646 [Bk. VII If, however, the prior custom was opposed to general law, which was not completely abolished by that earlier customfor the reason that the custom that derogated from it was not a universal, but a particular one—then it is probable that a subsequent prescriptive custom, of ten years’ stand­ ing, is sufficient. The reason for this is that this prescriptive custom is not of its essence opposed to the law, since the general law, to which a return is made by this custom, always stands. In that case the argument of Felinus stands [on Decretals, Bk. I, tit. 11, chap, viii, no. 30]. I could not approve it, however, if the prior custom were universal, and had completely annulled the universal law previously existing; for When forty years in that case, I think that a canonical prescription of are required. forty years is necessary against such a custom, because the subsequent custom is then completely contrary to the general law established by the previous custom. For any other law more ancient than either custom is as if it had not existed before the other two, because it has been entirely abolished. Let this suffice for our treatment of custom. When the period of ten years is suffi- Felinus. On Laws and God the Lawgiver [The 'Title-Page of the Pdition of 1613] A DEFENCE OF THE CATHOLIC AND APOSTOLIC FAITH IN REFUTATION OF THE ERRORS OF THE ANGLICAN SECT Reply To the Apologie for the Oath of Allegiance and to the admonitory Preface of His Most Serene Majesty James, King of England By Father FRANCISCO SUAREZ with a of Granada, Member of the Society of Jesus Primary Professor of Sacred Theology at the celebrated Academy of Coimbra Dedicated to Their Most Serene Majesties the Catholic Kings and Princes of all Christendom COIMBRA By privileges of his Catholic Majesty From the Press of DIOGO GOMEZ DE LOUREYRO Printer for the Academy In the Year of Our Lord 1613 [iü] FOR THEIR MOST SERENE MAJESTIES THOSE KINGS AND PRINCES WHO ARE THE CHILDREN AND DEFENDERS OF THE ROMAN CATHOLIC CHURCH Francisco Suarez of the Society of ftsus desires temporal and eternal blessedness His Most Serene Majesty James, King of Great Britain, in his recently published work, has called upon the Catholic Kings and Princes, as with a friendly trumpet blast, to share in his own religion, that those whom the King of Kings has bought with His own blood for the defence of the Church of Rome, and whom Christ, the Lord of Lords, has armed with supreme power, might be incited, by the counsel he has imparted, to attack that Church. His Most Serene Majesty, however, has wielded his pen in a vain attempt. For the gates of hell shall not prevail against the Church, nor shall the chill raging of the north wind have power to scatter those who have taken their stand upon the rock of Rome, and have been united by Christ, the corner-stone, in the strongest of bonds, that of true piety. Would that King James, following in the footsteps of his unvanquished royal ancestors, might rather combine with you to exalt the majesty of the Catholic Church, in such fashion as to be not inferior, in the zeal of true piety, to those whose peer he is, in power and sovereignty! Would that he preferred to be numbered among the kings whom divine authority has constituted guardians of that Church, rather than among those whom impious madness has inflamed against the Lord, and against His Christ ! Therefore, since the King of England has published a work testifying to his religion, and since he is waging war upon the Catholic Church, not with the regal majesty adorning him, nor with the clash and might of arms (whereunto the priest of Christ and religious cannot [iv] oppose resistance), but rather by the sharp edge of his unaided human talents and pen—I repeat, since this is the case—I have deemed it proper to my office and purpose that I should advance to the line of battle ; not with the intention of dimming the lustrous renown of so great a king, an end which I am neither capable nor desirous of achiev­ ing, but in order that the mists exhaled from the fetid pools of the Reformers, wherewith he attempts to obscure Catholic truth, mav vanish into air and smoke, being dispelled by the rays of true wisdom. That I might accomplish this purpose, I have with all my strength besought that light from God, the Father of light, that knowledge of the uncorrupted truth, which—handed down by Christ the Lord 1569.74 4. o 6ξο The Judgment of the Censor through His Apostles, and expounded by the wakeful toil of the Holy Fathers—should be striven after by one who desires to keep to the true path in his life and his beliefs. May my undertaking be granted the favour of that Divine Spirit in Whose hands he the hearts of kings. And do you—O Kings and Princes of the Catholic world, who in your sincere affection earnestly desire that His Most Serene Majesty, King James, should be even as you yourselves are—do you receive this work, such as it is, under your patronage, to be defended by your authority. For it is yours, and it is well said that, We make those things our own, to which we impart our authority. Therefore, receive the work as your own, that it may be made public, defended by the royal authority of your patronage, adorned by [your] renown and secure from danger; that it may make a brilliant entrance into the world ; that it may be deemed not unworthy of kingly eyes. For only under the protection of your name can wre oppose this book of ours, wherein we defend God’s cause, to that of His Most Serene Majesty. I have, indeed, been inspired by one sole design: the dedication, in dutiful humility, of this product of my labours to you who—as heirs to the sovereignty and piety of your forebears—have devoutly undertaken and unwaveringly administer the guardianship of the Catholic Church. For others, our work may serve as an antidote, but you yourselves, do not lack an antidote (namely, supreme piety, divinely inspired) against the madness of the Reformers ; for their poisons, drawn from Stygian streams, are powerless to injure you, who—joined in the bond of divine virtue— are protected as subjects in the unity of the true Catholic faith, under Christ the Lord and His earthly Vicar, the Supreme Pontiff, even as the noblest members of the body are subject to its head. And for so long as your supreme power is firmly founded upon Him, may it grow to a greater imperial glory and aid you toward eternal blessedness. Coimbra, On the thirteenth day of June, In the year 1613. [v] THE JUDGMENT OF THE CENSOR, HIS MOST ILLUSTRIOUS LORDSHIP D. AFONSO DE CASTELLO BRANCO, BISHOP OF COIMBRA, COUNT OF ARGANIL, LORD OF COJA, ETC., MEMBER OF THE ROYAL COUNCIL OF HIS CATHOLIC MAJESTY By commission of the most illustrious Bishop, D. Pedro de Castilho, Viceroy of Portugal, and Supreme Inquisitor in matters of the faith, I have read with the greatest care, and have studiously examined as Censor, the Defence of the Catholic Faith in Refutation of the Errors of The Judgment of the Censor 651 the Anglican Sect, with a Reply to the Apologie and Epistle to Christian Princes of His Most Serene Majesty, James, King of England, published by the illustrious Doctor, Francisco Suarez of the Society of Jesus. Not only do all the contents of this work accord scrupulously with the authority of Holy Writ, not only do they piously conform to Apostolic traditions, not only are they in learned agreement with the Oecu­ menical Councils and the Decrees of the Popes, but, furthermore, the wisdom of so great an author—drawn from the Holy Fathers rather than from human study—shines forth afar from this book. So fre­ quently and appositely does this author with the most scrupulous fidelity introduce their testimony, that they have all spoken through his mouth (so I venture to affirm) and have combined to strengthen this Defence, which is accordingly to be published with great benefit to the Catholic Church and great profit to Christian doctrine. The perusal of the work has recalled to my mind many admirable state­ ments made by the Church Fathers, statements which I had read long before; and I also, most enjoyably, became acquainted with many more. Would that the vision of the heretics, dulled as it is by the dark­ ness of perfidy, might be able to endure a fight so radiant. For they would then easily laugh to scorn the unstable falsity of their own beliefs, the foundations of which would be completely overthrown by a perusal of the present work, as they would most clearly perceive. And if it wrere permitted a Bishop who has attained to mature years in the School of the theologians, one who has grown old among the books of the Holy Fathers, to address personally His Serene Majesty the King of England, I should proclaim in all truth that which was attested by the Most August and Saintly Mary, his Mother, with her voice and her blood. Credence should be accorded to Irenaeus, Dionysius, Augustine, Jerome, and other Doctors of the Catholic Church, whose opinion we offer as presented in this book and whose sanctity of life is known to all ; rather than to Luther and Calvin, men whose evil deeds cannot but give rise to shame and condemnation even on the part of their own disciples (if the latter should read [the said book]) and whose capricious and inconsistent doctrine, alien to true religion, sufficiently demonstrates their ignorance. I should advise submission to Francisco Suarez—the devout disdainer of things temporal, and a most vigorous defender of one sole piety and religion, whom I regard (because of his rare wisdom, confirmed by so many tokens) as the universal master of this age and a second Augustine; rather than sub­ mission to the Reformers of England, who, in order not to confess that they have erred, cling with an obstinate disregard of consistency to their errors and, led astray by the enticement of their desires, have made shipwreck (in the words of Paul) concerning the faith. More­ over, I shall lay down the same declaration and admonition as did ■^1 652 The Judgment of the Censor Augustine formerly, under similar circumstances : let not the Fathers, Doctors of the Catholic Church, prevail, nor yet Luther and Calvin, those impious deserters from the true faith; let not Suarez prevail, the devout disciple of the Fathers, nor yet the Reformers, unhappy shades of Luther and Calvin ! Rather let the victor be truth in her purity, illuminated by the dissertations contained in this book, which I deem so worthy to be printed and set before the eyes of all, for the common advantage of the Catholic Church, that I furthermore con­ gratulate our age, and with good reason, on its possession of so great a teacher; as I congratulate the Society of Jesus because of such a disciple. Given at Coimbra, On the twelfth day of June, In the year 1613. N] THE JUDGMENT OF THE CENSOR, HIS MOST ILLUSTRIOUS LORDSHIP, D. FERNANDO MARTINZ DE MASCARENHAS, BISHOP OF ALGARVE, MEMBER OF THE ROYAL COUNCIL OF HIS CATHOLIC MAJESTY Not only because of the letter regarding this matter which was sent to me by the most illustrious D. Pedro de Castilho, Bishop and Inquisitor General of all Portugal, but also because my own pleasure inclined me to this course, I have attentively read in advance and care­ fully examined in my capacity as Censor the Defence written by that most celebrated Doctor, Father Francisco Suarez, wherein with mar­ vellous skill he upholds the Catholic Faith and assails the errors of the Anglican sect, making reply, moreover, to a certain Apology and Episde of His Most Serene Majesty, James, King of England. In this Defence I have assuredly1 come upon nothing that offends against the orthodox Faith, but have, on the contrary, found much that defends that Faith. For in my opinion, the work in question is another fateful shield, like that which by divine command the Hebrew leader so felicitously lifted up, in times gone past, towards the city of Hai. For thus indeed it shall come to pass that the Anglican errors will be completely wiped out by this Defence—as by the shield of Josue, lifted up on high in the hands of so great a leader and member of the Society of Jesus towards the armed forces of those errors, forces incited not by the King’s own mind, which of its own natural bent is inclined to piety (inasmuch as it was formerly trained by his most saintly and martyred mother), 1 [palne, in the Latin, is evidently a misprint for plane.—Tn ] The Judgment of the Censor 653 but rather by the mad fury of the Reformers that has of late sounded the war-trumpet in England, calling to Christian princes. And further­ more, it is to be hoped that His Most Serene Majesty, the King of England himself—possessing as he does a keen mind and highly exalted spirit—when he weighs all the content of this Defence in the balance of his own reasoning and poises it on the scales of his judgment, when he remarks at the very outset the submissiveness and modesty which (as is proper) characterize the most learned Father Suarez throughout the entire dispute with His Royal Majesty—it is to be hoped, I repeat —that the King of England will then be divinely inspired to turn his truly royal spirit towards saner counsels of the Mother Church ; imitat­ ing Clovis, indeed, that first, most Christian King of the Franks who, when he was near death, crowned the Roman Pontiff himself with the royal diadem, because he knew that the Pope was the only visible head of the whole Church, and who after doing so gave the Kingdom of Gaul as a pledge for the aid of, and in allegiance to, the Church of Rome. For that Crown was allotted to the Confession of Saint Peter, representing the kingdom. By this example of piety Clovis fortified his own kingdom uncommonly wrell upon a stable foundation—that is to say, upon the Rock and upon the successor of Peter ; and if his deed is imitated by the King of England, the latter will imitate also that most blessed end [attained by Clovis]. But I must return to the Judgment of the book. To the immense benefit of the Christian Commonwealth, and from a fertile and fruitful soil (as it were), this writer—pre-eminent in authority as in piety—has brought forth many evidences of his own genius, which the whole world reveres, admires, and cherishes. But, in very truth, the present Defence contains his shining masterpiece in its choice wording, its sublime thought, and its forceful arguments—abounding in efficacy and vigour. Thus the entire book is compact of strength, vitality, and inspiration. Admirable judgment is joined therein to erudition; facility of composition to care; orderly arrangement to a wealth of learning. In juxtaposition with memory, it reveals unwearying study; with Scholastic theology, skilled knowledge of both canon and civil law; with the genuine explanation of Sacred Scripture according to the mind of the early Church Fathers,1 the free and somewhat cor­ rupt interpretations of the preachers ; and finally, in juxtaposition with that more sublime science that relates to God, the separate divisions in the chain of time and a manifold knowledge of the chronology of the realm of Christendom. My Judgment of this book would grow into an overwhelming eulogy, were that not precluded by the well1 [The Latin text reads: geminae iuxta antiquos patres Sacrae Scripturae explicationi (to the explana­ tion of both [Testaments of] the Holy Scriptures, &c.) ; but geminae would seem to be a misprint for genuinae, in which case the correct translation is that given above.—Revisse.] 654 Fhe Judgment of the Censor known modesty of the eminent Father Suarez, who is wont to regard praises as darts, and encomiums as wounds, believing that eulogists are enemies. There is reason, then, to offer our congratulations to the Society of Jesus, as to a most excellent parent, on the fact that— although many men who are very princes in piety, in learning, and in probity of life have already streamed forth from that most holy Insti­ tute as from a Trojan horse—it furthermore possesses one man at the present time, this exceedingly eminent Doctor, Father Suarez, who hastens from battle to battle like some glorious warrior that he may quiet the sudden insurrections of error, displaying an eager activity that exceeds the allotted duties and the strength of the aged. Where­ fore I judge that this work, examined and approved by me, is most worthy of pubheation, and destined to illuminate the dense shadows of error. Given at Faro, On the sixth day of the month of December, In the year of our Lord, 1612. D. Fernando Martinz de Mascarenhas, Bishop of Algarve. [vii] THE JUDGMENT OF THE CENSOR, HIS MOST ILLUSTRIOUS LORDSHIP, D. MARTINHO AFONSO DE MELLO, BISHOP OF LAMEGO, MEMBER OF THE ROYAL COUNCIL OF HIS CATHOLIC MAJESTY. By commission of his most illustrious Lordship, the Inquisitor General, I have carefully perused the Defence of the Catholic Faith in Refutation of the Errors of the Anglican Sect, with a Reply to the Apologie for the Oath of Allegiance and Epistle to Christian Princes of His Most Serene Majesty, James, King of England. The said work was produced by Francisco Suarez, that Doctor of surpassing wisdom and Primary Professor of Sacred Theology at the Academy of Coimbra. This author, so exceedingly famous for his burning zeal on behalf of the faith, this most eminent theologian, who by the power of his wisdom lends strong support to the Church of God, now sinking into ruin in England, has engaged his pen in battle with the heretical pestilences raging in that Kingdom. He strives against the errors of the heretics, taking his stand upon an exposition of the Holy Scriptures, and the interpretation thereof in the authentic sense that accords with the design of the divine Author and with the text. In order to confirm the truths of the faith, he adduces the decrees of the sacred General Councils and the Supreme The Judgment of the Censor 655 Pontiffs ; for those who disobey the infallible authority of these decrees have ever been regarded by faithful Christians as enemies of the Church. He avails himself of the most apt, pertinent, and select testimony afforded by the Holy Fathers, whose piety and wisdom the Church of God has always esteemed and venerated. He so weighs all things minutely upon the most irrefutable scales of reason, as to pass over no point unconsidered and in silence ; but he treats with [a special] clarity those questions which are extremely troublesome and delicate, hastening to meet all difficulties of whatsoever origin, that the truth may be made known. With firm and unshaken arguments he defends the supernatural power of the Supreme Pontiff, showing that the King, enmeshed in errors, has acted with the greatest injustice in arrogating spiritual power to himself, and that the attribution to him of that power by the heretics of the Anglican sect is manifestly heretical. With discernment and wisdom he lays bare the errors opposed to the faith which lurk in the oath exacted by the King of England from the latter’s subjects; and he demonstrates that infidelity1 to Christ and His Church, as well as injustice towards the said subjects, are contained in that oath, so that in the very act of swearing it the subjects are compelled to deny the Catholic Faith. [Our author] treats of this matter vigorously, but with truth and moderation. His work is undoubtedly most learned, overflowing with rare piety and erudition, and such that even one who excelled in the art of writing would be unable to praise and extol it as it deserves. By means of the authorities quoted, and by the force of the reasons presented, the errors of the Anglican sect have been so refuted that the author’s adversaries are left with no means of evasion, no opportunity for reply, unless perchance that may be termed a reply which is but a battle waged with empty words, and a display of abuse, such as is customary among the demented and the furiously insane. May it be God’s will that, once consideration has been accorded to this’most efficacious and judicious defence of the faith (the faith which, con­ firmed by miracles and upheld by martyrdom, has persevered in the Roman Catholic Church in one and the same form, ever since the first days of its origin, under the instruction of the Apostles), His Most Serene Majesty, King James of England himself, giving heed, as befits his kingly mind, to the truth of Catholicism wrhich has been adequately expounded to him, will attach himself and his Protestant subjects to the Catholic Church, the Bride of Christ. It is my judgment that the present work of this surpassingly wise Doctor, Francisco Suarez, is most worthy of being printed and published, to the end that a signal 1 [The punctuation of the Latin text may seem to indicate that infidelitatem is in apposition with errores, rather than one of the subjects of contineri ; but that text is not free from errors in the matter of punctuation, and the Translator has not found it advisable to strain the sense merely in order to account for the semicolon that intervenes between infidelitatem and imusliiiam.—Ta.] Authorizations, &c. 656 victory may be achieved by our faith over the heretics, and for the public and universal advantage of all Christendom. Given at Lamego, On the twenty-fourth day of November, In the year 1612. Martinho, Bishop of Lamego. [viii] AUTHORIZATION OF THE PROVINCIAL I, Juan Alvares, Visitor and also Provincial of the Society of Jesus in the Province of Portugal, in virtue of the power conferred upon me by the Most Reverend Father Claudio Aquaviva, General of our Society, do authorize the printing of this work regarding the Anglican schism, a work which was composed by Father Francisco Suarez of our Society, Doctor in Sacred Theology and Primary Professor at the Academy of Coimbra, and which has been approved by the judgment of grave and learned men of the said Society. In testimony whereof we have given this writing, signed by our hand and confirmed by our seal. Given at Coimbra, on the fifth day of April, in the year of our Lord, 1612. Juan Alvares. AUTHORIZATION OF THE SUPREME SENATE OF THE HOLY INQUISITION We declare that this book opposing the English heresies may be printed, in view of the reports which we have examined concerning it; and that, after it has been printed, it shall be returned to this Council for comparison as well as for permission to go into circulation, without which permission it shall not circulate. Given at Lisbon, On the seventh day of January, In the year of our Lord, 1613. The Bishop Elyas. The Bishop of Nicomedia. Bartholomeu da Fonseca. of THE LICENCE OF THE COURT BOARD This book concerning the Anglican schism, composed by Father Francisco Suarez, Primary Professor at the University of Coimbra, Authorizations, tAc. may be printed, in view of the Licence accorded it by the author’s Superior and by the Council of the Holy Office; and after being printed, the said work shall be returned to the Board for determination of the price. Given at Lisbon, On the fifth day of February, In the year of our Lord, 1613. Luis Machado. D. Barbosa. AUTHORIZATION OF HIS MOST ILLUSTRIOUS LORDSHIP, D. AFONSO DE CASTELLO BRANCO, BISHOP OF COIMBRA, ETC. We grant to Father Francisco Suarez of the Society of Jesus, permission to print his volume opposing the Anglican sect, a volume destined to be universally beneficial. Given at Coimbra, On the fourteenth day of June, 1613. The Bishop Count. [ix] THE CENSORS’ JUDGMENT OF THE ACADEMY OF ALCALA DE HENARES We have perused with all the diligence and care in our power, this treatise dealing with the Anglican schism and comprising A Defence of the Catholic [and Apostolic] Faith, in Refutation of the Errors of the Anglican Sect, with a Reply to the work of His Most Serene Majesty, James, King of England, as well as to his Dedicatory Epistle to the Kings and Princes of Christendom ; a treatise produced by that most authoritative Doctor, Francisco Suarez of the Society of Jesus, Pri­ mary Professor of Theology at the Academy of Coimbra, handed over by the Supreme Senate [of the Holy Inquisition] for the judgment of the Academy of Alcala de Henares, and committed by that same body to our care and good faith. In this work there is discerned nothing alien to the truth of the Catholic faith, nothing departing from or discordant with that truth. On the contrary, the author has waged such successful warfare upon the said Anglican schism and upon the Reformers of our day, that he has won over them all a glorious victory ; and truly the said work contains naught undeserving of approbation and praise. For its pages radiate the author’s vigorous and active talent in the revelation of heretical artifices andin the painstaking and diligent exposition of the testimony proffered by Holy Writ, by the Sacred 1569.74 . p 658 Privilege of the King Councils, and by the Holy Fathers, as well as of the records of all antiquity; as they radiate, too, his marvellous dexterity in wielding the weapons of argument. In fine, there is in the entire work nothing repugnant to our undivided opinion, for on this point we are all of one voice, one mind, and one view. Wherefore, if he who is responsible for the said work orders it to be put into print with all possible speed, he will be judged to have championed aright the cause, not of the author, but of the whole Catholic and Apostolic Church; for [this work] will greatly solace the adherents of the true faith, and will confound those who have forsaken that faith. Given at Alcala de Henares, On the twelfth day of May in the year of our Lord, 1613. D. D. Prospero Spinola Doria, D. Enrique de Villegas Rector [of the Academy] D. Luis Montesinos D. Andrés Pérez D. Melquior Fernandez D. D. Juan de Pereda y Gudiel Bolivar Maestro Fray Lorenzo Gutierre de M PRIVILEGE OF THE KING Whereas, We have been informed on your behalf that you, Fran­ cisco Suarez, Religious of the Society of Jesus, have printed in our Kingdom of Portugal and with permission, a book entitled, A Defence of the Catholic and Apostolic Faith, &c., destined to be of great utility and benefit to the Christian Commonwealth; Whereas, to the end that the work thus printed might be brought to Our Kingdoms of Castile and sold therein, We have been asked and supplicated to order that permission be granted you enabling you to introduce the said book into these Our Kingdoms and to sell it there, together with a privilege embracing a period of twenty years or of such extent as We might be pleased to grant; And whereas, the above requests have been considered by the members of Our Council, and such measures have been taken by their order as are provided for in the decree that We recently issued con­ cerning the printing of books, It has been agreed that We should command this Our Order to be drawn up for you in regard to the said matter ; an agreement which has met with Our approval. And through this Order We bestow per­ mission and authority for the introduction of the aforementioned book into Our Kingdoms, although it was printed in the Kingdom of Portu­ gal; as We furthermore permit and authorize that, for the period of Privilege of the King 659 the next ten years (reckoned as beginning from the date of this Our Order), the said book, having thus been introduced into Our King­ doms, may by you or by your duly authorized representative, and by no other person whatsoever, be printed and sold in the original form seen by Our Council, which original carries at its close the endorse­ ment and signature of Jeronimo Nùfiez de Leon, Secretary for the Constituents of Our Supreme Council ; to which permission and au­ thority we affix the following provisions : Prior to the sale, you shall bring the work before the said Constitu­ ents, together with that original, in order that the Council may see whether or not the impression in question conforms with the original ; or, you shall present a certificate in official form to the effect that the Corrector appointed by Us has seen the said impression, which he has collated and corrected on the basis of the original; and on the book shall be placed the Corrector’s Censure together with this Our Order ; And We furthermore command the Printer to omit the first part of the first signature when he prints the said book; neither shall he deliver more than one copy, together with the original, to the author or the person at whose expense the printing is done or to any other person whatsoever, for purposes of the above-mentioned correction and the fixing of the price, until the said book has first been corrected, and its price fixed, by the members of Our Council ; which having been done and under no other conditions, it shall be permissible to print the aforesaid book, with its beginning and first signature, whereon there shall appear forthwith this Our Order and grant of privilege, together with the statements of approval, the evaluation, and the list of errata; [These commands shall not be disobeyed,] on pain of falling under' and incurring the penalties set forth in the above-mentioned decree [on the printing of books] and in the laws of Our Kingdoms which deal with this matter. We furthermore order that, throughout the said period of time, no person whatsoever shall print or sell the book without your permis­ sion, under penalty of forfeiting—by so printing it—all books, moulds, and apparatus that he may possess, of whatsoever kind, and of incurring a fine of fifty thousand maravedis, a third part of which fine shall go to Our Supreme Council, another third to the Judge who passes the sentence, and the remaining third to the person who makes the accusation. And as for the members of Our Council, the President and the Criers of Our Courts, the Alcaldes and the Constables of Our Resi­ dence and Court City and Our Chanceries, all the Corregidors, Officer[s] of Justice, Governors (of major or ordinary rank), and other Judges and Justices whomsoever in all the cities, towms, and villages 66ο Setting of the Price within Our Kingdoms and domains—as for all these persons, let them uphold in your behalf, and comply with, this Our Order, bestowed on you by Our grace ; and let them in no wise go against nor act in de­ fiance of its form and content : Given at San Lorenzo, On the ninth day of the month of June, In the year 1613. I, THE KING. (By command of the King our Sovereign. Jorge de Tobar.) SETTING OF THE PRICE I, Jeronimo Nûnez de Leon, Secretary of the Court of the King our Sovereign, and Resident of his Council, certify that : The members of the said Council, having given their permission for the introduction into these kingdoms of the books composed by Father Francisco Suarez of the Society of Jesus and entitled A Defence of the [Catholic and Apostolic] Faith, &c., together with their permis­ sion for its free sale, and also a privilege for a period of ten years, Have rated each signature of the said work at . . . maravedis ; and Have ordered that the said work shall be sold according to that evaluation, not at a higher price, and that this statement regarding the price shall be placed at the beginning of each copy; And in order that this matter may be made known, by command of the said members of the Council and at the request of the afore­ mentioned Francisco Suarez, I give this certificate. Madrid, On the twenty-fourth day of the month of June, In the year one thousand six hundred and thirteen. Jeronimo Nûnez de Leon. FRANCISCO SUAREZ A DEFENCE OF THE CATHOLIC AND APOSTOLIC FAITH Of this treatise, only the following Chapters are included in these Selections: Book III, Chapters V and XXIII ; Book VI, Chapter IV CONTENTS Pege Book III. CONCERNING THE SUPREMACY AND POWER OF THE POPE OVER TEMPORAL KINGS: Chapter v: Do Christian Kings Possess Supreme Power in Civil, or Temporal Affairs; and [, if so,] by what Right? ...... 667 Chapter xxiii: The Pope May Use Coercive Power against Kings, even to the Point of Deposing Them from their Thrones, if there be a Valid Cause . 685 Book VI. CONCERNING THE OATH OF ALLEGIANCE EXACTED BY THE KING OF ENGLAND....................................................................... 703 Chapter iv: Does the Third Part of the Oath [Exacted by King James] Contain any Requirement in Excess of Civil Obedience and Contrary to Catholic Doctrine ? . . ... 70? FRANCISCO SUAREZ A DEFENCE OF THE CATHOLIC AND APOSTOLIC FAITH BOOK III CONCERNING THE SUPREMACY AND POWER OF THE POPE OXER TEMPORAL KINGS CHAPTER V: DO CHRISTIAN KINGS POSSESS SUPREME POWER IN CIVIL, OR TEMPORAL AFFAIRS; AND [, IF SO,] BY WHAT RIGHT? ’569.74 +Q - 237 CHAPTER V DO CHRISTIAN KINGS POSSESS SUPREME POWER IN CIVIL, OR TEMPORAL AFFAIRS; AND [, IF SO,] BY WHAT RIGHT? I. A given power may be called supreme, when it recognizes no superior. For this word, ‘supreme’, connotes a denial of the existence of any superior whom the other party—the one said to possess supreme power—is bound to obey. But it is understood that we are speaking of earthly, or human superiors, inasmuch as we are not instituting a comparison with God. For what human prince, if he were neither an atheist nor a madman, would presume to withdraw himself from .divine authority, or even to attempt such a withdrawal? This denial, then, is one which excludes subjection to a human and mortal superior. However, this denial may be interpreted in a number of different ways. Consequently, in order that the title relating to this question may be understood, and may be distinguished from other questions which could be raised at this point, it is necessary to provide a clear explanation of the manner and meaning of the said denial. For, first, it is possible to deny in an absolute sense all subjection to any human superior, whether in spiritual matters, or in civil ones. Secondly, it is possible to deny subjection in these temporal and civil matters. Moreover, even though the gravest disagreement exists between our­ selves and the King of England with respect to the former question (since he desires to be subordinate to no earthly being, even in spiritual matters, a desire which we regard as contrary to the faith and to Christian obedience), nevertheless, we are not treating here of that question; for we have not yet discussed spiritual power, and without knowledge of this power, it is in no wise possible to arrive at an in­ telligible solution of the said question. Accordingly, we shall postpone its discussion to the closing portion of this Book1; and, for the present, we shall apply the term ‘supreme temporal power’ to that power which is not subject to any other within the same order, or [sphere of] subject-matter. 2. Furthermore, it is customary, in connexion with the question under discussion, to distinguish two forms of subjection, namely, Two forms of sub ^^reCt an<^ in · i the prince result from such defence, ror the right to preserve one’s own hfe is the greatest right; nor does the prince, in the situation described, labour under any need that obliges the sub­ ject to sacrifice his life for his sovereign’s sake, since, on the contrary, the prince himself has voluntarily and by his unjust behaviour placed himself in this perilous position. I say, ‘ordinarily’, however, for if the state would be thrown into confusion by the death of the king, or would suffer from some other grave injury detrimental to the common welfare, then the charitable love of one’s country and a charitable regard for that common welfare, would bind one—even at the peril of his own life—to refrain from slaying the king. But this obfigation falls within the order of charity, and with that order we are not at present dealing. 6. Again, if the question relates to cases in which the commonwhat of those wealth itself is to be defended, this [violent method of] in which the state defence is impermissible unless we assume that the is defended." acrtuajjy attacking the state, with the unjust — Chap. IV] 710 St. Augustine, A Defence of the Catholic and Apostolic Faith [Bk. VI intention of destroying it and slaughtering the citizens, or that some similar situation exists. Under such circumstances, it will assuredly be permissible to resist the prince, even by slaying him if defence cannot be achieved in any other fashion. One argument in favour of this assertion is as follows : if such action is licit in order to protect one’s own life, far more certainly will it be Heit for the sake of the common good. A further argument resides in the fact that the state or com­ monwealth itself is in that case engaged in a just defensive war against an unjust invader, even though he be its own king; so that any citizen whatsoever, acting as a member of that commonwealth, and impelled —whether expressly or tacitly—by it, may therefore defend the said commonwealth, in the course of that conflict, in whatsoever way is possible to him. However, we are not at present concerned with those cases in which the prince actually wages an offensive war against the state itself, with the intention of destroying it and slaying great numbers of the citizens. Rather are we concerned with those occasions when he rules the state peacefully, but disturbs and injures it in other ways [than by offensive warfare]. And in such cases, defence of the state by violence or by wiles directed against the life of the king is not to be permitted since the state is subjected, on these occasions, to no actual violence, such as might Hcitly be repelled by violence. Con­ sequently, an attack upon the prince, under these circumstances, would be tantamount to the waging of war upon him, on private authority; and such warfare is in nowise Heit, ‘because that1 natural order which is accommodated to the peace of mankind, demands that the authority to engage in a war should reside in the state, or in princes,’ as Augustine 718 declares (Contra Faustum, Bk. XXII, chap. Ixxiv [chap. Ixxv]). Another reason supporting the same conclusion is as foHows: even as it is not permissible that one should, on his private authority, punish the wrongful deeds of any person by means of that person’s death, just so is it impermissible to avert on one’s private authority, and by the slaughter of that individual, the wrongful deeds which one fears he may in the future commit ; and the principle involved is the same [with respect to both private and princely wrongdoers]; moreover, its validity is manifest in the case of private malefactors ; therefore, the said conclusion holds good, and with stiH greater reason, when apphed to offending princes. 7. In order, however, that we may elucidate our doctrine more 1 (St. Augustine has ordo . . . ide, which defines his meaning perhaps more clearly than does the Suàrezian quotation. The latter omits ide and varies slightly in other respects from the text of Augustine, which runs : . . . ordo tamen ille naturalis mortalium paci accommodatus hoc poscit, ut suscipiendi belli auctoritas atque consilium penes Principem sit.. . . Suarez quotes as follows : quia ordo naturalis, mor­ talium paci accommodatus hoc poscit, ut suscipiendi belli authoritatem [corrected to auctoritas in the Paris edition of 1859] Penes rempublicam, seu Principes sil.—Tr.] Chap. IV] Does Oath of King James exact more than Civil Obedience? 711 satisfactorily, and may the better apply the foregoing remarks1 to the ,It is. permissible . clause quoted above 2 from the oath, it will be necesto 1 , .... , . slay a tyrant whose sary to make a prior declaration as to whether or not title to the throne the doctrine already laid down holds good with reis tyrannical. . \ , spect to the second group, that is, with respect to rulers whose very title is tyrannical. For ordinarily a distinction is made between these two classes of tyrants, inasmuch as it is asserted that the tyrant whose title is ac­ quired in tyrannical fashion, may be slain by any private person whatsoever belonging to the state wdiich is subjected to the tyranny, provided that there is no other way in which the said person can free the state from that tyranny. So St. Thomas has held (on the Sentences, Bk. II, dist. xliv, qu. 2, art. 2, main part and conclusion), and his opinion has been adopted by almost all the Doctors above cited. The treatise of Conradus Brunus (De Seditiosis, Bk. VI, chap, iii), wherein he records various examples, may also be cited in this connexion, though his examples have been com­ piled from both just and unjust acts, so that they provide proof with regard not to what is just, but to what is customary. The reason, then, on which the said opinion is founded, is the fact that, under the cir­ cumstances described, it is not the king or prince who is slain, but an enemy of the state. Thus it is that St. Thomas (De Regimine Principum, Bk. I, chap, vi), similarly defends the deed of Aod, who—though he was merely a private person—slew Eglon, King of Moab, to whom Israel was subject, on the ground that Eglon was not the true King of God’s people, but was rather an enemy and a tyrant (Judges, Chap, v [Chap. iii]). Abulensis [Tostado] gives the same account (in his commentary on that passage [on Judges, Chap, iii], qu. 26), and adds that this tyrant could [licitly] have been slain by any Israelite whatsoever. So, too, did Judith slay Holofernes (Judith, Chap. xiii). And Jahel performed a similar deed when she killed Sisara judges, Chap, iv), a deed for which she is praised (Judges, Chap. v). In like manner, St. Thomas approves, in the passage previously cited [on the Sentences, Bk. II, dist. xliv, qu. 2, art. 2, main part and conclusion], of the opinion expressed by Cicero when the latter praises [in Philippics, I] the slayers of Caesar, usurper of sovereign power, not by a just title, but through violence and tyranny. Accordingly, the Doctors, too, maintain that the crime of lese-majesty is not committed against a tyrant of this sort, since no true majesty resides in him. They furthermore hold that the title of ‘prince’ does not apply to such tyrants and that 1 [Reading dicta with the 1859 Paris edition, not dictam with our own Latin text, and that of Mayence, 1619.—Tr.] 1 [Propositam in our text. The 1619 and 1859 «lirions have praepositam which is perhaps the clearer term in this context. In any case, the clause here referred to is evidently the entire third part of the oath quoted in the first sentence of this Chapter.—Tr.] St. Thomas, Comadus Abt/.ns·, iT«’*do]. Jud.ih, xin Judges.^. Tullius (,cero· 7I2 Gigas. St. Thomas. Abulensis [Tostado]. A Defence of the Catholic and Apostolic Faith [Bk. VI consequently the decrees declaring that it is not permissible to slay a prince do not refer to the said tyrants ; a fact which is made evident by Gigas in his Treatise On the Crime of Lese-majesty (Qu. 65). 8. However, St. Thomas (on the Sentences, Bk. II, dist. xliv, qu. 2, a limiting condi- art. 2., main part and concl.) adds [, to the propotion· sition that the slaying of these tyrants is permissible,] a limiting condition, as follows: such an act is permissible when no recourse can be had to any superior through whom judgment may be passed upon the usurper. This limitation has force most particularly when the tyranny is practised not by a sovereign prince but by some inferior. For not only [foreign] kings, but also powerful inferior lords are able to usurp through tyrannysome form of dominion, or juris­ diction, or magistracy. Accordingly, under such circumstances, although the people may resist an invader while he is in the act of making the attack, nevertheless, when the attack has once been made, and he has obtained possession and the power of dominion, they may not, on their own [private] authority, slay him or begin a new war against him, as long as it is possible for them to have recourse to a superior, inasmuch as they may not draw their swords on their own authority when they have a superior; and still less would this be permissible to every private individual whatsoever. For if it were permissible,1 general disorder would result, and great confusion would spring up within the state. Furthermore, and for the same reason, even in cases where there is no superior to whom recourse may be had, it is necessary that the tyranny and injustice be public and manifest. For The circumstances which must exist in if there is doubt of their reality, it will not be per­ order that a ruler missible to remove by force the person who is in pos­ whose title is tyran­ nical may licitly be session, since in case of doubt his position is the slain by a private stronger, unless it is at the same time certain that individual. his seizure of possession was tyrannical. Again, in order that such a tyrant may licitly be slain, this slay­ ing must be necessary to the liberty of the kingdom; for if the tyrant can be removed by any method that is less harsh, it will not be licit to slay him straightway without the sanction of any superior power and an examination of the case. 9. The commonly accepted opinion must also be understood [to include a further limitation, namely]: provided that no treaty, truce, or pact confirmed by oath shall have passed between the tyrant and the people; a point noted by Abulensis [Tostado] (on Judges, Chap, iii, qu. 26). For pacts and oaths, even those entered into with enemies, should be observed unless perchance they were manifestly unjust, and exacted by coercion. Yet another limitation should be added as follows: provided 1 [alias, in the Latin.—Tr.] Chap. IV] Does Oath of King James exact more than Civil Obedience? 713 that there is no fear lest the state suffer, in consequence of the slay. x. ...... ing of the tyrant, the same ills as those which it endures Another limitation. j ·ιι r™ r» i under his sway, or ills even more grave. I hus Bartolus has declared (in his Treatise On the Guelphs and Ghibellines, N0.9)1 that 719 it is permissible, under the circumstances described, to put to death a tyrant for the sake of the common good, not for one’s private advantage. For if any person slays a tyrant in order that he himself may by means of a like tyranny obtain possession of the sovereign power, he cannot but be held guiltyof homicide, as well as of fresh tyranny. Again, if it is believed that the son of a tyrant, or another person similarly allied to him, is destined to inflict the same ills upon the state, it will not be permissible [to slay that person], because [in the event of such slaughter] evil is done without hope of effecting thereby a greater good, and because, in such a case, the state is not actually defended, or freed from tyranny,yet these a re the sole titles by which that death maybe justified. And finally, it is required that the state shall not expressly oppose ... [the act of tyrannicide]. For, if the state offers an The last condition. u i r · r express objection, it does not merely retrain from bestowing authority upon private individuals, but furthermore de­ clares that [such a] defensive act is not desirable for it ; and the state must be believed on this point; so that, under these circumstances, it is therefore illicit for a private individual to defend the state by putting the tyrant to death. 10. Yet, in spite of the foregoing arguments, there are authors The opinion of who do not accept the distinction and opinion above other authors. set forth, believing rather that it should be uncondi­ tionally ruled that private individuals cannot licitly slay a tyrant, whether he be tyrannical solely in his exercise of the ruling power, or tyrannical even in the acquisition of his title. This is the view that Alfonso de Castro takes {Adversus Omnes Haereses, Bk. XIV, word Tyrannus), inasmuch as he expresses himseii unconditionally and interprets in this fashion the pronouncements of the Council of Constance. Moreover, all of his doctrines point to that conclusion. Azor has committed himself {[Moral Institutes,] \ol. II, bk. xi, chap, v, qu. 10) to the same stand more expressly, rejecting the commonly accepted opinion above set forth. His position is founded first, upon the fact that the Council of the Lateran2 treats of tyranny in absolute and general terms; secondly, upon the assertion (also absolute) of Augustine {On the City of God, Bk. I [, chap, xviij, that it is not per­ missible to slay any person without public authorization; thirdly, upon the indefinite nature of St. Thomas’ statement that the slaying ot the tyrant in question is laudable, whereas he does not say that the slaying 1 [In Consilia, Tractatus, Quaestiones (1527 Lugduni).—Revises.] 2 [SuArez, no doubt, intended to say ‘Council of Constance’.—Tr.] 1569.74 4 y Bartolus. Caatro. Azor. 714 Cajetan. A Defence of the Catholic and Apostolic Faith [Bk. VI of the said tyrant by any private individual whomsoever is laudable; and fourthly, upon the fact that no malefactor can rightfully be put to death, nor can he who is in possession be dispossessed forthwith, without first being heard and judged. Nor does evidence of an accomplished crime suffice, unless a pronouncement of sentence precedes [the act of tyran­ nicide]. ii. But these arguments are of little force when opposed to the Rejection of this commonly approved opinion. opinion. For, as j have said, the Council of the Lateran1 does not lay down the definite and universal negation, that no tyrant may be slain, but simply condemns the universal affirmation that every tyrant may be slain, a condemnation stated not in an absolute form but rather with a number of qualifying terms, so that the declaration of the said Council is reduced to the following loose formula : ‘Not every tyrant may be slain before sentence has been pronounced against him.’ And one cannot draw from this formula any argument in contravention of the common opinion. To the words ofAugustine I reply that the private A reply to Augus- individual who slays a tyrant of the kind in question, tine· does not commit this deed without public authoriza­ tion, since he is acting both12 by the authority of a tacitly consenting state, and2 by the authority of God, Who has granted to every man, through the natural law, the right to defend himself and his state from the violence inflicted by such a tyrant. To the argument drawn from St. Thomas, we reply;that his words are sufficiently clear, for in the body of the article cited [on the Sentences, Bk. II, dist. xliv, qu. 2, art. 2] he says : ‘When the authority [to do so] exists, any person may repel domi­ nion of this kind’ ; while in the reply to the fifth objection, St. Thomas makes it clear that he refers to a private individual in using the expression ‘any person,’ since he so interprets the words of Cicero concerning the slayers of Julius Caesar, and since, moreover, he comes to the following conclusion: ‘For he who under such circumstances slays a tyrant, in order to liberate his country, is accorded praise and given a reward.’ As to the [fourth and] last argument, we may say that it has force when any one is to be put to death in punishment for his offence, or deprived of those goods which he holds in peace and as possessions at the moment uncontested, whether formally or virtually; but the case with which we are dealing relates to defence, not to punishment ; nor is the tyrant in possession peacefully, but rather by actual violence, since the state— though it may perchance refrain from opening battle, owing to its inabi­ lity to do so—is nevertheless waging incessant and implicit war, as Cajetan rightly notes, in that it offers all the resistance of which it is capable. 1 [Here also Suarez, no doubt, intended to say ‘ Council of Constance *.—Tr.] 2 [This interpretation of the correlatives vel... vel, attested by Du Cange’s Glossary, is in the trans­ lators opinion preferable here to the classical interpretation (or ... or).—Tr.] Chap. IV] Does Oath of King James exact more than Civil Obedience? 715 12. A new difficulty, however, thus presents itself, namely, the fact that according to the doctrine expounded above there is no difference between the two cases, or two kinds of tyrant. For by that doctrine it is not permissible to slay on private authority even those whose titles are tyrannical, since, on the contrary, public authority is required; yet if the latter form of authority exists, it is also permissible to slay those [true] kings who rule in tyrannical fashion. Accordingly, I argue further as follows. Even a tyrant whose title is tyrannical should be slain [only] in punishment for his crimes or on the ground of defence. In the former case (as has already been pointed out), he may not be slain simply by any private person acting on private authority, because, in the first place, the imposition of punishment is (as I have remarked above) an act of jurisdiction, to be performed by a superior, and because, secondly, not even the very state that has been wronged by such a tyrant may thus punish him save by the intervention of a public council and after a hearing and an 720 adequate judgment of his case, so that the tacit or presumed consent of the state does not suffice to authorize the commission of this deed by a private individual, but rather, an express declaration made by special—or, at least, by general—commission is required. Wherefore it would be impermissible for a foreigner in a private capacity, or, indeed, for one in a public capacity but not endowed with jurisdiction over the said tyrant, to slay the latter on this [punitive] ground, save by express commission of the injured state. But if the act in question is permitted to a private individual only on the ground of defence, there is, consequently, no distinction between the two kinds of tyrant, since it is also permissible for a private individual to slay on that defensive ground a true king, who tyrannically assails [the rights of] his own kingdom, or state, as we have already pointed out. Moreover, on the same ground, it is not a power tacitly granted by the state to its members that makes such an act of homicide permissible; rather is it rendered permissible by the authority of God, VVho through the natural law has bestowed upon every person the right to defend himself, his country and, furthermore, every innocent individual. Therefore, the killing of a tyrant on this ground is permitted not only to the members of a state, but also to foreigners, in either case and with respect to either kind of tyrant, so that no difference exists. 13. To the last question I reply that, in the first place, it is true The difficulty is that a tyrant wrho seizes kingly power without a j ust title thereto may not justly be slain by any private individual whomsoever, as a measure of vengeance, or punishment. For this negation is conclusively established by the arguments set forth in connexion with the first part of our twofold proposition. A new difficulty is presented. 7i6 A Defence of the Catholic and Apostolic Faith [Bk. VI Consequently, I grant that with respect to this point no distinction is made between a tyrannical king of the kind in question [and one whose title to power is lawful], in so far as the essential principle of injustice is concerned ; although, in the case of a lawful king, the crime committed is much more grave and constitutes an act of lese-majesty, which does not occur in the case of tyrants of the other group, for such a crime, when committed against them is a simple act of injustice and of usurped jurisdiction. We are thus left to conclude that only the right of self-defence makes it permissible for private individuals to slay [even] this latter sort of tyrant. There is a great difference, however, between such a tyrant and a wicked [but legitimate] king. For [a true] king, though he may govern in a tyrannical manner, is not inflicting actual violence upon the state subject to him, so long as he does not begin an unjust war against it; and consequently, in so far as he is concerned, no occasion for defence is offered, and no subject may attack him or wage war against him on defensive grounds. A true tyrant, on the other hand, is inflicting continual and actual violence upon the state as long as he unjustly retains the royal power and reigns by force; so that the said state continually wages against him an actual or virtual war, not vengeful in its character (so to speak), but defensive. Moreover, pro­ vided the state makes no declaration to the contrary, it is always regarded as willing to be defended by any of its citizens, or, for that matter, even by any foreigner ; and therefore, if it cannot be defended in any way save by the slaying of the tyrant, any one of the people can licitly slay him. Thus it is indeed true, strictly speaking, that this act of slaughter is committed, under the circumstances described, not by private but by public authority; or rather, by the authority either of a kingdom willing to be defended by any citizen whomsoever as by its own members or organ, or else by the authority of God, the Author of nature, Who gives to every individual the power of defending the innocent. Accordingly, even in this respect no true distinction is made between the two kinds of tyrant, since neither of them may be put to death on private authority, public power being, on the contrary, always a necessary factor. The difference between the two cases, however, is as follows: owing to the distinction explained above, the power in question is considered to have been entrusted to every private individual as against a true tyrant, while this is not the case as against a true sovereign [who rules in tyrannical fashion]. 14. But in view of the foregoing, still another difficulty arises, , one whose treatment is necessary to our rpresent Another difficulty. ' purposes. For from the comment just made regarding true tyrants, it follows Chap. IV] Does Oath of King James exact more than Civil Obedience? 717 that the preceding comment regarding [true] kings who govern tyranni­ cally, is applicable only when sentence of deposition has not yet been passed against such a king, and not after the passing of that sentence; this is an inference which will not be pleasing to the King of England, and it is one which merits examination. For it has a firm basis, first of all, in the Council of Constance, inasmuch as that Council refers only to persons slaying tyrannical princes on private authority ‘without awaiting1 the sentence or man­ date of any judge whatsoever’ (since it is thus that the Council of Constance condemned the contrary proposition) ; so that consequently, if any judge possessing lawful jurisdiction with respect to such a [legitimate but tyrannical] king, whosoever that king actually is or may be, has pronounced against the latter a just sentence whereby the said king has ipso facto been deposed from his throne—if, I say, this should be the case2—the declaration laid down by the Council no longer holds; and therefore, the argument expounded above would cease to be valid, with the result that our comment regarding true kings, in the form previously propounded, would no longer be tenable. For under such circumstances, it is assumed that the sentence which has been awaited3 is a just and lawful one. Accordingly, the tyrant’s assailant acts not upon private authority but by virtue of the said sentence and, consequently, as an instrument of public authority. In short, when a king has been lawfully deposed, he is no longer a 721 legitimate king, or prince; and therefore, the statement [of the Council of Constance], which has reference to legitimate kings, cannot hold true in his case. And furthermore, if after the lawful deposition of such a king he should persist in his obstinacy and forcibly retain the royal power, he will become a tyrant even in regard to his title, since he is not a lawful king, nor is it by just title that he holds kingly power. This truth is more clearly evident in the case of a heretical king. For in a sense, and by reason of his heresy, such a king is forthwith The reason for* de- deprived, ipso facto, of his dominion over and propnving a heretical prietary rights in the kingdom, since the latter awaits nion over the king- confiscation, or is to pass ipso ture to nis lawtul dom· Catholic successor; and nevertheless, [this heretical ruler] may not be deprived at once of the kingdom itself, but on the contrary justly continues to possess and administer it, until at least he is condemned through a declaratory judgment of his crime. This point is brought out in the Sext (Bk. V, tit. 11, chap. xix). On the other Sat, v.n.xix. 1 [Vide footnotes 2, p. 707 and 3 of this page. Suarez has expectata, here.—Ta.] 2 [This parenthetical clause translates a single word in the Latin, tunc.—Ta.] 3 [expectata. Cf. notes 2, p. 707 and 1 of this page. One is tempted to give the term its late connotation of spectata, here, and transfate, ‘ the sentence referred to ’, or, ‘ the sentence in question’ ; but the closely preceding quotation from the declaration of the Council of Constance, in which expectata would seem to have the usual classical significance, makes such a translation inadvisable. Probably Suarez's implied meaning is, * the sentence which has been awaited before the ty rant is put to death.’—Ta.] 718 Vide Soto, De lustitia, Bk. V, qu.3 i, art. 3. Azor, Vol. II, bk. XXI, chap, v, qq. 8 and 9. St. Thomas. Soto. Bànez. Molina. Paris de Puteo. Antonio Massa. A Defence of the Catholic and Apostolic Faith [Bk.VI hand, once the sentence has been pronounced, he is deprived altogether of the said kingdom, in such a way that he cannot by any just title continue in its possession; and therefore, from that time forth, he may be treated absolutely as a tyrant, and consequently may be put to death by any private individual whatsoever. 15. This difficulty1 depends upon the assumption that even a king A solution of the who is supreme in temporal matters may be punished difficulty. with deposition and sentenced to be deprived of his kingdom; an assumption which the King of England declines to con­ sider, but which is nevertheless true and follows clearly upon the. principles laid down in Book III.2 Moreover, we shall have occasion to repeat it in a subsequent part of our discussion. To be sure, the question, By whom may such a sentence be imposed ? is a grave one. But for the present we shall assume, briefly, that this power to depose a king may reside either in the state itself or in the Pope, although differently in the two cases. For it resides in the state solely by way of a defence necessary to the preservation thereof, as I have already remarked (Bk. Ill, chap, iii).4 If, then, a lawful king is ruling in tyrannical fashion, and if the state finds at hand no other means of self-defence than the expulsion and deposition of Under what circum- this king> the said state, acting as a whole, and in stances the state accordance with the public and general deliberations may deprive ajtrue^ θ£ communities anj leading men, may depose him. tyrannical fashion, This would be permissible both by virtue of natural of his kingdom. [aWj renders it licit to repel force with force, and also by virtue of the fact that such a situation, [calling for measures] necessary to the very preservation of the state, is always understood to be excepted from that original agreement by which the state trans­ ferred its power to the king. This is the sense that we should give to St. Thomas’ declaration (II.—II, qu. 42, arts. 2 and 3 [art. 2, ad 3]) that it is not seditious to resist a king who is ruling tyrannically, provided at least that this resistance is offered through the lawful power of the community itself, and prudently, without causing greater injury to the people. Moreover, it is thus that St. Thomas himself has expounded this very point (De Regimine Pnncipum, Bk. I, chap, vi), as have his disciples, Soto (De lustitia, Bk. V, qu. 1, art. 3), Bânez (on 11.-I I, qu. 64, art. 3, doubt 1), and Molina (Vol. IV, De lustitia, Tract. Ill, disp. vi). Others, however, from among the jurists previously cited, take a mixed view of this matter. For Paris de Puteo, [De Sindicatu, § An liceat occidere Regem] and Antonio Massa (tract. Contra Usum Duelli, 1 [See Sect. 14, supra, p. 716.—Tr.] Bk. Ill, chaps, v and xxiii.—Tr.] 1 [For ‘4’ read ‘qu.’—Tr.] 2 [Supra, pp. 667 et seq.; Defensio Fidei Catholicae, 4 [Not included in these Selections.—Tr.] Chap. IV} Does Oath of King James exact more than Civil Obedience? 719 Nos. 78 and 79) support the statement in question in such a way that they apparently concede even to individual citizens the licence to act thus. Yet, on the other hand, Restaurus Castaldus ([De Imperatore,} Rettai.ru* aforesaid Qu. 82) supports the contrary view to such a degree that he CastalJu4· would seem to deny such license even to the community. But [these two extremes of opinion] should be modified, in accordance with our preceding remarks. 16. Nevertheless, the power of which we are speaking does indeed reside in the Pope, as in a superior possessed of jurisdiction for the cor­ rection of kings, even supreme monarchs, these princes being regarded as subject to him. This is a point which we have already demonstrated.1 Accordingly, in the case of crimes relating to spiritual matters, such as the crime of heresy, the Pope has direct power to inflict punishment therefor upon the king, even to the point of deposing the latter from his throne if his obstinacy and a consideration for the common good of the Church should so demand. Again, in the case of faults relating to temporal matters, in so far as these faults constitute sins, they, too, maybe corrected by the direct power of the Pope, to the extent, indeed, of their temporal harmfulness to the Christian State ; and punishment of these faults may at least be inflicted by his indirect power, in so far as the tyrannical rule of a temporal prince is always pernicious also to the salvation of souls. 17. Moreover, another point should be noted, as follows: even a Christian king- though a state, or human kingdom—regarded solely d°m thePopendhet ^rom t^ie standpoint of its own nature, as it existed h^epo^s^tyran" once among the Gentiles and exists still among the nicaiking. heathen—possesses the aforesaid power to defend itself against a tyrannical king, and to depose him with a view to such self-defence, in cases of necessity, I repeat, even though this be true, nevertheless, Christian kingdoms, when they so defend themselves, are in a sense dependent upon and subordinate to the Pope. This assertion is true because, in the first place, the Pope may demand of any [Christian] kingdom that it shall not rise hastily against its king, nor depose him, unless the cause and reason therefor have previously been examined by the Pope himself. The latter possesses this power because of the moral dangers and the loss of souls almost certainly accompanying these popular tumults, and also for the sake of averting sedition and unjust rebellion. Thus history records that Π. in such cases the kingdoms involved have almost always consulted the Decretum, xv. vi. iii. Pope, or even have petitioned that he should be the one to depose Duarte Nunez Liaô, Pn722 a wrongful king or a tyrant. We are told that this occurred in the do metra Parte case of Childeric, King of France, when Zacharias was Pope (Decretum, Dos Chronias Dos Reis dè Pt. II, causa xv, qu. vi, can. iii), and in the case of other persons whom Portugal, ados 1 [Supra, pp. 685 et seq.; Defensio Fidei Catholicae, Bk. Ill, chap, xxiii.—Ti.J Capello. 720 A Defence of the Catholic and Apostolic Faith [Bk. VI I have mentioned previously.1 Moreover, the histories of Portugal relate at length that Sancho II, king of that country, was deprived of his royal administrative powers by Innocent IV, when the latter was Pope, although Sancho’s kingdom was not taken from him. This incil.vin. ii. dent is recorded also in the Sext (Bk. I, tit. vm, chap. ii). Secondly, a Christian kingdom is dependent upon the Pope in that the latter not only has power to advise or consent to the deposition by the kingdom of a king destructive to itself, but may even command and compel the said kingdom to take this course, when he shall have concluded that such an act is necessary for the spiritual welfare of the realm and, especially, for the avoidance of heresies and schisms. For Vide Αζοτ, under these circumstances the exercise of [his] indirect power with Vol. Ill, bk. respect to temporal matters for the attainment of a spiritual end is II, chap, vii, most admissible. Another argument is afforded by the fact that, in a qu·3°· Castro, De situation of this sort, the Pope 'per se possesses direct power to depose lusta Haereti. Punit., Bk. II, the king; and therefore, he possesses the power by which he may chap. xiv. coerce the kingdom, in cases of necessity, to the execution of this purpose, since otherwise his power [of deposition] would be not only inefficacious, but also insufficient. And the final argument is, that such a papal command, under such circumstances, is [in itself] an exceedingly just command. 18. Accordingly, granting the truth of this basic assumption, we In what way a king maF assert> regard to the point last proposed, may be punished, that, after the rendering of a lawfully authorized after a just deciar- condemnatory sentence by which a kin? is deprived atory sentence. r, . . J J ° *. 01 lus realm, or—ana this comes to the same thing— after a declaratory sentence for a crime entailing ipso iure the punish­ ment in question, the person who has passed the sentence, or the one to whom that person has entrusted the task, does indeed possess the power to deprive the said king of his realm, even by slaying him, if no other means will avail, or if a just sentence includes such an extreme penalty. However, the deposed monarch may not be slain forthwith simply byany private person whatsoever, nor may he even be driven out by force, until that private individual has been commanded to act thus, or unless a general commission to this effect is contained in the sentence itself or in the law. The first part of our assertion2 follows clearly upon the principle above set forth. For he who can justly condemn a given person, is also able to execute—whether by his direct intervention or with such assistance as may be necessary—the punishment he has imposed; other1 [Supra, Defensio Fidei Catholicae, pp. 685 et seq. ; Bk. Ill, chap, xxiii.—Tk.J 2 [The assertion as a whole would seem to include both sentences of the immediately preceding paragraph in the English, and * the first part ’ of the assertion is evidently contained in the first, or affirmative sentence. Suarez undertakes to prove the second, or negative statement, in Section 19. -Tk.J Chap. IV] Does Oath of King James exact more than Civil Obedience? 721 wise, his power to declare the law, unaccompanied by any effectively coercive power, would be vain. It is for this reason, indeed, as Augustine says (On the City of God, Bk. I, chap, xxvi), that an agent of the king acts rightly in slaying a man at the king’s command, since under those circumstances he is carrying into effect the power of that monarch, rather than his own. Similarly, then, when a state can justly depose its king, the agents thereof act rightly in coercing that king, or—if it be necessary—in slaying him; for in such a case they are acting not on private, but on public authority. Thus Soto has well said (De lustitia, Bk. V, qu. I, art. 3), that even though a king who is a tyrant solely in his manner of rule [and not in his title to the throne] may not be slain simply by any one at all, ‘nevertheless, when sentence has been passed (these are the words of Soto) any person may be appointed as the agent for its execution.’ In like manner, then, if the Pope deposes a king, only those persons whom the Pope himself has charged with the task will have the power to drive out or slay that king. And if the Pope does not enjoin upon [specific] persons the execution of his decree, the said task will fall to the lot of the lawful successor to the royal power; or else, in the event that no such successor has been found, the kingdom itself will be charged with this function. Moreover, the Doctors hold that the same principle is to be observed in connexion with the crime of heresy, when declaration is made by public sentence depriving a heretical king of his kingdom. Castro (De lusta Haere­ ticorum Punitione, Bk. II, chap, vii) and Didacus de Simancas (Institu­ tiones Catholicae, Tit. xlvi [, chap, xlv,] no. 75) may be consulted on this point. 19. The foregoing remarks also afford a ready proof for the second part of our assertion.1 For even though a given person has been justly condemned to a private individual death’ be raaï not be slain at will simply by any may not on his own private individual whatsoever, unless this individual slay anmanawho°has bas been commanded or in some other way impelled been condemned to to the act of slaughter by one in authority. This condeath‘ dition holds because one person may not kill another, unless the slayer is either a superior possessing in himself the power to do so, or else the agent of such a superior; and he may not be called an agent unless his act is instigated by the authority of his principal. But if all this is true with regard to any malefactor, it will surely hold true with greater reason in the case of a prince. It will perhaps be argued that these requirements are satisfied by the implicit or tacit instigation of the state, which by virtue of the very fact that it has deposed the king declares its will that he be driven 1 [Le. the negative part, prohibiting completely unauthorized private persons from executing the sentences in question. Vide footnote 2, p. 720.—Tr.J 1569.74 . z Augustine. Soto. Castro. Simancas. 722 A Defence of the Catholic and Apostolic Faith [BE VI out, coerced, and even—in case he resists—put to death, by the agency of [any or] all persons. Such a contention, however, is false, a fiction devised in defiance of reason. For a judge, in condemning a heretic or malefactor who is a private individual, does not by that very act empower all persons to punish such an individual; and consequently, when the state, or the Pope, condemns a king who is heretical, or tyrannical in some other fashion, such [punitive] licence is not—even in a tacit or implicit sense—granted to every one [indiscriminately]. The consequent is true because there is no just reason to assume the existence of this licence as against a king, more readily than as against other persons. For prudence and just procedure in the actual execu­ tion [of a sentence] are always essential; and furthermore, a greater danger of disorder and excess attends the coercion of the person of a prince or king than that which attends the coercion of other individuals. Therefore, if the Pope issues a decree declaring that a given king is heretical and deposing him from his throne, but containing no fuller 723 specifications with regard to the execution of the sentence, all other princes are not forthwith empowered to make war upon the deposed monarch, since they are not (so we assume) his temporal superiors, nor does that Pope invest them, by the sole force of his decree, with the power to make such a war. Consequently (as I was saying) only the lawful Catholic successor of that monarch is invested under these circumstances with the said authority ; or, in case he should be disregardful of it, or no such successor should exist, the kingdom as a whole body, provided that it is a Catholic body, will succeed to the right in question. But if this kingdom itself seeks the aid of other princes, they may lend such aid, a fact which is self-evident. Furthermore, if the Pope bestows upon other kings the power to invade the kingdom of the deposed ruler (and the examples which we have adduced in Book IIP prove that the Pope has quite frequently done this), such an invasion may, under those conditions, be justly undertaken, inasmuch as they lack neither a just cause nor the necessary authority. 20. In the light, then, of these true and unquestionable principles, we find clear and convincing proof of the fact that the The principles ex­ third part of the oath exacted by King James in­ pounded above afford convincing volves, under various heads, an excessive assumption proof of the error involved in the of power, injustice opposed to righteous custom, and oath exacted by error in contravention of true Catholic doctrine. King James. To prove the first of these points, i.e. the fact that an excessive assumption of power is involved, I ask : By what authority does the King of England compel his subjects to swear that a certain proposition is heretical, when it has not been so condemned by the 1 [Supra, pp. 701-2 ; Depensio Fidei Catholicae, Bk. Ill, chap, xxiii, at end.—Tr.] Chap. IV] Does Oath of King James exact more than Civil Obedience? 723 Catholic Church ? For if the King maintains that the said proposition was condemned by the Council of Constance, we may object, in the first place, that it is impossible for him to make such an assertion consistently, inasmuch as he rejects the authority of the Councils, and particularly that of the modern Councils. By way of a second objection, we may ask where he can find, in the decrees of the Council of Constance, the words, ‘princes which be excommunicated or deprived by the Pope’; or these, ‘by their subjects or any other whatsoever?’ Accordingly, in view of the fact that the addition of these phrases to the proposition in question effects an immense change in it and in its purport, the inference by which [the condemnation of] this [altered] proposition is attributed to the Council, is fallacious and misleading.1 On the other hand, if King James condemns the said proposition, not on the authority of the Council of Constance, but simply on his own authority, then, beyond any possibility of doubt he exceeds and abuses a power which is not [even rightly] his. Moreover, it is very strange that he should repeatedly disparage the papal power of defining points of faith, while he himself dares to arrogate this same power to himself; for though he does not make this claim in so many words, he professes to do so by his acts. In this arrogation of power, the king is guilty of further inconsistency, inasmuch as he boasts in another passage of this Apologie for the Oath of Allegiance that he himself does not, after the fashion of the Popes, fabricate new articles of faith. In fine, since he holds that nothing is of faith save what is contained in the Scriptures, he should show us the Scriptural text condemning the proposition in question as heretical, or the text whereby the contrary proposition is divinely revealed, before we may regard as a heresy the one [condemned by him]. To be sure, Paul said [Romans, Chap, xiii, v. i]: ‘Let every soul be subject to higher powers’; but nowhere did he add: Let all be subject even to powers that have been excommunicated or deprived [of their authority] by the Pope. Neither may the one injunction be inferred from the other; for they are quite different from each other, not to say mutually opposed (as it were) since a king who has been deposed is no longer a higher power. Wherefore, I further conclude that the profession of the said oath of allegiance, in so far as this [third] part of it is concerned, is tantamount to an acknowledgement of the royal authorityand power both to condemn propositions as heretical at the king’s own pleasure, and to lay down rules for the faithful, on his own authority, as to what they should believe as proper to the faith and what they should denounce as heretical. On the part of the king, [the exaction ofjsuch anoath is anabuseand usurpation 1 [The translator has preferred here the ecclesiastical Latin connotation of illusorius (implied under illusio in Harper’s Latin Dictionary), although the classical Latin interpretation would not be inaccept­ able: ‘the inference ... is a fallacy and a mockery.’—Tr.] 724 A Defence of the Catholic and Apostolic Faith [Bk.VI of spiritual power, and on the part of those who take this oath, [its pro­ fession] is virtually equivalent to a profession of false faith. 21. Moreover, the very words of the oath are a clear proof of the AA convincing . . proof, fact that King James, in ..exacting the same, exacts . 0 J . .. . 0 of this same fact, more than mere civil obedience; that is to say, more based on the very than an oath pledging such obedience. words of the oath. . l· 0 ... ror something in excess oi civil obedience—which is a matter on a far lower plane than the Christian faith—is obviously involved in an oath by which one is pledged tc detest a given proposi­ tion as heretical. This is particularly the case when the injunction [condemning that proposition] is new to the Church, so that the king [issuing the injunction] does not simply compel Christian subjects to detest a proposition that is in any event already condemned by the Church (an action which is at times permissible to a Catholic king if it is executed in the proper manner), but even compels these subjects to detest a proposition which he himself newly condemns, upon his own authority. Such is the conduct of King James in the present situation. The foregoing remarks also afford satisfactory proof of [our second point],1 the fact that the oath in question is unjust on the part of King James, because it exceeds in many ways the proper limits of his power and so becomes a form of coercion by violence, and usurpation of another’s jurisdiction. Again, on the part of the faithful, acquiescence in the said oath is unjust. It is unjust partly for the general reason that they would be swearing either unlawfully or to a lie; since if they believe, solely on the King’s authority, that the [rejected] proposition is heretical, their act merits condemnation even on this ground alone. [But such acquiescence is also unjust] for a much more potent reason, namely, because the proposition condemned in this oath is altogether true, and is rendered certain by the true principles of the faith, as we have previously proved;12 and if, to all outward appearances, the subjects abjure a proposition of this sort, not believing in their hearts 724 that it is heretical, they are guilty of open perjury, a fact that is selfevident. Moreover, 'the profession of such an oath involves also a special and personal injury affecting the Pope, whose power and right to command obedience they deny, moved by the fear of man. 22. Finally, it is easy to draw from the remarks made above, the A twofold error in- inference [embodying our third point]3 as follows: voived in the third this third part of the oath of allegiance also involves part of the oath. , v erroneous doctrine. 1 [i.e. the second defect noted in the third part of King James’s oath : ‘ injustice opposed to righteous custom. ’ Vide the first sentence of Section 20 of this Chapter.—Tr.] 1 [Defensio Fidei Catholicae, Bk. Ill, chap, viii, which is not included in these Selections.—Tr.] 3 [i.e. the third defect in this part of the oath: ‘error in contravention of true Catholic doctrine.’ Vide the first sentence of Section 20 of this Chapter, and footnote 1 on this page.—Tr.] Chap. IV] Does Oath of King James exact more than Civil Obedience? 725 One error is the contention that the Pope is not endowed with power to depose a heretical or schismatic king who is dragging or perverting his kingdom to the point where it will embrace the same schism or heresy. For this error is upheld by the words of the oath most particularly, and more directly than by any other [words pro­ nounced on that matter], as will be immediately evident to every person reading the oath, and as we have previously proved1 by manifold arguments. A second error is not so definitely expressed in the wording, to be sure, but it is implicit in the very substance of the oath, and is virtually included therein, namely, the implication that a temporal king may even exact of his subjects a sworn belief in regard to those matters having to do with the doctrines of the faith and with the renunciation of heresies; and, indeed, the further impheation that the decree of the king is to be preferred, even on these points, to the decree of the Pope. And all this is surely equivalent to declaring that a temporal king holds the primacy in spiritual—or ecclesiastical—affairs. For the primacy of Peter includes no greater dignity, nor any that is more necessary to the conservation of the Church and the unity thereof, than the supreme authority to lay down the articles of faith and con­ demn heresies ; an authority which the King of England arrogates to himself, in the words already quoted. Therefore, the profession of the oath in question is an open profession of schism and error; and consequently, true Catholics are bound in conscience to reject the same. 1 [Defensio Fidei Catholicae, Bk. VI, chaps, i—iii, which are not included in these Selections.—Ta.]