The Thomist 74 (2010): 337-68 AQUINAS ON BATTLEFIELD COURAGE GREGORY M. REICHBERG Peace Research Institute Oslo (PRIO) Oslo, Norway O VER THECOURSEofhiscareer, ThomasAquinaspaused only once to reflect on battlefield courage-question 123, article 5 of the Secunda Secundae of the Summa Theologiae: "Whether fortitude is properly about the dangers of death which arise in war." 1 In light of his robust teaching on just war, 2 one would have expected him to elaborate on the special nobility of the military profession, or to detail the moral challenges faced by its practitioners. Instead, the article explains how "death in war" is an analogous term that applies to soldiers certainly, but also to civic heroes and even to martyrs for the faith. The theme of martyrdom occupies central stage 3 in Aquinas's overall discussion of courage. Some commentators have concluded that his main purpose in writing question 123 was to substitute the ancient Greco-Roman admiration for military heroism with a Christian focus on martyrdom. 4 In what follows, 1 The theme of battlefield courage is however announced earlier in question 50 on prudence. Having noted that generalship requires a special form of prudence, Aquinas adds that those who do the actual fighting (rank-and-file soldiers) stand in need of fortitude (STh 11-11, q. 50, a. 4, ad 3). For a treatment of the former virtue, see Gregory M. Reichberg, "Thomas Aquinas on Military Prudence," Journal of Military Ethics 9 (2010): 261-74. 2 STh 11-11, q. 40, "De hello." See Gregory M. Reichberg, "Thomas Aquinas between Just War and Pacifism," Journal of Religious Ethics 38 (2010): 219-41. 3 Among the acts of fortitude, martyrdom alone receives special treatment in a full quaestio (STh II-II, q. 124). 4 A particularly emphatic formulation of this reading has been advanced by Rebecca Konyndyk de Young, "Power Made Perfect in Weakness: Aquinas's Transformation of the Virtue of Courage," Medieval Philosophy and Theology 11(2003):147-80. To a lesser extent 337 338 GREGORY M. REICHBERG I argue that the substitution account is misleading. Despite Aquinas's obvious interest in highlighting martyrdom as the highest instantiation of fortitude, he does not discredit the value of battlefield courage within the Christian life of virtue. On the contrary, he elaborates a two-stage theory in which military heroism is put forward as the exemplar of acquired fortitude, while martyrdom is praised as the paradigm of infused fortitude. Having embraced the principle "grace perfects nature," Aquinas is attentive to the various relations that can exist between these two modalities-acquired and infused-of fortitude. 5 On the one hand, the heroism of soldiers provides him with a natural basis for understanding the supernatural fortitude of holy martyrs. On the other hand, he recognizes how infused fortitude can find expression in military deeds, such that death on the battlefield will sometimes count as martyrdom. The argument will proceed in six stages. In a first section I examine why Aquinas brings the theme of martyrdom into his account of battlefield courage in question 123, article 5. To this end, a comparison with his earlier discussion of prudence 6 will prove instructive. Whereas prudence is differentiated into five separate kinds, including a military kind, on the Aristotelian typology followed by Aquinas, courage is a unitary virtue. Unlike many contemporary Christian authors, who typically frame martyrdom as a category sui generis that would stand wholly apart from the soldier's active engagement on the battlefield, Aquinas is intent on encompassing the two sorts of death within a single account. 7 this viewpoint is briefly developed by Michel Labourdette, O.P., Force et temperance (IIa-IIae, 123-170) in Cours de theologie morale, Toulouse, annee scolaire 1961-62, unpublished manuscript. (Copies of Labourdette's typed course manuscript, which follows the order of the Secunda Pars, have circulated widely). Labourdette's treatment does have the merit of emphasizing the importance, in Aquinas's eyes, of acquired courage, while Konyndyk De Young's analysis is framed almost exclusively in terms of infused courage. 5 I thank an anonymous reviewer for suggesting this formulation. 6 In particular, STh 11-11, qq. 48 and. 50. 7 This is especially salient in STh 11-11, q. 124, a. 5, ad 3, where, after reproducing the objection that "it is not consistent with Church observance" that those who die fighting in a just war are celebrated as martyrs, he responds that "any human good insofar as it is referred to God may be the cause of martyrdom," with the discreet implication that even a soldier's AQUINAS ON BATTLEFIELD COURAGE 339 In a second section, moving more deeply into the specific characteristics of military courage, I explore how Aquinas goes well beyond the letter of Aristotle's treatment of this virtue. Whereas the Stagirite had simply stated that the courageous man faces death in the most noble of circumstances, namely, in war, Aquinas innovates by establishing a necessary link between courage and just cause (protection of the common good from external threats). He accordingly rules out any possible exercise of courage in unjust wars. Having delineated what goods are to be upheld by fortitude, Aquinas then explains how two passions in particular stand in need of regulation by this virtue: fear and daring. How these passions arise with particular vehemence in the military setting is the topic of this article's third section. But since in this connection Aquinas says little explicitly about war, my account of battlefield courage is supplemented by an analysis of the dispositions which, on his understanding, reinforce courage, namely, hope, anger, perseverance, and the like (sections 4 and 5). This analysis shows how Aquinas provides a nuanced set of principles for discerning the special emotive challenges that arise within the military profession, challenges that St. Augustine had highlighted but which commentators often assume Aquinas had neglected in favor of a more deontological approach. By emphasizing so strongly the military dimensions of courage, it would seem, however, that my interpretation of Aquinas is vulnerable to an objection. While the expectation of a future beatitude to be conferred by God provides a motivational grounding for infused martyrdom, no such premise comes to the support of acquired military courage. Why should soldiers be willing to give their all if the temporal city is in no way able to death in combat, undergone with the requisite intention, may fall under this heading. He is not thereby affirming that every death in a just war would count as martyrdom, nor that the battlefield is a typical setting for martyrdom, but only how, on his understanding, there exists sufficient commonality between the two sorts of death-the soldier's and the martyr's-that the same virtue can be predicated of each without equivocation. This commonality of meaning is assured by the nonmetaphorical extension of the predicate "in war" beyond its standard battlefield connotation (public war), to a violent conflict of individuals (private war). 340 GREGORY M. REICHBERG return the favor? Section 6 elucidates Aquinas's response to this question. I. COURAGE IN PUBLIC AND PRIVATE WAR In line with his earlier treatment of prudentia militaris, Aquinas devotes a single article to battlefield courage (STh 11-11, q. 123, a. 5). The approach adopted in this article is however markedly different from his antecedent analysis of prudence. In light of its wide scope (the sound practical judgment needed for upright choice), Aquinas subdivides prudentia into several distinct and full-fledged virtues, each with responsibility over a different sphere of human action-personal, familial, civil, or military. Fortitudo,8 by contrast, he describes as prima facie of quite narrow scope. Its task, as indicated by the article's title, is to regulate the most acute of fears, namely, those arising from an imminent risk of violent death. Its subject matter thus construed, courage, taken precisely as a special virtue, is deemed indivisible into multiple kinds. 9 Aquinas thereby faces the challenge of explaining how the single species of this virtue, which Aristotle had discussed exclusively in function of soldiers contending on a battlefield, could be applied to other settings as well. Aquinas is especially intent on enlarging the scope of courage to cover the special case of martyrdom, a case of little or no concern to Aristotle-despite the example of Socrates-but traditionally lauded by Christian authors as the preeminent exemplification of fortitude. Aquinas extends courage to martyr8 Fortitudo was the term used by William of Moeberke in his translation of the Nicomachean Ethics for civ&pda, which is ordinarily rendered into English as "bravery" or "courage." Aquinas quotes from this translation in his Sententia Libri Ethicorum, as well as in the Secunda Pars of the Summa Theologiae. In the present article, "fortitude," "bravery," and "courage" are accordingly employed as interchangeable terms. 9 See STh 11-11, q. 128, "The parts of courage." Aquinas does acknowledge that, taken broadly as an equivalent for resoluteness (firmitas), courage is a disposition that is needed for every other virtue. This general variant of the virtue stands in contrast to the special virtue Aristotle had discussed in the Nicomachean Ethics. For a good overview of Aquinas's teaching on courage, including the contrast between general and special courage, see R. E. Houser, "The Virtue of Courage (Ila Ilae, qq. 123-140)," in Stephen J. Pope, ed., The Ethics of Aquinas (Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press, 2002), 304-20. AQUINAS ON BATTLEFIELD COURAGE 341 dom not by modifying the essentials of this virtue as they are presented in the Nicomachean Ethics, an account he adheres to closely, but rather by finding a foundation in Scripture that enables him to widen the ordinary meaning of helium. This foundation he finds in the Church's Office of Martyrs, which, reproducing Hebrews 11:34, praises those "whose weakness was turned to strength, who became valiant in war and routed foreign armies." Aquinas is thus able to maintain that "sustaining personal attacks, for the sake of the highest good which is God ... is not alien to the genus of acts that concern war, for which reason martyrs are called courageous in war." 10 Beyond its standard active connotation of an army "fighting on a line of battle," helium may also signify, for Aquinas, a confrontation whereby an individual, risking a violent death at the hands of his opponent, holds firm to his purpose. This he names "particular war" (helium particulare), in contrast to the "general war" (helium generale) of an army engaged on a battlefield. 11 The first is a functional equivalent of helium privatum, a term Aquinas uses earlier in the Secunda Secundae,12 while the latter represents an early formulation of what medieval civil lawyers later termed helium puhlicum. 13 Since in each there is truly found a "danger of death in war," Aquinas is able to conclude that both military combat and martyrdom meet the strict standard set by Aristotle's definition of courage. Having found a scriptural basis for including martyrdom within the scope of courage, Aquinas can, in his general treatment of the virtue, remain faithful to the argumentation of book 3 of the Nicomachean Ethics. This has been called into question by STh II-II, q. 123, a. 5, ad 1. u The same terms, with slight variation, also appear in the plural, particularia bella and communia bella (STh II-II, q. 123, a. 5, ad 2). 12 STh II-II, q. 41, a. 1, where the sin of brawling (rixa) is called a "kind of private war" (quoddam privatum bellum). 13 See, for instance, Bartol us of Saxoferrato (1313-57), Secunda super Digesto nova (Lyon: Gryphius, 1533, folio 236r-v), commentary on Ulpian's definition of enemies (Digest, bk. 49, chap. 15, §24); translation in Gregory M. Reichberg, Henrik Syse, and Endre Begby, The Ethics of War: Classic and Contemporary Readings (Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 2006), 2059. 10 342 GREGORY M. REICHBERG some commentators. Michel Labourdette, 14 for instance, judges that Aquinas, by adhering too closely to Aristotle's terminology, attempts to synthesize a Christian conception of fortitudemodeled on the ideal of martyrdom-around the alien Greek ideal of a "beautiful death" on the battlefield. While admitting that the difference between the two approaches was somewhat obscured for Aquinas-where Aristotle wrote that the courageous man confronts "dangers that are not only great, but also beautiful" (Ev µEytaTW Kat KtvMvw KaAAtcrTw, the last word was rendered in the Latin translation of Moerbeke as "best" (optima)Labourdette nevertheless finds Aquinas's description of martyrdom under the equivocal concept of a "particular war" to be contrived. In the medieval context, the term helium enjoyed a range of application considerably broader than obtains for "war" or its equivalents today. 15 Policing could be described under this term, as in Gratian's Decretum, 16 as could acts of private self-defense, as in the influential gloss Qui repel/ere possunt (ca. 1200). 17 Aquinas himself characterized a condemned prisoner's forcible resistance against a just sentence of capital punishment as an "unjust war" (helium iniustum). 18 The extension of helium to interpersonal violence may be found as late as Grotius, who wrote (ca. 1625) that "[w]ar may be waged by private persons against private persons, as by a traveler against a highwayman. " 19 Operating within the medieval notion of "private war," there could be an easy transition from the causative meaning of helium to the receptive connotation of someone suffering violence, yet firmly by strength of soul. This more passive signification of helium represents an innovation on Aquinas's part, since in his era Labourdette, Force et temperance, 14-16. medieval usage of helium or guerra, see Peter Haggenmacher, Grotius et la doctrine de la guerre juste (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1983), 95. 16 See for instance the opening paragraph in Gratian's Decretum II, causa 13; translation in Reichberg et al., The Ethics of War, 109. 17 Translation in Reichberg, et al., The Ethics of War, 109-11, left column. 18 STh II-II, q. 69, a. 4. 19 Hugo Grotius, De iure belli ac pacis fiber tres, (ed. B. J. A. Kanter-van Hettinga Tromp [Leiden: Brill, 1939]), bk. I, chap. IV, sect. I, § < 1 >; translation in Reichberg, et al., The Ethics of War, 398. 14 15 On the AQUINAS ON BATTLEFIELD COURAGE 343 bellum privatum typically signified a resort to violence. In order to explain how martyrdom might represent an authentic instantiation of courage, precisely under the Aristotelian definition of the term, Aquinas is accordingly compelled to shift the meaning of bellum from causing violence to receiving violence. The result is an analogous usage that preserves reference to actual bloody confrontation, yet that eschews the active connotation of resorting to force. In place of the latter it substitutes the kindred ideas of determination and endurance. Finally, in yet a further extension, Aquinas contrasts physical fighting (pugnare corporaliter) to fighting in a metaphorical sense, as when he says that the saints wage a "spiritual combat" (spiritualiter certando) against their own wayward desires to gain eternal life. 20 The different senses of war that figure in Aquinas's treatment of courage are listed below. These are susceptible of further subdivision into "just" and "unjust," except divine martyrdom and spiritual combat, which designate good acts only. 21 Primary analogate: one army 22 confronting another on a battlefield-public war Secondary analogate: one individual interacting violently with another-private war Signified actively: resorting to force defensively or for other motives Signified passively: suffering violent attack with firm endurance; selfsacrifice, for God (martyrdom) or one's country Metaphorical analogate: resisting concupiscence-spiritual war 11-11, q. 140, a. 1, ad 1. instance STh 11-11, q. 124, a. 2, ad 2, where Aquinas explains how divine martyrdom is inseparable from charity, the primary source of good action. The same reasoning would apply to spiritual combat. Concerning the latter, in De civitate Dei 19.4 Augustine speaks of our "unceasing warfare with vices, not those external but internal, not other people's vices but clearly one's own." This metaphorical sense of combat is akin to what is termed the "greater jihad" by Muslims ("striving in the way of God") while "physical fighting" corresponds to the "lesser jihad." 22 In the text (STh II-II, q. 42, a. 1) that comes closest to defining helium, Aquinas writes that it consists in one multitude contending against another (multitudinis ad multitudinem), each considering the other its external enemy. "Multitude" signifiesthe fighting force (army) of an independent polity. 20 STh 21 See for 344 GREGORY M. REICHBERG Corresponding to these different senses of helium, Aquinas recognizes several analogous predications of courage. Public war (helium universale) he views as the chief arena for the exercise of acquired fortitude, because in this instance death is risked for the sake of a worthy good, namely, to preserve the polity from outward attack. Yet courage, properly speaking, may also be exercised in private war (helium particulare), as when an individual defends himself or others against the ambush of thieves, or a policeman gives chase to an armed criminal. 23 Still related, but nonetheless markedly different-as in this case violence is undergone, not applied-is the courage exhibited by those who bear witness to God in the face of persecution. But alongside this infused courage (fortitudo gratuita) that the Church celebrates in its martyrs, Aquinas recognizes that there is also an acquired courage of civic sacrifice (fortitudo civilis), as when individuals risk their lives for the sake of the common good. 24 The example of a "judge who does not refrain from giving a just judgement despite fear of an impending sword" is cited as an instance of someone who undergoes a just private war. 25 At this juncture it can be noted that Aquinas applies the term "martyrdom" only to the first form of endurance (divine, infused), but not to the second (civic, acquired). Finally, in a broader sense, Aquinas is able to admit that courage may be exercised even in settings apart from violence, provided that death is faced "on account of virtue." Attending to a sick friend despite the risk of deadly infection, or undertaking an unsafe journey for a worthy purpose, are the two examples cited. 26 Beyond this, on all the manifold occasions when inner strength is needed to confront nonlethal risks, Aquinas speaks not 23 In STh II-II, q. 123, a. 5, ad 2, Aquinas makes clear that a willingness to confront death in "personal or civil affairs," is an instantiation of "fortitude" in the proper sense of the term, precisely because this is an arena of war, albeit of the private sort. No examples of private resort to force are given in the text, but, from his comments elsewhere (especially STh II-II, q. 64, a. 7) we can surmise that he has in mind acts of self-defense or law enforcement. 24 STh II-II, q. 124, a. 2, ad 1. Gratuitous and civic courage are described by reference to these two ends for the sake of which courage may be exercised. 25 STh II-II, q. 123, a. 5. 26 Ibid. AQUINAS ON BATTLEFIELD COURAGE 345 of courage proper, but of magnanimity, patience, and other "potential parts" 27 of the virtue. Bearing a resemblance to courage, the primary or cardinal virtue, these secondary virtues extend its reach into the myriad challenges of daily life. 28 Aquinas on occasion also speaks metaphorically about bellum, using this term to designate the spiritual combat of the faithful against the attractions of concupiscence. Discussing the reward due to holy virgins, he notes how they win "a signal victory over the flesh, against which a continuous war is waged" (continue bellum geritur). 29 War waged in this metaphorical sense against disorderly internal passions is contrasted to the victory won by martyrs, "who fight against passions exteriorly caused" (pugna contra passionem exterius illatas).30 II. COURAGE, A VIRTUE IN }UST WARS ONLY Aquinas's analysis of battlefield courage is two pronged. He describes, in thick normative terms, what might count as the appropriate setting for the exercise of this form of courage. Then, adopting the perspective of moral psychology, he considers what 27 In contrast to "integral parts" which are subordinate skills needed for the exercise of a single virtue, "potential parts" are separate virtues that bear a resemblance to (although lacking a key feature of) the main, cardinal virtue. For this reason they differ from "subjective parts," which are distinct and complete instantiations (species) of one and the same (genus of) virtue. For Aquinas's explanation of the distinction between integral, subjective, and potential parts, see his analysis of the parts of prudentia in STh 11-11, q. 48, a. 1. In its application to fortitude, this categorization is further complicated by the fact that the same names, e.g., patience and magnanimity, serve to designate both integral and potential parts (cf. STh 11-11, q. 128, a. 1, where magnanimitas names an integral part of fortitude proper, and the following q. 129, where it names a separate virtue (i.e., a potential part). 28 In highlighting martyrdom as the paradigm of courage, Konyndyk de Young ("Power Made Perfect in Weakness") is motivated by a concern that emphasizing military heroism would result in an elitist conception of the virtue. However, she leaves out of consideration Aquinas's designation of analogous instantiations ("potential parts") of the virtue. In my opinion, this, and not the infused virtue of martyrs, was Aquinas's preferred strategy for broadening the scope of courage so that it would be readily applicable by ordinary people in their day-to-day lives. 29 IV Sent., d. 49, q. 5, a. 3, qcla. 1; reproduced in STh suppl., q. 96, a. 5. 30 IV Sent., d. 49, q. 5, a. 3, qcla. 2 (STh suppl., q. 96, a. 6). 346 GREGORY M. REICHBERG emotional reactions are characteristic of warriors who virtuously confront death in war. Regarding the first line of inquiry-which today would come under the heading of ius ad bellum or reasons for resorting to war-it is striking that Aquinas does not speak simply of war to protect the city or nation, as did his eminent predecessor. Instead he innovates by adopting the normative phraseology of just war: "The dangers of death which occur in battle," he writes, "come to man directly on account of some good, namely because he is defending the common good by a just war. " 31 The key notions invoked here-" defense," "common good," and "just war" -have no parallel in book 3 of the Nicomachean Ethics, where, concerning the object of courage, Aristotle had simply stated that the brave man faces death in the most noble of circumstances, namely, in war. He thereby excluded from the scope of the virtue those lethal dangers that human beings expose themselves to in other settings, sailors at sea, for instance, or physicians fighting disease. 32 While acknowledging that the temporal peace of one's country (pax republicae) is certainly worth dying for, as it represents an inherent good, 33 Aquinas is nonetheless keen to narrow the scope of courage to just wars (both public and private), with the result that the normative status of this virtue is considerably heightened. On his view, fully virtuous courage will arise only in those battles that are fought, not for any civic purpose whatsoever, but only such as are consistent with defense of the common good. Excluded from the scope of courage would be wars fought out of II-II, q. 123, a. 5. Ethic. 3.1115a28-31: "[The brave man] would not seem to be concerned with death in all circumstances, e.g. at sea or in disease. In what circumstances, then? Surely in the best [optimis]. Now such deaths are those in war; for these take place in the greatest and best [optima] danger." This translation follows the Latin version of William Moerbeke as it appears in Thomas Aquinas, Sententia Libri Ethicorum (Rome: Ad Sanctae Sabinae, 1969), bk. III, sect. 14, lines 30-31 (p. 159). In his commentary (ibid., 162), where Aristotle had spoken of "such deaths as are in war," Aquinas adds "for the defense of one's country" (propter patriae defensione), and, several lines later he may be found using the alternative expression "for the common good" (pro bono communi). He does not however employ the expression "helium iustum." 33 STh II-II, q. 123, a. 5, ad 3. 31 STh 32 Nie. AQUINAS ON BATILEFIELD COURAGE 347 private interest, say for the mere aggrandizement of the prince, or for reasons other than protection of the polity from external or internal threat. Willingness to face death on the battlefield must be conditioned, in other words, by the justice of the cause for which one is fighting. 34 This represents a considerably more stringent conception of the virtue than had been originally advanced by Aristotle (although a case could be made that Aquinas's linkage of courage to just cause is consistent with the overall tenor of Aristotle's moral teaching on war). 35 Regarding the second line of inquiry (in be/lo), where Aquinas outlines the emotional dispositions that should be cultivated to ensure virtuous participation in war, he begins by noting how courage exercises an auxiliary role; its function is to ensure that the pursuit of justice, as ordained by right reason, is not abandoned under peril of death. 36 When justice requires forcible action in defense of the polity, courage will necessarily be at the service of prudentia militaris, the virtue by which right reason is applied to the conduct of war. Chiefly a virtue of commanders, this prudence should also in some fashion be acquired by rankand-file soldiers, in parallel with Aquinas's teaching that there is a form of prudence (politica) by which citizens share in the prudential governance (regnativa) of their civic leaders. 37 On this understanding, solders, like citizens, are not expected to obey their superiors slavishly, with no reflection whatsoever. Personal judgment is called for even in the exercise of the most virtuous obedience. In at least one passage Aquinas may thus be found asserting that "soldiers are not bound to obey in an unjust 34 In this way, Aquinas discreetly joins his account of courage to the earlier discussion of just cause in STh II-II, q. 40, a. 1. The dependency of courage on just cause has been wellnoted by Josef Pieper, The Four Cardinal Virtues (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1966), 125. 35 See for instance Politics 7.2.1324b2-5a10. 36 Fortitude shares this auxiliary role with temperance; the function of both is to remove obstacles (occasioned by fear of death or the attraction of pleasure) that hinder the exercise of prudence and justice (STh II-II, q. 123, a. 12). 37 STh II-II, q. 50, a. 2. 348 GREGORY M. REICHBERG war. " 38 Courage is thus derivative upon right reason, a reason that must be liberated not only from undue passion, but also from attachment to interests that stand in opposition to the common good. In this connection, courage is also at the service of justice. Aquinas sums this up negatively with a quotation from St. Ambrose (De Offic. 1. 35): "fortitude without justice is an occasion for iniquity. " 39 This strongly normative conception of bravery would appear to rule out any possible exercise of the virtue in unjust wars. Soldiers fighting for a patently wrongful cause, or prosecuting war in an illicit manner, could not be designated "courageous" even if they exhibit much endurance and daring. 40 III. FEAR AND DARING Having delineated what goods are to be upheld by fortitudeprotection of the common good from external threats, or internally from grave untruth or injustice-Aquinas proceeds to explain how two passions in particular stand in need of regulation by this virtue: fear (timor) and daring (audacia}.41 In this connection, his comments on war (in the narrow sense) are extremely brief. His broader account is designed to apply throughout the range of acts where courage is called for-in war certainly, but in martyrdom also, and indeed in any sort of setting where one's life can voluntarily be placed at risk for the sake of the good. 38 In Titus, c. 3, lect. 1. I thank my colleague Henrik Syse for bringing this passage to my attention. Although the specific case of military service is not mentioned, in his general discussion of obedience in STh II-II, q. 104, Aquinas similarly states that "a subordinate is not held to obey an unjust command" (a. 6, ad 3). 39 STh II-II, q. 123, a. 12, ad 3. 40 Although they do not possess courage simpliciter, these unjust warriors are, in Aquinas's view, courageous in a limited fashion (secundum quid). See STh I-II, 65, a. 1, where he explains how between "complete" and "incomplete" virtue, there is a thin resemblance only. Aquinas does not take up the case, later explored by Vitoria, of soldiers who, by invincible ignorance, fight for a de facto unjust cause that they nonetheless sincerely believe to be just. Whether their courage should be deemed complete or incomplete is an issue that cannot be explored here. 41 STh II-II, q. 126, a. 2. AQUINAS ON BATTLEFIELD COURAGE 349 Fear and daring are emotional reactions that arise in us at the prospect of future harm. 42 In this respect they differ from the related passions of sorrow and anger-the first looks to a present harm for which there is no immediate remedy, while the latter pursues retribution for past wrongs. 43 Fear is the impulse of flight in the face of an evil that seems superior to our power, while daring is the contrary impulse 44 of attack, by which we thrust forward to eradicate the threatening object, confident in our ability to prevail over it. 45 Vis-a-vis fear, courage prompts endurance (sustinere).Indeed, the tendency of our animal nature is to flee the approach of bodily harm. Yet, as animals possessed of reason, we are able to recognize that the fulfillment of our nature is not found in the body alone. Above it are goods of the soul. 46 For their preservation we must sometimes "stand immovable in the midst of dangers," 47 willingly enduring harm even to the point of death. On other occasions the emotion that dominates is not fear but daring. Feeling superior to the threat, we go on the attack (aggredi),offensively seeking victory over it. 48 While this reaction can be morally appropriate, it can also happen that we act without due reflection, thereby underestimating the danger at hand to the detriment of the goods we wish to defend. Worse yet, this passion, left unchecked, can lead the warrior into a tunnel of 42 STh I-II, q. 41, a. 1 "fear involves future evil"; cf. STh II-II q. 123, a. 3, where Aquinas explains how daring sets out to dispel threatening evils, so as "to free oneself from them for the future." 43 STh I-II, q. 48, a. 1: "The movement of anger arises from a wrong done that causes sorrow." In STh I-II, q. 45, a. 1, Aquinas explains how daring and fear are related according to an opposition of approach and withdrawal, hence they are formally contraries. Fear also stands opposed to security (ibid., ad 3 ), its privation (he who feels secure experiences an absence of fear}, and in this sense the two stand opposed as contradictories. 45 STh I-II, q. 45, a. 1. 46 STh II-II, q. 123, a. 4. 47 STh II-II, q. 123, a. 6. 48 STh II-II, q. 127, a. 2, ad 3; Aquinas mentions "victory" in STh I-II, q. 45, a. 3: "the hope that leads to daring is roused by those things that make us reckon victory is possible." 44 350 GREGORY M. REICHBERG violence, wherein atrocities can readily be committed. 49 For this reason, Aquinas emphasizes how in relation to daring fortitude is mainly about restraint or moderation, while vis-a-vis fear it mainly prompts resistance. In each case, however, virtue consists in achieving the mean of excellence, so that where attack is called for, courage will stimulate daring; inversely, should a man be inclined to endure harm needlessly, holding his own life cheap, courage validates fear so that he flees from a harm the endurance of which will bear no fruit. Aquinas sums this up by noting how "the act of fortitude consists in enduring fear [of death] and going on the attack, not anyhow, but according to reason. " 50 In the military setting these two acts, endurance and attack, are complementary. Depending on the challenges proper to each concrete situation, one or the other will predominate. Warriors must accordingly be trained in such a way that they are able to elicit both reactions, 51 each of which is integral to the virtue. Aquinas acknowledges, however, that soldiers often believe they can bypass fear in favor of daring alone. Confident in their military prowess, "through practice in the use of arms," they "think little of the dangers of battle. "52 But this evacuation of fear, 49 Aquinas does not himself draw out this implication, but it is in line with the logic of his analysis. For a description of excessive daring as a causal factor in the commission of battlefield atrocities, see Randall Collins, Violence: A Micro-Sociological Theory (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008), 83-133. This analysis is focused on the notion of "forward panic," which the author describes as "a sudden rush of frenzied overkill in an atmosphere of hysterical entrainment" (ibid., 100). Collins likewise employs the image of a "tunnel" of violence: "persons who have fallen ... into a forward panic situation have gone down into a tunnel and cannot stop their momentum" (ibid., 94 ). To emphasize how this emotional state is indeed rooted in our sentient nature, he recounts how it may be found even among nonhuman animals, for instance elephants (ibid., 109). so STh II-II, q. 126, a. 2, ad 1. 51 Konyndyk de Young ("Power Made Perfect in Weakness") misidentifies Aquinas's position when she defines military courage by reference solely to daring (aggression), under the assumption that endurance is proper to the courage of martyrs (see in particular ibid., 163). In fact, for Aquinas military courage results from the appropriate balancing of both passions (not only daring but also endurance), while the other sort of courage consists in endurance alone. 52 STh II-II, q. 123, a. 1, ad 2. At this juncture Aquinas quotes the Roman military author Vegetius (De rei militaris,1.1): "No man fears to do what he is confident of having learned to do well." In rejecting this viewpoint as an adequate account of courage, Aquinas is clearly dependent on Aristotle's disparaging comments about professional soldiers (mercenaries) in AQUINAS ON BATILEFIELD COURAGE 351 by an overabundance of self-confidence, truncates the true nature of courage. These "men of daring" (audaces) fly headlong into danger, but once in its midst they retreat, suddenly aware how the difficulty is far greater than what they had imagined. By contrast, "men of courage" (fortes), listen to their fear, hence they attend more carefully to what lies ahead, and seek counsel, when needed. 53 Aquinas recognizes, however, that the Christian conception of martyrdom, exemplified by Jesus' voluntary acceptance of death at the hands of his persecutors, requires an adjustment to this teaching that courage results from a regulation of both fear and daring. The evangelists make clear that Jesus could have gone on the attack had he so wished, calling down the omnipotent intervention of God, and he instructed Peter to desist from forcible defense on his behalf (Matt 26:52-53). The courage thus shown by Jesus-imitated later by St. Stephen and the long line of Christian martyrs-consisted in endurance only. To show how authentic courage can subsist without preparedness for attack requires a modification of the military model of courage that Aquinas inherited from Aristotle. To effect this modification Aquinas explains 54 how between the two acts characteristic of courage, endurance and attack, there is an order of priority, the former taking precedence over the latter. This basis for this reasoning is a comment by Aristotle-"it is more difficult to endure affliction ... than to abstain from what is pleasant," 55 which Aquinas alters in view of the special case of courage: "To repress fear is more difficult than to moderate daring. " 56 Although daring becomes virtuous when it is tempered by reason and choice, the very propensity of our sentient nature supports this office of moderation, for "to lash out against that Nie. Ethic. 3.8.1116b5-23. 53 For the contrast between fortes and audaces, see STh I-II, q. 45, a. 4. On the benefits of moderate fear, see STh I-II, q. 44, a. 3, where Aquinas notes how this passion causes us to be more careful, attentive, and prone to seeking counsel. s• STh II-II, q. 123, a. 6; q. 124, a. 2, ad 3. ss Nie. Ethic. 3.9.1117a32; reference in STh II-II, q. 123, a. 6. s• STh II-II, q. 123, a. 6 352 GREGORY M. REICHBERG which promises harm" is spontaneously curbed by the contrary "fear of receiving harm from that source. " 57 Endurance enjoys no such support from our sentient nature. To the contrary, instinctively we flee an aggressor who appears superior to ourselves, so that if we are to hold fast in the face of onslaught this will be the fruit solely of a mental determination founded on inward choice. The above argument should not be taken to imply that moderating daring is in every instance easier than voluntarily enduring harm. Recent empirical research on the emotional dynamics of violent interactions has shown how the arousal of daring, and the resulting forward thrust of attack, can at times become almost irresistible. 58 This is especially likely to happen when after a period of acute confrontational stress soldiers suddenly find themselves secure in a position of dominance vis-avis their adversaries. The passion of daring then flows with full vigor, as it is no longer tempered by the countervailing pull of fear. Exercising moderation under such circumstances requires much inward discipline. A moral approach to military training will prepare soldiers for this eventuality. Beyond the issue of restraint, Aquinas maintains, more generally, that sustaining hardship is more difficult than going on the attack, for three reasons: 59 (1) daring implies a perceived STh II-II, q. 128, a. 2, ad 3. Again, see the description of "forward panic" in Collins, Violence: A Micro-Sociological Theory: "It resembles a panic, and indeed the physiological components are similar; instead of running away ... the fighters rush forward, toward the enemy. Running forward or backward, in either case they are in an overpowering emotional rhythm, carrying them on to actions that they would normally not approve of in calm, reflective moments" (ibid., 85). "It is like an altered state of consciousness, from which the perpetrators often emerge at the end as if returning from an alien self" (ibid., 100). This typically occurs when, due to a reversal or battlefield denouement, the sudden release of fear issues into a frenzy of attack: "It comes on with a rush, explosively; and it takes time to calm down .... Individuals in the throes of a forward panic keep repeating their aggressive actions" (ibid., 93). Collins usefully employs this concept of "forward panic" to explain the dynamics at work in some famous wartime incidents, including My Lai and Nanking. 59 STh II-II, q. 123, a. 6, ad 1. In his commentary on this passage, Cajetan notes that this comparison holds only with respect to one and the same threat. Should we compare two very different threats, attacking the one may well present a greater challenge than enduring the other (cited in Labourdette, Force et temperance, 17). 57 58 AQUINAS ON BATILEFIELD COURAGE 353 superiority of the attacker vis-a-vis the target of his hostility, while the relation is inverted with respect to endurance; (2) daring views the danger as still future, while endurance experiences it as already present; (3) daring is usually carried out in sudden and quick movements, while endurance stretches out in time. The conclusion thereby follows: voluntarily to sustain hardship, not out of passive resignation or a fear-induced paralysis, but with active endurance, is the "primary act" of courage, hence martyrs can truly be said to possess this virtue even though they have renounced any resort to attack. The argument that endurance is the primary act of courage should not be taken to imply a depreciation of daring, as though Aquinas was subtly advancing the Christian ideal of nonviolence (exemplified by the martyrs), as a normative substitute for just war and other forms of licit violence. That he did not intend to exclude daring from the virtues is made abundantly clear in question 127, article 1 of the Secunda Secundae ("whether daring denotes a sin") where he quite emphatically agrees (ad 1-3) with each of the objections that assert the praiseworthiness of this disposition. Moreover, Aquinas takes care to show how even the martyrs, who have renounced resort to violence, nonetheless cultivate dispositions analogous to daring. Possessed of magnanimity and magnificence, the "enterprising virtues," they willingly take bold risks, including confrontations with evil, in pursuance of the good. 60 IV. PREPAREDNESS FOR ATIACK Fortitude is supported in performing its office by several subordinate dispositions, which Aquinas terms "integral parts" of the virtue, or "things the concurrence of which are requisite" 61 for its full actuation. These dispositions are briefly discussed according to the support each gives to the two acts characteristic 60 See STh 11-11, q. 128, a. 1, ad 3: "To venture on anything great seems to involve danger, since to fail in such things is very disastrous." The expression "enterprising virtues" is from Labourdette, Force et temperance, 24-26. 61 STh 11-11, q. 128, a. un. 354 GREGORY M. REICHBERG of this virtue: attack and endurance. Regarding the first, a soldier will be inwardly prepared to mount an attack when he trusts the ability of himself 62 and his comrades to prevail over the adversary. This disposition of hope is strengthened by military exercises that foster the soldier's self-confidence in his fighting abilities, and that enhance the cohesiveness of the fighting unit of which he is a part. Virtuous soldiers will likewise evince a readiness to execute in full the noble action they have confidently begun (magnanimitas). The movement of attack (Aquinas remarks elsewhere against the Stoics) 63 is reinforced by the physiological changes arising from the passion of anger. 64 Aquinas would thus countenance a combat readiness that is reinforced by anger: "it belongs to anger to strike at the cause of sorrow [i.e., a wrong done against oneself or one's friends], so that it directly cooperates with fortitude in attacking. " 65 He cautions however that this anger must remain "moderate," in the sense that it is governed by reason, correctly identifying (and not merely imagining) an actual wrong. This teaching is well summarized in a parallel text 66 where Aquinas explains how the Stoics were mistaken when they assumed that anger, understood precisely as an emotional reaction (a passion), necessarily leads a man astray. This happens, he concedes, whenever the movement of anger is antecedent to reasoned judgment. But the Stoics failed to understand that anger can also be consequent upon reason. In this instance, the emotion does not impede, but rather fortifies the action that flows from correct practical judgment. By thus assuring a prompt and efficacious execution of rational decision, the passion of anger, with its attendant physiological changes, serves as an instrument of virtue. 62 See ibid., ad 2, where apropos the confidence which is a part of fortitude Aquinas notes how this proceeds from "hope in self [spem in seipso], albeit under God." 63 STh II-II, q. 123, a. 10. 64 STh I-II, q. 48, a. 2: "[A]nger consists not in recoil, which corresponds to the action of cold, but in prosecution, which corresponds to the action of heat; hence from anger there results fervor of the blood and vital spirits around the heart." 65 STh II-II, q. 123, a. 10, ad 3. 66 De Malo, q. 12, a. 1. AQUINAS ON BATTLEFIELD COURAGE 355 Anger calls for virtuous exercise in two quite different ways, according as it requires (1) an objective judgment on the nature and degree of punishment due, and (2) an appropriate emotive stance vis-a-vis the person of the offender. 67 In line with the first, the judgment in question will be regulated either by (a) commutative justice, when it is imposed by public authority in accordance with the relevant legal statute; 68 or (b) by the virtue named vindicatio (vengeance), 69 when the judgment is rendered by a private individual in accordance with a correct moral assessment of the wrong done. But beyond this concern with the measure of retribution due, according to (2) the virtue also assures an upright attitude of the avenger vis-a-vis the person who did him wrong. Clemency prompts compassion for his sinful condition and concern for his spiritual betterment, while mansuetude moderates the pleasure taken in seeing him justly suffer for his misdeeds. 70 Although the function of virtuous anger is to penalize wrongdoing, it never aims purely and simply at harming the evildoer, who, despite his offense, remains a worthy target of charitable concern. 71 Aquinas does not explicitly draw out the implications of this teaching for the ethics of war, but it certainly provides a remote foundation for the insight, embodied in modern laws of war, that enemy combatants should never be treated with hatred and cruelty, even when we are convinced that they fight at the service of a patently unjust cause. Despite Aquinas's strong show of interest in problems related to anger and punishment, it must be noted that, apart from his brief mention of anger in the context of courage (STh 11-11, q. 123, a. 10), he nowhere dwells expressly on this affect in relation specifically to war. The Dominican master's silence in this 67 Labourdette provides a systematic overview of Aquinas's teaching on the virtuous dispositions related to anger (Force et temperance, 81-84). 68 See for instance the treatment of capital punishment in STh II-II, q. 64, aa. 2-3, and of incarceration in II-II, q. 65, a. 3. 69 STh II-II, q. 108. 70 STh II-II, q. 157. See also the discussion of the opposing sin cruelty (II-II, q. 159). 71 See De Malo, q. 12, a. 1. 356 GREGORY M. REICHBERG connection should give us pause: one must be careful not to overstate the centrality of punishment in reconstructing his general theory of just war. 72 V. PREPAREDNESS FOR ENDURANCE Turning to endurance, the other act essential to courage, Aquinas explains how it is supported by four auxiliary dispositions-patience, perseverance, longanimity, and constancy.73This multiplicity is a reflection of the special difficulties inherent in endurance. While virtuous attack is supported by underlying passions-the impulse of aggression and the restraining influence of fear-virtuous endurance benefits little from our sentient nature. Moreover, endurance must contend not only with sufferings that are still future, but also with those that have already begun. Aquinas identifies the obstacles to endurance as four in kind, and to each there corresponds a disposition enabling the agent to mount a firm response. 74 The first and most basic obstacle to endurance is sorrow, the passion that arises in the sensitive appetite from a corrosive evil that is actually present. This harm may afflict the body, giving rise to "outward pain," or it may impact the mind, thus resulting in "inward pain." 75 In either case the obstacle is overcome by patience, the virtue by which we hold fast to an arduous good. But suffering need not be momentary; it can also stretch out in time. When an agent perceives his suffering as renewable, a foretaste of still more to come, his will to hold out erodes. This obstacle is overcome by perseverance, the virtue by which we persist in activity that promotes the good. 72 This has been well noted by Haggenmacher, Grotius et la doctrine de la guerre juste, 124. 73 In his overview of "the parts of fortitude" in STh II-II, q. 128, a. 1, Aquinas lists only patience and perseverance as dispositions supporting endurance. Later, in II-II, q. 136, a. 5, he adds longanimity to the list, and finally, in II-II, q. 127, a. 3, he includes constancy. 74 My account here benefits from Labourdette's careful analysis of endurance and its supporting virtues in Force et temperance, 40-47. 75 STh I-II, q. 35, a. 7. AQUINAS ON BATTLEFIELD COURAGE 357 When suffering is present, and renewable, the desired good-the object of one's hope and the reason for endurancecan appear to be far off in the future. Discouragement follows. This obstacle is overcome by longanimity, the virtue by which we know how to wait, holding out for the accomplishment of a future good. When endurance continues over a long time, new and unfamiliar evils often supervene, aggravating the weight of those already present. This obstacle is overcome by constancy, the virtue by which we keep loyal to our path, despite the unexpected obstacles arising on the way. This fourfold distinction of challenges and corresponding dispositions rests on a dialectic of the passions. Courage, we have seen, is concerned first and foremost with regulating fear. Yet rarely does fear operate in isolation from its kindred passion, sorrow. It often happens that evils anticipated (feared) become present (causing pain), giving rise, in turn, to the anticipation of still more pain, thereby intensifying the fear. The courageous man must accordingly know how to handle sorrow, not by expunging it altogether, but by guarding against an immersion so intense that it hinders the use of reason. 76 Courage likewise feeds upon hope-"a movement of the appetitive power ensuing from cognition of a future good, difficult but possible to attain" 77-and through longanimity it guards against the opposing passions of discouragement and despair. Ultimately, however, courage depends upon the root passion, love. 78 Only attachment to some good perceived as primordial can explain why other goods-including bodily integrity and even life itself-can willingly be put at risk: "the good for the sake of which one is willing to endure evils, is more desired and loved than the good the privation of which causes the sorrow that we bear patiently." 79 Why love of the temporal city might warrant such a sacrifice will be addressed in the next section. STh II-II, q. 136, a. 5. STh I-II, q. 40, a. 2. 78 See STh I-II, q. 26, a. 2. 79 STh II-II, q. 136, a. 3. 76 77 358 GREGORY M. REICHBERG Aquinas says little explicitly about the battlefield in his discussion of virtuous endurance. That he intends his account to apply to the military setting is however suggested by two comments. First, to the objection that patience is incompatible with the conduct expected of a warrior, since the brave man does not endure evils patiently but instead goes on the attack, Aquinas responds that "it is not contrary to the proper understanding of patience that someone should rise up against those who do evil, when this is required of him. " 80 The other passage even more explicitly links endurance with soldierly conduct on the battlefield. Discussing perseverance, Aquinas notes how, like every other virtue, it is a habit that directs us to do something well. Doing well can take on two forms. Sometimes it relates to the end of life as a whole (finis humanae vitae), as when Christians are expected to persevere in the faith every single day, up until the moment of death. In addition, they are called to complete tasks of more limited duration, in which case the perseverance is ordered to a temporally specified good work (finis operis). Thus "a soldier," Aquinas writes, is virtuous when he "perseveres to the conclusion of the battle." 81 It might seem that Aquinas's distinction between the end of the work and the end of human life is identical with the contrast he draws earlier 82 between art and prudence. If this were the case, a soldier's virtuous perseverance unto death would describe a morally neutral act, after the fashion of a work produced by art, such that his ability to hold firm on the battlefield could in fact be ordered to a good or to a bad end. But at this juncture Aquinas is in fact making a rather different point. His intent is to establish a division within the genus of complete virtue. Some virtues, termed "principal" are exercised throughout the whole of life; chief among them are faith, hope, and charity. Other virtues are of a conditional character, being exercised only when the requisite occasions arise-although the disposition to perform such acts should be permanently with us. Magnificence, the right use of q. 136, a. 4, ad 3. STh II-II, q. 137, a. 1, ad 2. 82 See in particular STh II-II, q. 47, a. 4, ad 2. 80 STh II-II, 81 AQUINAS ON BATTLEFIELD COURAGE 359 great wealth, is mentioned in this connection alongside battlefield perseverance. Aquinas clearly intends to affirm that these "secondary" virtues are full-fledged moral dispositions; they presuppose rectitude of the will, and are connected with the other moral virtues. Apart from these two comments, Aquinas does not elaborate on the special modalities of battlefield endurance. Had he explored this domain in greater detail he would have found much to say about the peculiar effects of fear on the psyche of soldiers in battle. The effects of sorrow, likewise, would have opened up a large vista for exploration. He certainly would have made use of the distinction, mentioned above, between the suffering occasioned by physical harm to oneself, and the inner pain, in some measure even more intense, 83 occasioned by the psychological impact of seeing others suffer. True enough, virtuous warriors would not be burdened by the recollection of their own misdeeds-having abstained from improper conduct in war. 84 But they would sorrow at the harm suffered, not only by their comrades in arms, but even by enemy combatants, with whom they remain united as fellow children of God. Above all, they would sorrow at the harm inflicted on bystanders to war, who by no fault of their own are pressed into the line of fire. This sorrow will be most acute when the virtuous warrior recognizes his own role in causing this harm, not intentionally of course-as this would be morally reprehensible-but as a side-effect, whether accidental or foreseeable, of proportionate military action. 85 On the greater intensity of inner, psychological pain, see STh I-II, q. 35, a. 7. Naturally, those who act wrongly in war should appropriately experience the sorrow of shame, and seek repentance for what they have done or failed to do. See STh I-II, q. 35, a. 8, on the various species of sorrow, and ibid., ad 2 on repentance. In this article Aquinas expressly discusses the sorrow that rightly arises in us when we witness the suffering of others; this sorrow he terms "mercy" (misericordia). 85 For an application of Aquinas's teaching on side-effect harm to the military sphere, see Gregory M. Reichberg and Henrik Syse "The Idea of Double Effect-In War and Business," in Responsibility in World Business: Managing Harmful Side-Effects of Corporate Activity," ed. Lene Bomann-Larsen and Oddny Wiggen (Tokyo: United Nations University Press, 2004), 1738. 83 84 360 GREGORY M. REICHBERG Aquinas's doctrine of just war thus does not entail a stance of insensitivity vis-a-vis the horrors unleashed by war. To the contrary, "[i]t is a sign of moral goodness," he writes, "when a man sorrows on account of an evil that is actually present; for should he fail to experience sorrow or pain, this could be only because he feels it not, or does not deem it repugnant; both [attitudes] are manifest evils. " 86 VI. DYING FOR ONE'S COUNTRY Courage is called for whenever the risk of serious bodily harm or death is consciously assumed in pursuit of a worthy good. Falling outside the scope of this virtue are situations in which such risks are incurred unwittingly, 87 for reasons incommensurate with the potential harm, or for ends incompatible with moral goodness. Moreover, the possessor of courage will recognize that the risks in question represent real and not merely illusory evils. "Of all the goods of the present life, man loves life itself most, and consequently he hates death more than anything, especially when it is accompanied by pains of bodily torment. " 88 Aquinas thereby acknowledges the evilness of death even though he simultaneously holds that the human soul, by reason of its immateriality, necessarily continues in existence after its separation from the body. The two assertions are compatible because on his understanding body and soul enjoy much more than an accidental union. The soul is, in his words, "naturally united to the body, for in its essence it is the form of the body." 89 He is thus able to conclude, quite emphatically, that "it is contrary to the nature of the soul to be without the body. " 90 This metaphysical truth leaves a trace in human consciousness, since we spontaneously anticipate STh I-II, q. 39, a. 1. Death arising from illness, storms at sea, or the attacks of robbers, are cited by Aquinas as kinds of risk not directly assumed in connection with the pursuit of an inherent good (STh 11-11, q. 123, a. 5). 88 STh 11-11, q. 124, a. 3. 89 ScG IV, c. 79. ' 0 Ibid. 86 87 AQUINAS ON BATTLEFIELD COURAGE 361 death with dread; we assume, instinctively, that it is a form of violence. Death for us is accordingly an unnatural state that cries out for a remedy. Aquinas would accordingly take issue with accounts of courage that trivialize death, as were expressed, for instance, during the 1930s by exponents of militant ("imperialway") Zen Buddhism. 91 Aquinas adheres to Christian teaching in maintaining that a remedy for death is found in the resurrection of Christ. By the divine efficacy of his rising, we too, after dying, will recover our bodies, though in our case this happens not immediately but at the end of time. On this premise-which Aquinas connects with the related doctrine of the separated soul's enjoyment of the beatific vision immediately after death-it is understandable how some might be willing to undergo a martyr's death, witnessing to their love of God and in hope of a future bliss with him. But, prima facie, it would seem that no such premise comes to the support of civic courage. Why should soldiers be willing to give their all if the temporal city is in no way able to return the favor? Aquinas responds to this query with two different lines of argument, one of which places the soldier's death under the category of martyrdom, while the other focuses on the special character of acquired courage. The first line of argument is framed as a response to an objection which holds that fallen soldiers do not merit the heavenly reward of martyrs. 92 While acknowledging with Aristotle that the common good of the nation (gentes) is indeed higher than private good of the individual, and likewise that service to one's country in a just war bears an inherent value, the objection asserts nonetheless that only those who have suffered a violent death in witness to God, the uncreated good, can be venerated in the 91 "I believe that if one is called upon to die, one should not be the least bit agitated. On the contrary, one should be in a realm where something called 'oneself' does not even intrude slightly. Such a realm is no different from the practice of Zen." This passage, quoted in Brian Daizen Victoria, Zen at War (Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield, 2006), 103, is taken from an article published in 1937 by a Zen priest, Ishihara Shummyo, who sought to explain why Zen Buddhism could make a vital contribution to the development of a martial spirit in Japan. 92 STh II-II, q. 124, a. 5, ad 3. 362 GREGORY M. REICHBERG Church as martyrs. Tacitly agreeing with this conclusion, in his response Aquinas notes however that any human good-including presumably a willingness to die in a just war defending one's homeland 93 -can become a cause of martyrdom if it is sought for a divine end. 94 No example is given in this passage from the Secunda Secundae. But in his youthful commentary on the Sentences of Peter Lombard, Aquinas gives a more elaborate explanation for this same point: 95 When a person dies for the common good, but does not relate this to Christ, he will not merit the aureole [of a martyr]. But should this be referred to Christ he will merit the aureole and will be a martyr, as happens, for instance, when against the attack of an enemy who seeks to corrupt the faith of Christ, someone defends his country, suffering death as a consequence. Two different scenarios are entertained in this text. On the one hand, someone can willingly die for his country, taken precisely as the highest of all temporal goods, yet prescinding from any ulterior ordination to the transcendent divine good. This may very with the faith and well be a virtuous death-compatible charity-but it falls short of the special honor signified by the ecclesial title "martyr," since in this instance death is undergone for a temporal, not a transcendent end. On the other hand, one's country can bear reference to a transcendent end insofar as the temporal common good includes the public practice of religion. By thus protecting the worship of God from those who would violently impede it, armed defense assumes a religious character. "Christ's faithful frequently go to war [bellum movent] against unbelievers," Aquinas writes, "not indeed for the purpose of forcing them to believe ... but to prevent them from hindering The reply does not refer to dying in a just war; but since this was the very example given in the objection, we can safely assume that military martyrdom is the implied referent in ad 3. 94 STh 11-11, q. 124, a. 2, ad 1: "Martyrdom is related to faith as the end in which one is strengthened"; cf. ibid.,ad 2: "charity inclines one to martyrdom as its first motive cause." 95 IV Sent., d. 49, q. 5, a. 3, qcla. 2; reproduced in STh Suppl., q. 96, a. 6, ad 11. The corresponding objection contains what is most likely the very first mention of helium iustum in Aquinas's corpus of writings. 93 AQUINAS ON BATTLEFIELD COURAGE 363 the faith of Christ." 96 Should one die in the process, this death will count as martyrdom. It is in this manner that Aquinas describes the military efforts of those religious orders-for instance, the Knights Templar-that had assumed arms to defend the Holy Land. 97 To underscore how military martyrdom involves ordination to transtemporal spiritual goods, Aquinas states that it is the fruit not of civic, but of infused virtue. 98 In thus allowing for military martyrdom, Aquinas seems to have contradicted his other claim, discussed above, that the martyr's courage, consisting as it does solely in endurance, excludes a stance of attack. 99 On this basis the very notion of a "military martyrdom" (a term admittedly not employed by Aquinas himself) would seem to be an oxymoron. This problem is not addressed by Aquinas directly, perhaps because he assumed that military martyrdom would apply only to soldiers who die in a purely defensive posture, such as those who are captured and executed, or who are otherwise unable to mount a forcible resistance. 100 Thomas's older brother Renaud, a knight in the service of pope Innocent IV, underwent a death of this sort. 101 96 STh II-II, q. 10, a. 8. Konyndyk de Young ("Power Made Perfect in Weakness") overlooks this and related passages when she writes that "Aquinas never mentions the possibility of an act of aggression being ordered to a divine good" (167 n. 88). 97 See STh II-II, q. 188, a. 3, ad 3 ("ut militant in subsidium Terra Sanctae"). 98 IV Sent., d. 49, q. 5, a. 3, qcla. 2 (reproduced in STh Suppl., q. 96, a. 6, ad 9). Concerning the infused virtues, see STh I-II, q. 51, a. 4, where Aquinas explains how "these are habits by which a person is disposed to an end which exceeds the proportion of human nature." 99 The exclusion of attack from the sphere of martyrdom is clearly stated in STh II-II, q. 124, a. 2, ad 3. And only three short articles later (II-II, q. 124, a. 5, ad 3), Aquinas posits a form of military martyrdom. 100 Jacques Maritain alludes to such a death, passively sustained on the battlefield, "the sustinere of one who offers his body to immediate death," apropos his friend Ernest Psichari, who died in the First World War (Freedom in the Modern World, in The Collected Works of Jacques Maritain, vol. 11 [Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1996], 92-93 n. 14). This essay contains nuanced discussion of the two acts of courage, endurance and attack. 101 Renaud had originally been in the service of the emperor, but after Frederick II was deposed by Innocent IV, Renaud joined the pope's army. Renauld was executed after being captured by Frederick's troops. See Jean-Pierre Torrell, Initiation a saint Thomas d'Aquin (Fribourg, Switzerland: Editions Universitaires, 1993), 4-5, who notes how Thomas's family considered Renaud a martyr for the Church. Thomas seems to have believed this himself, as he was persuaded that Renaud's execution was gravely unjust, and furthermore he had had 364 GREGORY M. REICHBERG Thus, even if Aquinas did allow for military martyrdom of this limited sort, he would not employ this expression to designate a willing acceptance of death by someone initiating an attack-even under the hypothesis that the attack was mounted for a religious purpose and in due observance of noncombatant immunity and other fundamental norms of war. "Martyrdom-seeking operations," as the term is used in some Islamic writings today, would thus not find acceptance within Aquinas's more restrictive frame of discourse. Alongside military martyrdom-whereby death is willingly undergone for a religious purpose-Aquinas acknowledges that courage may also be exercised directly for the common good of the temporal city. His most explicit treatment of this theme appears in his commentary on Matthew 5: 3 9, "do not resist evil," where he reasons that the individual person stands in relation to the common good of his polity (respublica), as does a part to a whole. However, unlike the parallel passages where the partswhole formula is advanced as justification for capital and other forms of corporeal punishment, 102 in the present case it is employed to explain why an individual might voluntarily risk his life for the welfare of the body politic. After noting that we instinctively recoil at the approach of harm, Aquinas observes that we are nevertheless naturally inclined to expose ourselves individually to harm so as to protect the whole from a harm even greater, for every part naturally loves the whole more than itself. Just as a man would permit his diseased limb to be severed in order to save his life, by extension he would be naturally inclined to sustain evil when necessary for the public good. This willingness to confront danger pertains to fortitude and related political virtues. 103 And from the related assertion that "each man, a dream in which his sister, recently deceased, told him that their brother was among the elect in heaven. 102 For instance STh II-II, q. 62, a. 2; and II-II, q. 65, a. 1. 103 For the Latin text of this passage, see J.-P. Renard, ed., "La Lectura super Matthaeum V, 20--48 de Thomas d'Aquin (Edition d'apres le ms. Bale, Univ. Bibi. B. V. 12)," Recherches de theologie ancienne et medievale 50 (1983): 145-90: "[D]icendum quod naturalis inclinatio est quod quelibit res exponat se ad proprium detrimentum ut uitet detrimentum comune, sicut man us exponit se periculo propter corpus et quelibet pars pro suo toto. Vnde natural est quod AQUINAS ON BATTLEFIELD COURAGE 365 in all that he is and has belongs to the community," 104 Aquinas makes clear the confrontation with evil can require of us even the ultimate sacrifice, death. The parts-whole analogy is of limited applicability, however. Human beings-having God for ultimate end-possess an intrinsic value that cannot be reduced to the service they might render to the temporal common good. Counterbalancing his affirmation that "each individual person is related to the entire community as the part to the whole," 105 Aquinas also writes that "man is not ordained to the political community according to all that he is and has." 106 While we can be called on to sacrifice our corporeal existence for this whole, this mode of our being does not exhaust all that is in us, certainly not the full dimensions of our soul. In this vein, Aquinas explains how the brave man, who risks death for the good of the city, does so also out of a love of his own virtue and perfection. The loss of one's body can willingly be sustained because it is subordinate to the soul's exercise of virtue. The body is loved both because it is a natural good and also because of its instrumentality in performing acts of virtue. When a worthy cause is at stake, the second rationale takes precedence over the former. Subordinating the one to the other is in line with our human self-love: the body exists for the higher good of the soul, and the soul itself comes to perfection through exercise of the virtues, including courage. Paradoxically, then, the brave person's confrontation with death can be a source of delight. 107 Taken in itself, death is an evil and the prospect of dying naturally fills us with dread (an admixture of sorrow and fear). Yet courageous acts are nonetheless pleasurable, insofar as they are an expression of virtue homo sustineat malum pro bono rei publice et ad hoc pertinent uirtus pollitica sicut fortitude et huiusmodi" (179, II. 736-43). 104 STh I-II, q. 96, a. 4. 105 STh II-II, q. 64, a. 2. 106 STh I-II, q. 21, a. 4, ad 3. On the compatibility of Aquinas's two assertions, see Jacques Maritain, The Person and the Common Good, trans. J. J. Fitzgerald (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1947), 70-76. 107 STh II-II, q. 123, a. 8, ad 3: "In the brave man spiritual sorrow is overcome by the pleasure of virtue." 366 GREGORY M. REICHBERG whereby the soul finds its natural completion. Enabling its possessor to remain steadfast in the good despite the presence of evil, while contemplating the triumph of good in the future, courage brings with it a distinctive pleasure, a sense of accomplishment at dying in a moment of excellence and for a great purpose. 108 Aquinas does however add an important caveat to this reasoning. Only when sorrow takes the form of a spiritual affect can courage stand a reasonable chance of prevailing over it, for in this case one spiritual affect-the pleasure arising from awareness of oneself as the performer of a virtuous deed-overcomes the other affect that is formally speaking its contrary-the sorrow that arises from the mental perception of imminent death. But if physical pain supervenes there will be no contrary affect to chase the attendant sorrow away. And should this pain be intense, the spiritual pleasure of virtue cannot be sustained. On this basis, Aquinas concludes that the habit of acquired fortitude is more effective in enabling a person to hold fast in the face of death than in resisting acute bodily pain. By contrast, infused fortitude is effective even in the latter respect, since "by a copious assistance of God's grace," enabling the martyr to "delight in divine things," 109 the pleasure of virtue is reinforced to the point where it can overcome extreme corporeal pain. In the preceding analysis of military courage, we have focused on situations where there is a risk, but not a certainty, of death. Soldiers going into battle know they may die, yet they typically carry with them a hope of survival. Military annals do however tell of self-sacrificing missions that are undertaken with little or no hope of survival, such as the kamikaze bombing raids of World War IL 110 Did Aquinas envision these self-sacrificing missions within his treatment of acquired courage? 108 STh II-II, q. 123, a. 8: "The brave man ... [experiences] spiritual pleasure, namely in the act itself of virtue and the end thereof." 109 Ibid. 110 See the essays in Diego Gambetta, ed., Making Sense of Suicide Missions (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005). AQUINAS ON BATTLEFIELD COURAGE 367 The question is addressed obliquely apropos of the biblical figure Samson Qudg 16). Taken prisoner by the Philistines, who tied him to a temple column, and after invoking God to regain his strength, Samson managed to pull down the column, collapsing the temple, killing three thousand of his enemies who were celebrating his capture on the roof above. In this manner he knowingly went to his own death in order to fulfill a mission of revenge. Was Samson's action condemnable on moral grounds as a suicide? This is the question posed by Aquinas (STh 11-11, q. 64, a. 5, ad 4). Setting up a contrast with Razias (2 Mace 14:42), who unjustifiably killed himself in order to avoid capture ("this was not true fortitude but rather weakness of soul unable to bear penal evils" [ibid., ad 5]), he quotes Augustine (De civitate Dei 1.26) to the effect that Samson's act was allowable because it resulted from an inner prompting of the Holy Spirit. No further explanation is given, although the point is reinforced by a parallel drawn to the case of the holy virgins [of Aquileia], celebrated by the Church, who took their own lives to avoid rape. Acknowledging the praise of St. Paul (Heb 11:32), who numbered Samson among the elect, Aquinas understands his fortitude to be an expression of infused virtue, whereby the ordinary rules prohibiting suicide could be lifted due to a special dispensation of God, the Master of life and death. 111 Significantly, however, a supplementary explanation was advanced by Aquinas's commentator Vitoria. 112 Samson's act cannot be described as a suicide, precisely because he never intended to take his own life; rather, he wished to kill his enemies, in the wake of which his own death followed as a foreseeable side-effect. Citing the related story of Eleazar (1 Mace 6:43-47), who was crushed after stabbing the underbelly of an elephant in order to bring down the enemy commander, whom he 111 In the next article (STh 11-11, q. 64, a. 6), Aquinas likewise states that an innocent person may be put to death (despite the strict prohibition against the same) if such has been commanded by God (with reference to the story of Abraham's call to sacrifice his son Isaac). 112 See Francisco de Vitoria, On Homicide & Commentary on Summa theologiae Ila-Ilae Q. 64 (Thomas Aquinas), trans. with an introduction and notes by Joseph P. Doyle (Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1997), 107 and 183-85. 368 GREGORY M. REICHBERG believed was sitting above, Vitoria applies double-effect reasoning in order to demonstrate how even without divine inspiration the actions of Eleazar, and by extension Samson, were conceivably licit: "for who doubts that someone in a battle, or defending a city, would undertake an action for the welfare of his homeland and for the great detriment of its enemies, even though it would involve his own certain death?" 113 To this question Vitoria emphatically responds in the affirmative, concluding that "Eleazar and ... anyone else who has killed himself [unintentionally yet foreseeably] for the republic ... should be excused. " 114 Vitoria's reasoning seems compatible with Aquinas's principles, but why the latter did not propose it himself cannot readily be ascertained. CONCLUSION Despite the marginal place battlefield courage occupies vis-avis the chief purpose of the Secunda Pars-how human beings advance toward union with God-Aquinas does accord it a special role within his typology of the virtues. This role is of a piece with his conviction that the temporal common good, while not constituting the ultimate goal for human beings, is still an inherent good that merits the formation of the relevant moral virtues, among them military courage. In this connection, he demonstrates an awareness of the distinctive moral challenges of the military life, a setting wherein its participants struggle to find the mean of virtue amid the darker passions-fear, aggression, sorrow, and anger. By situating just war in this emotive context, Aquinas balances out the more principled approach of the question "De hello" (STh 11-11, q. 40) and in so doing he provides a virtueethical blueprint for the revival of just war thought in our own day. Vitoria, On Homicide, p. 107. Commentary on Summa theologiae IIa-IIae Q. 64 [a. 5], p. 185. Maritain, likewise, argues that these "special missions" can be licit, provided they are carried out by volunteers (The Person and the Common Good, 68-69). 113 114 Vitoria, The Thomist 74 (2010): 369-405 THEOLOGICAL FAITH ENLIGHTENING SACRED THEOLOGY: RENEWING THEOLOGY BY RECOVERING ITS UNITY AS SACRA DOCTRINA 1 REINHARD HOTTER Duke University Divinity School Durham, North Carolina Es ist mit der Wissenschaft iiber Gott die Gefahr verbunden, daR sie unser tiefstes Innere Gott entfremde, anstatt es Ihm zu niihern. 2 Ceslaus Maria Schneider Nihil est pauperius et miserius mente quae caret Deo et de Deo philosophatur et disputat. 3 John Climacus T HE FOLLOWING considerations arise from an indisputable, albeit regrettable fact: the pervasive fragmentation of contemporary Catholic theology and the consequent urgent need of renewal. Such renewal will have to come about by way of recovering theology's inner unity. And the latter requires nothing less than allowing theology's soul- supernatural, divine faith-to inform again the whole body of theology. The authority of America's foremost Catholic theologian, the late Avery 1 An earlier version of this essay was presented on 17 October 2009, at the first "Thomistic Circles" Conference on "Thomism and the Renewal of Theology" at the new Academic Center of the Dominican House of Studies, Washington, D.C. 2 "The science of God is accompanied by the danger that its pursuit estranges our innermost self from God instead of bringing it closer to Him." 3 "There is nothing more miserable and desolate than a mind bereft of God that speaks of and philosophizes about God." 369 370 REINHARD HUTTER Cardinal Dulles, S.J., shall suffice as a warrant for the way I characterize the present state of Catholic theology. In his important essay, "Wisdom as the Source of Unity for Theology," published shortly before his death, he observes: Over the past fifty years we have all heard the repeated complaint, amounting sometimes to a lamentation, that theology has lost its unity. Like Humpty Dumpty it has suffered a great fall, and all the pope's theologians have not succeeded in putting it together again. Theology is splintered into subdisciplines that insist on their own autonomy without regard for one another. Biblical studies go in one direction, historical scholarship goes in another, ethics in a third, and spirituality in a fourth. In addition to this fragmentation of disciplines, there is a growing breach between past and present. The classic statements of the faith are studied historically, in relation to the circumstances in which they arose. If their contemporary relevance is not denied, they are reinterpreted for today in ways that preserve little if anything of their original content. The Magisterium, which has traditionally been the guardian of theological orthodoxy, is simply ignored by some theologians and bitterly criticized by others. Dogmatic theology, which seeks to ground itself in official Catholic teaching, is shunned as being servile and unprogressive .... Each theologian is expected to be creative and is encouraged to say something novel and surprising. A theologian who reaffirms the tradition and fails to challenge the received doctrine is considered timid and retrograde. 4 Cardinal Dulles' analysis is true in every respect. Furthermore, his constructive proposal is as salient as it is salutary in retrieving Thomas's three kinds of wisdom as the source of unity for theology: philosophical wisdom, theological wisdom, and infused wisdom. While philosophical wisdom arises from the natural capacity of the human intellect to investigate the structures of reality, infused wisdom, the immediate gift of the Holy Spirit, enables the believer to form right judgments by means of a divinely given connaturality. Theological wisdom, finally, considers all reality in light of revelation and is thus constitutive 4 Avery Cardinal Dulles, S.J., "Wisdom as the Source of Unity in Theology," in Michael Dauphinais and Matthew Levering, eds., Wisdom and Holiness, Science and Scholarship: Essays in Honor of Matthew L. Lamb (Naples, Fl.: Sapientia Press, 2007), 59-71, at 59£. FAITH ENLIGHTENING SACRED THEOLOGY 371 of theology as sacra doctrina. 5 In the following, I wish to build upon Dulles's proposal by expanding it in one important regard: the crucial connection between theological wisdom and the infused, supernatural virtue of faith. Such an attempt is not as farfetched as it might at first seem. The most recent magisterial teaching-Pope Benedict XVI's encyclical Spe salvi-encourages a genuine recovery of the supernatural character of the faith. By drawing out the implications of such a recovery for Catholic theology as a unified sapiential theology, the internal unity of which arises from its essential correlation to supernatural faith, I intend to receive this magisterial teaching as an impulse for a genuinely Thomist contribution to the renewal of contemporary Catholic theology. It is worthwhile to quote at length the pertinent passage from Spe salvi: In the eleventh chapter of the Letter to the Hebrews (v. 1) we find a kind of definition of faith which closely links this virtue with hope .... "Faith is the hypostasis of things hoped for; the proof of things not seen." For the Fathers and for the theologians of the Middle Ages, it was clear that the Greek word hypostasis was to be rendered in Latin with the term substantia. The Latin translation of the text produced at the time of the early Church therefore reads: Est autem {ides sperandarum substantia rerum, argumentum non apparentium-faith is the "substance" of things hoped for; the proof of things not seen. Saint Thomas Aquinas, using the terminology of the philosophical tradition to which he belonged, explains it as follows: faith is a habitus, that is, a stable disposition of the spirit, through which eternal life takes root in us and reason is led to consent to what it does not see .... [T]hrough faith, in a tentative way, or as we might say "in embryo"-and thus according to the "substance"-there are already present in us the things that are hoped for: a whole, true life. And precisely because the thing itself is already present, this 5 Thomas never discusses the three kinds of wisdom together in one single place of his vast oeuvre. For a discussion of philosophical wisdom, see IMetaph., lect. 1-2; for a discussion of theological wisdom, see STh I, q. 1, a. 6; and for a discussion of infused wisdom, see STh II-II, q. 45. In the twentieth century, French Thomists took Thomas's teaching on the three kinds of wisdom to offer the best possible access to the intricate interplay of sacred theology and metaphysics in Thomas's thought. See Reginald Garrigou-Lagrange, O.P., Le sens du mystere et le clair-obscur intellectual: Nature et surnaturel (Paris: Desclee de Brouwer, 1934); and Marie-Dominique Philippe, Les trois sagesses: Entretiens avec Frederic Lenoir (Paris: Fayard, 1994). 372 REINHARD HUrrER presence of what is to come also creates certainty: this "thing" which must come is not yet visible in the external world (it does not "appear"), but because of the fact that, as an initial and dynamic reality, we carry it within us, a certain perception of it has even now come into existence .... Faith is not merely a personal reaching out towards things to come that are still totally absent: it gives us something. It gives us even now something of the reality we are waiting for, and this present reality constitutes for us a "proof" of the things that are still unseen. Faith draws the future into the present, so that it is no longer simply a "not yet." (§7)6 In this crucial passage, the source for the renewal of contemporary Catholic theology is as plainly stated as is the name of the doctor communis who in his theology offers the very resources for such a renewal. To put the encyclical's teaching on faith into Thomas's somewhat more technical language: Faith is an infused habitus, that is, a stable supernatural disposition of the human spirit, indeed, the effect of the "new being" of sanctifying grace in believers, through which eternal life takes root in us such that reason is led to assent to what it does not see, and in consequence of which the human person is enabled to attain the transcendent God who is the First Truth.7 It is this attaining of the transcendent God who is the First Truth that makes supernatural faith "theological" in the proper sense of the word. For in virtue of the infused habitus of faith, "'in embryo'-and thus according to the 'substance' -there are already present in us the things that are hoped for: a whole, true life." This is what the Thomist tradition calls the "theological life," "la vie theologale. " 8 When Catholic theology becomes again intrinsically ordered to and informed by the supernatural dynamic and content of theological faith, it will recover its unity as sacra doctrina and thereby will undergo a salutary renewal. In this regard, I would like to submit, Thomism-which constantly teaches the essential correlation between theological faith and the sapiential character 6 This as well as all further quotations from Spe salvi are taken from the Vatican website: http://www. vatican. va/hol y _fa ther/benedict _xvi/ encyclicals/documents/hf_ benxvi_enc_ 20071130 _spe-salvi_en.html (accessed 12 May 2010). 7 STh 11-11, q. 4, a. 1. 8 See M.-M. Labourdette, O.P., "La vie theologale selon saint Thomas," Revue Thomiste 58 (1958): 597-622. FAITH ENLIGHTENING SACRED THEOLOGY 373 of theology, between the simple understanding of faith and the discursive and contemplative operation of theological wisdom-is in an advantageous position to make a salient contribution to such a contemporary renewal of Catholic theology. 9 In order to avoid the danger of vague and largely unsupported generalizations about contemporary Catholic theology, however, I shall build upon and advance Dulles's proposal by way of examining two paradigmatic sketches of the nature and task of Catholic theology. I shall first consider a programmatic postVatican II revision of the nature of Catholic dogmatic theology. The author is the already-then-noted German Catholic dogmatic theologian Walter Kasper, now cardinal and former president of the Pontifical Council for Promoting Christian Unity. Kasper's treatise originated in a lecture he presented at the first postconciliar Conference of German Dogmatic Theologians, which met in Munich, 2-5 January 1967. The German original was published the same year under the title "Die Methoden der Dogmatik-Einheit und Vielheit" ("The Methods of Dogmatic Theology-Unity and Plurality"). 10 In 1969 an English translation appeared, although its title omitted what is most indicative of 9 Instantiations of such Thomistic contributions to a renewal of Catholic theology indeed already exist. Arguably, one of chem is Jean-Herve Nicolas, O.P., Synthese dogmatique: De la Trinite a la Trinite (Fribourg: Editions Universitaires; Paris: Editions Beauchesne, 1985), with a preface by then Cardinal Joseph Ratzinger. Romanus Cessario, O.P., aptly characterizes Nicolas's magnum opus as taking the proper course between the reductive alternatives of theological rationalism and theological positivism: "Theology, after all, according to the Thomisc viewpoint, develops out of faith's seeking to deepen its understanding of revealed truth. Rationalism reduces theology to a purely human enterprise. Practitioners of chis kind of theology perceive themselves either as peers of secular professors in academic circles or the religious counterparts of other learned professions, like social work or psychology. Whatever are the merits of the science of religious studies, theology in service of the Church requires more than academic credentials to communicate a revealed doctrine. Theological positivism, on the other hand, which relies on authoritarian pronouncements to support Church doctrine, closes off the theological project by replacing demonstration with the weakest form of argument, authority. Its practitioners find satisfaction with repetition of what the Church teaches, but recoil from the hard work of making that teaching intelligible to contemporary hearers. Father Nicolas offers the theologian a model to avoid these unfortunate and disserviceable alternatives" ("Theology at Fribourg," The Thomist 51 [1987]: 325-66, at 339). 10 Walter Kasper, Die Methoden der Dogmatik-Einheit und Vielheit (Munich: Kosel, 1967). 374 REINHARD HUTTER Kasper's program: "Unity and Plurality. " 11 This elimination was unfortunate, because Kasper is quite explicitly concerned with recovering the inner unity of dogmatic theology and thereby contributing to the integration of all branches of Catholic theology. 12 In the foreword to his treatise, Kasper emphasizes that this work claims to be nothing more than "a preliminary probe." 13 Yet precisely because of its experimental and preliminary character, Kasper's opuscule represents an instructive and indeed paradigmatic example of what, in the years immediately following the Second Vatican Council, was widely regarded as an overdue fresh theological venture. 14 In a second step, I shall turn to an equally brief programmatic treatise, "The Work of Theology," 15 of the Spanish Dominican Francisco P. Muniz, who taught at the Angelicum in Rome. 11 Walter Kasper, The Methods of Dogmatic Theology, trans.John Drury (Glen Rock, N.J.: Paulist Press, 1969). 12 "There is a growing splintering of methods within one and the same discipline and by one and the same theologian. At one point the dogmatic theologian may utilize exegetical, historical and philosophical arguments; at another point he may adopt a pastoral, an anthropological, or a sociological approach. But if dogmatic theology is to avoid dilettantism, if it is to remain a scientific discipline, then it must look for the one dogmatic method" (Kasper, The Methods of Dogmatic Theology, lf.). Kasper's express goal of his treatise is "to arrive at a single, unified epistemological process that is proper to theology" (ibid., 21). 13 Ibid., vii. 14 I do not know how forty years later Cardinal Kasper would assess this brief work. (For a complete bibliography of Walter Cardinal Kasper's very impressive opera, see the Festschrift in honor of his seventy-fifth birthday, introduced with a personal salutation by Pope Benedict XVI, Gott denken und bezeugen, ed. George Augustine and Klaus Kramer [Freiburg: Herder, 2008].) While there are tangible influences of Kasper's important earlier scholarly work upon this treatise, in the following I will be unable to do full justice to the complex ways in which Kasper's opuscule depends on and departs from his doctoral dissertation on the concept of tradition in the nineteenth-century Roman school and his Tiibingen Habilitationsschrift on the philosophy and theology of history in the later period of Schelling's thought: Walter Kasper, Die Lehre von der Tradition in der Romischen Schule (Giovanni Perrone, Carlo Passaglia, Clemens Schrader), Die Uberlieferung in der neueren Theologie 5 (Freiburg: Herder, 1962); idem, Das Absolute in der Geschichte. Philosophie und Theologie der Geschichte in der Spiitphilosophie Schellings (Mainz: Grunewald, 1965). See also his important early essay, "Grundlinien einer Theologie der Geschichte," Theologische Quartalschrift 144 (1964): 129-69. 15 Francisco P. Muniz, O.P., The Work of Theology, trans. John P. Reid, O.P. (Washington, D.C.: The Thomist Press, 1953). FAITH ENLIGHTENING SACRED THEOLOGY 375 Translated by the American Dominican John Reid, Mufiiz's humbly titled "Work" was published in English in 1953, during those theologically and ecclesiastically complicated years leading up to the Second Vatican Council. Thus fifteen years before Kasper's treatise appeared in English and about ten years before the council, Mufiiz's preoccupation with the unity of theology, with theology as a proper whole (totum), and his creative use of Thomas's metaphysics of the totum potestativum, was made available to an English-speaking theological readership. One could hardly imagine two treatises on the renewal of Catholic theology more different in rhetorical posture, intellectual orientation, and theological patrimony. Each bears the traces of the particular intellectual moment in which it was conceived in the history of Catholic theology. Mufiiz's treatise embodies in an unencumbered way the conceptual rigor of Scholastic discourse, to which we have largely grown unaccustomed in the last fifty years. Kasper's treatise embraces in an equally unencumbered way the later Heidegger's consistent historicizing of being and Gadamer's version of a tradition-dependent universal hermeneutics, two philosophical interventions of undoubted importance that, however, forty years later-and especially outside of the confines of the German intellectual context-convey an indisputable datedness. Moreover, the all-too-conventional postVatican II hermeneutics of discontinuity, which is as superficial as it is erroneous, would most likely dismiss Muniz's approach as a typical instantiation of a static, unhistorical metaphysical and theological framework and embrace Kasper's program as a properly dynamic and historically sensitive stance. Among other things, I hope to show that such a contrastive reading of pre- and post-Vatican II accounts of the nature of theology misses the real issues at stake, robs itself of a most salutary theological patrimony, and does justice neither to Kasper nor to Muniz. In what follows, I examine what Kasper and Muniz have to say about (a) the nature and task of theology; (b) the nature of faith; (c) the relationship between faith and theology; (d) the impact of their variant understandings of the nature of faith on their 376 REINHARD HUTTER respective accounts of theology; and finally (e) whether and, if so, how each programmatic proposal can be received in light of Spe salvi's teaching on supernatural, divine faith. I Walter Kasper's Methods of Dogmatic Theology is divided into five sections: (I) "The Present Crisis," (II) "The Historical Background," (III) "Theology's Starting Point," (IV) "History and Theology," and (V) "The Goal of Methodology." In the first section, "The Present Crisis," Kasper characterizes the intellectual situation of the 1960s as a "crisis of faith" in which "the fundamental principles of faith itself and the possibility of saying anything about God" (1) 16 have been called into question. He understands Vatican II as addressing this critical situation with a call for "a new theology, a dogmatic methodology that was more biblically and pastorally oriented" (2). This new theology is to be fueled by "the new spirit which pervades [the Second Vatican Council's] statements and declarations. Dogmatic theology as a whole is presented as being more dynamic, more catholic, more oriented to this world and the future; moreover, in many respects, it is portrayed as something possessing less certainty than heretofore" (3 ). According to Kasper, there is an urgent need for such a new theology, for he sees a real crisis threatening the foundations of theology, a crisis caused primarily by rapidly accelerating new developments: "Justifiable criticism of the a-worldliness of theology in the past now threatens to drive us to the other extreme, to give rise to a secular theology which has no real tradition" (ibid.). In order to check the move to this extreme, Kasper explicitly recalls the traditional, sapiential understanding of theology: Theology belongs to the realm which tradition sums up under the word sapientia (wisdom). Through it we savor (sapere), we come to know, "the glory of God Parenthetical Arabic page numbers in this section refer to pages in Kasper, Methods of Dogmatic Theology. 16 FAITH ENLIGHTENING SACRED THEOLOGY 377 shining on the face of Christ Jesus" (2 Cor 4, 6). This is the type of experience which is proper to theology, and the modern-day emphasis on truth requires that this experience be given a new, more intensive form of methodological selfverification. For even though theology cannot simply appropriate one or other of the secular methods, it is not a purely whimsical process either. Theology, too, must be rigorous and serious. It, too, must draw reasonable conclusions. It, too, must use exactness in posing and answering questions. Theology, too, has its methods. (5) Hence, in contrast to the newly emerging "secular theology," Kasper very much regards theology as a methodical inquiry into the truth, an inquiry in which tradition is an essential ingredient. To put it into Maclntyrean terms, for Kasper theology is irreversibly tradition-constituted: "Only tradition, dominated as it is by the quest for truth, can put us on the road where the search for truth is made" (6-7). The concept of ecclesial-doctrinal tradition that Kasper introduces and consistently applies throughout his treatise is deeply shaped by his interpretation of the doctrine of tradition held by the nineteenth-century Roman school. 17 More importantly, however, Kasper normatively contextualizes and thus interprets his understanding of ecclesialdoctrinal tradition further by way of a more comprehensive and indeed foundational philosophical-hermeneutical understanding of tradition that is explicitly indebted to Heidegger's late philosophy: 17 We might not go completely wrong in finding echoes of Kasper's interpretation of Passaglia's and Schrader's interpretation of tradition in his own programmatic and eschatologically determined vision: "Die Tradition 'ist' nicht, sie geschieht, sie ereignet sich. Die Tradition ist der Akt, der von Christus im Heiligen Geist getragen ist, der