatory, persuasive, and rhetorical styles of Scripture without removing its dependence on it. Scripture's importance is conveyed by the allusive and implicit so that its influence might be maximally present when its assimilation into theological language makes it almost invisible. Thus we are led to the third point-the qualitative dimension-where Scripture is not simply one element in theology, but is the text's determinative ground. Here Valkenburg parts ways with the Neoscholastic approach which conscripted Scripture primarily for underwriting the doctrinal conclusions of speculative theology. He develops a heuristic framework that analyzes quotations at the "micro-level" of argumentation (the article), the "meso-level" of literary genre (the quaestio), and the "macro-level" of purpose (the text). The macro inquiry probes the primary and secondary uses of Scripture: revealing God's actions or intentions, often in terms of the appropriateness (convenientia) of divine interventions, and providing examples and illustrations, respectively. Chapter 2 applies this heuristic framework to III Sent., d. 21, q. 2 and STh III, qq. 53-56 by examining the place and function of Scripture in the questions on the resurrection. Painstakingly working through the earlier work's questions, Valkenburg finds that Scripture is quoted more than all other sources, and more often here than in the Sent. taken as a whole. Furthermore, it serves as the main auctoritas for the quaestiones by revealing the divine origin of the contents of faith, which becomes even clearer in the Summa. Thomas's soteriology is found to be rooted in his incarnational Christology, which in turn arises out of his theology of God, and an implicit justification for Scholastic argumentation is given in the risen Christ's use of arguments for making the apostles his suitable witnesses. In the Summa, where Thomas is free to arrange the subject matter as he pleases, the resurrection is placed in the new context of Christ's exaltation rather than his death. Again, hermeneutical gems are uncovered: Scripture provides solutions to the problems it creates; Thomas's preferred expression, Christus resurgens, should be literally translated and theologically pondered; and the unity of the rational interpretation and the interpretation secundum mysterium must be respected. Finally, the Summa offers BOOK REVIEWS 487 an increased role for Scripture, both in the number and kinds of quotations and as authoritative source, due to frequent borrowings from the style and contents of the expositio of the biblical commentaries and Catena Aurea. Chapter 3 confirms Valkenberg's thesis within the larger terrain ofThomas's theology as a whole through a comparative analysis with texts where the scriptural influence and role are different. We learn that the primary use of Scripture as communicating the truth of revelation to theology remains constant, while its secondary functions vary according to subject matter, literary genre, and sources. The subject matter's influence is tested by comparing the resurrection texts with other themes, the literary genre's influence is probed by examining resurrection texts in other theological works, and the influence of sources is appraised by studying contemporary works. Thomas's various "appearances" in different genres is examined (e.g., the more personal face revealed in the commentaries), and his working division of the various scriptural senses is simplified from the traditional four to the literal and mystical (spiritual). Valkenberg follows Corbin in noting that the conventional view of Thomas as representing the historical shift from the more spiritual and monastic expositio to the more Scholastic and logical quaestio requires modification in light of his generous inclusion of materials from the scriptural commentaries in the Summa. Paradoxically, the Aristotelian conception of science helped Thomas to rediscover the dependence of theology on God's revelation given through Scripture. Not surprisingly, the more traditional approach of In Sent. discloses the influence of contemporary sources, whereas the Summa manifests a greater originality and biblical influence. Chapter 4 concludes the study by examining the relevance of Thomas's use of Scripture for contemporary theology. His ability to couple a deep respect for Scripture as normative source and framework for theology with a freedom to interpret it creatively is imitable, as is his allowance for a plurality of interpretations within the bounds of orthodoxy. A brief comparison of Thomas's theological horizon and our own can help us recover Scripture as primary horizon to draw us to the mystery of God revealed in human words. Valkenberg's study offers a clearly outlined text which assures that the reader is never lost. Although it manifests patient research and meticulous attention to textual details, the principal theological principles and conclusions are never lost to view. In a word, the micro and macro dimensions of texts and their referents are both distinguished and integrated, showing how complex and yet simple is Thomas's use of sources, including Scripture. Although the text is written in a clean style, there are difficulties in the flow and nuance that compromise Valkenberg's obviously precise way of thinking. The book is almost too concise, suggesting that this former dissertation was overedited. Occasionally extremely important material is consigned to the footnotes. A number of infelicities appear, ranging from misspellings and grammatical errors to confusing word choices. Most of these are irritants; a few might lead the reader astray. Despite his impressive command of English, 488 BOOK REVIEWS Valkenberg would have been well served by a competent native Englishspeaking editor. More substantively, the study stumbles at the outset by a slightly dated presentation of sacra doctrina. The gradual emancipation of the medieval thinkers from the auctoritatesis inadequately treated. Important contributions by T. C. O'Brien andA Patfoort are missing in the argument and bibliography. The major difficulty, however, is that scant attention is given to the ecclesial dimension of Thomas's use of sources. Combining articles of the faith as defined by the Church with patristic sources, saints, and liturgical texts under the rubric of the "Fathers" skews a correct understanding of Thomas's use of Scripture. To argue that speculative theology ultimately must "be related to the language of Scripture as the authoritative source of all theological language" (147) without reference to ecclesial mediation is to invite a fundamentalist reading of Thomas and even to misinterpret his Christology. It is simply incorrect to interpret STh Ill, qq. 1-26 as "a speculative or transcendental reflection" which offers "presuppositions" for the "historical or categorial reflection" of questions 27-59, or as simply formulating "the conditions of possibility for any theology on Christ," or as intended to "sharpen one's intelligence and linguistic skill" (145)-and then to call the first set of questions "christological" and the second set "soteriological" (31). One is hard pressed to find a more soteriological text than STh Ill, q. 1, a. 2. As Thomas emphasizes in the prologue to the Christology tract, the distinction between these sets of questions is that between the mystery of the Incarnation considered in itself and the personal life of Christ-what he did and suffered. That Scripture is less abundantly cited in the questions on the hypostatic union implies not only that Thomas is relying most heavily on ecdesial tradition, which the sed contras verify, but that this reading provides the framework for his overall theological approach. What Valkenberg calls transcendental would be better understood as Thomas's commentary on the dogmatic tradition as opposed to his commentary on the scriptural tradition. "Scripture" for these two parts of Christology is shorthand for "Scripture as interpreted by the Church" and "Scripture as read in the Church." While one can laud a rejection of a proof-text approach, it is possible to go too far in the other direction and give priority to the putatively "direct" and "historical." Valkenberg sees that theology today is contextualized by a larger secularism in which Christendom is not so much lived and breathed as imagined and desired. Experience reinterpreted as religious experience provides the basic theological context. Christianity, usually in the form of a specific tradition with Scripture, is introduced to clarify and customize, confirm and critique. What we can learn from Thomas through Valkenberg is that it is our privilege to insert ourselves in God's vision rather than .the other way around. Reading the Summa for what it is-an advanced systematic commentary on Scripture-can help with this. Inserting ourselves within this vision requires that it be spelled out and sharpened-the work of systematic theology-in order that the parts, BOOK REVIEWS 489 including the fragments of Scripture and of our own lives, find their place. In this way, systematic theology requites biblical theology in some small way for blessings received. LAWRENCE}.DONOHOO,0.P. Dominican House of Studies Washington, D.C. The Common Things: Essays on Thomism and Education. Edited by DANIEL MCINERNY, intro. by BENEDICT M. AsHLEY, 0.P. Mishawaka, Ind.: American Maritain Association, 1999. Pp. x + 281. $15.00 (paper). ISBN 0-9669226-0-3. This book is the fruit of a colloquium on education and Thomism of Catholic intellectuals who have taken Jacques Maritain's Education at the Crossroads as their point of departure. In 1943, Maritain saw Western educational philosophy at a crossroads. Half a century later Daniel Mcinerny finds the West at a spiritual dead end and urges a reconsideration of the road not taken. Educational institutions have turned from common things and especially from truth and "toward the privacies of custom, technique, and contingent desire" (ix). Such is the premise that authorizes the collection of the 23 essays that make up this book. Its contributors include Benedict M. Ashley, John M. Palms, Herbert I. London, Alice Ramos, Francis Slade, Donald DeMarco, Curtis L. Hancock, Gregory Kerr, Robert J. McLaughlin, Robert E. Lauder, James V. Schall, Gregory M. Reichberg, Joseph Koterski, Romanus Cessario, Peter A. Redpath, Daniel Mcinerny, Ernest S. Pierucci, Michael W. Strasser, Walter Raubicheck, Henk E. S. Woldring, Jerome Meric Pessagno, Mario Ramos-Reyes, and Charles R. Dechert. In the introductory essay Ashley focuses on the "sapiential unification" that metaphysics provides for the many arts and sciences. In opposition to the adherents of transcendentalist or existentialist Thomism, Ashley's metaphysician does "not claim to have any data other than that supplied by the special sciences nor to be independent of these sciences in its own conclusions" (8). He insists that disciplined understanding of human nature in anthropology is a requirement for ethics, just as disciplined understanding of natural science is necessary if metaphysics is to rise above a commonsense understanding. In the course of a running critique of Maritain's theory of education, Ashley makes a trenchant case for a core education in the natural sciences. Needless to say, the institutions of Western education have strayed far from the path 490 BOOK REVIEWS marked out by Ashely's Thomism and the order of arts and sciences that it requires. Mcinerny ("A Humble and Trembling Movement: Creative Intuition and Maritain's Philosophy of Education") uses Maritain's Creative Intuition in Art and Poetry to fill in gaps in his Education at the Crossroads. He directs our attention to "what Maritain calls the dynamics of education, i.e., to 'the inner vitality of the student's mind and the activity of the teacher"' (188). Most interesting is his development of Maritain's rich concept of the preconscious life of the intellectual soul and its affective connaturality in learning. Mcinerny knows his texts well, but he also speaks convincingly out of his personal pedagogical art. In the end, he teases the reader with suggestive remarks about the liberation of the student as the essential aim of education. In one of the more elegant essays ("Studiositas, the Virtue of Attention"), Reichberg examines what Aquinas has to say about studiositas, a moral quality that introduces both moderation and courage into the life of the mind. His particular observations on the personal moral conditions for intellectual inquiry are both interesting for the philosopher and practical for the student. His concluding comparison with Simone Weil enriches the essay's overall effect. Cessario ("John Poinsot: On the Gift of Counsel") offers a careful, almost literal exposition of John Poinsot's treatment of counsel, the supernatural gift that intervenes "in practical intelligence [as an aid to] the moral conscience in making concrete choices" (169). Cessario hopes to demonstrate the relevance of Poinsot's Treatise on the Gifts to contemporary moral theory. He argues that this early modern treatise effectively bridges "classical explanations of the moral life that view the human person as a free agent within a universe of divinely established purposes and ends and modern accounts of human agency that emphasize personal purposes and self-determination as the starting-point of moral evaluation" (177). Among the virtues of Poinsot's theory, therefore, is its ability to accommodate the objective reality of both human subjectivity and normative, divine truths. In parts of their essays Schall ("On the Education of Young Men and Women") and Koterski ("Education: Restoring the Goal of Development to the Ideal of Learning") recognize that the interests of life and learning must stretch beyond the formal structures of schools and universities. Out of concern for integral personal development, both thinkers want to introduce into the life of students structured programs for study, prayer, and conversation in a quasifamily environment. Inspired by Maritain's Thomist Circles, Schall proposes the formation of "spiritual centers wherein spiritual life and instruction could be developed" (139). Koterski experiments with ideas on how to recover in the contemporary university setting the ideal of medieval cathedral schools that "integrat[ed] ... learning with an entire way of living, and a religious one at that, whose structured habits of prayer and communal life were designed to live out the lessons of the classroom" (158). It was, however, one of Maritain's BOOK REVIEWS 491 paradoxical insights that the most essential end of education is not the proper work of the schools. As he put it at the end of the first chapter of Education at the Crossroads, "Direct action on the will and the shaping of character . . . depends on educational spheres other than school and college education." Although Schall and Koterski bring characteristic learning and sage experience as spiritual directors to their reflections on this problem, students and parents should keep in mind Maritain's wariness of university personnel directly extending their professional reach into the hearts and wills of their students. Pierucci ("Great Books Business Education") presents a sensible, principled discussion of liberal learning at the basis of the education of the business manager. It is a system of education concordant with human nature and the highest ideals of a university. Along the way, he helpfully contrasts Mortimer Adler and Jacques Maritain, favoring the latter's appreciation for transitive action and business as worthy concerns of higher education in the liberal arts. Central to his understanding of Maritain's importance is the idea of "natural intelligence." In a short compass Pierucci makes a persuasive case for the integration of practical and liberal education. Francis Slade opens his brilliant essay, "Was ist Aufkliirung? Notes on Maritain, Rorty, and Bloom, with Thanks but No Apologies to Immanuel Kant," by observing Maritain's public loneliness, which he credits to his fidelity to untimely conceptions of truth and reason, long since disestablished by the dominant authorities of modern philosophy. This opening meditation quickly develops into an illuminating contrast between premodern and modern philosophy. "Reason understood as rule is what makes modern philosophy modern" (58). The ensuing analysis of the conception of reason at the foundation of modern political philosophy and its invention of the State is an invaluable contribution to any philosophy of education that includes among its aims the availability of truth by revelation and the natural good of contemplative thought. In his closing assessment of the prospects for philosophy in postmodernity Slade makes a harsh critique of Allan Bloom in The Closing of the American Mind. He characterizes Bloom's thought as an example of "what happens to philosophy when it loses what Maritain called 'the natural faith of reason in truth,' or what is the same thing, when its premise is 'our inability to acquire any genuine knowledge of what is intrinsically good or right,' and in Rorty's words, 'substitutes Freedom for Truth as the goal of thinking"' (68). Notwithstanding the many excellent individual contributions, the book's single most important contribution may be the simple fact that it raises the question of the philosophy of education among Catholic thinkers. What Catholic philosopher has spoken in an authoritative and influential way about the larger concerns of education since Maritain's slender volume of lectures, which he delivered in the midst of World War II? In his preface, Mcinerny laments the road not taken. More interesting to me is the silence of Catholic minds reflecting systematically on the meaning of education. The decisive 492 BOOK REVIEWS questions about education seem to have been deeded over to the practical interests of social-policy makers, while the theoretical research has been left to the social scientists. Yet the important work of education is as universal as the languages we speak and the cultures that inform our actions and desires. Education is a topic all too ripe for philosophical reflection. Mclnerny's book is especially welcome for its move in this direction. WILLIAM A. FRANK University of Dallas Irving, Texas Contingency and Fortune in Aquinas's Ethics. By JOHN BOWLIN. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999. Pp. 234. $59.95 (cloth). ISBN 0-52162019-8. This book is set to join several other recent books in English-Jean Porter's The Recovery Of Virtue: The Relevance of Aquinas for Christian Ethics, Daniel Mark Nelson's The Priority of Prudence: Virtue and Natural Law in Thomas Aquinas and the Implications for Modern Ethics, Romanus Cessario's The Moral Virtues and Theological Ethics, Daniel Westberg's Right Practical Reason: Aristotle, Action, and Prudence in Aquinas, Pamela Hall's Narrative and the Natural Law: An Interpretation of Thomistic Ethics-that have become mainstays in reading and construing the ethical thought of St. Thomas in our contemporary setting. That is, the book is in large measure an effort in Thomistic interpretation, but one that is as much influenced by our contemporary collaborative effort to make Thomas's ethics applicable to modern circumstances as it is influenced by received canons of interpretation of medieval texts. In this case it is fair to say that the work's interpretive trajectory has been set primarily by contemporary concerns in the philosophical community and secondarily by the direction Thomas himself placed upon his ethical teaching. Bowlin is aware of this issue, and admits early on that the Thomas he considers sometimes emerges "less as a historical figure and more as a contemporary conversation partner" (18). There is nothing in principle wrong with that, of course; Bowlin is to be thanked for being honest with his reader when he notes that his desire to see whether Thomas has anything to say to us today (19) of necessity requires him to be "harmlessly anachronistic" in reading Thomas's moral theology in a philosophical way, consumed as it is in contemporary ethics by the problems left behind after Hume, and only partially BOOK REVIEWS 493 corrected by Anscombe. The question that remains after the book is whether, despite the interesting and useful philosophical fruit obtained from a harmlessly anachronistic reading, the result is what Thomas would have recognized as his own. What led Bowlin to this book was the fact that most contemporary writers who have written about Thomas's ethics have almost universally centered their considerations upon the role of natural law in his teaching, thus giving rise to disputes about the nature, content, and certitude of the first principles of natural law and the precepts that are generated from them. As Bowlin sees it, both friend and foe ofThomas's teaching have started in the wrong place, and have concentrated "on a side show" of his ethical teaching (3). Bowlin instead notices that the overwhelming mass of moral material in the Secunda Pars of Thomas's Summa Theologiae concerns passions and virtues and vices. More than that, he sees that the concrete, various goods with which the passions and virtues are concerned are, in the quasi-Heraclitean world in which we dwell, difficult to know with certitude in the particular, and difficult to produce even when they are known with certitude. In other words, since Thomas's ethics is about our lived life, as distinct from the life we would live, if possible, we would do well to note how much the notion of difficulty enters into any realistic consideration of the moral life and into the ethics that is meant to describe and ultimately to inform that life. It is true that ethics is about obtaining "the good," but in reality ethics is about obtaining "the difficult good." Thus chapter 1 of the book is devoted to the intimate link between virtue and difficulty, such that, not surprisingly, the cardinal virtue that emerges for special consideration is the virtue of courage, which precisely concerns the "good as difficult to attain"; being seated in the irascible appetite, courage is the development of our ability to "stay and fight" even when every other inclination is bidding us to escape from hardship or pain. Yet life is full of hardship and pain precisely because of the contingency of our existence, so in chapter 2 Bowlin explains that the human good is contingent, dependent upon the virtue of prudence, which characteristically approaches the concrete, singular action with a host of allied "potential parts," chief among which is caution. The goodness in our life is so contingent because even though the human will has a necessary and direct inclination toward "the good" what that good is in this or that circumstance, or under the influence of this or that passion (emotion), is not absolutely clear. Even if a certain good should emerge as possible, other goods could emerge as worthy competitors-as happens in the case of moral incontinence. Thus Bowlin in this chapter builds the case that, given the freedom of the human will (depending here upon the fact that the human intellect can spot the intelligible item "goodness" in almost anything, be it a real or a perceived good), and given the host of items that can act upon our human emotions-or not, or at least not today but maybe 494 BOOK REVIEWS tomorrow-and given the role that sheer chance (fortune in the wide sense) can play in this, the virtue of prudence must be developed in order for us not to fall into moral error all the time. But because prudence pertains to the intellect in its practical mode, Bowlin in chapter 3 considers the "matter," as it were, that prudence employs in arriving at judgments. Hence he must concern himself with Thomas's account of natural law. To speak of Thomas's doctrine of natural law these days requires that one contend with the various approaches proposed by writers such as Alasdair Macintyre, Ralph Mcinerny, Jean Porter (who, Bowlin tells us, think that Thomas's account of natural law can result in a set of moral prescriptions that guide concretely) and the largely collaborative approach of Germain Grisez, John Finnis, and Joseph Boyle (who contend that Thomas's doctrine can yield moral prescriptions, but only after some crucial intermediate steps are taken, which they provide). Bowlin disagrees with what he takes to be a common thread among all these writers: that Thomas intends his account of the first precepts of natural law to produce a set of rules. Bowlin argues at length that Thomas intends no such thing, but rather regards the first principles as descriptions of our basic inclinations toward various goods, goods indicated to us by God through his eternal law, which are highly variable and contingent, requiring therefore not a deduction from preset rules of conduct, but a cautious investigation of prudence, with its attendant investigation and deliberation: "the first precepts are the conclusions of God's practical deliberations about the ends that give our agency its natural shape and human character" (127). Because of the intimate link between natural law (whose contours are viewed by Bowlin as less sharpened than other interpreters consider them) and the virtues, which are multiplied according to their more clearly specified objects, Bowlin thinks that moral decision-making in concrete circumstances is more indebted to the influence of virtue, and less to the dictates of these first principles of practical reason which, he thinks, "by themselves, leave us very nearly morally destitute" (133). In the last two chapters of the book Bowlin turns to virtue's role in human happiness. Is virtue said to be essential to human happiness because it produces it, or because virtue is human happiness? In other words, are the virtues merely instruments, or do they collectively comprise happiness? In chapter 4 Bowlin balks at the disjunction and answers that the full answer includes both. The virtues aid in effecting happiness, especially when we must struggle to attain the good, and hence have an instrumental, effective character about them. Yet they are also developed tendencies of the human nature given to us by God, who in his eternal law has staked out the boundaries of what human nature, and hence completeness, is, and in this respect the virtues constitute, on an ontological level, human completion. Although virtue is a developed and lasting feature of the human moral agent, it also is in some way subject to fortune. In the last chapter Bowlin BOOK REVIEWS 495 considers how virtue is subject-and therefore happiness is subject-to fortune, a discussion that leads to an interplay of the authorities with whom Thomas was most familiar: the Stoics (who wanted to remove the virtuous man from the vagaries of fortune) and Aristotle (who considered some goods subject to fortune and therefore, when those goods were prerequisite to happiness, even happiness itself, at least in part, was subject to fortune). As Bowlin reads Thomas, the goods that are subject to fortune are instrumentally useful, but the instrumentality they exercise can be provided for by other means. Hence happiness is not, per se, prevented by fortune. The book comes to its close with a short epilogue whose theme emerges naturally from what has gone before. Given the predominance of contingency in the world in which we live, which is such that it can hamper, but not prevent altogether or destroy, human happiness, aren't we inclined to some sort of disappointment about our lot-a "discontent," to use Bowlin's term of choice? We should not be, Bowlin says, because virtue is something we should have confidence in, for we can look to the example of Adam before the fall as something of which human nature is in principle capable. Aquinas, after all, places his hope in the Christian God, under whose governance the fulfillment of all is intended. Bowlin's book has been widely reviewed and well received, and rightly so. The book is at once a discovery of sorts and an assessment of that discovery's implications for Thomas's moral teaching, generally. But the manner in which he has chosen to read Thomas does raise the question whether Thomas would be satisfied with the portrait that Bowlin paints. ls the totality of Thomas's ethics to be found in the Secunda Pars? Is that portion of the work "Thomas's ethics"? One only need read the introduction to the Tertia Pars to see how centrally Christ was to function in the manifestation of the ethical teaching sketched out in the Secunda Pars. There is a consideration of the virtue of penance in Summa Theologiae III, q. 85, which suggests that, at least at a material level, the consideration of morals does not completely stop at the end of the SecundaSecundae.Can an account of "Thomas's ethics" be even partially complete without a consideration of sanctifying grace (STh 1-11, qq. 109££.), merit before God, or the doctrine eternal life, when we "shall become like God, for we shall see him as he is"? These are the complaints that a historically trained theologian raises against much philosophically inspired readings of Thomas's works. It is a virtue of Bowlin's book that he knows in advance what some concerns will be. The book will be much consulted, and unfortunately there is no index of Thomistic sources cited, which would have been a great help. The index itself, of names and subjects, is a scant three pages. The bibliography at the end refers entirely, save a single reference or two, to English-language sources. These defects do not minimize Bowlin's contribution. Although individual readers may shy away from constituting difficulty as a centerpiece of Thomas's ethics, 496 BOOK REVIEWS and contingency almost as the dominant formal element of the universe in which we live, there is no getting around the fact that difficulty, particularly as exemplified in the virtue of courage, will become a mainstay of our consideration of the ethical project associated with Thomas. MARKJOHNSON Marquette University Milwaukee, Wisconsin "Creatio ex nihilo" and the Theology of St. Augustine: The Anti-Manichaean Polemic and Beyond. By N. JOSEPH TORCHIA, 0.P. New York: Peter Lang, 1999. Pp. 312. $49.95 (cloth). ISBN 0-8204-3775-1. Torchia explores creatio ex nihilo first as a doctrine in its own terms, as well as its background and development in Augustine's thought, and second as a doctrine that functioned in a pivotal way in the larger whole of Augustine's theology. He construes Augustine's theology as, in a way, a radical theology of creation. In this he largely succeeds, tacitly undoing certain theological cliches about Augustine along the way. The helpful introduction displays scriptural, patristic, and philosophical backgrounds, suggesting what access Augustine had to them and what use he may have made of them. Succeeding chapters trace the development of the doctrine of creation in the context of the development of Augustine's antiManichaean polemic. Chapter 1 depicts the "anti-cosmic mentality of the Manichaeans" for whom the visible universe "was but a painful (albeit necessary) stage in the process whereby Light would ... be liberated from its imprisonment in matter" (78-79). Chapter 2 treats Augustine's exegesis of Genesis, focusing on the crucial issue of "God's action in creating and forming matter" (98). Christianizing the Platonic doctrine of creation meant distinguishing creatio ex nihilo from the Timaeus's doctrine of the formation of pre-existent matter, and from the Neoplatonic doctrine of the cosmos as a great continuum in which "'creation' amounts to the emergence of the different levels of the One's power and goodness" (111). For Augustine, creation establishes God's independence of all else that is. The "expression of the unconstrained Divine will," its motive is only "God's love of what He wills to create" (117). Augustine's exegesis becomes increasingly Trinitarian; by the De Genesi ad litteram he places his theory of creatio ex nihilo "squarely in a moral context," by interpreting formatio as a kind of conversioor imitatio analogous, on the level of created being, to the eternal unity of Father and Son. (An BOOK REVIEWS 497 important corollary might be that we cannot understand scriptural teaching on creation apart from our own growth in conversion.) Augustine's exegesis of Genesis establishes the sovereignty of God as Creator, with goodness correlative to being, and evil simply a corruption of being, non-existent in its own right, contrary to the Manichaean cosmogony and theodicy (chapters 3 and 4). Since evil can manifest itself only in relation to good things, it cannot assume an ontological priority enabling it to "shape and dominate" (153) what God creates, as the Manichaeans believed. Torchia, following Bonner, explains that the doctrine of evil as a corruption of the good is not strictly speaking Plotinian, as commonly believed, but represents a development. Plotinus links evil with matter, unformed and on its own, farthest from the One on the continuum of being, an ontological deficiency characterized by lack more than by being. There is, in effect, a substantiality to evil as a necessary terminus of an ontological continuum (174), a necessary stage in the emanation and return of being to its source (182). Augustine departs from this scheme because he "completely separated evil from matter" and so "imparted a more thoroughgoing negativity to evil as an absence (in varying degrees) of being itself" (174). In creatures in their original condition, evil exists only as the negativity of the lack of the higher perfection of unchangeability proper only to something not created from nothing, namely God. Torchia calls this negativity "metaphysical evil," carefully qualifying his usage to distinguish it from the position that evil has any substantiality (175). Chapter 5 demonstrates the position of creatio ex nihilo in Augustine's defense of monotheism, preparing the reader for an extensive treatment of the foundational role of the doctrine of creation in Augustine's theology (chapters 6 and 7). Creatio ex nihilo in Augustine entails the omnipotence of God as Creator of all else and the consequent doctrine of the complete dependence of everything on God. Creaturely status is defined, in a way, by susceptibility to return to nothingness. For rational creatures this metaphysical evil "carries a certain propensity for sin" (237) and even "an inherent tendency to sinfulness" (246). This "inherent tendency toward non-being" is only "intensified" by Original Sin (238). The doctrine of grace, and the correlative doctrines of redemption and predestination, are implied in the doctrine of creation. "[O]ntological contingency implies a moral contingency: humans cannot hope to do good without God's assistance, any more than they could have come into existence without God's creative efficacy" (243). The doctrine of creatio ex nihilo means, for Augustine, that we are ultimately completely reliant on God for our creation and for our perfection. The reader is in Torchia's debt for his excellent synthesis and analysis. Still, one may be permitted a few worries. Is it going too far to talk about creaturely dependence on God implying a "metaphysical evil" and an "inherent tendency to sinfulness?" Is Augustine's God so reluctant a Creator?-his creation's dependence upon him construed in such a way that its independence involves 498 BOOK REVIEWS "evil"? This is not a problem with the doctrine of creatioex nihilo itself. Origen and the Greek patristic tradition espouse such a doctrine, but they are more careful to have God "back off" from what he creates, so that creation is more clearly exhibited as an act of self-limitation on God's part. God's creative power is, in part, God's loving self-limitation, making room for a created freedom and sovereignty. In the end, Torchia, despite his best intentions, has a hard time demonstrating that Augustine really is any different from Plotinus ("metaphysical evil" is not so very far from Plotinus's position despite disclaimers) or even the Manichees (for whom the visible creation is not unequivocally evil, but part and parcel of the Light's return, as Torchia himself realizes). It is hard to see the love which Torchia claims as Augustine's Creator's motive for creation. The problem is that, more than with the Greek fathers, Augustine's theodicy, and therefore his doctrine of creation, is not completely explained without an exposition of the Incarnation (which Torchia explicitly states at one point, but does not elaborate (245]). Augustine replies to the theodicy of the Manichaeans partly by accepting their doctrine of the vulnerability of God, but sublating it into an historical, rather than metaphysical, venue. God's vulnerability amounts only to myth if it is not the true vulnerability of an historical person (Jesus). In Augustine, the doctrine of the self-limitation of God is tied so thoroughly to the doctrine of the Incarnation that no treatment of his theodicy, or his doctrine of creation, is complete without it. For Augustine, we do not understand the mystery of the goodness of creation until we see what God is willing to pay for it, as it were, and the mystery of the original refusal of conversiois meaningless to us apart from the mystery of the rejection of an historical person by historical persons (ourselves). There is a perversity about the rejection of Love personified which is not captured by the phrase "inherent tendency to sinfulness." Such a tendency, stated just that way, is not a mystery, and in fact tends to occlude the mystery of evil in Augustine, because it makes it seem less perverse and more in keeping with our (almost Manichaean?) nature. Thus I would caution against the use of such phrases. In the end, though, this is really asking Torchia to write another book, supplementing this, and that is unfair of any reviewer, so I will finish simply by thanking him for the excellent one he has written. JOHNC. CAVADINI Universityof Notre Dame Notre Dame, Indiana BOOK REVIEWS 499 Thomas von Aquin und die Liturgie By DAVID BERGER. Cologne: Editiones Thomisticae, 2000. Pp. 120. ISBN 3-89811-286-1 (paper). This modest study of St. Thomas's texts and motifs relevant to the Church's liturgical life is designed to reassure those who suspect that the liturgy played no serious part in his theological vision. Aside from a shortish conclusion, the book consists of four chapters which consider in turn Thomas's authority and the value of his thought today, the role of the liturgy in his life and spirituality, the liturgy as a locus theologicus in Aquinas's theological argumentation, and, finally-and here, if the texts adduced are familiar the concept under which they are brought is, in this context, an unusual one-St Thomas's "liturgics." Berger's account of Thomas's ecclesial standing covers well-trodden territory from Baronius's comments on his influence at Trent to Pope John Paul H's Fides et ratio. The section on Thomas's actuality is more interesting. By repackaging the philosophical Thomas as a modern avant la lettre, Transcendental Thomism succeeded in making him boring, for what could be less interesting than someone who simply states what all enlightened people know anyway? If anything is to be liberating about Thomist thought it will be what makes it different in some respect. The question then naturally presents itself in a book with such a title as the present one: what by way of useful dissonance from contemporary assumptions does Thomas have to say to us on the liturgy? Two planks of the author's platform must be put in place first. Thomas's "spirituality" was deeply liturgical; he treated the liturgy as theologically authoritative. Unless these claims can be substantiated (this appears to be Berger's thinking), the mystagogical and epistemological preconditions for taking seriously anything thought-provokingly different in Thomas's liturgiology will be absent. It can hardly be said that the Christian thinking of St. Thomas is as thoroughly liturgical in its inspiration and content as that, say, of Blessed Columba Marmion. Still, it is not difficult to show that the pertinent preconditions are met by this Eucharistically oriented, fervent friar, brought up among the "sons of St. Benedict," a doctor who in the prologue to his Postilla super Psalmos gave it as his opinion that the Psalter "contains the whole of theology at large" and in the Summa Theologiae ascribes maxima auctoritas to the sacramental consuetudo &clesiae. Given all this, it was probably unnecessary for Berger to make so much of St. Thomas's allegorical defense of the numerous signs of the Cross required of the celebrant over the Gifts in the pre-modern Roman Rite (44-51). That is part and parcel of the author's attempt not only to tie such liturgical principles as we can infer from St. Thomas's corpus to that liturgy (a proceeding which is of course historically correct) but, further, to insinuate that those principles are incapable of informing the theological awareness of a Western Catholic using the modern rites (with their enfeebled ability to stimulate contemplation, 500 BOOK REVIEWS exaggerated emphasis on subjectively experienced needs, and reduced emphasis on the identity of the sacrament of the altar with the mystery of the Cross). These criticisms certainly apply de facto to much contemporary celebration; whether they can be laid at the door of the Pauline Missal simply as such is another question. It would, however, be a pity if the deficient sympathy of many readers for the author's liturgical preferences stopped them reading on and reaching his valuable statement of Thomas's "liturgics." Here he brings together a number of principles, discussed at some length by Thomas in the two Summas, and capable of acting as building blocks for the theology of the liturgy Thomas never got around to constructing. Within an "analectic" reading of Thomas's intellectual vision as characterized by deliberate balance, comprehensiveness, and interconnection, Berger sets out in brief compass such themes as: theocentricity; man's physical-spiritual nature as a worshiping being; the return of man to God through the instrumentality of the humanity of Jesus Christ, the High Priest whose continuing action the liturgy is; the sacraments as efficacious signs of his saving work; the Eucharist as the center of the "liturgical cosmos"; and the sacramental character as the share of Christians in the high priesthood of Christ. What is needed and, for reasons of the book's brevity, cannot be furnished, is the integration of these, more fully reflected on, into a satisfying whole. The footnotes provide useful bibliography for those interested in the conservative wing of theology and liturgical commentary in present-day German Catholicism. AIDAN NICHOLS, 0.P. Blackfriars Cambridge, England The Collected Works of Bernard Lonergan, vol. 1: Grace and Freedom: Operative Grace in the Thought of St. Thomas Aquinas. Edited by FREDERICKE. CROWE and ROBERT M. DORAN. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2000. Pp. xxiii + 513. $24.95 (paper), $80.00 (cloth). ISBN 0802083374 (paper) 0802047998 (cloth). Grace and Freedom: Operative Grace in the Thought of Thomas Aquinas is the latest volume of the Collected Works of Bernard Lonergan, a series arranged and edited by the Lonergan Research Institute. This new volume contains two important works of Lonergan: a critical edition of his 1971 book Grace and Freedom and his doctoral dissertation, entitled Gratia Operans. The editors BOOK REVIEWS 501 made the decision to publish these two texts together because the 1971 book is a reorganized and reedited form of the dissertation. The central thesis governing both of these works is that St. Thomas continually refined his conception of the human condition, causing developments in his understanding of operative, cooperative, habitual, and actual grace. Lonergan contends that these refinements can best be understood by tracing the historical development of St. Thomas's thought through three major periods. Lonergan presents St. Thomas's first period as roughly coinciding with the completion of his Commentary on the Sentences. There, St. Thomas maintains that perfection is measured by the proportion between potency and act. God is all act and is therefore perfect. Humans are mostly potency and, while open to perfection, are not perfect. They must develop in space and time, and this process of growing creates the possibility of flawed development. Saint Thomas believes, Lonergan argues, that perfection becomes possible for humanity only through the infusion and action of new habits-what he terms operative and cooperative habitual grace. Operative habitual grace establishes new habits and desires; cooperative habitual grace works in conjunction with the human will to bring these new habits and desires into fruition through external action. Together, these graces enable human persons to actualize their potency effectively and become more perfect, more Godlike. Lonergan contends that while St. Thomas has a clear understanding of habitual grace during this time, he barely develops the category of actual grace. Actual grace encompasses an enormous variety of events and gifts that may lead to one's repentance and conversion (e.g., a preacher's sermon, loss of health, speaking in tongues), but the category lacks any definitive meaning. On Lonergan's account, St. Thomas's second period is roughly equivalent to the completion of De Veritate. In this text, St. Thomas slightly alters his understanding of the human situation and, consequently, his solution to it. God alone is the fullness of perfection and truth, and things approach perfection as they approach God. God, then, must be the source and principle of all of a person's actions. Since no habit is equivalent to God, St. Thomas recognizes that his earlier solution to the human condition (relying solely on new habits) is insufficient. What humans need is an intervention by God to make Him the source of their acts. Lonergan maintains that this need was the impetus that began St. Thomas's reflection on actual cooperative grace. In clarifying the category, St. Thomas attributes several characteristics to it. Actual cooperative grace helps the will move, it expedites the external act of the will, and it helps to ensure perseverance. Most importantly, actual cooperative grace makes God the principle of human actions. This new category was the solution to the difficulty raised by St. Thomas's revised understanding of the human condition. Thus, according to Lonergan, during St. Thomas's second period he held that salvation comes not only from operative habitual grace (i.e., the infusion of 502 BOOK REVIEWS new habits) and cooperative habitual grace (i.e., these habits put into action with the assistance of the will) but also from actual cooperative grace (i.e., a divine intervention on the human will). Lonergan situates St. Thomas's third stage during his writing of the Summa contra Gentiles and the Summa Theologica. During this period, St. Thomas augments his previous understanding of the human condition. In order to reach perfection, humans still need the infusion of new habits, assistance in acting on them, and perfection of action through divine intervention; however, these graces are not enough. For true perfection, all human action must be oriented toward God. Ultimately, God brings about this transformation of human activity, frequently through a conversion experience, by infusing the needed reorientation. St. Thomas designates this divine gift as "actual operative grace." Lonergan concludes his study by reading this development as a balancing of the importance of habitual grace with a recognition of the integral role of actual grace. Initially, St. Thomas prioritizes habitual grace, breaking it down into the two further categories of operative and cooperative grace. As St. Thomas continues his reflection on the human situation, he comes to a better understanding of the category of actual grace. In his early thought, St. Thomas's perspective on actual grace reflects those of his predecessors, theologians like St. Augustine, St. Anselm, and Peter Lombard. Actual grace denotes any of the variety of gifts or events that God bestows upon people. In the next period, St. Thomas develops the category of actual cooperative grace to address the need for human actions to flow from God. Saint Thomas continues his reflection in his third period and recognizes the need for human actions to also have their end in God; hence he distills actual operative grace. With the advent of the last category, St. Thomas arrives at a position where the primary categories for the solution to the human situation are actual and habitual grace that are each subdivided into operative and cooperative grace. This overview merely highlights the major contours of Lonergan' s argument. Obviously, his work includes a number of elements that support, nuance, and develop this argument. The most significant of these are: St. Thomas's changing position on divine intervention and human freedom, a survey of the thinkers that established the context within which he did his work, and his notion of divine operation and divine transcendence. While the most important aspect of the volume is Lonergan's argument, the editors, Frederick Crowe and Robert Doran, add a number of features that support, and thereby enhance, Lonergan's thought. They include a glossary of Latin terms. In the footnotes, they translate the numerous Latin texts Lonergan quotes. They also append an extensive glossary, a bibliography of St. Thomas's works, and a preface that explains the history behind Lonergan's research. Hence, the present volume is important for both Lonerganian and Thomistic scholars. For Lonerganians, it brings to light Lonergan's thought on grace as reflected in his scholarship on St. Thomas, exemplifies his historical approach to theology, and makes his dissertation readily accessible. For Thomists, BOOK REVIEWS 503 Lonergan offers a viable interpretation of the developments and refinements of St. Thomas's thought on actual, habitual, operative, and cooperative grace. JASON KING Marymount University Arlington, Virginia