[The Title-Page of the Edition of 1621] A WORK ON THE THREE THEOLOGICAL VIRTUES FAITH, HOPE AND CHARITY Divided into Three Treatises, to Correspond with the Number of the Virtues Themselves by Doctor FRANCISCO SUAREZ of Granada Member of the Society of Jesus and Sometime Primary Professor Emeritus of Theology of the Royal Academy of Coimbra Dedicated to the Most Illustrious and Most Reverend Lord D. JOÀO MANOEL Bishop of Vizeu, &c. With the Privilege of the Inquisitors, of the Ordinary, and of the King Printed at Coimbra By NICOLAUS CARVALHO, Printer to the Academy In the Year 1621 •--------------- : I i 'Ί - -é; [iü] TO THE MOST ILLUSTRIOUS LORD D. JOÂO MANOEL, MOST EMINENT BISHOP OF VIZEU, WISEST OF COUN­ SELLORS TO THE CATHOLIC KING The Jesuit College of Coimbra Far more tardily than befits us, most illustrious Bishop, this Col­ lege of Coimbra, belonging to our Society, and by many titles yours also, offers to you this gift, such as it is. For this College is keenly aware that in you alone there are combined in the highest degree all those qualities by which authors are customarily moved to pay such tribute to their benefactors. They are the glory of your name, and of your truly royal lineage, the distinction of episcopal rank, choice literary culture, and what surpasses and almost eclipses all other titles, an admirable union of all the virtues that adorn a man and a prince. For if it is not unbecoming to pass over other considerations, it would seem to betoken not a human, but (as it were) a divine excellence, that one who excels in every way, should be unassuming in his mode of life, not elated by honours, and, though of an exalted position, not disdain­ ful even of humble friends. For those reasons, indeed, Father Francisco Suarez, while living, had long been aware that he ought by some outstanding product of his talents, to manifest in unique fashion the gratitude due to you before all others. This, I bear witness, was the perpetual and constant -wish, this the ardent endeavour, of one whose last wishes it would be wrong, in our judgment, utterly to disregard, especially as he could have found no more favourable advocate for his teachings, no readier champion of his labours. However, we found at hand no work of this kind by which the debt could be completely discharged, and which could be considered a gift worthy of your acceptance. [iv] But, lo ! there now speaks one from above (in my belief, none other than the author), who says: ‘You have here the treatise on the theo­ logical virtues, by means of which you may carry out the wishes of Suarez, and which you may quite fittingly lay before the illustrious Bishop of Vizeu, so that he who is known to have cultivated these virtues long and well, shall also be the patron of that teaching concern­ ing them, by which the minds of men are disposed to harmony? Doubtless, Suarez had foreseen that this posthumous offspring of his talents, when it had come into our possession, and being bereft of its parent, would have need of your protection and your guardianship, so that, should it chance to be exposed to the arrows of the envious, I5Î9.74 5A Ίο the Readers 73° it might be sheltered as by a rampart. For though the author was one whom the plaudits of the world, already universal, had raised above the reach of envy, nevertheless, now that he has attained to that more blessed felicity, far removed from human intercourse, he has been able to look, for this solicitude, to you alone, his strongest and most loving defender. In truth, how’ever, our College has been moved [also] by this consideration, namely, that the work should by preference be dedicated to you, if not as an [adequate] manifestation of the cherished hope that we may requite our own debt of gratitude, yet as some slight testimony of the sentiments which, each and every one, we entertain for you. Even though you accord but scanty credit to our own labours in connexion with this work, yet the author was one on whose behalf those labours will seem not unfruitful, and to you, most Eminent Lord, before all others, the fruits of that author should be dedicated. Vale. [v] BALTHASAR ALVARUS, DOCTOR OF THEOLOGY, OF THE COLLEGE OF COIMBRA OF THE JESUIT SOCIETY To the Readers on behalf of the Author There are three chief reasons which have urged us not to confine within the enclosure [of our College] these lectures on the theological virtues. First, one might in all justice anticipate that a discussion of theological virtue by so great a theologian would be worthy, indeed, of so eminent an author and so weighty a subject. Secondly, the greater part of this wrork, which treats of faith, is (as it were) the last offspring of Suarez, generated that he might give a final proof, from his exalted position, of the wealth of his genius and the rich vein of his wisdom. Although, in Spain or in Italy, before he was summoned to this Academy of Coimbra, Suarez dealt more concisely (as he WOuld do in the schools) with the subject-matter of the other two treatises, yet, they cannot fail to evince traces of the author’s power and artistry. Thirdly, since— owing to the reasons which we have just mentioned—many copies of those lectures on faith were transcribed incorrectly, and since the number of these copies increased daily, we have decided to make them public, thoroughly freed from copyists’ errors, and readily accessible to all students, thanks to the help of the press. It will, however, appear that in this work one thing is lacking in [vi] doctrinal method—though you would hardly find any other writer so successful and scrupulous in the observance of that method—that is io say, the author ought first of all to have discussed the theological virtues in general, and then treated thereafter of the points proper to To the Readers 731 each. But a reply is ready to hand. For since all habits that accompany grace, chief of which are the theological virtues, go by the name of holiness, there remained hardly anything to be said as applicable to them in common, that would not be applicable also to sanctifying grace. The matter has been treated by Suarez in his work De Gratia * lately published, in questions such as these: first, are there any such habits per se infused and dwelling in the soul ? Are the principles of their acts adequate (a point fully treated in Book V I) ? Secondly, do the aforesaid habits demand a special co-operation of grace, in order that they may be actualized, or is the general co-operation sufficient (a ques­ tion accurately treated in Book II) ? Then again, thirdly, can these habits become more intense or remiss or be lost altogether (treated in full in Books IX, XI)? However, if an explanation as to other more common elements in these virtues is desired, it will be published, God willing, in the fourth treatise, that on Passions and Habits, where the treatment by St. Thomas (I.-II, qq. 62 et seq.) will be amplified. Fale. 1 [No part of Suarez’s treatise De Gratia is included in these Selections.—Ta.] FRANCISCO SUAREZ A WORK ON THE THREE THEOLOGICAL VIRTUES FAITH, HOPE AND CHARITY Of this treatise On Faith, Hope and Charity, only the following Dispu­ tations are included in these Selec­ tions: Disputation XVIII of On Faith and Disputation XIII of On Charity CONTENTS Page ON FAITH Disputation XVIII: On the Means which may be used for the Conversion and Coercion of Unbelievers who are not Apostates • 737 ON CHARITY Disputation XIII: On War . 800 FRANCISCO SUAREZ A WORK ON THE THREE THEOLOGICAL VIRTUES FAITH, HOPE AND CHARITY ON FAITH: DISPUTATION XVIII [467] DISPUTATION XVIII ON THE MEANS WHICH MAY BE USED FOR THE CONVERSION AND COERCION OF UNBELIEVERS WHO ARE NOT APOSTATES The means by which men may be drawn to virtue and faith, or , recalled from ·vice and unbelief,z are. ·*·partly thosea which The mccins dv which ,* unbelievers may be move the will through persuasion, instruction or 468 converrt^> differ in kindness ; and partly those others, which hold man to his duty through punishment or coercion. Of such means, the former class are, without doubt, more in har­ mony with faith, because their influence is brought to bear more upon the will, and faith should be voluntary. But the latter class are sometimes necessary, if there is not to be a lack of power; and con­ sequently, we are bound to treat of both groups, beginning with the former. Nevertheless, since the second group depend especially upon A twofold coercion: authority, which must reside in some individual, in direct, and indirect, order that he may coerce or punish another, we must first state that this coercion may be twofold, direct and indirect. As to this issue, in order that coercion may be directly applied, two things are required. One is that it should be derived from the power of jurisdiction; the other is that this means should be used to draw men to the faith. Indirect coercion will be present, when com­ pulsion is exerted not intentionally but in self-defence, or else in order to punish the injustice or crime of another. Therefore, this latter sort of compulsion might be exercised withEcciesiasticai juris- out anY Power of jurisdiction. With regard to this diction is twofold in power, it is well to note at the outset that jurisdiction this matter. -n Qlurc}1 js twofold, spiritual and temporal. Hence, unbelievers may be subject to the Church in either of two ways, namely, with respect to the spiritual jurisdiction, as apostates are, or merely with respect to the temporal jurisdiction, as in the case of un­ believers who are not apostates. SECTION I1 HAS THE CHURCH THE POWER AND RIGHT OF PREACHING THE GOSPEL TO ALL UNBELIEVERS EVERYWHERE ? I. In the caption introducing this question, two words, power _Explanahon , t (-potestas} and· right (ius\ must be noted andi-disof what H · j r ' i constitutes the right tmguisned, since they do not mean the same thing, and power of preach- ρ0Γ there are two ways in which one may have the power to perform a given act. First, there is the per1 [It should be borne in mind by the reader that this Disputation and the one following are divided by Suarez into Sections and Sub-sections instead of Chapters and Sections, as elsewhere.—Tr.] 740 Mark, last chap. Colossians, i. Luke, xxiv. The Three Theological Virtues: On Faith missive sense; since one may be allowed to perform an act, although he may have no peculiar right to do so, no proprietary privilege (so to speak) with regard to the practice or act in question, as when I am allowed, for example, to enter the house of another. In the other sense, this power is coupled with right, as in the case of the powrer to make use of one’s own house or of common property. Hence, in the question propounded above,1 the power referred to must be understood in both senses. Therefore, we must assert, first, that the Church has that power [The first proposi- by which it may legitimately preach the Catholic faith tion:] the Church everywhere and to all kinds of unbelievers. This is has lawful power to./ , . . , r r . , . . preach the Catholic obvious and is clearly a matter of faith, as is proved faith in all regions, fay- the words of Christ in the following passages: {Matthew, Chap, xxiv [, v. 14]) ‘And this gospel [of the kingdom,] shall The foundation [of be preached in the whole world, for a testimony to all this proposition]. nations’; (Chap, xxviii [, v. 19]), ‘Going [therefore], teach ye all nations’ ; and (Mark, Chap, xvi [, v. 15]), ‘preach the gospel to every creature.’ For He Who gave this command, gave also the power of carrying it out, as the event has proved. Paul said (in the Epistle to the Colossians, Chap, i [, v. 6]), speaking of the Gospel: ‘It has come unto you, even as it is in all the world bringing forth fruit and growing.’ The reason [for the existence of this power] is also clear. For faith is necessary to all for salvation; and therefore, it was likewise necessary that there should be some way of announcing this faith to the whole world, since otherwise there would not be salvation for all according to the ordinary law, in view of the fact that, by the common and ordinary process, faith comes only through hearing and preaching, as Paul bears witness in the Epistle to the Romans (Chap, x [, w. 14 et seq.]). For this reason also Christ Our Lord said (Luke, Chap. xxiv[, w. 46-7J: Thus it is written, and thus it behoved Christ to suffer, and to rise again from the dead [, the third day]: And that penance [and remission of sins] should be preached in his name [...].’ Consequently, this act of preaching the faith is righteous in its very nature and by reason of its object; hence, it is permissible of itself; and therefore, the power of executing that act is everywhere essentially legitimate, and proper to the Church. Finally, the [possession of the power] in question is also in harmony with natural reason. For the reproval of a brother by fraternal correction, and the instruction of the ignorant, especially regarding those things which relate to good conduct are [acts pre­ scribed] by natural law, and the power of performing these acts— nay more, the obligation to do so at an opportune time—is there­ fore given to all; consequently, when once the fact of revelation and 1 [Le. the heading for Section I. ‘Has the Church the Power and Right of Preaching the Gosoel to All Unbelievers Everywhere ?’—Tn.] Disp. XFIII: On Means for the Conversion of Unbelievers 741 the necessity of faith, are assumed, the act of communicating that revelation through speech and teaching, and the permission to do so, follow (as it were) from the natural law, and therefore, the power of preaching is also derived from it. We may infer incidentally that this simple power (so to speak) The inference [from normally belongs in some degree to all believers, if the first proposithey are sufficiently instructed to exercise it, and are tionl* not otherwise forbidden. This is obvious, for the reason that [such preaching] is a work of charity, and one of the works of mercy, a fact which will be more fully expounded in connexion with the next proposition. 2. My second proposition is as follows : the Church has not only The second proposi- the simple and (so to speak) the permissive faculty of tion concerns the preaching the Gospel everywhere, but also the right ChÏÏSiï power to *° preach thus, coupled with a special power. This 469 preach the true faith is evidently the opinion of St. Thomas, as expressed St. Thomas. everywhere. jn & passage (Π.-ΙΙ, qu. io, art. 8), on which Cajetan Cajetan. and other commentators are in agreement; as are other scholastics (on the Sentences of Peter Lombard, Bk. II, dist. xli), especially Major Major. (ibid., Dist. xliv, qu. 3), others on the Sentences (Bk. IV, dist. iv), Soto. including Soto (ibid., Dist. v, the sole question, art. 10), and V ictoria Victoria. (Relectio I: De Indis, Sect. II, no. 9 [Relectio V: De Indis, Sect. Ill, no. 9]). The basis of that opinion is that Christ our Lord had this power Rack of the second over all men, as His heritage. For that heritage was proposition. to j,e obtained by means of preaching the faith; and since all the nations were not to be instructed by Himself, Christ bestowed the power of giving such instruction, coupled with the corresponding right and authority, to His apostles, and through them to the Church ; therefore, the Church has this special right. The entire first proposition of the foregoing argument may easily be drawn from the Old and New Testaments. For in Psalms, ii [, v. 6], the Psalmist, Psalms, d. speaking in the person of Christ, says : ‘But I am appointed king by him over Sion his holy mountain’, while the mode of acquiring the kingdom is indicated by the phrase [ibid.], ‘preaching his command­ ment’; and then these words are added [ibid., v. 8]: ‘Ask of me and I will give thee the Gentiles for thy inheritance, and the uttermost parts of the earth for thy possession,’ plainly declaring a plenitude of jurisdiction over the whole world. That this prophecy was fulfilled last in and through Christ, Our Lord Himself has testified, saying, Matthew, Mauhm, rhap. last Chap. [chap, xxviii, v. 18], ‘All power is given to me in heaven and in earth’; then follows the command [ibid. v. 19], ‘Going [therefore], teach ye all nations’, whereby He communicates His own right and i Comtfaasu, power to the Apostles. This is Paul’s meaning in the words(2 Corinthians, 742 Three Theological Virtues: On Faith Chap, v [, v. 19]), ‘hath placed in us the word of reconciliation’; to which he adds [ibid., v. 20], ‘For Christ therefore we are ambassa­ dors’ ; and an ambassador, indeed, represents his prince and shares in Ephesians, iv. his power. Accordingly, Paul also said (Ephesians, Chap, iv [, w. 11—12j), ‘And He gave some apostles [. ..] and other some pastors and doctors [...] for the edifying of the body of Christ’ ; and, in his Second Epistle 2 Timothy, a. to Timothy (Chap, ii [, v. 9]), ‘[I labour even unto bands, as an evildoer,] but the word of God is not bound’; that is to say, it is not bound, because the Church has this right of spreading the word, and not merely the right, but the necessity and obligation as well, according j t0 tjie passage Corinthians, Chap, ix [, v. 16]), ‘For woe is unto me if I preach not the gospel, for a necessity lieth upon me.’1 Finally, the John, soi. words of Christ to Peter (John, Chap, xxi [, v. 17]), ‘Feed my sheep,’ support this truth; for the term ‘Feed’ refers not merely to an in­ definite sort of power, but to one coupled with jurisdiction, which is exercised, or rather, is begun, by preaching. Therefore, since this power was given to Peter that it might persist in the Church forever, the Church possesses such right and power. 3. Moreover, if we regard the end to be achieved, a reason can _ c «.· be given for the existence of this authority, namely, authority, in terms tnat the power of teaching the faith was necessary, as of the end m view, is j have said, for the salvation of men, and in order that the redemption of Christ might be brought to all men. Therefore, in order that the said power of teaching might be efficacious, it was necessary to communicate it not only with a simple authorization and (as it were) permission, but also with its own proper right and power. The Lord Christ was able to give that power in this way; hence, He did so give it. Furthermore, although the exis­ tence of such power cannot be demonstrated by natural reason, it is still entirely in harmony therewith, since, as I have said, the right of teaching the ignorant is (as it were) connatural to every man. There­ fore, assuming the necessity for faith, it is entirely consonant with reason that the Author of faith should leave to His ministers and especially to His Vicar this special right of instructing men in the doctrines of the faith. 4. From this second proposition, a third follows, namely: the Church has the right of defending its preachers, and The third proposi­ of subduing those who by force and violence hinder tion : the Church has the right of pro­ or do not permit this preaching. This is the opinion tecting its preachers, held by the authors above cited, and especially by and of punishing those who hinder its Major and by Victoria. It is possible also, in a sense, preaching. to confirm this proposition by an example from Paul (Acts, Chap, xiii [, w. 8-11]), who condemned Elymas the sorcerer to Acts, xiii. 1 [The word order, as given by Suarez, varies somewhat from the Vulgate.—Tr.] Disp. XVIII: On Means for the Conversion of Unbelievers 743 a perpetual blindness for resisting the ways of the Lord, as Jerome stated in his letter Ίο Riparius against Vigilantius [= Letters, cix. 3] and cited in Decretum, Pt. II, causa xxm, qu. viii, can. xiii, where there are many references to the Fathers who confirm this truth; see also Decretum, ibid., can. xi, and other passages therein. Reasons in support of this proposition are easily inferred from The first reason in what we have already said. The first is that if the proof of this proChurch has the right of preaching the Gospel every1,051 on’ where, then whoever by force or violence prevents the exercise of this right, does an injury to the Church. Therefore, the Church may repel such violence and protect its own right; for this [secondary right] follows naturally from the original right [of preach­ ing], especially since the authority in question is supreme within its own order, as is this right in the Church. Secondly, this same reason is reinforced by another principle of _ . both canon and civil law,7 namely: when jurisdiction The second reason. . , , . ,, J . is granted, everything morally necessary for the exer­ cise thereof is granted as well, because otherwise the grant would be minimized and inefficacious {Digest, II. i. 2; and likewise Decretals, Bk. I, tit. xxix, chap, v and other similar passages). But the right in question has been given to the Church as a true power and jurisdic­ tion over the whole world, a fact which has been proved by the words of Christ, ‘Feed my sheep’; and the exercise of that jurisdiction 470 should begin with the preaching of the Gospel; therefore, it is neces­ sary that the Church should at least have the power of protecting [its preachers]. The third reason, which is very cogent, concerns a power that is . natural (so to speak) though indirect. For every state has the power to protect innocent persons who surfer grave injury from those stronger than themselves; but whoever hinders the preaching of the Gospel does the gravest injury to many who per­ chance might have been converted if they had heard it, and who would willingly have heard it, if it had been preached to them; therefore, the Church has the power of protecting those who in that respect are innocent and who suffer a grave injury. Finally, there is another analogy showing that the existence of this power is consonant with. natural reason. It, is as The fourth reason. ri.r , , , r follows: every state has the right of sending ambassa­ dors to treat of peace with another state, and consequently the former has the right of protecting those ambassadors and of avenging an injury if they are ill-treated ; therefore, much more has the Church this right with respect to her own ambassadors who are the preachers of the faith, especially since the Church, as was proved above, has the power, given by Christ, to expand and to occupy the whole world. Jerome. 744 ^he Three "Theological Virtues: On Faith 5. But first we must inquire: In whom is vested this right or power which we have said exists in the Church ? This mg the faith rests question may be asked either with regard to the immem pastors separ- j. J _ ° ately, and is one of diate power of preaching the Gospel, or secondly, common right. with regard to the right to send forth preachers, or thirdly, with regard to the right of defending those preachers and of removing any obstacle in their way. As to the first phase of the question, it must be said that this power is vested as one of ordinary right in each of the pastors of the Church respectively; and by delegation it is vested in those only who are legitimately sent forth by those pastors. The first half of the immediately preceding statement is clearly true, because this power is not only highly necessary to the pastors of the Church, but, more than that, it belongs by virtue of their office to them alone. For the sheep of Christ are to be fed chiefly with the word of faith, and Christ committed His sheep to the charge of these pastors. Moreover, I have said, ‘respectively’, because the power in question, in so far as it is supreme and universal over the whole world, resides in the Roman Pontiff alone, as Salmeron (on the Acts of the Apostles, Vol. XII, tract, xxxviii) well taught. And by delegation, t^ie case bishops, this power is limited to each the power in ques- one’s own diocese, with dependence on the supreme oniy fwho^are Pontiff. In the case of parish priests, it exists in a fully sent out to proportionate degree, as I assume from other paspreach. r sages. The second half of the same statement1 is proved by the custom of the Church. For the practice which has always been observed, from the beginning, is that the ministers of the Gospel should be sent out by the Apostles or by other pastors, according to the passage (2 Corinthians, Chap, iii [Chap, viii, v. 22]), ‘And we have sent with them our brother,’ &c. More explicitly, elsewhere occur these words also (Romans, Chap, x [, v. 15]) : ‘And how shall they preach unless they be sent ?’ Secondly, this restriction is necessary for the observance of due order, upon which depend the peace and the tran­ quillity of the Church, and also for the sake of purity of doctrine; for errors would easily be implanted if any person whosoever should as­ sume to himself the power of preaching the faith; and consequently, this office must be exercised by commission from the Church or from its pastors, a rule which is laid down in the Decretals (Pt. V, tit. vn, chap. xii). Finally, the right in question pertains to the power of jurisdiction ; nor can any one of his own authority usurp the jurisdic­ tion of another, particularly not when this jurisdiction is spiritual and supernatural, and should therefore flow from Christ immediately, The power of preach- Salmerôn. 2 Corinthians, iii [viii]. Romans, x. 1 [FÙÙ two paragraphs above.—Tr.] Disp. XVIII: 0?i Means for the Conversion of Unbelievers 745 or from him to whom Christ directly granted such jurisdiction when he said, ‘Feed my sheep’, or, ‘I send you’. However, all this must be understood as referring to public This must be under­ preaching, which is carried on by virtue of special stood as referring authorization; inasmuch as private instruction and to public preaching, and not to private teaching can be conducted by any one of the faithful instruction. sufficiently learned, when the principle of charity and the occasion should so demand. This is the meaning of the statement in Ecclesiasticus (Chap, xvii [, v. 12]), ‘And God gave to every one of them commandment concerning his neighbour.’ For this sort of in­ struction is not a usurpation of jurisdiction, since such private teaching is given, not as though by virtue of the pastoral office, but by reason of a duty or counsel of charity. St. Thomas (on Romans, Chap, x) adds also that the passage in Romans refers to theordinary [public church] law; for the Holy Spirit, by a private law, may send whomsoever He shall wish, inspiring such a minister with a special impulse to this service. But in that case the Church must be assured by some supernatural act or sign of the validity of this private law, a fact which is brought out in the Decretals (Bk. V, tit. vn, chap. xii). Otherwise—that is to say, if anyone wishes to exercise this gift contrary to the precept and [right] order of the Church (as Innocent III said in a similar case, Decretals, Bk. I, tit. ix, chap, x), such an inspiration must be judged as proceeding from an evil spirit rather than from a good one. 6. In accordance with the foregoing statements, and in regard to the second phase1 of the question above propounded it must be The supreme and asserted that the absolute, supreme and universal ^ndfrSaforthWer °f of sending preachers of the Gospel to such unpreachers°resides in believers resides in the supreme Pontiff alone; because the supreme Pontiff. he a]one is the supreme pastor of the whole flock of Christ, according to the words of Christ, ‘Feed my sheep’ ; and further­ more, because the special duties of extending the bounds of the 471 Church and of disseminating the faith pertain to him, since the other bishops have their jurisdiction limited within definite territorial boundaries. Hence, if there should be any unbelievers of this kind within such territory, any bishop within his own diocese could send to them preachers, or teachers. But as to the territory outside his own diocese, by the ordinary law (as it were) and normally speaking, no bishop below the Pope has this power. However, if necessity presses, or if there should arise a fit occasion for converting any one to the faith, the bishops, as a duty of charity, could send preachers to neighbouring provinces with the approval and the tacit, or interpreta­ tive, consent of the supreme Pontiff, who always in such cases should 1 [Le. ‘In whom is vested . .. the right to send forth preachers?’ See the first paragraph of Sub­ section 5 of this Section, supra, p. 744.—Tr.] >569.74 ς c 746 The Three Theological Virtues: On Faith be consulted as soon as is conveniently possible, that he may, in ac­ cordance with his office, provide for the necessity or take advantage of the occasion which has arisen. 7. With regard to the third aspect1 of our question, there is even The right of protect- greater reason to observe that the duty of defending the PenemerS even t^ie a^oresa^ right, even by coercion and war, if such through war and by defence should be necessary, belongs solely to the coercion, resides in supreme Pontiff. In defence of this statement, we the supreme Ponr ~ , . . . . . tiff; and in what argue, tirst, tnat it is ms duty to defend the universal way this is true. rights of the Church. Secondly, such defence involves the waging of war, and therefore normally requires power of a sove­ reign order; this power does not reside per se in temporal princes, for it is derived from a spiritual right which is not granted to them, but is, on the contrary, joined to spiritual power, the latter being indirectly De Legibus, extended to temporal affairs, as was shown elsewhere. Therefore, the Bk. Ill, chap. via and in other power in question resides only in the supreme Pontiff. places and De­ It must be added, however, that this power does not so belong fensio Fidei, Bk. Ill, from to the Pope that it should be exercised by himself or through eccle­ chap, xxii.2 siastical persons. For it is no part of the priestly office, nor of the ecclesiastical status, to take up corporeal arms, as was rightly held by Ambrose. Ambrose [Letters, xx. 8, To Marcellina], who is cited in the Decretum (Pt. II, causa xxm, qu. viii, can. xxi), where, throughout the first sir chapters [of the Causa], this fact is supported by manifold evidence. Consequently, the Pope has the pow’er of entrusting this defence— that is to say, its execution—to temporal princes, and may even com­ mand them to undertake the change {Decretum, Pt. II, causa xxm, qu. viii, can. viii with other canons in said question viii). It follows, therefore, as Major and Victoria [De Indis, Sect. Ill, Major. Victoria. The supreme Pon­ no. 10] rightly observe, that the Pope can distribute tiff may entrust this among temporal princes and kings the provinces and right of defence to _ _and _ ____ kings, distribute realms of the unbelievers; not in order that the former to them the king- may take possession of these regions according to their doms of unbelievers. own for tbat WOuld be tyranny, as I shall explain later, but in order that they may make provision for the sending of preachers of the Gospel to those infidels, and may protect such preachers by their power, even through the declaration of just war, if reason and a rightful cause should require it. For this purpose, then, the Pope may mark off specific boundaries for each prince, which that prince may not later transgress without committing an injustice. This, as we read, was done by Alexander VI in the case of the kings of Portugal and of Castile. The chief reason of all [for asserting this principle] is the fact that 1 [Le. ‘In whom is vested.. · the right of defending... preachers and of destroying any impediments in their way ?’ See the first paragraph of Sub-section 5 of this Section, supra, p. 744.—Tr.] 2 [Not included in these Selections.—Tb.] Dis'p. XVIII: On Means for the Conversion of Unbelievers 747 it is expedient that this matter, w’hich most gravely concerns the Church, should be conducted in an orderly manner. For that is most necessary, both for preserving peace among Christian princes, and also in order that each of these princes may procure with the greater care the welfare of the people committed to his charge. Therefore, this prerogative belongs wholly to the Pope as one who gives the first im­ pulse (so to speak); for kings are (as it were) his organs and instruments, and consequently no [temporal prince] can transgress the limits pre­ scribed to him, since he cannot act unless he has received this impulse. 8. A further inquiry may be made regarding this same doctrine, and especially regarding the third proposition: an inquiry that is, as Whether the defence to whether such defence of preaching and of preachers of preachers of the of the Gospel is allowed only after injury has been faith is allowed be­ fore any injury has inflicted by unbelievers, or some obstacle has been been done to them. placed in the way of the preaching of the faith; or —The affirmative opinion of some is whether that defence is permitted as a precautionary stated. measure (so to speak) and soldiers may be employed in order to prevent injury to the preachers, or in order that their ministry may not be hindered. For some have said that a Christian prince may justly seize the The affirmative territory of a pagan king on this ground alone, namely, opinion of certain in order that the Gospel may be preached with greater persons. ease anj securjty under a Christian prince. But since this opinion understood, without limitation,is incredible, as will be made clear from what we shall say later on, some have modif fied it by declaring that Christian princes may send forth preachers accompanied by a military force, sufficient, not for the waging ot* war, but in order that the preachers may proceed in security. They add also that a Christian prince may build towers and fortified strongholds in the lands of unbelievers, especially at the national boundaries, in order that entrance and access to such lands may be made easier and 472 more secure for the faithful. Finally, they hold that a prince may collect, from the unbelievers who inhabit the territory in question, whatever expenses he has incurred in such enterprises, since that sum is spent for the benefit of those unbelievers; and that, consequently, he may resort to violence and warfare in order to exact payment, if it is denied, and may proceed even to the occupation of the territory if this should be necessary. That is the opinion of Major ([on the Sentences,] *ÿor· Bk. II, dist. xliv, qu. 2 [qu. 3], and it is based solely upon the principle that preferential favour should be shown to the faith. 9. But this teaching is not to be approved, according to the The negative sounder opinion of Victoria, Bânez, and other modern opinion is approved, authors, as set forth in the passages cited above. First, because it has no foundation in the teachings of Christ, but 748 The Three Theological Virtues: On Faith is rather repugnant to his very words (Matthew, Chap, x [, v. 16] and Luke, Chap. x[, v. 3]), ‘Behold I send you as sheep in the midst of wolves’, words by which He plainly meant that the preaching of the faith was introduced not by arms, but by gentleness, patience, and the power of the word, and also by living example, according to the asser2 c^nnthians, tjon θρ pau] Corinthians, Chap, x [, v. 4]), ‘For the weapons of our warfare are not carnal, but mighty to God.’ Secondly, the opinion in question is opposed to the custom and practice of the Church, for the Apostles and their successors assuredly did not preach the Gospel in that way, nor were the Popes, even after the conversion of the emperors to the faith, accustomed to send forth preachers to unbelievers in such fashion, a fact which is evident from the caseofGregory,whosent preachers toEngland,andfromsimilar instances. Thirdly, the practice under discussion is, in point of fact, not defensive, but aggressive; therefore, it is a virtual coercion to the adoption of the faith, or at least, to a hearing of those who preach the faith ; and such coercion, as we shall presently explain, is not permissible. The first member of this proposition may be explained thus: if preachers are sent with an army, those to whom they are sent may— morally speaking, and not without obvious reason—presume that these preachers have come to seize their territory rather than to provide for their spiritual welfare ; hence, even as a general rule, [these unbelievers] may justly defend themselves, acting upon a prudent presumption; accordingly, an occasion for a just war is given them, and under these Φ circumstances, the practice in question becomes an aggressive rather than a defensive measure; and on the other hand, if [the unbelievers] are not able to resist, and yield through fear, that, in turn, is coercion, even in the highest degree. From this explanation is derived a confirmation of the [concluding] statement [of our proposition, namely,] that such means are not fitted for the introduction of the faith. For they lead to its injury and defamation; since the infidels will think, [if we resort to these means,] that our faith gives us the privilege of violating the ius gentium, and even the law of nature, by our seizure of the property of others against the -will of the owners and by our waging of war without any just ground; and since these same infidels will consequently become more hardened, and more indisposed to receive the faith. Therefore, this mode of introducing the preaching of the faith is not permissible. 10. Accordingly, it should be stated that one ought first to try In what way Chris­ peaceful means, inviting and repeatedly urging infidel tian princes ought to conduct themselves princes and states to permit the preaching of the faith with unbelievers, in in their realms, and to offer or allow security to persons order that the latter may provide oppor­ who come into or dwell within their domains for the tunity for preaching. purpose of performing that task of preaching. This Luke, x. Disp. XV111: On Means for the Conversion of Unbelievers 749 is clearly what Christ Our Lord meant, when He counselled the Apostles whom He was sending forth to preach, that above all things they should proclaim peace {Matthew, Chap, x [, v. I2]). But if the unbeliev­ ing princes resist, and do not grant entrance, then, in my opinion and on account of the reasons given above, they may be coerced by the sending of preachers accompanied by an adequate army. In like manner, if, after the preachers have been received, the infidels should kill them or treat them wrongfully, when the victims are blameless, and for no other reason than that they have preached the Gospel, then an even better reason for just defence and, indeed, for righteous vengeance, has arisen, the latter sometimes being neces­ sary in order that other infidel chiefs may be coerced and may fear to practise like acts of tyranny. For such [defensive action] is in harmony with the natural law and is not opposed to any command of Christ; and if, during the first years of the Church, this mode of coercion was not customarily practised, the reason was, not that this coercion was impermissible, but that the Church in those days had not the temporal means of resisting the enemies of the faith. For in the beginning, Christ our Lord willed to conquer the world by the power of the word and by that of miracles, in order that His own power and the truth of His doctrine might be made more manifest. SECTION II IS IT PERMISSIBLE FOR THE CHURCH AND CHRISTIAN PRINCES TO FORCE THESE UNBELIEVERS TO GIVE EAR TO THE FAITH ? I. With regard to this point, there are two opposing opinions. The first affirms absolutely and unconditionally that opinion. such coercion is permissible. This appears to be Major’s opinion ([on the Sentences,] Bk. II, dist. xliv, qu. 2 [ qu. 4]), M although he does not state it in set terms. 473 Moreover, this view may be suggested by what we have already said {supra, p. 741, Sect. I, sub-sect. 2). For if the infidels could not be forced Argument I in sup- to listen, then the power to teach would be superfluous, port of the affirma- or, at least, in the highest degree useless, since teaching tive opinion. vajn> jf there is no one to hear; but we have said that the Church does possess the power and the right to teach the faith ; and therefore it has, accordingly, the power to obtain a hearing through compulsion. Secondly, the force of the foregoing argument is clear from analogy. For Christ said to his Apostles [John, Chap. xx. v. 23] : gument ' ‘Whose sins you shall forgive,’ &c., wherefore the Church very properly infers that He commanded the faithful to con­ fess their sins, inasmuch as sins cannot be forgiven unless they are The affirmative 750 Valentia. Salmerôn, Luke, ίχ. The Three Theological Virtues: On Faith heard and known; hence, by the same reasoning, if He gave to the Church the power of teaching unbelievers, He therefore gave it the power to force unbelievers to hearken, since there can be no teaching without an audience, or since, at least, such teaching would be vain and useless. Hence, the opinion in question is founded, thirdly, upon the . principle that when ionei of two correlatives is ®granted, Argument III. r i · i . tne other is granted also; since the one cannot exist without the other, as is usually taught in the matter of privileges in a like connexion. What has been stated elsewhere {De Legibus, Bk. VIII, chap, xi)1 may be consulted. Another principle set forth above has a like bearing on this point, namely, the principle that when jurisdiction has been granted, everything is granted without which that jurisdiction could not well be exercised. Finally, I contend, in the fourth place, that an argument is derived . x __ from what was stated above, namely: it is permissible to employ coercion m order to prevent resistance to the preaching of the faith; but if the pagans are unwilling to listen, in that very unwillingness they resist and impede the preaching of the faith; therefore,. . . 2. The second opinion denies unconditionally that the coercion in The second and question is permissible with respect to any unbelievers negative opinion. whomsoever, whether or not they are temporal sub­ jects of the Church or of Christian princes. This opinion was held by Valentia ^Commentariorum Theologicorum,] Vol. Ill, disp, i, qu. x, point 6, near end), and Salmeron (Vol. XII, tract, xxxviii [, on the Acts of the Apostles^ appears to have upheld the same doctrine. The proofs of the negative opinion are, first, that we do not read that Christ gave this coercive power to the Church; neither does it necessarily accompany the power of preaching, since the latter may have been given with respect to those who wish to hear, and since we often see that a given person has the power, the duty and the right of teaching, but has not the power to compel others to hear him. Secondly, such coercion does not seem to be in harmony with the example of Christ. For we read (in Luke, Chap, ix [, w. 54-5]), that once, when He went into Samaria, and the Samaritans proved un­ willing to receive Him, certain of His disciples said : ‘Lord, wilt thou that [we command] fire [to] come down from heaven’, &c. ; to whom Christ replied : ‘You know’ not of what spirit you are. [The Son of Man came not to destroy souls, but to save’,] as if to say that force and threats were not to be used against the Samaritans ; and accordingly, He peacefully withdrew. The same principle of conduct may be observed in other passages, also. According to one of those other passages 1 [Not included in these Selections—Tr.] Disp. XVIII: On Means for the Conversion of Unbelievers 751 [Matthew, Chap, x, v. 14], He said to His Apostles, ‘And whosoever shall not receive you, nor hear your words: [.. .] shake off the dust,’ &c. Thirdly, there is an excellent reason, namely, that faith should be voluntary; therefore, the means to faith Should also be voluntary; consequently, coercion to the faith in the case of the unbelievers in question is not permissible, as we shall observe in the following Section ; and accordingly, coercion to the hearing of the faith is also impermis­ sible. The proof of this deduction is as follows : the essential desirability of the means is the same as that of the end, especially when the means are entirely necessary, and desirable solely on account of the end. The fourth is the principal argument and is as follows: the coercion which we are discussing is either direct—that is, it employs fear, which it inspires with the intention of forcing these unbelievers to the desired act—or else it is indirect—that is to say, it employs fear which is instilled on some other ground, but one from which it is hoped that the act in question will result, even though this result is not intended directly and for its own sake ; this latter method of coercion ordinarily has no place in cases of the sort under discussion, because subject­ matter and occasion for such coercion are lacking with respect to un­ believers of the kind in question; the former sort of coercion, indeed, is always illicit; therefore, . . . The truth of this second proposition is established thus : without jurisdiction, there is no just coercion; the Church has no jurisdiction over unbelievers who are not its [temporal] subjects, while over those infidels who are its subjects it has at most a temporal jurisdic­ tion, which does not extend to spiritual affairs ; and to give ear to the preaching of the faith pertains to the spiritual sphere. 3. A third opinion, which is intermediate between these two, and The third and true which distinguishes between infidels subject to Chris°Pinion· tian princes and those who are not subject, seems to me worthy of approval. Accordingly, I hold, first, that it is permissible for Christian The first proposiprinces to force their own infidel subjects to hear the tionfaith. Such is the opinion held by Pezant and Binez (on II.-II, qu. 10, art. 8). Moreover, although the latter author shrinks from the view because he thinks that this practice was never customary on the part of the Church, nevertheless, the example of Rome has great weight with me. For the Roman Pontiffs use coercion upon the Jews who are their This proposition is subjects, compelling those Jews to hear the preaching proved by means of of the faith once a week, and imposing a penalty upon an example. those who refuse to hear. On this point, one may con474 suit the Bull of Nicholas III which begins ‘Fineam*, and that of Gregory XIII beginning ‘Sancta Mater Ecclesia’. MaUhn, x. Pesant. Bâôex. 752 Some persons, however, reply that this imposition constitutes, not of the a penalty, but a species of tribute, which may justly be foregoing proof. imposed upon such infidels, in their capacity as subjects, but which is remitted by the kindness of the prince in the case of those who hear the preaching; so that the practice in question is not coercion, at least not coercion of a direct kind, but, at most, indirect—or rather a method of inducement through the kindness displayed in the remission of the tribute, a method the use of which is permissible, as we shall explain in the following Section. This evasion of the difficulty, however, although it cannot be clearly This means of eva- refuted, would nevertheless seem to have been devised sion is precluded, without any foundation; for that sum of money whichis imposed upon those refusing to hear, is levied, not on the extrinsic title of a just tribute, but only on account of an omission, or act of dis­ obedience; and apart from this tax, there are other sufficient tributes which are levied upon such infidels because of their temporal subjection. 4. Our proposition, then, may be maintained by an appeal to The rational proof reason· For there are two ways in which the subjects of the same proposi- in question may be compelled to hear the preaching tion· of the word. First, they are bound by divine command to hear the faith, as Victoria maintained (Pt. I of the aforesaid Relectio, no. 36 [De Indis, Sect. II, no. 12]). To be sure, this point does not suffice to justify coercion, at least, direct coercion ; for the observance and enforcement of that command do not pertain to temporal jurisdiction, a fact which is self-evident. Secondly, then, it is possible that there might intervene in this matter some just command issued by the prince himself, for the observance of which he might use coercion upon his subjects. This assumption seems entirely plausible; for the hearing of preaching, is not, in itself and of its own nature, an action that falls within the supernatural sphere, and under the present circumstances subjects could be convinced that it was right and calculated to be for their advantage. Indeed, [such a command on the part of the prince] could even be referred to that welfare of the realm which a temporal prince may and ought to preserve—that is to say, the greater concord and peace of all the subjects: either in order that the unbelievers them­ selves may be set free from the errors [of whose falsity] they can be convinced because these errors are opposed to natural reason as are those which the Gentiles adopt; or else because such errors are opposed to what they themselves admit and believe, as happens in the case of the Jews ; or, finally, because this action [on the part of the prince] may be directed to enabling the subjects to choose the true religion and the true worship of God, since in every human state that is well An evasion Victoria. The Three Theological Virtues: On Faith Disp. XKIII: On Means for the Conversion of Unbelievers 753 governed this care must be taken. Therefore, such a mandate, issued by the prince, is just and does not exceed his jurisdiction; and conse­ quently, he may, by imposing a penalty, compel his subjects to obey the mandate in question. 5. The arguments adduced in support of the second [and wholly The arguments ad­ negative] opinion,1 then, do not militate against this duced in connexion proposition, for they relate only to non-subjects. with the second Thus, in reply to the first argument, we confess that opinion do not mili­ tate against this this act [of coercion] is not to be ascribed to any special proposition. power given by Christ, but we maintain that the ordinary power of a temporal prince is sufficient. Therefore, the second argument is fallacious in appealing to the example set by Christ and His Apostles ; for they did not assume or make use of a temporal principate. As to the third argument, indeed, regarding coercion to belief, although the introductory statements2 may be admitted, the final inference3 is denied : partly on the ground that one may be forced to hear, but not be forced to believe (just as a person may be forced to hear the preaching of the evangelical counsels or that on the grant of indulgences, without on that account being forced either to follow the counsels or to gain the indulgences) ; and partly on the ground that it is not necessary that the command in question be imposed for the specific reason of belief in a given supernatural faith, but for the general reason of choosing the true religion and of avoiding errors which are repugnant even to reason. The same reply may be made to the fourth argument. Bânez, however, adds two limitations to the proposition in quesA twofold limitation tion·4 The first is that this coercion may be allowed of the proposition, solely for the sake of a single hearing of the faith; since by Bânez. otherwise, if it took place frequently, there would be a virtual compulsion to belief. The other limitation is that it be attended by a moderate punishment [in case of disobedience]. But I disagree as to the first of the two limitations: I do so, partly because the contrary is proved by the Roman custom mentioned above; partly because, practically speaking, the [single exercise of] coercion The first limitation would be useless, since, for the acceptance of faith, it is is rejected. not enoughthat its preaching should be heard once, and especially not, in the case of men who have grown accustomed to their errors; and partly, in fine, because there is no reason, if the coercion has been licit once and has had no effect, to prevent it from being licit again. Neither does there follow from such a procedure any virtual coercion to the faith; for our assertion is not that it is permissible for princes to 1 [Supra, p. 750.—TR-] 2 [i.e. ‘faith should be voluntary; therefore, the means to faith should also be voluntary; conse­ quently, coercion to the faith in the case of the unbelievers in question is not permissible. ..TtJ 3 fi_e. ‘and accordingly, coercion to the hearing of the faith is also impermissible.’—Tr.J ♦ [i.e. the first proposition under the third opinion, supra, p. 751.—Tr.J 1569.74 - d 754 I Corinthians, ii. The Three Theological Virtues: On Faith impose this burden simply at will, but that it is permissible for them to do so with prudence and moderation, and in accordance with the attendant circumstances, as may be seen in the case of the example set by Rome. The other limitation, however, is decidedly acceptable. For judge- 475 The second limitament in the case of such coercion should be passed on tion is approved. the same grounds as in the case of a penalty imposed upon one who fails to observe some civil law, the transgression of which, politically speaking, neither causes great disturbance to the state nor is considered to be a very grave matter. 6. Secondly, I hold : it is in nowuse permissible to coerce unbelievers The second proposi- who are non-subjects, to a hearing of the faith. This tion· proposition is much more nearly a certainty than the first ; and is commonly accepted as such, being furthermore proved by the first and second reasons in support of the second opinion, and, especially, by the fourth. The sources of proof I set forth and urge [the second proposition], in the for this proposition, following manner: all coercion, whether it be direct or indirect, requires in the person exercising it a certain jurisdiction or power over the person coerced, since—in view of the fact that all coer­ cion is executed by the infliction of some ill—it cannot be licit except in virtue of a superior power; but Christian princes have no power or jurisdiction over the unbelievers in question; therefore, . .. This minor premiss is proved both by the very terms themselves, in that these unbelievers are assumed to be non-subjects ; and also by the fact that the Church has no spiritual power over such persons (a point which I shall for the present assume to be true, and which I shall discuss more fully in the next Section) ; nor has the Church a temporal jurisdiction, since that jurisdiction resides in the princes and kings of the said unbelievers, these rulers being supreme in their own order; and therefore, such coercion cannot under any title be just. 7. Neither do the arguments relating to the first opinion1 avail against this proposition. For to the first argument, we The answer to the first argument. reply that the power to preach is not formally a power of jurisdiction, but merely the virtue (so to speak) of The arguments re­ enlightening through teaching ; so that the efficacy of lating to the first opinion are this power resides, not in any coercive virtue, but in answered. the efficacy of the word and in the showing of the Spirit and power,2 as Paul said [z Corinthians, Chap. ii]. Nevertheless, it does not follow that this power is fruitless ; for it is morally certain that there will be some who will give ear voluntarily, if there is one to preach. 1 [Supra, p. 749.—Tr.] 2 [virtus, translated ‘virtue’ immediately above, and probably having the same significance here; whereas the ‘power’ referred to earlier in the same sentence is potestas, not virtus. The slight inconsistency in translation is due to the fact that the Biblical passage here cited (Douay version) contains the phrase, ‘in shewing of the Spirit and power.’—Tr.] Disÿ. XVIII: On Means for the Conversion of Unbelievers 755 Accordingly, the reply to the second argument, which was derived by analogy and by similitude with the words, ‘Whose second argument. sins y0U shall forgive,’ is easily evident. For the power to remit sins is one of jurisdiction, and applies to the subject as such; so that, in this respect, there is involved in such power a very different essential principle from that involved in the power to preach. But a certain proportion may be preserved with regard to this point, since, just as the divine precept to confess is joined with the power to give absolution, even so a divine precept to hear and to embrace the faith is imposed together with the power and the right to preach the faith. There is, however, a difference. For the precept enjoining confession falls upon those who are members of the Church, and they can certainly be compelled, through that same Church, to fulfil the said precept; whereas the other precept includes also those persons who are not subject to the Church, and over them the Church can certainly exercise no compulsion. The answer to the third argument is as follows: the principle The answer to the there set forth, with regard to correlatives, applies third argument. only jn the case of those things which are necessary to the use of a power granted in connexion with one of the correlatives; whereas, in the case under discussion, it is not necessary, in order to use the pow’er of preaching, that it should be possible for others to be forced to hear; rather does it suffice that they are licitly able to do so, and that they ought to hear voluntarily. Moreover, the same is true of the other principle adduced. Hence, the reply to the fourth argument is evident, since the The answer to the reasons for maintaining the power to resist those who fourth argument. place unjust impediments in the path of preaching the faith, differ greatly from the reasons for maintaining the power to compel a hearing of the same. For the former power is a means morally necessary, and assumes that an injury which one is allowed to repel, has been committed; whereas neither of these conditions can be found to exist in the latter case, and thus the grounds [for maintaining the existence of this second power] are entirely different. 8. But hereupon a difficulty arises, since it follows from what has . been said that if, perchance, in the case of any infidel kingdom both the king and the leaders of the realm are unwilling to admit the preachers of the Gospel, or to permit them to come into the kingdom, the Church cannot use any violent means or coercion in order that the Gospel may be preached there; and this seems unfitting, because such a nation would not be sufficientlyprovided for ; therefore,... The truth of the [primary] inference is evident. For in such a case, the entire nation is unwilling to hear the Gospel ; and— as has been said—they cannot be compelled to hear it; therefore,. . . The answer to the 756 The Three Theological Virtues: On Faith As to this argument, some simply concede the inference; since follows thence, not that men are insufficiently pro­ certain persons to vided for, but only that they are not thus effectually this objection. provided for, because under such conditions, men may by their own malice, hinder the means of salvation given them, as it is probable that they will do. Nevertheless, I think that, as a general rule, some coercion is 476 allowable under the circumstances posited. In par­ The true solution. ticular, if any pagan state wishes to hear preachers, and if the pagan king prevents the people from so What should be done if the king and doing, then the said state may resist him ; and in this the leaders of the matter it may be aided by Christian princes, in order realm hinder preachers from that the unwilling king shall permit the preaching of preaching. the faith; for in thus [restraining] his subjects he does them an injury, by setting obstacles in the way of their salvation. According to the same reasoning, if the king consents to and desires the preaching, but does not dare to allow7 it on account of the resistance of the leaders or of the realm at large, the king may bring force to bear upon his subjects; and if he lacks the power, then, in this matter, also, he may be aided by Christian princes, for the reason given above. Finally, if both the king and kingdom offer simultaneous resistance, I think that they may be forced to permit the preachers of the Gospel to live in their territories; for this tolerance is obligatory under the ius gentium and cannot be impeded without just cause. Moreover, that king and that people may be forced to permit these preachers to declare the word of God, without suffering violence or treachery, to those who are willing to hear; since it is probable that there will never be lacking individual persons who will hear voluntarily. For, even if we assume that the king and his kingdom are offering resistance, still, not absolutely all individuals are included under the term ‘king­ dom’, but rather, the Councils or chief men, or else the greater or greatest part of the kingdom; and always, without exception, the Church retains unimpaired its right to preach in that kingdom, and to defend the innocent (so to speak)—to defend, that is, individuals who may wish to hear the word. Accordingly, under such circum­ stances, there is involved no coercion to the hearing of the faith, but only a coercion to refrain from impeding the preaching of the Gospel, or placing obstacles in the way of those persons who may voluntarily choose to give ear to such preaching. The reply made by Disp. XFLII: On Means for the Conversion of Unbelievers 757 SECTION III AFTER A SUFFICIENT PRESENTATION OF THE GOSPEL, IS IT ALLOW ABLE TO USE FORCE TO COMPEL BELIEF ON THE PART OF THOSE INFIDELS WHO HAVE BEEN SUFFICIENTLY INSTRUCTED ? [1.] This question may be discussed both in its relation to those . . unbelievers who are in every sense non-subjects, and e rs opinion. .q re]atjon to those who are temporally subject to the Church. Hence, we have the first opinion, which teaches that it is permissible to use force upon unbelievers, even upon those who are not subjects, in order that they may accept the faith after it has been sufficiently expounded to them. Such is the opinion of -Major (on the Sentences, Bk. II, dist. iv [dist. xliv, qu. 4]); and—so it is said—in the time of Charles V, and with reference to the Jews, a certain Genesius Sepûlveda [, De Fato et Libero Arbitrio] strenuously defended the same view. This opinion may find a basis in the words of Christ {Luke, Chap. xiv [, v. 23]):‘Compel them to come in’, that is, into The first proof. Church, as Gregory (Homily XXXIX [Homily XXXVI], On the Gospel) and Chrysostom explain (Homily XIV, [On Matthew}1 in their discussion of that point. Therefore, Christ gave the power to compel unbelievers to come into the Church; and that power given by Christ extends to every one. This point is confirmed by the example of Christ, who used force upon Paul to make him sub­ mit to the faith. Augustine {Letters, xlviii [xciii, no. 5]) makes use of this example in a similar case. I base a second argument upon reason, as follows: these pagans , , sin grievously in not accepting the faith after it has The second proof. , ° mii it t t r been sufficiently heard by them; therefore,on account of this sin, they may justly be punished, and through punishment coerced to accept the faith; consequently, men have power to punish the sin in question, for it pertains to the Providence of God so to order human affairs that public crimes shall not remain unpunished; there­ fore, the power under discussion resides in the Church alone, because that power presupposes the existence of the faith which is found in the true Church and there only. Thirdly, expediency may be adduced as an argument. For through , such coercion great bgood may be anticipated; since, The third proof. , i b i i S r i l granted perhaps that those who are coerced may be converted less sincerely or even fictitiously, still those who follow,— and wrho will greatly outnumber the former—will believe the more easily, and many innocent children will be saved through baptism. 1 [St. Chrysostom there speaks very indirectly of the Church. His main point is that St. Matthew was speaking of the kingdom of God.—Reviser.] Major. Genesius Sepulveda. Luke, xiv. Gregory. Chrysostom. Augustine. 758 Gregory. Scotus. Gabriel. Angelus. Council of Toledo. Decreturn. Decretals. Gregory. Augustine. The Three Theological Virtues: On Faith Therefore, because of this beneficial result, the coercion in question may be allowed. For if any evil follows therefrom, that evil is not wrought, but [merely] permitted, by the Church. This argument may­ be supported by the authority of Gregory ([Letters,] Bk. IV, letter vi), according to a passage in which, for a similar reason and with regard to a similar case, he uses almost the same words. 2. According to the second opinion, the Church and Christian . . . princes -, may compel acceptance of the faith on, the The second opinion. x 7 ,r r ,, , . part 01 those who are temporally subject to them, although this is not the attitude taken with regard to those who are not subj'ects. Scotus (on the Sentences, Bk. IV, dist. iv, qu. 6) upholds this second opinion; while Gabriel and Angelus follow him, but on the condition that the coercion be indirect, not direct, a limitation which will be discussed later. The opinion in question is founded first of all upon the arguments in favour of the first opinion, which a fortiori support this one. Secondly, the practice of the Church may also be adduced in 477 support of the latter view, for the kings of Spain used the power of which we are speaking. Ferdinand forced the Moors to accept the faith; and before Ferdinand, King Sisebut, he who is called ‘most religious’, had done likewise in the case of the Jews, and is praised for that deed by the Fourth Council of Toledo (Chap. Ivi [Chap. Ivii] cited in the Decretum, Pt. I, dist. xlv, can. v and the Decretals, Bk. Ill, tit. XLii, chap, iii, last section). The Sixth Council (Chap, iii), and the Seventeenth Council of Toledo (Chap, viii), have also expressed a favourable opinion of the act of Sisebut. The Decretum (Pt. II, causa xxiii, qu. vi, can. iv) quotes Gregory, too, as declaring in his Letters (Bk. Ill [Bk. Π ], letter xxvi), with regard to the Jews who were subject, that : ‘They should be burdened with such a weight of fines that they are compelled through punishment [to accept the faith].’ Lastly, there is the rule of Augustine (Letters, cciv [clxxiii. 2, in Migne ed.]),‘Wicked men are to be restrained from evil and compelled to do good’, cited in Decretum (Pt. II, causa xxm, qu. iv, can. liv). Unbelievers are wicked, and the faith is for them a great good; therefore, they may be forced by their princes to accept this good. 3. Finally, a special argument may be added as to these unbelievA confirmation as to ing subjects, namely: that the coercion in question is unbelieving subnot repugnant to the faith; that with respect to such jects’ unbelievers the power to coerce is not lacking, nor is there lacking a suitable reason for such coercion; and that therefore, the coercion is permissible. The major premiss of this argument may be proved, first of all, from the example of heretics, on whom the Church imposes the faith Therefore, the sort of coercion under discussion is not repugnant to Disp. XV111: On Means for the Conversion of Unbelievers 759 the faith. Hence, there does not seem to be any solid and true basis for the contention urged by some persons, in this connexion, namely, that faith resulting from coercion is slavish and involuntary, and there­ fore a sacrilege. For in the example mentioned [that is, in the case of heretics] this contention appears to be proven erroneous. Its erro­ neous nature may also be proven by reasoning, as follows : when the wish is forced it retains, absolutely speaking, its character as a wish, although relatively it may be involuntary; but it is sufficient for the acceptance of the faith that the act be voluntary, absolutely speaking. To this we may add the consideration that a man is very often induced by punish­ ment and coercion to change his will utterly and absolutely; and there­ fore, coercion is permissible with respect to many benefits which could not well exist without an absolute wish, as Augustine teaches at some length (in the aforesaid Letters, xxiv [Letters, cciv, which is clxxiii, no. 2, in Migne ed.]) and as we read in the Decretum (Pt. II, causa xxm, qu. iv, can. xxxviii). The minor premiss1 of the chief argument may be proved as follows : the unbelievers in question are assumed to be subjects of Christian princes ; and a prince has powrer to coerce his subjects, especially as to those matters which are necessary for their salvation; moreover, the prince or the immediate prelate may compel a subject to obey not only his owm commands, but also the law of a superior sovereign; and therefore, much more certainly may a temporal prince compel his subjects to obey the law of the Supreme Heavenly Prince, and to obey, consequently, the law of faith. Furthermore, a prince may forcibly restrain a pagan subject from blaspheming against the Christian reli­ gion, and from inflicting any injury upon it; but those unbelievers have blasphemed in not believing a faith sufficiently set forth to them, for they think and declare that it is false, and therefore may justly be punished and through punishment forced to conversion. This is especially true since these pagans may be convinced that what is set before them is much more prudently credible than the errors in which they themselves live. Therefore, the power in question is not wanting to Christian princes. Finally, and in accordance with the preceding remarks, it is easy to prove the remainder of this minor premiss, namely, that a suitable reason [for such coercion] is not lacking. For it is to be hoped that much good will result from this coercion, either to the parents or to the children or to those who follow, as we have gathered from Gregory [Letters, Bk. IV, letter vi]. Neither is there any reason to fear greater evils, for it is worse that unbelievers should persist in their errors than that their conversion should be fictitious. They and not the Church are responsible for that fiction, and conse1 [ix. the statement that, ‘with respect to such unbelievers the power to coerce is not lacking, nor is there lacking a suitable reason for such coercion’. See the first paragraph of this Sub-section.—Ti.] Augustine, 760 St. Thomas. Cajetan. de la Palu. Durandus. Soto. Richard Middleton. Antoninus. Abulensis [Tostado]. Sylvester. Castro. Victoria. Salmeron. Henriquez. The Three Theological Virtues: On Faith quently, there is no reason to consider this coercion as an evil in itself. 4. Nevertheless, the third and common opinion of theologians is The third and true that unbelievers who are not apostates, whether sub­ opinion. jects or not, may not be coerced to embrace the faith, even after it has been sufficiently proposed to them. So St. Thomas teaches (IL-II, qu. 10, arts. 8 and 12); as do also Cajetan [on II.-II, ibid.], de la Palu (on the Sentences, Bk. IV, dist. iv, qu. 4), Durandus (ibid., qu. 6), Soto (ibid., dist. ix, qu. I, art. 3 [dist. v, sole question, art. 10]), Richard Middleton (ibid., dist. vi, art. 3, qu. 1), Antoninus (\Summa Theologica,'] Pt. II, tit. xn, chap, ii), Abulensis [Tostado] (on Kings, Bk. I, chap, viii, qq. 34, 182, 183), Sylvester (word baptismus, Pt. iv, qu. 6), Alfonso de Castro (De lusta Haereticorum Punitione, Bk. II, chap, iv), Victoria, at length (Relect. De Indis, Sect. II, no. 15), Salmeron (Vol. XII, tract, xxxvii) and Henriquez (Summa Theologiae Moralis, Bk. II, chap, iv, no. 8 [Bk. II, chap, iii, no. 8]). This is abso­ lutely a true and certain opinion, which we shall prove, in separate sections dealing first w’ith non-subjects, then with subjects. More­ over, we shall speak first of direct coercion, and shall then add some remarks as to indirect coercion. 5. We hold, first, that it is essentially wTong to force unbelievers who are not subjects, to embrace the faith. The first proposition: to The proof of this proposition is that such compel unbelievers who are not subjects to em­ coercion cannot occur without lawful power, as is brace the faith is essen­ self-evident, since o thenvise all wars and all acts tially wrong. of violence could be called just; but the Church The proof of the first pro­ does not possess this lawful power with respect position. to such unbelievers. Therefore, . . . The minor premiss of this argument may be proved as follow's: the power in question has not been given by Christ, 478 tïnuXpÎemiif. nor does it: reside in the princes of the Church from the very nature of the case—not, at least, with respect to the unbelievers mentioned. The first half of the foregoing state­ ment—namely, the assertion that Christ did not give this special power to the Church—may be proved, first, from what we have said in the preceding section [Sect, n, subsect. 2], where we demonstrated that Christ did not give such power of forcing these unbelievers to hear the faith, therefore, neither [did He give the power of forcing them] to embrace the faith after hearing it; for the same reasoning is valid in both cases. Secondly, this minor premiss may be proved by a negative argument, since, in the tradition of the Church, there thTSTrVimiil· is no trace of sucil P°wer> either in its practice, or in Scripture; for the words of Christ, ‘Compel them to Disp. XVIII: On Means for the Conversion of Unbelievers 761 come in’ have a meaning very different from this, as I shall show below. Thirdly, the same premiss is established affirmatively by the words of Paul (z Corinthians, Chap, v [, w. 12-13]), I Corinlhùuu, ‘For what have I to do to judge them that are without ? For them [. . .] God will judge ; words based, surely, upon the fact that these persons are not under our jurisdiction. This was the opinion expressed by Innocent III in the aforesaid Decre­ Dtcretals. tals (Bk. Ill, tit. xlii, chap, iii) and enunciated by the Council of Council of Trent (Session XIV, chap, ii), as follows: ‘The Church passes judge­ Trent. ment upon no man who has not first entered it, through baptism.’ Innocent III upholds this same view in another Chapter of the Decretals Innocent III. Chrysostom. (Bk. IV, tit.xix, chap, viii); and it is the common opinion ofChrysostom, Theophylact. Theophylact, Ambrose, Anselm, St. Thomas, on the text cited (on Ambrose. i Corinthians, Chap, v, v. 13), and of Augustine (De Verbis Domini, Augustine. Sermon VI, chap, vii [in Sermones supposititii, Sermon λ I, chap, vi, Vol. V, col. 1751 Migne ed.]). Therefore, Paul, loc. cit. [z Cor., v. 13] in order to make it clear that this power was not given to men, added, ‘For God will judge them that are without.’ The judgment, then, and consequently the punishment and coercion of such unbelievers, have not been committed to men. Wherefore, Christ our Lord instructed the Apostles (Matthew, Chap, x [, v. 10]) whom He sent forth to preach, Maiûm, x. not to carry a staff or a sword; and with respect to this passage, Jerome Jerome. [on Matthew, Chap, x] notes that Christ forbade methods of coercion and taught peace, concluding His instructions with the words: ‘Who­ ever will not receive you, it shall not be remitted to them on the day of judgment’, meaning thereby that God has reserved to Himself the punishment of this crime, just as He said elsewhere (Matthew, MaUkrtr. la*t last chap. [Mark, Chap, xvi, v. 16]): ‘He that believeth not shall be ch*p. condemned.’ Fourthly, the same premiss is proved by the canon law, for this coercion is prohibited therein (Decretals, Bk. V, tit- VI, chap, ix; Decretum, Pt. I, dist. xlv, cans, iii and v). The prohibition, however, arises, not so much from a prohibition of the Church, as from an explanation of the same. Hence, in the Decretals (Bk. II, tit. xlii, chap, iii) such coercion is said to be contrary to the Christian religion. Pope Gregory was of the ' same opinion (Letters, Bk. I, letter xci [letter xlvii] and Bk. XI, letter xv [Bk. IX, letter vi]) as were Ambrose (on Luke, Chap, x), and Chrysostom Ambrose. Chrysostom. (on Matthew, Chap, xxxiv). From the foregoing, the strongest argument is derived, namely, that if the power in question had been specially granted prSiiif by Christ it WOuld not be vested immediately in temporal princes, because Christ granted no power 1569.74 .5* 762 The Three Theological Virtues: On Faith immediately to them. Therefore, this power would reside in the bishops, and especially in the supreme Pontiff. But the pastors of the Church themselves do not acknowledge the possession of this power, nor have they ever used it ; and Christ our Lord said to Peter simply this: ‘Feed my sheep.’ Therefore, it is certain that Christ has not given this power to the Church. 6. Finally, an argument may be derived from the end in view; for such a coercive method of drawing men to the the ïïmePpremis. would not befit the Church; on the contrary, it would be much more expedient that the first accep­ tance and profession of the faith should be absolutely and entirely spontaneous. This spontaneity is desirable, first, in order that the power o£ the divine word and of the grace of God may be manifested in this work of conversion, which is especially the work of God, as Christ John,™. said (John, Chap, vi [, v. 29]). Accordingly, Paul wrote (2 Corinthians, 2*Conntkians, χQv . ψΟΓ tpe weapOns of our warfare are not carnal’, &c., i Corinthians, and again (z Corinthians, Chap, i [, v. 26]): ‘[there are not many wise according to the flesh,] not many mighty [, not many noble].’ The same spontaneous element is desirable, secondly, because the coercive method in question would involve many disadvantages, since it would, as a general rule, be followed by feigned conversions and innumerable acts of sacrilege. The unbelievers also would be much scandalized and would blaspheme the Christian religion if, by any human power, they were forced to embrace that religion, which is entirely supernatural. Therefore, the special supernatural pow'er of which we are speaking has not been given to the Church. Again, as to the fact, no proof is needed that this power, in so far as concerns pagans who are not subj ects, does not reside in the Church from the very nature of the case ; for this truth is expressed in the terms themselves, since from the very fact that we assume that these pagans are not subjects—at least, not temporal subjects—we consequently imply that the Church has no temporal power over them; therefore, it has no other power with respect to them from the nature of the case; for there exists no other power derived from the law of nature over human beings as members of a human state. Moreover, even the power in question comes not immediately from God or from the law of nature, but mediately through man’s devising and from the ius gentium. Therefore, to no state or prince is this power given with respect to aliens, but only with respect to the members of that particular state; and these unbelievers, in addition to the fact that they are not members of the Church, are supposedly not even members of a secular state under the rule of a Christian prince. Therefore, the power in question does not extend to them. Disp. XV111: On Means for the Conversion of Unbelievers 763 7. Secondly, the following proposition must be laid down: the Church may not exercise compulsion even upon those tion· pagans who are temporally subject to it, in order that they shall embrace the faith. This proposition is easily proved from 479 the preceding one, since the reference is to direct compulsion, which requires power and jurisdiction. For from what has been said, it is evident that the Church has not such power over the infidels in question, by any special grant from Christ; inasmuch as the proofs adduced above are universal, and the canon laws, when they forbid any coercion [of subjects] and declare it to be contrary to the Christian religion, refer to pagan subjects in particular. Yet the Church is not forbidden to wield temporal power over these pagan subjects, for the latter can be members of a civil state, although the supreme temporal power of that state resides in a Christian prince. Nevertheless, that power does not extend to the act of punishing such subjects because of their sin in not embracing the faith after it has been sufficiendy proposed to them; for the power in question, being proximately derived from men, is accordingly directed only to a natural end, and especially to preserving the peace of the state, and natural justice, and the virtue appropriate to such an end ; whereas the aforementioned sin of unbelief is a matter entirely apart from that purpose and end, so that the punishment of it does not fall within the scope of this [tempo­ ral] power. Therefore, the power of coercion to effect an acceptance of the faith cannot rightfully be claimed by virtue of such [temporal] power; for that coercion cannot be justly exerted unless it be in the form of a just punishment for an offence opposed [to the acceptance of faith]. Hence we see, even in the case of the Church, that to what­ ever extent it may justly compel unbelieving apostates to return to the faith, to precisely that same extent it may justly punish them on ac­ count of apostasy from the faith professed by them in baptism ; and therefore, wherever the power for the punishment of unbelief is want­ ing, there is lacking also the power to compel an acceptance of the faith. This fact is further confirmed by all the arguments from inexpediency w’hich have been adduced in this, and in the preceding Sub-section. 8. From this proof it may easily be understood that the preceding proposition refers to direct coercion exerted directly The fourth [third] proposition: in­ to this end, namely, the prevention of unbelief and direct coercion to the acceptance of the faith. Accordingly, we must compel acceptance of the faith is not make an additional statement as to indirect coercion, intrinsically evil. to the effect that such coercion is not in itself and intrinsically evil, if applied under the proper conditions. This is the opinion of Saint Antoninus, Angelus in passages already cited, and V alentia (Vol. Ill, disp. i, [qu. x,] point 6, [ad 4]); and the same view is The second proposi- St. Antonin». Angelus. Valentia. 764 Gregory. The Three Theological Virtues: On Faith to derived from Gregory {Letters, Bk. VII, letter xxx [Bk. II, letter xxxii] and Bk. IV, letter vi [letter xxvi]), for in the first mentioned place he advises that a portion of the just tribute be remitted to pagan subjects, so that through kindness they may be drawn to the faith; and in the latter place, he says that if some of the pagans become too contumacious, they are to be loaded with burdens in order to recall them to their senses, a course of action which is indirect coercion. He states a like view elsewhere {Letters, Bk. Ill, letter xxvi, cited in Decretum, Pt. II, causa xxm, qu. vi, can. iv). The reason [supporting the proposition that such indirect coerThe reason for the cion is not intrinsically evil] is as follows: coercion is proposition stated indirect when any right [asserted] or punishment inabove‘ flicted under one particular title or on account of a given offence is secondarily directed by the one exercising [the right, or inflicting the penalty,] to the end of inducing another to exercise some act of the will ; and in the case under consideration, the power to punish or to exercise compulsion on account of a just end is not lacking, while the secondary end, consisting in the conversion of another to the faith, is not evil, but, on the contrary, is in itself vir­ tuous. Therefore, the act of indirect coercion [to this secondary end] is not in itself evil, but can be justified. The truth of the major premiss and of the consequent is clear. The minor is also proved bv the fact that the Christian princes in the case under discussion mar justly punish the pagan subjects on account of offences other [than unbelief], or they may impose tributes upon such subjects. Therefore, if the princes should judge that this [imposition of penalties or of tribute] WOuld be useful for the conversion of the subjects, they mar bear in mind this additional intention and may impose the burden in the manner best adapted to such a [secondary] end. 9. However, as I have said, this indirect coercion should be apUnder what circum- P^ed under the proper conditions ; for there are two stances indirect coer- conditions, above all others, which must be observed, cion should be used. Qne that ·η impOSing any burden or in inflicting any evil, the bounds of justice are not to be transgressed, since if they should be transgressed, the coercion would, for that reason, be inequit­ able. Take, for example, the statement of Gregory, [Letters, Bk. IV, letter xxvi] to the effect that greater taxes could be imposed on such pagans for the purpose in question, provided, however, that these taxes be just; for within the limits of just taxation one tax may be heavier than another even to the maximum amount, which, for the rest, is termed ‘rigorous’ ; up to that limit, then, a tax may be increased, but no further. The same is true as to punishment, which may be increased or diminished at the will of the prince; and thus a rigorous punishment, which is nevertheless just, may be imposed. In the same Disp. XFIII: On Means for the Conversion of Unbelievers way, Catholic princes have, when there is just cause, the power to prohibit unbelievers from dwelling in their kingdoms: as when [such fellow-countrymen] would be dangerous to the faithful; or after un­ believers have been conquered in a just war, so that they may be expelled on that ground and punished (as it were) by exile; or surely, if they are strangers and aliens, and may [on that account] be forbidden to acquire a domicile in the kingdom. In such cases, then, a Christian prince may prohibit unbelievers from dwelling in his realm unless they are converted, as was stated in the Sixth Council of Toledo (Chap, iii); and that act on his part is, indeed, a form of indirect coercion. It is necessary, however, that this act of expulsion be just. io. The other condition [to the proper exercise of indirect coer480 Prudence must be cion] is that the end of conversion shall be sought observed in the use prudently. For the kind of coercion in question, even of indirect coercion ·* · ·.. to convert unbe- though indirect, carries with it the danger of a counter­ lievers to the faith. fei t conversion, and therefore thorough precautions must be taken lest unbelievers be admitted to the faith and to the Sacraments without sufficient examination, and without a moral certi­ tude that their conversion is real. On this point it must be especially noted, that to take such precautions is the duty of the pastors of the Church, rather than of temporal princes; for the princes may work piously in this way, by striving for the just conversion of un­ believers, but it is not for them to admit to baptism those who are thus converted and ask for baptism. This function pertains rather to the pastors of the Church, and therefore it is for the latter to test and examine such conversions, and to avert in all cases the moral peril of a pretence. ii. From all of the above it may be gathered that this indirect indirect coercion to coercion, strictly speaking, takes place only in regard takes^piace'oniy7 to su^Jects> because lawful power to inflict ills upon with respect to7 non-subjects is lacking, unless they are first reduced pagan subjects. to subjection by reason of an offence committed in a kingdom not their own, or by the title of a just war. However, I have used the term ‘strictly speaking’, because even though non-subjects may not positively (as it were) be afflicted with punishments and loaded with burdens, nevertheless, they may be de­ prived of gratuitous benefits, advantages, or favours; and such means also may be well adapted to drawing them to the faith or to a favour­ able inchnation towrard it, and may be considered as a kind of indirect coercion. Without doubt, coercion exercised only in this way is per­ missible, because no jurisdiction or superior power is required in order to deprive any one of such benefits. Moreover, since it is entirely per­ missible to entice these unbelievers to the faith by kindness and good deeds, when there is hope of success, as is evident from the statements Council of Toledo. y66 isaias, xxviii. Chrysostom. The Three Theological Virtues: On Faith made by Gregory (Letters, Bk. XIII, letter xii [in Migne, P.L., p. 1268, col. 2]); therefore, conversely, when kindness is of no avail, these same pagans may rightfully be deprived of such benefits, in order that ‘vexation may give them understanding’ [Isaias, Chap. xxviii, v. 19]; for this vexation is legitimate, as I have already ex­ plained. 12. The first argument in support of the first opinion1 was T . derived from the words of Christ, ‘Compel them to first argument in come in’, words which Augustine (in Letters, xlviii and opCfiontSu^sec^if1 Lxc^· 2 and clxxxv]) interprets as referring to real the passage in Luke, compulsion by means of a penalty. However, he applies plained literally*' t^ie Passa£e *n question to heretics and apostates; for he explains that the first group who have been invited, are the Jews; the second, who have simply been called, are the Gentiles; while the third, who are under compulsion, are the heretics. Concern­ ing the latter, we shall answer, first, that it is indeed permissible to use force upon them. But the literal interpretation would seem, in my opinion, to be that adopted by Chrysostom and others, who say that this passage refers to the end of the world, at which time, in order to complete the number of the elect, there will be used a kind of compul­ sion upon the number lacking—compulsion, not by means of punish­ ments or real violence, but by the might of signs and miracles and by the efficacy of preaching and of inner grace. Such was the power manifested in the conversion of Paul, which is cited as an example by the authorities above-mentioned. The second argument in support of the first opinion is based The answer to the uPon tiie Power of punishing wrongdoing, to which second argument for we reply that God has not given men the power of the same opinion, punishing all the evil deeds of mankind; since He has reserved some of these deeds for His ow*n tribunal, because otherwise the human race could not be governed with peace and justice. And among these sins which God has reserved for His own judgement, is the sin of unbelief, in those who have not professed the faith through baptism. This inference we may well derive from the words of Christ and of Paul, quoted above; for without such a divine reservation, even greater evils would necessarily result. Therefore, as to the third argument, based upon expediency and The reply to the upon the fact that the successors of such unbelievers third argument. might, [by the coercion in question,] be more easily and more surely converted, it should be replied, first of all, that evil should not be done in order to bring about good. Furthermore, experience ^Sëi-V 1 [Le., the opinion that: ‘it is permissible to use force upon unbelievers, even upon those who are not subjects, in order that they may accept the faith after it has been sufficiently expounded to them.’ Vidt the first paragraph of Sub-section i, p. 757.—Tr.] Disp. XVIII: On Means for the Conversion of Unbelievers 767 has taught that such success is not obtained by that kind of coercion, but rather, that the contrary is true. Hence, Gregory did not adduce the argument of expediency, save in the case of indirect coercion, to be exercised only in a lawful manner and with due circumspection. 13... As to the arguments in favour of the second opinion,1 the ...... _ ina examples set by the Spanish kings which are cited, The arguments ffavour of the second chiefly regard indirect coercion applied in virtue of a opinion, and set just title, such as was the practice of Catholic kings. forth in Sub­ sections 2 and 3, are For if formerly Sisebut somewhat exceeded due limits, answered. his intention only and not his action is to be praised; and similarly if, perchance, a proper moderation is not observed in indirect coercion, although that fault may be excused on the ground of good faith, yet the result proves that the act was not fitting. As for the second argument in support of the second opinion, the argument regarding the law of a superior, the reply is that this holds good with respect to subjects and in connexion with delegation by a sovereign prince; but, as I have explained, God has not com­ mitted such pow’er to men. Finally, it is not enough that the faith should be capable of being made clearly credible; for authority {potestas) is requisite to coercion, and authority is lacking in the case under discussion. 481 SECTION IV MAY UNBELIEV ERS BE FORCED TO ABANDON THOSE OF THEIR ERRORS AND FALSE RITES WHICH ARE CONTRARY NOT ONLY TO FAITH BIT ALSO TO REASON ? I. In the subject-matter of faith we have distinguished, in former Chapters, between two main categories—one concern­ Two kinds of un­ belief are dis­ ing the entirely supernatural mysteries; another con­ tinguished. cerning a group of either divine or moral truths which can also be known through a natural process [, that is, by reason]. Therefore, a twofold kind of unbelief may, in like manner, be dis­ tinguished ; the unbelief which is opposed to supernatural truths only, and with which we have hitherto been chiefly concerned; and the unbelief which is opposed also to natural reason, and concerning which something remains to be said. Now in regard to the latter point, we may also assume, from 1 [i.e. the opinion that, ‘the Church and Christian princes may compel acceptance of the frith on the part of those who are temporally subject to them, although this is not the attitude taken with regard to those who are not subjects.’ Vide the first sentence of Sub-section 2 of this Section, p. 758.—Tt] 768 what has already been said, that unbelievers may not be coerced to accept this [set of truths] as revealed, and as something believers may be to be believed by faith ; but we ask whether or not, in ercori whidTtS t^s m^tter, they may at least be compelled to think contrary to natural correctly in accordance with reason or with some kind understanding. of ]luman faith, anj consequently to abandon external rites contrary thereto, such as idolatry and the like. In the consideration of this question, the usual distinction must be made, with respect to those unbelievers who are civil subjects of the Church, or of Christian princes. 2. Concerning non-subjects, Major (on the Sentences, Bk. II, dist. xliv, qu. 4) and Sepûlveda {De Fato et Libero The first opinion affirms [that com­ Arbitrio), then, have logically maintained that pagan pulsion may be idolaters may be forced by the Church to worship used] even against non-subjects. the one God and to relinquish the rites of idolatry, and that if these pagans refuse [to do so], they may justly be punished and deprived of their liberty and their kingdoms. Possibly, the basis of this view is the fact that a Christian state The basis of this has the right to defend the divine honour, and to supview· press and avenge blasphemies against God ; but idolatry is a serious offence to the Almighty and connotes blasphemies against Him, as St. Thomas (II.-II, qu. 94, art. 3, ad 1) teaches; therefore,... The major premiss of the argument is also derived from St. Thomas {ibid., Qu. 10, arts. 8 and 11), where he asserts specifically that un­ believers may be forcibly prevented from uttering blasphemies against God’s name. The same opinion can also be supported by reasoning, as follows : one man may licitly defend the life or the honour of another; and therefore, still more rightfully may a man defend the honour of God. The first confirmation of such a view is this: if the heathen The first confirma- sacrifice grown men or children to their gods, they tion of the view in may be forcibly compelled to abandon this practice, question. least on the ground of defence of the innocent; therefore, Christian princes may take the same measures towards any heathen people, on behalf of the honour of God. The second confirmation is that the Romans have been praised The second confir- for the reason that they made subjects of the barbarian mation. nations, in order to recall those nations to a better way of living; as is evident from Augustine {On the City of God, Bk. V, chaps, xii and xvii), and from St. Thomas {De Regimine Principum, Bk. Ill, chaps. iv et seq.). The final confirmation is that certain peoples are so barbarous, The third confirma- so unfitted to acquire naturally the knowledge of God, tionthat they seem fashioned by nature for a state of Whether un- Major. Sepulveda. St. Thomas. Augustine. St. Thomas. The Three Theological Virtues: On Faith Disp. XVIII: On Means for the Conversion of Unbelievers 76c) slavery, as Aristotle {Politics, Bk. I, chap, i [, §§ 4-6] and chap, iii [Bk. I, Aristotie. chap, ii, § 15]) has remarked; therefore, even on this ground, they might be forced to true knowledge and to an upright way of life. 3. Nevertheless, the true and certain opinion is that those un. .. believers who are. not subjects, cannot normally be The second and true r . . J, . J. opinion denies the forced even to change their errors and their rites. tru* ί This is the view of the commentators on the above men a ve. cjtejartjcjesjn.Thomas, namely,on[II.-II, qu.10,] St. Thomas. arts. 8 and 11, and by Cajetan (on II.-II, qu. 66, art. 8), Victoria in Cajetan. Victoria. the aforesaid Relectio, no. 40 [De Indis, Sect. II, no. 16], Soto (on the Soto. Sentences, Bk. IV, dist. v, sole question, art. 10), Covarruvias (on Covarruvias. Sext, in rule peccatum, De Reg. Jur., Pt. II, § 10, no. 3), Valentia (Vol. Valentia. Aragôn. Ill, disp. i, qu. 10, point 7), and Aragôn (on II.-II, qu. 10, art. 8). This true opinion may be proved, first, by appeal to divine example; for when God wished to destroy or punish The proof of the true opinion, the people living in the Promised Land, He willed, through an example. not that they should be conquered by the Israelites solely on account of idolatry, but that they should thus be conquered on account of the wrong they had committed in denying to the children of Israel a peaceful transit through their lands, and because of other similar wrongs; a fact which one deduces from the Book of Numbers (Chap. XX). Augustine, too, has noted this point (on Num- Augustine. bers, Qu. xliv [in Questions on Heptateuch, Bk. IV, qu. xliv]; on Josue, Qu. x [in Questions on Heptateuch, Bk. VI, qu. x]) ; and it is also brought out in the Decretum (Pt. II, causa xxm, qu. ii, cans, ii and iii). From this example the general rule is inferred that it is not permissible for a prince to make war on the peoples in question, save in order to avert or vindicate some injury inflicted upon himself or upon his subjects. Therefore, the sole purpose of overthrowing idolatry is not a sufficient ground for a just exercise of coercion. Hence, Pope Nicholas, in reply P<4* i3‘ to the questions of the Bulgarians, said : ‘As to those who sacrifice to idols, we can say nothing more than that such persons must be reclaimed by reason rather than by force.’ The reason supporting the true opinion is the same as that which has been suggested in previous passages, The proof of the true opinion, namely, that the Church has no jurisdiction over the through reason. unbelievers in question, and that coercion or punish482 ment without jurisdiction is unjust; for both these points have been proved. Therefore, just as one private individual may not punish or coerce another private individual, and just as one Christian king may not be accorded such treatment by another Christian [king], nor an infidel ruler by another infidel [ruler], so neither may an infidel state, supreme in its own order, be punished by the Church on account of its crimes, even if those crimes are contrary to natural reason; and 1569.74 //ο The Three Theological Virtues: On Faith consequently, it may not be compelled to give up idolatry or similar rites. 4. Neither is it pertinent that such sins (as was noted in the basic The reply to the argument [for the first opinion])1 are sins against grounds on which God. For as I have already said, God has not made the^rst opinion is men judges to avenge all wrongs done to Him by any man; on the contrary, He has willed that due order be observed in this respect, [namely,] that subjects should obey their princes, while, on the other hand, He has reserved sovereign princes for His own tribunal in those matters which relate to the natural order, because greater evils would result from the opposite course. Moreover, in reply to the observations made concerning blas­ phemy, it should be said in the first place that idolatry is not formal blasphemy, but only virtually and inclusively such. It should also be said that a Christian prince may compel the unbelievers to cease from blaspheming, when their blasphemy is in contempt of the Church and to the injury of the Christian religion, because from such an act on their part there arises a just ground for war; even as these same infidels may be forcibly prevented from harming Christians, and from dragging the latter into error or compelling them to desert the faith; whereas the case is far otherwise when the sins of infidels, although contrary to religion, are against God alone. The reply, then, to the first confirmation [of the first opinion]2 is The reply to the first eyident. It wras in view of this reply, moreover, that confirmation [of the I inserted [the limiting term,] ‘normally’, in my statefirst opinion]. ment [of the second opinion].3 For, in order to defend the innocent, it is allowable to use violence against the infidels in question, that they may be prevented from sacrificing infants to their gods; inasmuch as such a war is permissible in the order of charity and is, indeed, a positive duty if it can be conveniently waged. It should be added that this course of action is licit, not only in order to free children, but also for the purpose of freeing adults, even though the latter may consent and wish to be sacrificed to idols; because in this respect, they are worse than madmen, and because, moreover, they are not the lords of their own lives, so that, accordingly, any man can be restrained by another from committing suicide. But what has been stated [concerning sacrifice] must be limited to cases where such killing is unjust. For if infidels had a custom of sacrificing to idols only those criminals who were justly condemned to death, such infidels could not be coerced solely on that ground, since in this prac1 [i.e. the opinion that even in the case of non-subjects, ‘pagan idolaters may be forced by the Church to worship the one God and to relinquish the rites of idolatry, &c. Vide Sub-section 2 of this Section, p. 768.—Tr.] * [Vide Sub-section 2 of this Section, p. 768.—Tr.] » [Vide the first sentence of Sub-section 3 of this Section, p. 769.—Tr.] Dis}. XV111: On Means for the Conversion of Unbelievers 771 tice they would sin, not against justice, but against religion only, and the excuse of defending the innocent would therefore cease to avail. 5. The reply to the second confirmation [of the first opinion]1 is this: the practice of the Romans is praised, not as The answer to the being virtuous in an absolute sense, but as a lesser evil second and third confirmations [of possessing some semblance of virtue because of its the first opinion]. material object. As for the saying of Aristotle quoted in the last [and third] confirmation,1 it would indeed be duly applic­ able, if there existed any people so barbarous that they were neither united in a civil society, nor capable of exercising government. For in that case, it would be not on the ground of religion, but on that of the defence of humanity (so to speak) that they might be forcibly subjected to the government of some state. But, in my opinion, no people so barbarous have yet been found. 6. As to infidels of the kind in question, who are nevertheless infidels who are subjects of Christian princes, it should be said that, subjects of a Chris- in the first place, they may be forced by such princes to profess the worship of the true God, and conseto profess the cult of quently to cease from professing errors contrary to the true God. natural reason and to the faith. So St. Thomas teaches, St. Thomas. as do the other theologians, in the passages cited. Moreover, the truth of this assertion can be proved, first, from The first roof of a Passa§e Deuteronomy (Chap, xiii), wherein God this assertion, from orders that unbelievers of this kind—namely, unDeuteronomy, Chap, believers who are in any way subjects [of a faithful state]—shall be put to death on account of such wrong­ doing. On this passage, and others like it, one may consult Cyprian’s C>TnaB· Exhortation to Martyrdom (Chap, v), and other references given there by Pamelius.2 Pamela», Secondly, the assertion in question can be proved from the prac__ J t . tice of the Church, since from the beginning, the the same assertion Christian emperors followed this course m so far as based upon the prac- tbe circumstances of the times rendered it advisable, tice o e urc . pOJ. Constantine forthwith ordered that the temples, of the idols should be closed and that idolatry should be abolished, as we may gather from Eusebius (On the Life of Constantine, Bk. II, Eusebw. chaps, xliii and xliv and Bk. IV, chap, xxiii), Rufinus (Ecclesiastical Ruhnus. History, Bk. II, chap, xix), and Nicephorus (in Bk. λ III, chap, xxxiii Mcephons. and also in Bk X, chap, xxxix), where he cites a similar order issued by Jovinian.3 Later, indeed, Theodosius entirely destroyed the temples, 1 [Vide Sub-section 2 of this Section, p. 768.—Tb.] 3 [Jacobus Pamelius (Jac. de Joigny de Pamele, 1536-87), Flemish priest, edited the works of Cyprian.—Tb.] 3 [Suârez probably refers to Jovian or Jovianus Flavius Claudius who became Emperor of Rome m 363 A.D.—Tr.] 772 Ambrose. Council of Carthage. African Council. Council of Toledo, &c. St. Thomas. Romans, xiii. The Three Theological Virtues: On Faith according to Rufinus (Bk. II, Chaps, xxii and xxiii]), and Nicephorus (Bk. XII, chap. xxv). Subsequently, the same Theodosius framed many laws in which he condemned the worshippers of idols and which are to be found in the Theodosian Code (tit. On the Pagans [Code, XVI. x]). Moreover, he was imitated by Justinian in his Code, same title [Code, I. xi]. Augustine {Letters, xlviii, 1 and xxiv [Migne ed. Letters, xciii, clxxxv and cci]) approved of these laws, while Ambrose, 483 too {Letters, xxx [xl]), and many Councils also, approved of the practice in question : for the Fifth Council of Carthage (Chap, xv [Chap, xvi]) declared that the Emperor must be petitioned to destroy the remnants of idolatry; the same view was upheld by the African Council under Boniface (Chap, xxv) ; the Third Council of Toledo (Chap, xvi) ordered that idolatry be uprooted from the lands of the faithful, a decree which was also issued by the Twelfth Council of Toledo (Chap, xi), and the Sixteenth (Chap, ii); and finally the Council of Elvira (Chap, xli) ordered that Christians having pagan servants should not allow the latter to keep idols in their homes. 7. The reason [for the opinion under discussion1] is that these Christian princes do not lack jurisdiction with respect The assertion set i » v · · · , . r forth [in Sub-section to the unbelievers in question, since the latter are 6] is confirmed by assumed to be subjects, and since the action of which we are speaking does not exceed the limits of that jurisdiction. A second reason [for the same opinion] is as follows : it is the duty of a civil state, by virtue of reason and the natural law, to provide for the true worship of God within its borders ; accordingly, in that same state there exists a directive power for the government of men with respect to this sort of worship; consequently, that state possesses also a coercive power for the punishment of offences contrary to such worship and for the coercion of men, lest they become involved in errors of the kind (for a directive power WOuld be ineffective, and of insufficient use to the state, without an accompanying coercive power); and this coercive power, in so far as it is natural, resides in Christian princes; therefore, Christian princes may thereby exert force upon their own subjects, in the manner above-mentioned, even if the latter are un­ believers. The entire argument is clear. Its foundation, moreover, which is expressed in the first antecedent, is laid down by St. Thomas {De Regimine Principum, Bk. I, chap, xiv, and Bk. II, last chapter). This assertion is, furthermore, a self-evident truth. For the power in question is of God, as Paul testifies in Romans (Chap, xiii [, v. 1 J), adding, immediately thereafter, the words, ‘And those [powers] that 1 [Le. the belief that infidels who are subjects of Christian princes, ‘may be forced by such princes to profess the worship of the true God, and consequently to cease from professing errors contrary to natural reason and to the faith.’ Vide the first sentence of Sub-section 6 of this Section, p. 77Γ.—Ta.] Disp. XVIII: On Means for the Conversion of Unbelievers are, are ordained of God.’ Hence, this power has pre-eminently been given for the honour and worship of the one God, of Whom human princes are the ministers, as Paul says, in the chapter cited. The confirmation of our argument is that the purpose of such power is to maintain the state in peace and justice, which cannot be done un­ less the state is also induced to live virtuously; but men cannot live according to moral and natural virtue, without true religion and the worship of the one God; therefore, natural power and the jurisdiction of a human state are extended to include this purpose. 8. From this reasoning I infer, first, that even a pagan—that is, c „ a non-Christian —king, if he has a knowledge of the The first corollary i r i · i · of the immediately true Lrod, may use force upon nis own subjects to menÿÙlg cause them to believe that truth, either by their own reasoning if they are intelligent, or by putting human faith in more learned men, if they are ignorant; and consequently, he may compel those same subjects to cease from the worship of idols and from similar superstitions contrary to natural reason. The proof of this inference is that there resides in such a king all power which, according to natural reason, is suitable for a human state. Secondly, it follows from that series of statements that the princes in question not only have the aforesaid power, but The second corol­ lary of the same are moreover bound to use it in the manner indicated. statements. The proof of this second corollary is as follow’s: by virtue of their office they are under an obligation to govern their sub' jects well, in accordance with the purpose for which they possess power; and good government demands this use [of such power], as has been proved; hence, this obligation is more weighty in the case of Christian princes, because they have a greater knowledge of truth, and because in Christian kingdoms this coercion is especially necessary in view of the welfare of the Christian subjects also; consequently, princes of the kind in question are bound to frame laws prohibiting offences in this matter [of worship], for they cannot inflict punishment for such offences, if they observe a due order, unless they first prohibit the offences in their laws. Thirdly, it follows that such power is to be exercised by public, The third corollary not private authority; and hence a private citizen of those statements. wh.o is a Christian may not force another and infidel citizen to refrain from the worship of idols; neither may that Chris­ tian citizen, acting on his own private authority, destroy those idols, [a prohibition] which is indicated by the civil law {Code, I. xi. 3 and 6). In this sense, also, one should understand Canon 60 of the Council of Elvira, according to which a Christian who breaks an idol and does so on his own private authority, is not reputed a martyr, even though he be slain for that action, because he thrust himself 774 Mendoza. Matthew, xüi. Augustine. The Three Theological Virtues: On Faith forward indiscreetly and on his own initiative, as Mendoza explains at length, in dealing with the said Council ([Λetustissimum et Nobilis­ simum Concilium Illiberitanum cum Discursibus . . .,] Bk. Ill, chap, xlv). 9. Finally, there remains for discussion an obvious question connected with the foregoing, a question of which St. Are the rites of un­ Thomas (II.-II, qu. 10, art. 11) treats, namely: are believers to be toler­ ated in Christian the rites of unbelievers to be tolerated in the kingdoms kingdoms? of the faithful? From what has been said, it would seem that such rites ought not to be tolerated; for they are supersti­ tious and injurious to God, Whose true worship the princes of those kingdoms are bound to advance. However, St. Thomas makes a valid distinction between two kinds of rites: those which are contrary to natural reason, and opposed to God as known by the light of nature, for example, idolatry, and so4S4 forth; and those others which are indeed superstitions, by comparison with the Christian faith and its precepts, but which are not intrinsi­ cally evil or contrary to natural reason, for example, rites of the Jews, and perhaps even many of the rites of the Saracens and of similar infidels who worship only the one true God. As to the first group, then, the inference stated at the beginning of this section1 is valid; for the Church ought not to tolerate these among her infidel subjects, a point proved by all the passages which we have cited and by the fact that, in such toleration or permission, there is no advantage either to the unbelievers themselves or to the Christian state. This assertion must be understood, however, only in a general sense ; for it often happens that a Christian king is not able to destroy these rites entirely, without great loss to his kingdom or to the other Christian subjects, in which event he may, without sin, connive at and allow [the continued observance of the rites]. This concession has its foundation in the words of Christ {Matthew, Chap, xiii [, v. 29J as set forth in the parable in which the servants asked the head of the household whether the cockle should be rooted up, whereat the latter replied: ‘No, lest perhaps rooting up the cockle, you root up the wheat also together with it’. So it is that the Church often tolerates grave sins even in the faithful, lest schisms still more grave result. Such is the doctrine upheld by Augustine refuting Parmenianus Contra Epistolam Parmem am, Bk. Ill, chap, ii [, no. 13]), and set forth in Decretum (Pt. II, causa xxm, qu. iv, can. xix). The reason for this view is clear, namely: prudence teaches that of many evils the least should be chosen, while the rule of charity demands that correc­ tion should not be exercised save for a fruitful result; and therefore, much less should coercion be exercised when greater harm would ensue. 1 [Sect. 9; Le. the inference that, ‘such rites ought not to be tolerated’, &c.—Tk.] Disp. XVIII: On Means for the Conversion of Unbelievers 10. As to the other rites of unbelievers, those which are opposed only to the faith but not to natural reason, it is a cer­ Unbelievers are not tainty that unbelievers, even though subjects, should to be compelled, even when they are not be compelled to abandon them; on the contrary, subjects, to abandon such rites should be tolerated by the Church. So St. rites which are merely in opposition Gregory teaches (Letters, Bk. I, letter xxxiv [Bk. Gmr>ty. to the faith. XIII, letter xii]), especially with respect to the Jew’s, when he forbids that the latter be deprived of their synagogues, and urges (Bk. XI, letter xv) that they be permitted to engage in their ceremonies therein. He likewise teaches that the Jews should be per­ mitted to celebrate their solemn rites. The reason for such a view is that these rites are not intrinsically The proof of this evil according to the natural law, and that therefore, assertion. the temporal power of the prince does not per se in­ clude the authority to prohibit them ; since no reason for the prohibi­ tion can be given, save that the rites in question are contrary to the faith, and this is not a sufficient reason in the case of those who are not spiritually subject to the power of the Church. The confirmation. The congrmatjon of this argument is the fact that such a prohibition would be (so to speak) a coercion to the acceptance of the faith ; and this coercion, as we have said, is not permissible. The fore­ going argument applies in general to the Saracens and to the other unbelievers who know and worship the one true God, in so far as pertains to those rites which are not contrary to natural reason. However, the Church has always considered that this tolerance is especially advisable in dealing- with the lews, because Why the Jews are to .r 7 r -? · J l r· l be permitted to ceie- the errors of the latter furnish a testimony to the faith brate their own rites jn many particulars. In the first place, the Jews admit m hnstian states. Messiah was promised, and they accept the Scriptures from which we clearly prove that the promise has been ful­ filled. Secondly, we see fulfilled in them what the Prophets and Christ foretold regarding their desertion of Him and their hardness of heart. Finally, Augustine has said (On the City of God, Bk. XV III, chap, xlvi) a that the Jews should be preserved and allowed to five in their own sects, in order that they in turn may preserve a testimony to the Scriptures such as the Church received, even from her enemies; and, in this connexion, Augustine quotes the words of Paul (Romans, Chap, xi [, v. 1i J), ‘But by their offence, salvation is come to the Gentiles’ ; and also a passage from the Psalms (Iviii [, v. 12]), ‘Slay them not, lest at any time my people forget, scatter them by Thy power, &c.’ Augus­ tine cites similar examples in his first sermon, on Psalm xl, near the end. II. However, it should be added that the Church has allowed these rites within certain bounds and limitations. The first and general limitation is that such rites are not to be 776 Three Theological Virtues: On Faith celebrated to the scandal of the faithful ; a fact which one may gather from the Decretals (Bk. V, tit. vi, chaps, iii, iv, vii and these rites should be xv) and from the Code (I. ix, throughout many laws allowed to the Jews, there given). Among the Laws of Spain, too, there are many of the same sort ([Las Siete Partidas,\ Pt. VII, tit. xxiv, laws I et seq. and Pt. I, tit. iv, law 63). Secondly, and specifically, although the Jews are permitted to retain and to keep in repair their old synagogues, they are nevertheless forbidden to erect new synagogues. On this point, see the Code (I. ix. 18), and the Decretals (Bk. V, tit. vi, chaps, iii and vii). Thirdly, although it is forbidden that their synagogues should be taken away from them, nevertheless, if these are once so taken, and consecrated as churches, they are not to be restored, and the loss must be made good in some other way; as Gregory indicates in Letters (Bk. VII, letter Iviii [Bk. IX, letter Iv]). Fourthly, the Jews are not allowed to do anything which has not been ordained in their law, a limitation which is laid down by Gregory in the same Letter Iviii [Iv]. Fifthly, they are not allowed to have their synagogues in the neighbourhood of Christian churches, according to the same Gregory 485 (Bk. XII, letter xviii [Bk. I, letter x]). Sixthly, on the day of the Passover, Jews are forbidden to go out in public; nay more, they are ordered to keep their doors and windows closed, as we read in the Decretals (Bk. V, tit. vi, chaps, iv and xv). According to this same authority, they are also commanded to wear an outward sign by which they may be externally distinguished from the faithful. And in general, they are to be severely punished if they do anything or make any public manifestation, in opposition to the honour of the Christian religion ; a fact which is also brought out in the Decretals (Bk. V, tit. vi, chap, xv) and in the Decretum (Pt. II, causa xxiii, qu. viii, cans, viii et seq.), and in the civil laws cited above. Finally, for the reason already expounded, the ancient rabbinical books which were written sincerely and without any hatred of the Christian religion are tolerated; but the Books of the Hebrews, who later corrupted the Scriptures, are banned, as Cajetan has noted (on II.-II, qu. 10, art. 11). Within what limits Gregory. Gregory. Caje tan. SECTION V MAY THE UNBELIEVERS IN QUESTION BE DEPRIVED OF ALL SUPERIOR POWER WHICH THEY HOLD OVER CHRISTIANS, THAT IS TO SAY, OVER THE FAITHFUL? I. This power may be manifold, but it can be reduced to four heads. First, there is the power of jurisdiction, whether it be supreme Disp. XVIII: On Means for the Conversion of Unbelievers 777 as in kings, or inferior as in their ministers. The second sort is The fourfold power t^ie P°wer oftrue dominion, to which absolute slavery of unbelievers over corresponds. The third is the power which may be Christians. called domestic, to which sendee corresponds. The fourth is the patria potestas. The question stated above may be applied to all these forms of power, but w'e shall speak chiefly of princes; and that point being made clear, the other headings will be disposed of easily. Moreover, all these forms may be treated as relating to non-subjects [as well as subjects]; and in either case a twofold procedure is distinguishable by which the holders may be deprived of this power—that is, they may be deprived directly, merely by reason of the unbelief of the superiors, or because of the faith of the subjects ; or only indirectly, on account of other intrinsic purposes. 2. In the first place, then, as to those non-Christian princes some or many of whose subjects are converted to the faith, The opinion of cer­ tain persons, who there is the opinion of certain persons who hold that affirm the right these unbelievers may be absolutely and directly de­ even of direct deprivation. prived by the Church of their power over their Christian subjects. Hostiensis (Summa, Bk. Ill, De Koto, p. 263, at end) has Bitwise, been cited as supporting this opinion; but he does not really hold such a view, although in other matters he differs from what we have said above, expressing himself in a somewhat inconsistent manner. Alvaro Αλ-aro Paet. Paez (De Planctu Ecclesiae, Bk. I, chap, xviii [chap, lix]), however, inclines more definitely to the view in question. The ground on which that opinion is based is the contention that it is not fitting, but on the contrary, seems wholly disgraceful, that the faithful should be governed by unbelievers. This statement is made in the Decretals (Bk. V, tit. vi, chap, i) and is derived from Paul’s writings (z Corinthians, Chap. vi). Moreover, there are cited in favour of this view other Scriptural testimonies which I shall not discuss here, since I speak ot them in another passage presently to be cited. However, the opinion in question is wholly false. 3. The following proposition must, then, be laid down at the outset : unbelieving princes may not simply and direcdy The first proposi­ tion: unbelieving on the ground [of unbelief], be deprived by the Church princes may not be of the power and jurisdiction which they hold over deprived of their jurisdiction over Christian subjects. This is the common opinion, and their Christian sub­ it is drawn from a passage in the works of St. Thomas St. Thome. jects, simply and directly [on the above cited ([II.-II,] qu. io, art. io), in connexion ground of unbelief]. with which Cajetan and all the more recent commentators uphold such a view; as do the other Scholastics, especially Duran­ Duraadus. dus (on the Sentences, Bk. II, dist. xliv, qu. 3), the canonists, in general, on the Decretals (Bk. Ill, tit. xxxiv, chap, viii), St. Antoninus Antonuna. 1569.74 - c 77% Sylvester. Waldensis. Driedo. Victoria. Soto. Salmerdn. Romans, xiii. Titus,ni. Eusebius. The Three Theological Virtues: On Faith (Pt. II, title x, chap, xv, § i, at end [tit. xn, chap, iii, § I, at end]), Sylvester (word infidelitas, Qu. 4), Waldensis {Doctrinale Antiquitatum Fidei, Bk II, chaps. Ixxxi et seq.), Driedo {De Libertate Christiana, Bk. Ill, chap, ix, at end), Victoria (Relect. De Indis, 'passim), Soto {De lustitia, Bk. IV, qu. ii, art. 2) and Salmeron (Vol. XIII, tracts, xxxvii and xxxviii [Vol. XII, tract, xxxviii]). Other authorities, who will be referred to below, support the same opinion. 4. The basis of this truth rests on the fact that either the princes The basis of the Question may be deprived de facto of such jurisfirst proposition diction and power, on the ground that they do not stated as a dilemma. ρθδδ€δδ ^tiis jurisdiction and power by divine right, or else they are unworthy on account of their unbelief to hold the power which they may actually have, and consequently may justly be deprived of it; but neither of these arguments is valid; therefore, . . . The first part of the minor premiss, which I have elsewhere An exposition Of the proved at length {Defensio Fidei, Bk. Ill, chap, iv, first part of the no. i),1 is most certainly true. Briefly, the argument is dilemma. as foj]ows. Chj-jst our Lord has not deprived the afore­ mentioned princes of the power in question; nor does baptism— whether ipso iure or de facto—exempt the Christian from the power of his king, even though the latter be an unbeliever. The proof of this argument is sufficiendy evident, both in the fact that neither from Scripture nor from tradition can such depriva­ tion or exemption be derived; and, more especially, in the fact that486 both Scripture and tradition clearly uphold the contrary practice. This is true of Scripture, because Paul said {Romans, Chap, xiii [, v. 1]) : ‘Let every soul be subject to higher powers’; an admonition which, under the expression ‘every soul’, manifestly includes the faithful, and under ‘higher powers’, includes the emperor and the princes of those days, who were unbelievers; wherefore in the Epistle to Titus (Chap. iii [, v. I]), Paul also said, ‘Admonish them to obey princes’,2 and Peter wrote (r Peter, Chap, ii [, v. 13]), ‘Be ye subject,’ &c. Again, as to tradition, [viewed in relation to our argument,] it is well-known from the ancient custom of the Church, which I have elsewhere pointed out, in the work cited [Defensio Fidel], in accordance with the comments of many of the Fathers. To these citations I now add only the name of Polycarp as quoted by Eusebius {Ecclesiastical History, Bk. IV, chap, xiv, or xv [chap. xv]). The former, speaking of non-Christian princes, says, ‘We are taught to render to the magistrates and the powers constituted by God, in proportion to their dignity of rank, such honour as is in no 1 [Not included in these Selections.—Tr.] 2 [The Vulgate reads: * Admonish them to be subject to princes and powers, to obey at a word’, &c.—Tr.] Disp. XV 111: On Means for the Conversion of Unbelievers j"j<) way detrimental to our salvation orto our religion.’ St. Thomas (II.-II, qu. io, art. io) also defends this view very cogently by argument, when he reasons as follows : the political powerin question springs from natural law and the ius gentium, whereas faith springs from divine and super­ natural law; and the one law does not destroy or alter the other; neither is the natural law founded on the divine positive law; rather is it in a way subject thereto, constituting (as it were) the presupposition of the latter; and therefore, positive power is not founded on faith in such, a way that one may lose that power on account of unbelief nor, on the other hand, is positive subjection, i.e. [subjection in the political sense] to one who is an unbeliever, repugnant to faith or to the baptismal character, so that, consequently this subjection is not auto­ matically dissolved [by faith and baptism]. 5. The other part1 of the proposition which we have stated as 2 dilemma follows clearly from what has been said An exposition of the latter part of above. For the unbelieving princes of whom we speak, the dilemma. may not rightfully be deprived of their possessions without some just ground; and included within those possessions is the jurisdiction which they are assumed to have over Christian subjects; therefore, they may not be deprived of such jurisdiction, simply and directly [on the ground of unbelief]. The truth of the antecedent in both its parts is self-evident. The proof of the consequent is as follows : there is no just ground on which such an act of deprivation may be committed; for the pretext would be specifically that very unbelief, since strictly speaking, no other ground exists or can be conceived; and in truth, unbelief is not, per se, a just ground. For if we consider it purely as an absence of faith, we must admit that, as I have said, such a lack does not destroy the basis of political power; and if, on the other hand, unbelief is con­ sidered as a sin worthy of such punishment, even so, it is not within the power of the Church to punish these unbelievers, since the Church has no jurisdiction over them, as I have also proved. Therefore, just as they may not be punished by the loss of other temporal goods, in view of the fact that their ownership of those goods is not based upon faith, similarly, they may not be deprived of the power in question. Proof of this fact may be derived by analogy. For if there were a demonstration by two sovereign princes who were unbelievers, and one anaJ°gyof them worshipped the true God as known by the light of nature, while the other prince was an idolater some of whose subjects worshipped the true God, the latter prince could not, on the ground of his idolatry, be deprived by the former of his jurisdiction 1 β-e. the assumption that the princes in question, ‘are unworthy on account of their unbelief to hold the power which they may actually have, and consequently may justly be deprived of it.’ Vide the first sentence of Sub-section 4 of this Section, p. 778.—Tr.] 780 The Three Theological Virtues: On Faith Over such subjects, since the prince who worshipped the true God would have no jurisdiction over the other, and since the idolatrous prince would not lose his jurisdiction over the subjects in question owing to the mere fact of his idolatry. There is, then, an indication from natural law that this order must be preserved, because that preservation is expedient to the welfare and peace of the world and to a just equity; but the power given to the Church does not interfere with natural rights, since it has [rather] been given for edification and is to be used in the way best adapted to the preservation of the faith; therefore, the Church has not been given the aforementioned power of deprivation, a power which would serve for destruction instead [of serving for edification], inasmuch as it would result in harm to the faith and in scandal to those who are not of the faith. 6. Nevertheless, we must state, in the second place, that the The second proposi- Church may indirectly 1 deprive these non-Christian may indkecUyUdeh Pr^nces their power over those subjects who are prive non-Christian believers, if the welfare or defence of the latter makes princes of their this necessary. St. Thomas so teaches (II.-II, qu. 10, power over those of their subjects who art. 10), as do others cited above; and I also have are believers. touched upon this subject in the Defensio Fidei (Bk. Ill, chap, xxiii, no. 21).2 The reason in support of this second proposition is as follows: The reason suppor- the baptized faithful, by the fact of their faith and ing this proposition, their baptism, are subjects of the Church in spiritual matters, so that the Church has the power to rule them to the extent that is necessary or highly expedient for the welfare of their souls; and therefore, if it should become necessary to this end, to free such persons from the power of non-Christian lords, the Church may do so, and consequently may deprive those non-Christian princes of their power over the persons in question. For he who gives the form, gives also those things that are consequent upon the form; and whoever gives power and jurisdiction in order to attain any end, gives conse­ quently, all the means necessary to reach that end. This argument is confirmed by the example of a marriage contracted between unbelievers, one of whom is later converted to the faith. For if either party wishes to 487 remain in wredlock without injury to God, the other may not sever the bond; but if, on the other hand, the unbelieving spouse is the occasion to the Christian partner of evil living, then the latter both may and ought to be separated from that unbeliever, as Paul declares (z Corinthians, Chap, vii [, v. 15]). Thus the unbelieving partner, indirectly (as it were) and for the good of the faith, is deprived of the 1 [Le. incidentally, in the process of attaining some other end.—Tr.] 1 [Supra, p. 700.—Tr.] Disp. XVIII: On Means for the Conversion of Unbelievers 781 power and dominion which he has over his spouse. Therefore, the same holds true to a far greater degree in the case which we are dis­ cussing; for the marriage bond is of its nature more nearly indissoluble than the bond of political subjection. 7. It should be noted, however, that there are two ways in which such Christians may be freed from the power of un­ The first mode of believers. freeing the faithful from the power of The first primarily affects the subjects themselves, non-Christian who may change their domicile and pass over to the princes, viz. through change of realms of Christian princes; for then it follows of domicile. necessity that they are no longer subject to their for­ mer prince. This method is easy and entirely just; and therefore, it may be employed by any Christian subject, acting on his own authority, for he is not bound to remain always in the same territory. Conse­ quently, if any prince attempts to prevent his Christian subjects from thus transferring their domicile, he may be forcibly resisted by Chris­ tian princes, and justly subdued in war in defence of these subjects, because they are being deprived of their right which they wish to exercise. 8. These unbelieving princes may be deprived of their power over their Christian subjects in another way, which affects The second mode of [primarily] the princes themselves; that is, though the depriving an un­ believing prince subjects in question remain in that territory, the either of his sove­ reignty, or of his prince may be deprived [either of his sovereignty],1 or power over the at least of his power over such subjects. But this result faithful. could hardly be effected without a change of ruler, so that the second method is more difficult [to follow’ than the first]; and therefore, although the power [to employ that method] is not lacking [to the faithful], nevertheless, great caution is necessary in its employ­ ment. In the first place, [if this second method is to be used,] the faithful should constitute a great multitude; or, if they be few, it must be practically impossible for them to change their domicile to a place where they may practise their faith without scandal. Furthermore, the successful issue of the enterprise must be morally certain, lest it come to pass that in wishing to eradicate the cockle, these Christian subjects should pull up the wheat. Durandus requires Durandus [on the Sentences, Bk. II, dist. xliv, qu. 3] that some injuries be committed on the holds, moreover, that it is necessary, [in order to justify part of the prince [before the second the method in question,] that the non-Christian prince mode may be em­ shall first have been the cause of injuries and obstacles ployed]. to the faith—such as attempting to entice his subjects to unbelief, or impelling them to observe his own rites, or prohibiting 1 [The bracketed English phrase has been supplied from the Latin phrase, sd regno, which occurs in the marginal note, but not in the body of the text.—Ts.] 782 St. Thomas. The Three Theological Virtues: On Faith them from practising the Catholic rites and. from obeying their own spiritual pastors, or similar injuries—since both necessity and the ground of justice would then exist. St. Thomas (PI.-II, qu. 10J art. 10), however, thinks that, although these factors may, in a general sense, be necessary for the Yet the moral peril exercise of the power in question, yet the Church of injury is suffi- has the power, even before the infliction of this kind of injury, to remove such non-Christian sovereigns solely on the ground of moral peril to the faithful. This opinion I too have approved, in the aforesaid Defensio FideifBk. Ill, chap, xxx, no. 6),1 because, in moral questions peril must be guarded against before any specific injury occurs, a principle which certainly is very true when the peril is imminent and concerns the moral order. Therefore, as regards the matter specifically under discussion [—that is, the second mode of depriving an infidel prince of power—] all the circumstances in any particular case must be taken into consideration, and [in view of them], such peril to the faithful must be judged to exist [before resort to that second method is justifiable]. 9. Furthermore, I note that this indirect power, which we hold, in whom this inexists in the Church for the removal of the above­ direct power resides, mentioned princes, is a public power and not a private one, a fact which is self-evident. Therefore, it may be considered as residing either in the Pope, or in some sovereign Catholic king. The Pope has, by reason of his supreme spiritual jurisdiction, the power to secure and watch over the salvation of souls ; whereas this power exists in a temporal prince only as a means of defending his neighbours, and especially the faithful, for such a prince has no spiritual jurisdiction. Consequently, a temporal lang may not use this power on his own authority until a non-Christian prince has inflicted violence upon his own Christian subjects, since measures of defence are not lawful before an act of aggression occurs. But both the Pope, and a king as moved by the Pope and as his instrument (so to speak) may well take preventive measures solely on the ground of peril, since the power of jurisdiction extends to the prevention of evils lest they occur. These remarks will suffice as to sovereign princes. In due propor­ tion, the same conclusions might easily be applied to other and inter­ mediate rulers, as well as in the case of all unbelievers not subject to the Church who exercise jurisdiction over the faithful. 10. In view of the foregoing, it is easy to deal with the second _ . division [of power],2 that which relates to Christian The third propos- , 4 ,r. . . . tion:infidel masters, slaves and tneir infidel masters, ror, following a simi1 [Not included in these Selections.—Tr.] 2 [secundum membrum, referring to true dominion, the second of the four divisions mentioned in the first paragraph of this Section. The various series of numbers used by Suarez in the course of the section are somewhat confusing.—Tr.] Disp. XV1I1: On Means for the Conversion of Unbelievers 783 lar line of reasoning, we must state that these masters, who are not in any other respect subjects of the Church, may not be deprived of their Christian slaves, directly [on the ground of unbelief], whereas they may indirectly1 be deprived of those slaves. The first half of this proposition is certainly true and commonly accepted. With regard to it, and in addition to the authors already 488 cited, Sylvester (word furtum, Qu. 6), may be consulted ; and by him, at that place, Rosella ([word furtum,] No. 25) is quoted, although in another passage {ibid., No. 24) Rosella seems to hold a different opinion. In the latter case, however, he was probably speaking of Christian slaves captured in an unjust war; otherwise he would be speaking incorrectly and contradicting himself. Angelus de Clavasio (fSumma, word domi­ nus,] No. 56) may also be consulted on this point. The statement in question is upheld, too, by Navarrus {Summa, chap, xvii, nos. 103 and 104), Covarruvias (on Sext, rule Peccatum, De Reg. Jur., Pt. II, §11, no. 6), and Molina {De lustitia, Bk. I, disp. xxxù). The argument supporting this statement is similar to that given above. For Christians who before baptism were subject to unbelievers are not released from temporal servitude to the latter by the simple force of divine law, that is, of baptism; and, therefore, infidel masters, who are not in any other respect subjects of the Church, may not, directly [on the ground of unbelief,] be deprived by the Church of their dominion. The truth of the antecedent, Paul clearly assumes, when he says in the Epistle to the Ephesians (Chap, vi [, v. 5]) : ‘Servants be obedient to them that are your lords according to the flesh [...] as to Christ.’ This injunction is repeated in the Epistle to the Colosstans (Chap, iii [, v. 22]), in that to Titus (Chap, ii [, v. 9]), and in the First Epistle of Peter (Chap, ii [, v. 18]). Wherefore Augustine (on Psalms, cxxiv [, no. y]), also, rightly says : ‘Christ did not make free men out of slaves, but made good slaves out of bad ones.’ He upholds this same doctrine at some length in his thirty-first sermon, on Psalm cxriii, and under His name in Questions on the Old and New Testaments (Qu. xxxv). From what has been said above, the truth of the consequent is also evident, namely, that these non-Christians, since they are not subjects of the Church, may not justly be deprived of their slaves. ii. The second half of our third proposition,2 indeed, that half Heverthei these re^ates to the power [to deprive infidel masters] infidel masters may on indirect grounds of their dominion over Christian suffer such depnva- slaves—is applicable when non-Christian masters are tion, indirectly. , fs, _... hostile to their Christian slaves, especially if that hos­ tility involves matters of faith. In that case, these very slaves have not subjects of the Church, cannot be deprived of their dominion over their Christian slaves, directly [on the grouncfof unbelief]. 1 [i.e. incidentally.—Tb.] 2 [Vide the first paragraph of Sub-section io of this Section, p. 7S2.—Tb.] Sylvester. Rosella. Angelus. Navarrus. Covarruvias. Molina. Ephesians, vi. CnlAtrtAut' yj. Psalms, otxnr. Augustine. 784 St. Thomas. The Three Theological Virtues: On Faith the right to defend themselves, or to recover their original freedom if they can do so through flight; and certainly, in view of the arguments already set forth, the princes of the Church have the right, in this connexion, to exercise coercion upon unbelievers. From the above statements, we derive sufficient enlightenment as The same holds true to what should be said on the third point,1 which as to servants. relates to servants and the power of the head of the household over them ; for the solution [in this case] should preserve a similar proportion. With respect to the fourth point, however [—that which relates to the patria potestas—] there arises a serious question, of iVIay tne children of 1 · i_ c τί. /γττ tt π \ unbelievers be bap- which bt. Ihomas ([11.-li, qu. io,J art. 12) treats, tized against the win namely: may these unbelievers who are non-subjects be forcibly deprived of their infant children in order that the latter may be baptized ? But this question pertains to the subject of baptism, with which I have dealt in Vol. Ill, disp. xxv, §3 [De Sacramentis].2 Enough has been said, then, as to unbelievers who are not subjects. 12. We must consider, secondly,3 [whether] unbelievers who are The fourth proposi- [themselves] subjects of Christian princes [may be tion· deprived of power over Christians]. Under this head those four topics discussed above may be examined and treated. As to the first point, indeed—that which relates to jurisdiction— the question has no application with respect to a sovereign prince; for we are assuming that these unbelievers are subjects of some Christian sovereign. Therefore, we have only to inquire as to Infidel judges under a Christian the inferior judges or governors ; and on this point it king may be de­ prived of their power should be stated briefly that the Church can deprive either directly or in­ such unbelievers, either directly or indirectly, of all directly. jurisdiction of this kind over Christians, or—what amounts to the same thing—it may determine that in a Christian king­ dom the faithful shall not be governed temporally by infidel judges or other infidel officials. The direct power to do so clearly exists, because it is a Christian The first proof: prince who has jurisdiction over the subjects in quesfrom reason. tion, and he may require in his judges and officials such qualifications as he deems necessary for honour, or for distributive justice, or for the peace and safety of his state. On this ground, then, it is easily possible to exclude certain persons from the offices men1 [Le. domestic power. Vide the first paragraph of Sub-section 1, pp. 776-7.—Tr.J 1 [Not included in these Selections.—Tr.] J [Le. ‘secondly*, as opposed to ‘In the first place’, the opening phrase of Sub-section 2 (p. 777), where Suarez introduces the discussion relating to non-Christian princes whose subjects are converted to the faith.—Tr.] ♦ [Vide the first paragraph of Sub-section 1 ; and also, footnotes, 2, p. 782 and 1, this page.—Tr.] Disp. XVIII: On Means for the Conversion of Unbelievers 785 tioned. The existence of the indirect power, on the other hand, is a self-evident fact; for the act in question is highly expedient to the welfare of the faith, an argument which proves the existence, not only of the power, but even of the obligation. 13. This teaching agrees with the words of Paul (z Corinthians, iCerinAunt, The second proof: Chap, vi [,v.6]), ‘But brother goethto law with brother **· from Paul. and that before unbelievers’, clearly reproving such behaviour as indecorous ; at least, in cases in which it can be avoided. To the same effect is his saying elsewhere (2 Corinthians, Chap, vi [, v. 14]), ‘Bear not the yoke with unbelievers’. For although there may be other interpretations of this passage, this also is a probable one; or, in any case, the phrase may well be adapted to such an interpretation by a parity of reasoning. Furthermore the existence of this power may be clearly proved The third proof: from the application of human laws. For in the Code from law. (I. Justinian forbids the Jews to hold public offices affecting Christians. Innocent III makes a similar ruling in the innocent Decretals (Bk. V, tit. vi, chap, xvi), when he imposes a penalty upon Jews who accept or hold such offices. Moreover, the application of this rule is extended to the pagans,1 that is, to Saracens, as may be learned from the last chapter of the same title [, i.e. Decretals, Bk. V, tit. vi, chap, xviii], in which Portugal is expressly enjoined to obey this law, with an additional statement to the effect that she may not sell tribute or royal grants to the Jews except when the latter are joined [in partnership] with some Christian, who will take care lest injury 4891 be done to believers. A similar law is laid down by the Third Council Council of Toledo. of Toledo (Chap, xiv [cited in] Decretum, Pt. I, dist. xxiv, can. i [Pt. I, dist. Liv, can. xiv]) ; and in the Fourth Council of Toledo (Chap. Ixiv [cited in] Decretum, Pt. II, causa xvn, qu. iv, can. xxxi), it has been enacted that those who entrust such offices to Jews should be ex­ communicated. The reason given is that, relying on this authority, the Jews take occasion to*do injury to the faithful. Finally, the same rule is laid down in the First Council of Macon (Chap. xiii). 14. Secondly, as to slavery, it should be stated that the faithful may not be slaves of the unbelievers in question, [i.e. of those unbelievers who are subject to a Christian tion : Christians may not be slaves of prince or state,] and consequently the Church has those unbelievers been able 3 to deprive her infidel subjects of such power who are subjects of the Church or of over Christians . So the Emperor Justinian also ordered, Christian princes. in the Code (Lx, only law) ; and in the Decretals (Bk. V, tit. vi, chap, v) there is a similar rule with respect to Jews. Gregory, Gregory. 1 [Paganos, where one would expect infiddes. Cf. note to first paragraph of Sub-section 15, infra, p. 787.—Tr.] * [The Latin text incorrectly has ‘493’.—Tr.J 3 [potuisse. Possibly Suarez intended posse.—Tr.] 1569.74 5h y86 The Three Theological Virtues: On Faith too {Letters, Bk. II, letter xxxvi or Chap. Ixxvi [Bk. Ill, letter xxxviii]) and the Decretum (Pt. I, dist. liv, cans, xiii and xiv, with other Chapters of the same dist. liv), have rulings to this effect. A special reason for such provisions may be inferred from the danger that would result to the faithful themselves if they should be allowed to dwell under the dominion of unbelievers. Another reason is that occasions of blasphemy, contempt of faith, and injury to the faithful might arise from such a relation. These reasons pertain rather to the question of indirect power, although I may add that they have to do also with the direct power of Christian princes. For, in the first place, a Christian king may issue a general decree to apply throughout his realm, to the effect that Chris­ tians are not to be made the slaves even of other Christians, a rule which many kingdoms even now observe; because, though the civil power is not directly derived from the faith, nevertheless, when it is joined thereto, it is directed, and (so to speak) elevated thereby, so that it may do much for the welfare of the faith ; therefore, the same law may far more readily be decreed with regard to unbelieving masters. Secondly, a king may impose upon his subjects such tribute and burdens as he deems necessary for good government ; therefore, in like manner, he may impose upon infidel subjects the burden of an incapacity to be masters of Christians. So it has been ordained that if an unbeliever, the slave of another unbeliever, is converted to the faith, by that very By what right the conversion he shall be emancipated. In the same way, Christian slaves of unbelievers are if a Christian is bought by an infidel as a slave for freed from servitude. purposes of servitude, he shall become free, by the very nature of the transaction, and the buyer shall lose his purchase money. But if the said Christian be bought for purposes of trading, he shall be sold to a believer within three months ; otherwise, he be­ comes free. The same provision is laid down in the Code (I. ix, last law [only law] and I. iii, last law, last section [Code, I. iii. 54 (56), §§ 8 et seql\). However, the canonists note, with respect to one of the chapters cited above {Decretals, Bk. V, tit. vi, chap, ii), that these rulings do not prevent a Christian from working as a farm-servant, whether as a new­ comer to the lands or estates of an unbeliever, or as one born thereon, for the following reasons: the permission to do so may be inferred from the passage in question; moreover, such labour is not servitude, and consequently is not included under the aforesaid prohibition; and finally, in the case of farm-servants there does not exist the same peril [to the faith], or likelihood of scandal, since the believer and the un­ believer do not live together or engage in frequent and familiar inter­ course by reason of such occupation. Disp. XVIII: On Means for the Conversion of Unbelievers 787 15. Thirdly, on the question of servants it must be stated that the Church has this same power to prohibit Christians The sixth proposi­ from acting even as free servants of unbelievers. This tion : the Church has the power to assertion may be proved without difficulty by applying command that Christians shall not to the present case the reasons given above,1 an applica­ act as servants of tion which is easily made and which I therefore omit. unbelievers who are For this subject to her ; and Usage also confirms the same assertion. the Church does in principle is laid down in a Chapter of the Code (I. fact so order. iii. 55, § 5 [54, §§ 8 et seq.f), already cited; and its application is extended to the pagans,2 in the Decretals (Bk. V, tit. vi, chap, viii [chap, xiii]), in a passage where the Saracens are expressly mentioned. Finally, with respect to the patria potestas, it is certain that the x . .. son of an unbeliever, as soon as he is baptized, must regarding the power in view or that very fact be treed from the power of chddren^ °ver thek unbelieving parent, for the sake of the safety of the faith, and because by reason of baptism he is now under the law of the Church. This rule has been laid down in the Councils of Toledo, cited above, and is proved by the Decretals (Bk. Ill, tit. xlii, chap. iii). Whether the infant children of these unbeliev­ ing subjects may be baptized when the parents are unwilling, and whether the former may be taken from the parents with that end in view, are, however, disputed questions, which I have discussed [in De Sacramentis], Vol. Ill, pt. m, disp. xxv, §§ 4, 5 and 6, to which the reader may refer.3 SECTION VI WHETHER EVERY OTHER FORM OF COMMUNICATION BETWEEN CHRJSTIANS AND UNBELIEVERS IS OR MAY BE PROHIBITED 1. Three kinds of communication between Christians and un­ believers must be distinguished: the first may be The three kinds of called formal, that is, communication in the works of communication between Christians unbelief; the second is communication in the works and unbelievers. of our religion, and in a way this approximates to formal communication; the third is purely secular and human, and with 490 respect to faith and unbelief, it is merely material [, i.e. incidental]. 2. The first kind is certainly forbidden by the divine and the The first kind of natural law. This prohibition, by its very nature, is communication, ^in directed primarily to Christians; yet it may be apte°forbiddtmby the plied to the unbeliever himself, either because unbelief natural law. js itself forbidden thereby, or—again—because the 1 [Püfc 785 ; the fifth proposition in the preceding Sab-section.—Ta.] 2 [Paganas again occurs where infideles would seem to be the more appropriate term. Cf. note I, p. 785.—Tr.] 2 [Not included in these Selections.—Tr.] /88 1 Corinthians, x' 2 Corinthians, * Azor. The Three Theological Virtues: On Faith act of drawing a Christian into the intercourse or co-operation in question, is per se an evil act. However, this negative command regard­ ing Christians is issued primarily to us, to whom these words were addressed (z [2] Corinthians, Chap. vi[, w. 14,16,15]) : ‘For what fellow­ ship hath light with darkness [...] or what agreement hath the temple of God with idols [ . . . ] or what part hath the faithful with the unbeliever?’ Paul repeated this admonition in the same Epistle (z Corinthians, Chap, x [, v. 20]) : T would not that you should be made partakers with devils.’ And a similar sense may be given to the passage (2 Corinthians, Chap, vi [, v. 14J): ‘Bear not the yoke with unbelievers.’ The same prohibition, both in its general form and with reference to many specific points, is found in the Sacred Canons (69, 70)1 of the Apostles, in the Canons (61, 62) of the Trullan Synod, held after the Sixth [General] Council, in the Collection (71 to 75) of Martin, Bishop of Braga, compiled after the Second Council of Braga, and in the Council of Laodicea (Canons 37 et seq.), and also in the Decretum(f\. II, causa xxvi, qu. v, can. iii). Now the reason [for this prohibition] is that such intercourse is A proof by reason- both irreligiously superstitious and opposed to the “<· profession of the faith. Therefore, all that we said above about the necessity of professing the faith has due application at this place, as have our remarks in Vol. I : De Religione (Tract. Ill, _ . bk. n)z 2 on , the. sin . of superstition. . The appearance and , , r , moral suspicion of VV e need only add that not merely actual commumto beavoia>d°n cat^on unbelievers] must be avoided, but also the appearance and moral suspicion of the same, such as the frequenting of the synagogues and temples of unbelievers, especially at the hours when their rites are celebrated. For this practice may give rise to scandal and provide occasion for the suspicion that those temples and rites are acceptable or approved. Azor (Moral Institutes, Vol. I, bk. vm, chap, xxii, qu. 3 and ah i-.-_-.n-ii.Li: · IX’ c^aP Qu· 3) maX ke consulted on this point, the wô^E^o^un! as may also my own work, the Defensio Fidei (Bk. VI, believers is stiu chap, ix),2 in which I have added that all co-operation moreto be avoided. . x ,z . . . , r i · · · i is much more to be avoided [than is communication]. However, it is difficult to determine whether or not any co-operation takes place in particular cases: as when [Christians] sell to Jews or to pagans any animal or other object necessary for the sacrifices of the latter. But wfith respect to this point, one must observe the rule that if a thing cannot possibly be put to a good use, the sale of the same is co-operation; whereas if the object in question can be put to a licit use and in itself is neither good nor bad, then, normally, its sale is not co1 [Canons 70, 71 in the edition of Funk.—Reviser.] 2 [Not included in these Selections.—Tr.] Disp. XVIII: On Means for the Conversion of Unbelievers 789 operation. This is the rule laid down by Cajetan (on II.-II, qu. 10, art. Cajetan. 4), a rule which conforms with the opinion expressed by St. Thomas St.Thomaj. (II.-II, qu. 169, art. 2, ad 4); moreover, the same view is held by Sylvester, Angelus de Clavasio, and others (on word infidelitas)', while Sylvester. I, too, have touched upon this subject in the aforesaid Chap, ix [Defensio Αηβ'1“· Fidei, Bk. VI, chap, ix],1 and have discussed it at length in the treatise on The Sacraments in General,1 andon Oaths,1 and in other passages ; for this question is indeed of a very general application. 3. The second kind of communication of unbelievers with beJ, lievers, that which takes place in connexion with communication is sacred matters and with the works or our own religion, prohibited by the js at times forbidden by divine and natural law as natural law. z being intrinsically evil. An instance of such a forbidden act is the admission of an un­ believer to partake of the Sacraments, this act of admission being absolutely and directly prohibited to believers; but unbelievers, too, are forbidden to obtrude themselves into the rites in question, and ac­ cordingly, they may be punished as injurious to the Christian religion, if they do so forcibly. Under this part of our discussion, we may include the prohibition of marriage with unbelievers, although an infidel who has been con­ verted to the faith may remain in wedlock already contracted with another infidel, provided that no offence2 to the Creator results there­ from. Nevertheless, a baptized Christian is forbidden to contract marriage with an unbeliever, as I assume from the treatment of the subject of matrimony. It is true indeed that this prohibition is eccle­ siastical rather than divine; and yet it seems to have been enacted not only on account of peril [to the faith], but also because of reverence for marriage, which, among the faithful, has been elevated to the character of a Sacrament. Accordingly, other acts of communication of this sort are for­ bidden by human law; for example, it is prohibited that unbelievers should be present at the sacrifice of the Mass, or should behold the Sacrament of the Eucharist, prohibitions recorded by St. Thomas St. Thoma. (Summa, Pt. Ill, qu. 80, art. 4, ad 4) commenting on Dionysius (Eerie- Dwcysra». siastica Hierarchia, Chap. vii). This view is supported by Clement (Con- Oenx-nt. stitutions, Bk. VIII, chaps, viii and xii), whereon Turrianus comments Tuman™-. at length; by the Fourth Council of Carthage (Chap. Ixxxiv); and in the Decretum (Pt. Ill, dist. iv [dist. 1, can. IxviiJ). According to the latter passage, unbelievers are allowed to be present at that portion 491 of the Mass which is called the Mass of the Catechumens, and far 1 [Not included in these Selections.—Tr.] 2 [‘offence’. The Latin words contumelia, injuria, are used indifferently to express any grievous sin which the unbaptized partner induces, or might induce, the Chrkiffon partner to commit.—Reyisul] 79° St. Thomas. Chrysostom. St. Thomas. Gregory. The Three Theological Virtues: On Faith more readily are they allowed to be present at discourses on sacred matters delivered for their benefit; just as it is also permissible to pray privately for them or even to instruct them in the mysteries of religion. In this connexion, there arose also a question of which St. Thomas treats ([II.-II,] qu. 10, art. 7), namely: is it permissible to debate with . unbelievers, on sacred matters ? The discussion of this detet?w^unbe- point, I shall reserve for Disputation XX [, i.e. De iMttM3?0n sacred Remediis Ecclesiae contra Haereses et Haereticos,] Sect. i),1 in which we are to ask the same question with re­ gard to heretics, because that aspect of the question involves the same principle. For the present, I shall state briefly that such debating is not in itself evil, since it is often essential to the conversion of those unbelievers ; but it should be conducted under proper circumstances, of which we shall speak in the Disputation above-mentioned. 4. The third kind of communication is secular, or human, and it is with this kind in particular that we are now deal­ The third kind of communication, ing. In this connexion, three points should be briefly that which takes discussed. place in secular affairs, is not in­ The first is that the sort of communication in herently evil, nor is question is not in itself evil or forbidden by divine it forbidden by divine law; but inci­ law. This is certain; for Paul (r Corinthians, Chap, dentally, in certain cases, it may be for­ vii [, w. 12-14]) permits complete domestic and human bidden. communication between a Christian spouse and an unbelieving partner, and in the same Epistle to the Corinthians [Chap, x, v. 27] he allows the faithful to eat with unbelievers, upon invitation from the latter, a fact which both Chrysostom thereon (in Homily XXV [on First Corinthians, Chaps, vii and x] and Homily XXV, on Hebrews) and St. Thomas ([II.-II, qu. 10,] art. 9) note. Furthermore, a general prohibition with regard to such matters would not be expedient, because the conversion of unbelievers would thereby be rendered practically impossible. This would be the result, in the first place, in so far as preachers are concerned; for how could they approach those unbelievers for the purpose of instructing them, without first having had human intercourse with them ? Therefore, this kind of communication is not only not prohibited, but even encouraged, as wre learn from she Decretals (Bk. V, tit. vi, chap, x) and from the Decretum (Pt. II, causa xi, qu. i, can. xl), following Gregory {Letters, Bk. Ill, letter xxvi). Secondly, in so far as the unbelievers themselves are concerned, how could a father be converted to the faith, if he were to be immediately cut off from com­ munication with his children or with his entire family, or even with his friends ? This kind of communication, then, is not evil in itself; neither do we find that it is forbidden by divine law. The fact is simply that 1 [Not included in these Selections.—Tr.] Disp. XVIII: On Meansfor the Conversion of Unbelievers "91 any believer is bound by virtue of the natural and the divine law to avoid that kind of human communication or converse with unbelievers which threatens peril to himself or is scandalous to others. This dis­ tinction as to different sorts of human intercourse is clear from general principles, but in a particular case it is based upon circumstances and the exercise of prudence. 5. Hence, secondly,1 it must be stated that the Church can prohiNevertheiess, the bit this sort of communication between Christians third kind of com- ancj unbelievers. This is evident, because there is no forbidden by eccie- lack of jurisdiction for the making of such a law; and siasticai law. subject-matter is also capable of being placed under such a prohibition, since the latter may be conducive to the peace and security of the faithful. Therefore, that prohibition must, as a general rule, be held to fall directly upon Christians alone, because, as St. Thomas noted (II.-II, qu. 10, art. 9), they are the true subjects of the Church. We must add, however, that the law in question may also [in special cases] be directly applied to non-believing subjects, either in punishment for some offence—as is the case with many laws which we shall presently cite—or in order to promote sound external government of the state, or even for the sake of the security of the faithful. Consequently, there are times when a Christian prince can, for the sake of religion, place a ban, directed even to foreign and non­ subject unbelievers, upon this intercourse within his own kingdom. 6. Thirdly,2 the statement must be made that the Church has, in actual fact, laid down many prohibitions with respect to the sort of communication under discussion. In the first place, indeed, familiarity with Jews is placed under „ . a general prohibition. On this point, the Decretal Tw Moreover, familiar. .... , f 111 ' ity with tfie jews is V, tit. vi, chap, vui) may be consulted. In fact, it «^actual fact for- WOuld seem that absolutely all converse and communi­ cation with them was forbidden by the Fourth Council of Toledo (Chap. Ixi [Chap. IxiiJ). However, that prohibition has refer­ ence, not to all the faithful, universally, but to those who have been newly converted to the faith from among the ranks of the Jews them­ selves. To these new Christians, converse with those of their own people who persevere in Judaism is forbidden, because of the peril attending such converse. Therefore, this prohibition should be understood to refer to frequent, or continued converse, which may result in peril. Thomas Sanchez {Opus XIorale in Praecepta Decalogi, Bk. 11, chap. xxxi), following Sanchez. St. Thomas, Sylvester, and others, limits this general prohibition in such St. Thoms, a way as to exclude its application in the case of those believers who 1 [Le. this is the second of the three points to be discussed in connexion with secuhr, or human, communication. Vide the first paragraph of the immediately preceding Sub-section, p. 79c.—Tr.] 2 [This is the third of the three points to be taken up in connexion with secular, or human, com­ munication. Vide, Sub-section 4, p. 790.—Tr. 792 Council of Orleans. Council of Agde. The Three Theological Virtues: On Faith are firm in the faith and with respect to whom there can be no fear of moral peril. However, if the prohibition contained in a law is general, it does not cease to bind in an individual case, even if the purpose of the law does, in a purely negative sense, cease to be realized in the individual case, as I assume from the treatise on laws. I therefore thinl that there is a limitation to the prohibition in the case of those persons whose care it is to convert such infidels as we speak of, because the purpose of the law then does not simply cease to be realized in a nega­ tive sense, but in addition, it ceases by contrariety.1 7. Secondly,2 living in the same house with Jews is specifically Secondly, living in forbidden (Decretum, Pt. II, causa xxvin, qu. i, can. 492 the same house with Decretals, Bk. V, tit. vi, chap. v). The reason for forbidden.^ this prohibition is the avoidance of harm. But the objection may be made that a Christian An objection. can own a sfoye who is an unbeliever, and that conse­ quently, he can live with that unbeliever. The antecedent is supported in the Decretals (ibid., chap. xiii). Our reply is as follows : either this fact constitutes an exception The solution. to t^ie prohibition set forth above ; or else it cannot properly be said that the master dwells with, the slave, but rather the converse, so that the prohibition in question does not apply to such a master; or, at least, a certain equality of fellowship and familiar intercourse is required for ‘dwelling together’, in the true sense of the phrase, so that the Christian master, in accordance with other laws above-mentioned, must avoid also this equal association with an unbelieving slave. Thirdly, a Christian is forbidden to invite an unbeliever to his banquet table, or to accept such an invitation from Furthermore, it is forbidden to eat at the latter; for this also is dangerous association. This the same table with prohibition was especially directed against Jews in the Jews. Third Council of Orleans (Chap, xxiii [Chap, xiii]), and in the Council of Agde (Chap, xl cited in Decretum, Pt. II, causa xxvin, qu. i, can. xiv), the special reason being given that Jews dis­ criminate among different sorts of food, a practice which is not permis­ sible to Christians. However, as a special concession, this eating in common is permitted to preachers who are sent forth to convert unbelievers. Fourthly, in these same laws, and in the Apostolic canons cited 1 [Le. harm to the individual. The above is what is taught by all theologians on law, viz. if law ceases to secure its purpose negatively in a given case, it still binds ; if, however, it ceases contrarie, as is said, it ceases to bind, Le. if a law does some real extrinsic harm to a person, it would not bind him. This is clearly seen in the laws of fasting and abstinence. If such a law would make a person unwell, it is said to cease contrarie. However, the law against reading certain books may cease negafttvly, but never contrarie.—Reviser.] 2 [This introduces the second of the prohibitions mentioned at the beginning of the preceding Sub-section. Six more, making eight in all, are discussed in the immediately succeeding pages.—Te.] Disp. XVIll: On Means for the Conversion of Unbelievers above, Christians are specifically forbidden to eat the unleavened bread of the Jews; an act which is evil in itself, if it The eating of un­ leavened bread is is understood to involve the consumption of such food also forbidden. as a Jewish rite; but this rule is also interpreted as a prohibition, in order to avoid suspicion and peril [to the faith], against any partaking of the azyme with the Jews themselves or receiving it from them. When there is no danger of scandal, however, and espe­ cially if necessity requires, the eating of this food as ordinary bread is not forbidden, as the eating of idolothytes is forbidden in the Decretum (Pt. II, causa xxxn, qu. iv, can. viii). 8. Fifthly, in case of illness, Christians are forbidden to call in Jews; at least they are forbidden to do so for the pur­ It is forbidden, moreover, to call in pose of [medical] treatment (Sixth Synod, Chap. XI, Jews in case of cited in Decretum, Pt. II, causa xxvin, qu. I, can. illness. xiii). This rule may have been made not merely be­ cause of special peril to the soul, but also to avoid bodily contact. Hence, a further rule has been laid down against receiving medicine from Jews, a prohibition which is chiefly understood to mean medicine is not to be received at their hands and administered by them, lest familiarity and peril result. But these and like prohibitions should be interpreted as applying only when the case is not one of necessity, since necessity knows no law. Sixthly, Christians are further ordered not to bathe with Jews at the same time at the same public baths, a prohibition It is likewise for­ which is laid down in the above-mentioned Chapter bidden to frequent the baths in the xiii [Decretum, ibid.']. This rule should be understood as company of Jews, if this be done in ac­ applying only in a general sense, namely, as referring cordance with a pre­ to the act of walking to the baths with them, that is vious agreement. to say, [the act of bathing together] as the result of an intention to do so. For this deliberate practice involves true social intercourse and familiarity, against which, on account of the danger involved therein, all the prohibitions under discussion are especially directed. If a Christian, then, should come accidentally to a public bath where a Jew is bathing at the time, the rule has no application, and it is not necessary that the Christian should on that account forgo what is convenient to him, or postpone it. Seventhly, it may be especially noted that Christian women are forbidden to act as nurses for Jewish children, a fact Furthermore, it is forbidden that which is brought out in the Decretals (Bk. V, tit. vi, Christian women should nurse _Jewish chap. viii). However, this qualifying phrase is added: children. ‘in their homes’—that is, in the homes of the Jews— so that apparently, the rule in question is made solely to guard against the practice of dwelling together. Consequently, the inference may be drawn that a Christian woman is not forbidden to nurse a Jewish 1569.74 5 i 794 Three "Theological Virtues: On Faith child, in her own home; since the words of the law do not include such a case and should not be so extended. However, although this is true in so far as the strict letter of the law is concerned, nevertheless, the situation in question should be avoided because of the familiarity and peculiar affection which, as a general rule, result therefrom. 9. Eighthly, it is forbidden that Christians, in their wills, should It is also forbidden name Jews as their heirs and legatees. This is the doc­ to make heirs or trine of the canonists {Decretals, Bk. V, tit. vi, chap, legatees of of Jews. legatees Jews. anj eSpecjaHy of Felinus (on Decretals, ibid., no. 3), the Gloss thereon, and Sylvester (on the word iudaeus, Qu. 1 [, no. 2]). The Code (I. ix. 1) may be cited on the same rule; but in the Code the prohibition refers only to the Jews as a whole, that is, as a community, and prohibitions expressed in such terms are not usually extended to apply to individuals, as the Gloss thereon indicates. In this case, how­ ever, the extended application is allowed in the interests of the faith and of religion. Yet another chapter in the Decretals (Bk. V, tit. vn, chap, v) and one in the Decretum (Pt. II, causa xxiv, qu. ii, can. vi) may be mentioned in this connexion, in which the said prohibition is imposed upon bishops, in particular, while in the Decretals (Bk. V, tit. vn, chap, vi) it is extended to clerics. The Doctors, however, apply that rule to all Catholics, either by the same process of reasoning, or at least a fortiori ; and such should be the practice observed by all Catholics, especially since there exists a general warning lest they render aid and favour of this sort to Jews. This was the ruling of the Fourth Council of Toledo (Chap. Ivii). One must note, with respect to these and like questions, that the 493 prohibitions involved are grave, both because of their subj’ect-matter and because of the purpose they serve; and that by their nature, and generally speaking, they are binding under pain of mortal sin, although occasionally, when the particular instance happens to be of slight importance, the transgression may become venial. Moreover, since a prohibition of the sort under discussion is part of the common law [of the Church], dispensations therefrom cannot usually be given by bishops; but when in any given case the necessity is urgent and delay would be dangerous, then, according to the com­ mon teaching on law, the granting of such dispensations is within the power of a bishop. 10. Finally, it may be asked whether the laws in question are to be interpreted as applying universally to all unbelievers, Are these prohibi­ or whether they have reference only to the Jews. tions extended to apply to all unbe­ The cause of the doubt is that the laws cited speak lievers ? expressly of the Jews, so that some persons hold that, the said laws being penal in nature, there should be no extension of their application. A special reason which is customarily given is that, Disp. XV111: On Means for the Conversion of Unbelievers according to the Decretals (Bk. V, tit. vi, chap, xiii), the Jews are not only subjects but also slaves. Hostiensis (Summa, Bk. V, De ludaeis, Hosier»·, p. 349) holds that the passage in question refers only to one’s own purchased slaves, a view which certain of the Summists adopt. How­ ever, such a limitation is certainly not contained in the text, where, on the contrary, it is stated that the Jews have indeed inherently merited this slavery, but that in point of fact they are tributaries with the civil status of subordinate subjects, as Panormitanus (on Decretals, Bk. V, Panormuan tit. vi, chap, xiii) notes with reference to this point, and as St. Thomas St. Thomas. (II.-II, qu. 10, art. 12, ad 3 and Pt. Ill, qu. 68, art. 10, ad 2) and Soto Soto. (on the Sentences, Bk. IV, dist. v, sole question, an. 10, ad 2) have also explained. Therefore, the true reason for this discrimination against the Jews is thought to be the fact that intercourse with the Jews involves more peril on account of their greater peninacity and their hatred of the Christian religion. Nevertheless, it is my opinion that the prohibitions which we are discussing, apply also to the Saracens1—that is, the Mohammedans — both because such an extension of their force is repeatedly indicated in the civil and canon law (Code, I. iii. 57, § 5 [I. iii. 54 (56), §§ 8 (3) et seq.~\ and Decretals, Bk. V, tit. vi, chaps, viii, xvi, xv, xix, v); and also because there is an analogy in the reasoning applicable to both cases, inasmuch as these [Mohammedan] unbelievers are also enemies of the Christians, and attempt with all their strength to pervert the faithful. As for other unbelieving pagans, however, they do not seem to have been included in the aforementioned laws, a fact which has been noted by Sanchez ([Opus Morale in Praecepta Decalogi, Bk. II,] chap. ^chex. xxxi, no. 25), of whose opinion I approve in so far as relates to this matter. Many statements concerning these prohibitions may also be found in the writings of the jurists on the laws in question, in the comments of the Summists (on the word iudaeus), and in the state­ ments of St. Antoninus (Pt. II, tit. xn, chap, iii), as well as in those s«. Antoc.no·. of Azor and Sanchez, already cited; and these authorities quote A«cr. many others. The foregoing may suffice on the subject of unbelief. 1 [The Code refers to ‘pagans’.—Tb ] FRANCISCO SUAREZ A WORK ON THE THREE THEOLOGICAL VIRTUES FAITH, HOPE AND CHARITY ON CHARITY: DISPUTATION XIII 641 TO THE GENTLE READER The primary cause, gentle reader, of the unusually brief form in which the following treatises on Hope and Charity are published, was the fact that even the members of the very school over which Suarez presided at Rome, during the time when he lectured on these subjects, became wearied of extremely diffuse and excessively elaborate disser­ tations, wherefore he readily bowed to the precepts and wishes of that school, such was the simple sincerity of this noble Doctor. Furthermore, this treatment is brief, because he disregarded not a few matters that are usually dealt with, especially on the subject of Charity, for these matters are either entirely or in great measure appli­ cable to grace, a subject which Suarez, in his work thereon, had very cogent reasons for thinking to be distinct from Charity (De Gratia, Bk. VI, chap, xii).1 Such matters concern the supernatural entity of Charity, the production, increase, and loss of habits, the power of sanctifying and meriting. These are explained at length in that same work, and partially, in his treatise on the resuscitation of merit (section 3).2 Grace itself, which of its nature precedes Charity, demanded that all of those matters should have a prior claim to treatment, and if the reader should here find them to be missing, they will be fully supplied in the passages indicated above. However, the fact that these treatises, if compared with others which the author has already published, are briefer, is no indication that they are in any respect unsuited to the character of his genius and judgment. On the contrary, we venture to assert that when the author employs this concise method of composition, he appears, not merely to be equal to, but in a certain sense, to surpass himself. For the discursive reasonings of his profound genius and keen discernment, as well as the cogency of the arguments set forth by him, which attain a felicitous amplitude in other works of his, are here compressed into small compass, and more readily understood, without any loss of efficacy and force. Consequently, these treatises contain the pith and marrow of the subjects at hand, as you yourself, gentle reader, will (I hope) admit, when you have made the test of experiment. Nor will it be difficult, if you observe the similarity of this work3 with others, its order and method, to divine the author of both the one and the others, recognizing (as it were) the lion by its claws. In addition, in order that all this matter may be readily intelligible even to those who are not very well versed in the works of Suarez, we 1 (Not included in these Selections.—Tr.J * [Opusculum; Relectio de Meritis mortificatis, &c., Disp. I, sect, in, which is not included in these Selections.—Tr.J j [hujus operis, referring evidently to both disputations (those on Hope and Charity).—Tr.] 800 The Three Theological Virtues: On Charity indicate in the margins of these disputations on Hope and Charity identical or similar points which Suarez discusses elsewhere more at length.1 For the author will thus come to his own assistance, where there might seem to be need, without help sought from any other source. DISPUTATION XIII ON WAR An external contest at arms which is incompatible with external peace is properly called war, when carried on between sense is manifold. two sovereign princes or between two states. When, however, it is a contest between a prince and his own state, or between citizens and their state, it is termed sedition. When it is between private individuals it is called a quarrel or a duel. The difference between these various kinds of contest appears to be material rather than formal, and we shall discuss them all, as did St. Thomas (II.-II, qq. 40, 41, 42) and others who will be mentioned below. War in a genera] SECTION I IS WAR INTRINSICALLY EVIL? The first heresy [in connexion with this subject] consists in the assertion that it is intrinsically evil and contrary to The first error. On this and the follow­ charity to wage war. Such is the heretical belief attri­ ing error see Bellar- buted by Augustine to the Manichaeans {Against mine, De Laicis, Bk. Ill, chaps, xiv Faustus, Bk. XXII, chap. Ixxiv), whom Wycliffe fol­ and xvi. Molina, De lowed, according to the testimony of Waldensis {De lustitia, Disp. xc. Sacramentalibus [which is Vol. Ill of Doctrinale Antiquitatum Fidet\ last title, next to last chapter). The second error is the assertion that war is specifically forbidden to The second error. Christians, and especially, war against Christians. In opposition to So Eck maintains (Enchiridion Locorum Communium, these heretics, others are also cited Chap, xxii) ;2 and other persons of our own time, who by Cenedo, Collect., are heretics, advance the same contention. They LIX, pt. I. distinguish, however, two kinds of w’ar, the defensive and the aggressive, which we shall discuss in Sub-section 6 of this Section. The conclusions that follow will elucidate the matter. 2. Our first conclusion is that war, absolutely speaking, is not _ c_, , . intrinsically evil, nor is it forbidden to Christians, which is negative, I his conclusion is a matter of faith and is laid down in 2th a matter of the Scriptures, for in the Old Testament, wars waged by most holy men are praised (Genesis, Chap, xiv I. Genesis, xiv. 1 [Of the volume De Triplici Virtute Theologica, only Disp. XVIII of the treatise On Faith, and Disp. XIII of the treatise On Charity are included in these Selections.—Tr.] ’ [Eck speaks of the lawfulness of Christians waging war against Turks and heretics.—Reviser.] 797 Disp. XIII: On War 801 [, w. 19-20]) : ‘Blessed be Abram [...·] And blessed be God by whose protection the enemies are in thy hands.’ We find similar passages concerning Moses, Josue, Samson, Gedeon, David, the Macha bees, and others, whom God often ordered to wage war upon the enemies of the Hebrews. Moreover, the apostle Paul {Hebrews, Chap, xi [, v. 33]) said that by faith the saints conquered kingdoms. The same principle is confirmed by further testimony, that of the Fathers quoted by Gratian {Decretum, Pt. II, causa xxm, qq. 1 and 2), and also that ot Ambrose {On Duties, various chapters). However, one may object, in the first place, that the Lord said to The first objection: David Paralipomenon, Chap, xxviii, v. 3]: ‘Thou based on i Paralipo- shalt not build my temple because thou art a man who menon, xxviii. has shed blood.1 Secondly, it will be objected that Christ said to The second objec­ tion: based on Peter {Join, Chap, xviii [, v. 11]) : ‘Put up thy sword Matthew, Chap, xix [John, Chap, xviii] into the scabbard,’ &c. ; and that Isaias also said {Isaias, and on Isaias, Chap, ii [, v. 4]) : ‘They shall turn their swords into Chaps, ii and xi. ploughshares [. . .] neither shall they be exercised any more to war’ ; and, in another Chapter (Chap, xi [, v. 9]) : ‘They shall not hurt nor shall they kill in all [my] holy mountain.’ The Prophet is speaking, indeed, of the time of the coming of the Messiah, at which time, especially, it will be made clear, what is permissible and what is not permissible. Thirdly, at the Council of Nicaea (Chap, xi [, can. xii]), a penalty _ xt_. . was imposed upon Christians who, after having received based on the Coun- the faith, enrolled themselves for military service, letter οΓρορ ^eo Furthermore, Pope Leo {Letters, xcii [Letter clxvii, inquis, xii]) wrote that war was forbidden toChristians, after a solemn penance. Fourthly, war morally brings with it innumerable sins; and a The fourth objec­ given course of action is considered in itself evil and tion: based on forbidden, if it is practically always accompanied by reasoning. unseemly circumstances and harm to one’s neighbours. [Furthermore,] one may add that war is opposed to A confirmation. peace, to the love of one’s enemies, and to the forgiveness of injuries. 3. We reply to the first objection that [the Scriptural passage in The answer to the question] is based upon the unjust slaying of Uriah; first objection. and, also, upon the particularly great reverence owed to the Temple. 798 [As for the second objection, we may answer, first, that] Christ our 1 [Suare?\ quotation of Paralipomenon, Chap, xxviii, v. 3, reads: Non aedificabis mihi templum, q we find this additional passage: ‘For he beareth not the sword in vain. For he is God’s minister: to work vengeance upon evildoers.'1 Secondly, it is objected that [if our second general conclusion The second be true,] then, as a consequence, the same party in objection. one and same case is both plaintiff and judge, a situation which is contrary to the natural law. The truth of the conclusion is evident, since the prince who has been wronged, assumes the role of judge by his act of aggression. The objection is confirmed, in the first place, by the fact that the The first confirma- r^ht to avenge themselves is denied to private indivition of this duals, for this reason, namely, that they would pracobjection. tically exceed the bounds of justice; and yet the same danger exists in the case of a prince who avenges himself. A second confirmation of the same objection is that, by a like reasoning, any private person who might be unable to The second con­ tinuation of the secure such punishment through a judge could take second objection. the law into his own hands, executing it on his own authority; since this privilege is granted to princes, on the sole ground that there is no other way of securing a just vengeance. 7. Our reply is, that it cannot be denied that in this matter [of The soluti n. public vengeance], one and the same person assumes, in a sense, the role of plaintiff and that of judge; even as we perceive that God, to Whom there is some analogy in the public authority, assumes this double role. But the cause [of such an assump­ tion on the part of public authority] is simply that this act of punitive justice has been indispensable to mankind, and that no more fitting method for its performance could, in the order of nature and humanly speaking, be found. This is especially true, since we must presuppose, prior to the war, the contumacy of the offending party in not wishing to give satisfaction; for then (contumacy being established) if he finds himself in subjection to the offended party, he may impute his own misfortune to himself. Neither is this case analogous to that of a private individual. For The reply to the in the first place, such an individual is guided by his first confirmation. OWn [unaided] judgment, and therefore he will easily exceed the limits of vengeance ; whereas public authority is guided by public counsel, to which heed must be paid, and consequently authority of this sort may more easily avoid the disadvantages arising from personal inclination. In the second place, this power of punishment has for its essential purpose not private but public good, and hence it has been committed not to the private individual, but to the public 1 [Suarez’s quotation for the latter part of this passage reading: ad vindiciam mali jactorum, varies somewhat from the version found in the Vulgate which reads: vindex in tram à qui malum agit.—Ttj Ramans, xiii. 820 Covarruvias. Victori i. Soto. The Three Theological Virtues: On Charity body. Therefore, if the latter is unable or unwilling to punish [an injury], the private individual shall patiently endure his loss. From the foregoing remarks, then, our reply to the first confirmation of the objection is evident. As to the second confirmation, it has been said by some persons The 1 of certain t^ie situatæn referred to, a private individual authorities to the is allowed to avenge himself secretly; and in the Code second confirmation there is a title, Ouando liceat sine iudice Γ.. .1 se vindicare [. . .] (when it is permitted to avenge oneself without recourse to a judge = Code, III. xxvii). But this must be understood as referring to restitution for losses suffered; for in so far as 806 it refers to the punishment of an offence, it is an inadmissible error. An act of punitive justice, indeed, is an exercise of that jurisdiction which private individuals do not possess, and cannot obtain through an offence committed by another. For if they could possess it, there would be no need to employ the public power of jurisdiction; or at least, since this power of jurisdiction is derived from men themselves, each one would have had the power to refrain from transferring it to the state official, retaining it, on the contrary, for himself; a conclusion which would be opposed to the natural law, and to the good governance of the human race. Therefore, we deny the consequent involved in the second conA dear reply firmation. For laws regard those things which are true in an absolute sense, and private individuals, absolutely speaking, may obtain a ready revenge for offences because there is a public authority, while the fact that sometimes they are not able to do so, is an accidental occurrence which, for that reason, must necessarily be endured, as we have said. But the relationship between two sovereign powers is based on an absolute necessity. It is in the light of this necessity that certain civil glosses cited by Covarruvias (on Sext, rule Peccatum, Bk. I, pt. ii, § 9), should be interpreted. On this point, Victoria fie Potestate Civili, no. 6 fie lure Belli, no. 56]) and Soto fie lustitia, Bk. IV, qu. iv, art. 1) may also be consulted. 8. Thirdly, I hold that whoever begins a war without just cause, The truth of a sins not onty against charity, but also against justice; third condusion is and hence he is bound to make reparation for all the harm that results. The truth of this conclusion is manifest. The only question which arises in connexion with this point is A doubt which whether or not there may sometimes exist a cause for ariseswar which absolves one from the charge of injustice, but not from the charge of sinning against charity. The reply must be that such a situation rarely occurs; and yet it is by no means incon­ ceivable. For just as it happens among private individuals that one Disp. XIII: On War 821 person may take what is due to him from another, an act which is not opposed to justice, but which is opposed to charity at times (namely, when the debtor incurs very serious losses in consequence, while the property in question is not in great degree necessary to the creditor); even so, a similar situation might arise between princes or states. In this connexion, however, it should be noted that in a war of the kind described, it is possible to consider, first, the loss to the state against which the war is waged; secondly, the loss to the state which com­ mences the war; thirdlyandfinally,thepossiblelosstotheentireChurch. With respect to this third contingency, we may easily find support A discussion of the for our assertion. For although a Christian king may tolie^hurch1 harm ^ec^are war on some particular just ground, it will nevertheless be possible for him to sin against the would result from war. charity due to the Church, in pursuing his rights. For example, he may foresee the consequent growth in power of the enemies of the faith, and so forth; so that, in that case, it may be a sin to wage war, and yet there arises no obligation to make restitution, since the particular just ground that he has extinguishes such an obligation. When the harm is of the kind first mentioned, [a harm, that is, to the state against which war is waged,] then there is no Discussion of the great obligation to make restitution, since the mali­ cases in which harm to the enemy cious intent of the state inflicting the original injury would result. was the cause of the loss in question. Nevertheless, if in a particular case the latter state should be unable to give satisfaction or make restitution without suffering great injury, and if such satis­ faction should not be necessary to the prince of the other state, then the latter, by insisting that satisfaction be given, would clearly be acting against charity. Finally, turning to the second case mentioned, if one prince begins A discussion of the a war upon another, even with just cause, while ex­ casesm which harm pOSing his own realm to disproportionate loss and would result tothe r ., ® , , .„ t ·___·_ _r . , peril, then he will be sinning not only against charity, party that com­ mences hostilities. but also against the justice due to his own state. The reason for this assertion is as follows: a prince is bound in justice to have greater regard for the common good of his state than for his own good; otherwise, he will become a tyrant. So a judge who condemns to hanging a criminal deserving of execution but very necessary to the state, would act in a manner opposed to his official obligations, and, consequently, to justice. Similarly, a physician would sin against the justice required by his profession if he should give medicine which would heal a present disease but would cause more serious diseases to ensue. 9. However, with respect to this last point, we must take into consideration the fact that a single king who rules over A modification of the last statement. several kingdoms, can often make war for the sake of 822 The Three Theological Virtues: On Charity one of these to the detriment of another. For though the various king­ doms may be distinct from one another, nevertheless, inasmuch as they are subject to one head, they can and should be of mutual aid, since the defence of one contributes to the benefit of another and in this way, the principle of equality is preserved. For in its own emergency, one kingdom might require the aid of another. In addition to all these considerations, the mere fact that their [common] prince is rendered more powerful, is in itself extremely advantageous to each of the king­ doms involved. In short, greater peace, and other advantages, may perhaps accrue to a state so supported ; and many other [similar] points can easily be perceived upon reflection. There are, then, numerous considerations which may oblige a prince to abandon his right to make war lest his realm suffer loss. io. Furthermore, we should call attention to the conclusion, The conclusion of drawn from these primary considerations by Cajetan Cajetan. (on Π.-ΙΙ, qU> ç>6, art. q [qU. qO, art. i]), namely, that for a war to be just, the sovereign ought to be so sure of the degree of his power, that he is morally certain of victory. The first reason for this conclusion is the fact that otherwise the prince would incur the 807 evident peril of inflicting upon his state losses greater than the advan­ tages involved. In the same way, says Cajetan, a judge would do wrong in attempting the arrest of a criminal without a force that, to his certain knowledge, could not be overpowered. Secondly, w’hoever begins a war assumes an active role; and the one who assumes such a role must always be the stronger, in order to vanquish the one who plays a passive part. But this condition [of certitude] does not appear to me to be How much truth is absolutely essential. First, because, from a human there in this con- standpoint, it is almost impossible of realization, elusion? Secondly, because it is often to the common interest of the state not to await such a degree of certitude, but rather to test its ability to conquer the enemy, even when that ability is somewhat doubtful. Thirdly, because if the conclusion were true, a weaker sove­ reign could never declare war upon a stronger, since he is unable to attain the certitude which Cajetan demands. Therefore, the following rules should be laid down. A prince [w’ho declares war] is, indeed, bound to attain the maximum certitude possible regarding victory. Furthermore, he ought to balance the expectation of victory against the risk of loss, and ascertain whether, all things being carefully considered, expectation is preponderant. If so great a degree of certitude is impossible of attainment, he ought at least to have either a more probable expectation of victory, or one equally balanced as to the chances of victory or defeat, and that, in proportion to the need of the state and the communal welfare. But if Disp. XIII: On War 823 the expectation of victory is less apt to be realized than the chance of defeat, and if the war is offensive in character, then in almost every case that war should be avoided. If [, on the other hand,] rhe war is defensive, it should be attempted; for in that case it is a matter of necessity, whereas the offensive war is a matter of choice. All of these conclusions are sufficiently clear in the light of the principles of conscience and justice. SECTION V CAN CHRISTIAN PRINCES HAVE ANY JUST GROUND FOR WAR BEYOND THAT WHICH NATURAL REASON DICTATES .’ I. The first opinion [which we shall discuss in this connexion] is affirmative, and is defended by Hostiensis, Panormiaffirmative. tanus, and other canonists (on Decretals, Bk. Ill, tit. xxxiv, chap, viii), as well as by Alvaro Paez (De Planctu Ecclesiae, Bk. I, chap, xxxvii [chap, xiii and Bk. II, chap, xlvi]), Gabriel (on the Sentences, Bk. IV, dist. xv, qu. 4) and other authorities to whom Covarruvias refers (on Sext, rule Peccatum, Pt. II, § 10). But these authors do not all express themselves in the same manner, for they mention varying grounds for the opinion in question. The first ground is that of simple unbelief [on the part of the enemy], that is, a refusal to accept the true religion. The first ground which may be ad­ But this is a false ground, a point with which we deal vanced is rejected in the treatise De Fide.1 by the author, in the treatise De The second ground is that God may be avenged for Ftde(Disp. xviii).1 injuries which are done to Him by sins against nature, by idolatry. Alfonso de Castro (De lusta The second ground and is also rejected. Haereticorum Punitione, Bk. II, chap, xiv) supports this latter contention. But this opinion is also false, and it is $0 first of all, even if we speak of ‘vengeance’, in the strict sense. For God did not give to all men the power to avenge the injuries they do to Him, since He can easily avenge Himself, if He so wills. Moreover, it would not have been well for the human race had men received this power from God, for the greatest disorder would have resulted there­ from. The same argument holds true with respect to the plea of defending [the majesty of God]; since the sins against Him would thus be multiplied rather than prevented. On this same ground, moreover. Christian princes could declare war even upon one another, for many of these princes also are offenders against God. Likewise, since such a ground of aggression could never be sufficiently established, those who were so attacked could justly defend themselves, and the war would thus become just for both sides. The first opinion: 1 [Supra, p. 754.—Tb.] HortiensM. Panormi Un u». Gab rid. Covamiviw. 824 The Three Theological Virtues: On Charity 2. The objection may be made that the people of Israel were permitted to make war against idolaters on this very upon Leviticus, ground, aS is clear from the Old Testament (Leviticus, XV111· Chap, xviii [, w. 24-8]). I reply that various grounds are assigned for [the justification of] its solution by the war in question. Augustine (Sermones, CXV, De Augustine, Epipha- Tempore [also C\ = Sermones De Scripturis, xxxiv, nius and Cassian. in γθρ y, Appendix? coL l8n> Migne ed.]), Epiphanius ([Panarium Adversus LXXX Haereses, Lib. II, tom. 11,] haeres Ixvi, [no. Ixxxiii]) and Cassian (Collationes, V, chap, xxiv) hold that the [dis­ puted] land belonged by hereditary right to the children of Israel as descendants of Sem, to whom Noe had given it as an inheritance, and that it had been forcibly seized by Cham, the brother of Sem. I neither accept nor reject this ground, because the arguments adduced on both sides are insufficient. Others say that the title in question was a gift of God, and this is indeed a valid title. Augustine adds, however (Ques­ The solution of other authorities tions on Josue, Qu. 20 [= Questions on Heptateuch, is approved. Bk. VI, qu. 20]), that although this title was just, nevertheless, since it could not be proved, other reasons, more firmly and clearly established, have always been sought, namely: that the enemy forbade [the Israelites] passage over common highways; or again, that the former were the aggressors, and began the war. It may also be said that these enemies were not only idolaters, but homicides, since it was their custom to sacrifice innocent little children ; hence, on the ground of the defence of the innocent, it was permissible to subdue them in war. 3. It must be noticed, however, that the second ground men­ tioned1 has been virtually accepted by a number of A further explana­ tion of the second authorities, with respect to cases in which it happens ground mentioned that a state worshipping the one God inclines toward above. idolatry through the wickedness of its prince; these authorities claim that it is allowable to make war upon that prince. Their contention would be valid if the Concerning this prince forcibly compelled his subjects to practice 808 second ground, see De Fide, Disp. idolatry ; but under any other circumstances, [such a XVIII, sect, rv.2 ground] would not be a sufficient cause for war, unless the whole state should demand assistance against its sovereign. For where compulsion does not intervene, defence has no place. This position is supported, first, by the fact that, if the reasoning in question were valid, it would always be permissible to declare such a war on the ground of protecting innocent little children. Secondly, An objection based 1 [That is, the avenging of God for sins which are against nature, or idolatrous.—Tr.] 1 [Supra, p. 767.—Tr.] Disp. XIII: On War 825 on the basis of that same reasoning, Christian princes would always be permitted to wage war among themselves, upon their own authority. Finally, by whatever arguments this ground for war may be justified, [the title urged] is not confined to Christians alone, but is possessed in common with all unbelievers who worship only the one God; and accordingly, these unbelievers could rightfully defend those who wished to worship the same God, and who were forced by others into idolatry. 4. A third ground for war is advanced, namely, the supreme The third ground is temporal dominion [of Christians]. That is to say, the absolutely rejected, authorities mentioned above maintain either that un­ believers are not true owners of their possessions ; or else that the Chris­ tian Emperor, or—at least—the supreme Pontiff, has direct temporal dominion over the whole world. But all such claims are vain inventions, a point which we discuss π „ r .t elsewhere, on the subject of dominion and laws. In the in, chap, vii [chap, second place, even if we grant that such a title does inyj], Defensio Fidei, deecf exist, still it would be impossible either to demonBk. IILchaps.ijiv.v.’ . . , J r r. . strate its existence to the satisfaction of infidels, or to force them to believe in the existence of such dominion ; and therefore, they could not be forced to obey. Finally, on that same ground, the Pope or the Emperor could make war [even] upon all Christian princes. Wherefore, it must be observed that although the Pope has indirectly supreme power in temporal affairs, nevertheless, the existence of such temporal power is always based, essentially, upon the assumption of direct power in spiritual matters; and therefore, this indirect power does not essentially extend to unbelievers, over whom no direct spiritual dominion exists even in the Pope himself. Butluse the term, ‘essentially’ (per se loquendo), because ‘incidentally’ {per accidens) the case may be otherwise, as I shall presently show. 5. A fourth ground urged is that unbelievers are barbarians and A fourth ground is incapable of governing themselves properly; and that examined. the order of nature demands that men of this condi­ tion should be governed by those who are more prudent, as Aristotle Anstc {Politics, Bk. I, chap, i) has taught, saying {ibid., chap, v [Bk. I, chap, iii, § 8]) that a war is by nature just, when it is waged against men born to be under obedience but unwilling to accept that condition; a ground [for war] which is approved by Major (on the Sentences, Bk. II, dist. Major, xliv, qu. 3), and at great length by Sepûlveda (Bk. MI, chap, ii [De s?chRegno et Regis Officio, Bk. Ill, near end]). In the first place, however, such a contention cannot have a general application; for it is evident that there are many unbelievers more gifted by nature than are the faithful, and better adapted to 1 [Of these chapters, only chap, v of Bk. Ill of the Defensio Fidei is included in these Selections. Vide supra, p. 667.—TR.] 1569.74 ς x 826 The Three Theological Virtues: On Charity political life. Secondly, in order that the ground in question may be valid, it is not enough to judge that a given people are of inferior natural talents ; for they must also be so wretched as to live in general more Eke wild beasts than like men, as those persons are said to live who have no human polity, and who go about entirely naked, eat human flesh, &c. If there are any such, they may be brought into subjection by war, not with the purpose of destroying them, but rather that they may be organized in human fashion, and justly governed. However, this ground for war should rarely or never be approved, except in circumstances in which the slaughter of innocent people, and similar wrongs take place; and therefore, the ground in question is more properly included under defensive than under offensive wars. Finally, Aristotle, in the passage cited above, declares that a war of this sort is permissible only when those men who are subdued in order that they may be governed, are as different from the rest of man­ kind as is the body from the soul ; a proposition from which one must conclude, however, that the said ground for war, if it really exists, is valid not only for Christians, but also for every sovereign who wishes to defend the law of nature, which, when understood in an absolute sense, gives rise to that ground. 6. Therefore, the assertion must be made that there is no ground for war so exclusively reserved to. Christian, rprinces The true solution , . , .J . . . of this question, that it has not some basis in, or at least some due relaby means of three tion t0 natural law, being therefore also applicable to conclusions. . , . .. σ rr princes who are unbelievers. By way of explaining this assertion, I conclude, first, that a Chris_ e—. . · tian prince may not declare war save either by reason of some injury inflicted or for the defence of the inno­ cent. We have already given sufficient proof of this fact, by rejecting all the invalid grounds for war, [advanced above]. The arguments we have adduced are a proof of this same fact ; for the law of grace has not destroyed, but on the contrary completes the natural law. 7. Secondly, I must say that the defence of the innocent is perThe second conclu- missible in a special sense to Christian princes, and that ston· the same proposition holds true, proportionately, with respect to avenging injuries. For if a state subject to an unbelieving prince wishes to accept the law of Christ and the unbelieving sove­ reign prevents that acceptance, then Christian princes have the right 809 to defend that innocent people; but if the same kingdom wishes to submit to the law of unbelievers—for example, to the Mohammedan —and its prince is opposed to this submission, then an unbelieving Turkish prince would not have a similar right of war against that other sovereign. The reason for this distinction is that to prevent the acceptance of the law of Christ does indeed involve grievous injustice Disp. XIII: On War 827 and harm, whereas there is no injury at all in prohibiting the accep­ tance of another law. Likewise, if [a given people] are willing to listen [to the Gospel], they may be convinced through reason that this is the more credible faith and that it ought to be believed; and therefore, it is just to assist them, under these circumstances. Similar examples may be adduced, relating to the first1 part of our conclusion, as when injuries are inflicted upon preachers of the Gospel; or certainly when unbelieving princes act to the harm of the faithful, for this is an injury to the Church which she has a special right to repel and avenge. This right is in part supernatural, that is, in so far as the power from God to preach the Gospel is concerned, and in this sense, it surely is not possessed by unbelievers; all of which we have sufficiently proved in treating of faith (De Fide, Disp. XVIII, sect, i).2 8. I hold, thirdly, that all of the foregoing considerations are so The third conclufounded on the natural reason that they may, to a SIOncertain extent and in due proponion, be applied to unbelievers. The explanation of this conclusion is that if any state wishes to worship the one God and observe the law of nature, or to listen to preachers who teach these things, and if the sovereign of that state forcibly prevents it from doing so, there would spring up in consequence a just ground for war to be waged by some other prince, even if the latter should be an unbeliever, and guided solely by natural reason; because that wrar would be a just defence of inno­ cent persons. In like manner, if any nation should worship the one God and observe the laws of nature, while another nation practised idolatry and lived contrary to natural reason, then the former state would have the right to send missionaries to instruct [the citizens of the latter state], and to free them from their errors. And if this action were forcibly prevented, then war could justly follow; first, for the reason that such a right is entirely in harmony with nature; secondly, because the defence of the innocent would be involved in that procedure, since, speaking generally, there would not fail to be some who wished to be taught the natural truths necessary for an upright and virtuous life, and who would be wickedly impeded in the attainment of this wash, and finally, because of other reasons which we have set forth in our discussion of faith (De Fide, Disp. XVIII)2 and which, in due pro­ portion, are applicable to the point under discussion. 1 [Sie (primam) ; but the reference is apparently to the second conclusion. which relates to ‘avenging injuries Vide the first sentence of Sub-section 7 of Section V, supra, p. 826.—Tr.] 2 [Supra, p. 739.—Tr.] 8z8 The Three Theological Virtues: On Charity SECTION VI WHAT CERTITUDE AS TO THE JUST CAUSE OF WAR IS REQUIRED IN ORDER THAT WAR MAY BE JUST Three kinds of persons must here be distinguished, to wit: the sovereign king and prince, the leading men and generals, and the com­ mon soldiers. It is to be assumed that practical certitude is required of all these persons, a certitude which may be expressed in the statement : ‘It is lawful for me to make war.’ The whole doubt is concerned with theoretical certitude, which is to be expressed as follows: ‘This cause of war is just in itselF, or, ‘This thing which I seek through war is rightfully mine’. I. I hold, first, that the sovereign ruler is bound to make a diliThe first conclusion : gent examination of the cause and its justice, and that which is twofold. after making this examination, he ought to act in accordance with the knowledge thus obtained. The basis of the first part of this conclusion is that war is a matter of The proof of the first the gravest character; and reason demands that in any P*111· matter whatsoever, deliberation and diligence should be applied, commensurate with its importance. Furthermore, a judge, in order to pass judgment in a private matter, ought to make diligent investigation ; hence, the necessity for such diligence exists in due pro­ portion in a public cause of war. Finally, if the ruler were not bound to make this investigation, the rashness of princes would easily result in universal disturbance. With regard to the first part of this assertion, then, there is no difficulty. 2. The explanation of the second part of the conclusion is as The second The second part part of of follows. Let us suppose that the ground for a war is this conclusion is the fact that a certain king claims a certain city as explained. **· belonging to him, or as falling newly to him by heredi­ tary right. Now if, when the matter has been carefully examined, the truth of that claim is clearly established, what I have asserted is ob­ viously true. But when the case of each side contains [an element of] probability, then the king ought to act as a just judge. Therefore, if he finds that the opinion favouring his own side is What [should the t^ie more probably true, he may, even justly, prosecute king do] when [the his own right ; because, so I believe, the more probable arbore1 puLdbie opinion ^should always be preferredHn passing judg[than those of the ment. For that is an act of distributive justice, in other side] ? which the more worthy party is to receive the prefe­ rence ; and he is the more worthy party w-ho enjoys the more probable right, as we shall explain below’ at greater length. For the same reason, however, if the more probable opinion favours the opposing side, the prince in question may on no account proceed to war. Disp. XIII: On War 829 3. If, finally, after diligent investigation, the probabilities on both What should the sides are found to be equal, or if, at least, equal uncer­ king do, when the tainty exists—whatever the ground of the uncertainty doubt is equal on both sides and the —then, if the opposing party is in possession, he ought opposing side is in to have the preference, because even in a judicial pro­ possession? cess, that party is favoured, inasmuch as he has the greater right. On this account, the party who is not in possession cannot proceed to war against the possessor; while the latter, on the other hand, is secure [in his conscience] and may justly defend himself. Adrian (on the Sentences, Bk. IV, concerning restitution, and in Adrian Quaestiones Quodlibeticae, Qu. ii, art. 2), however, maintains an opinion contrary to this last statement. ‘For that person’(he says) ‘is in doubt as to whether he is retaining the property of another. Therefore, he is not secure [in his conscience].’1 Soto (De lustitia, Bk. IV, qu. v, last arg.) Soto, also says that the one who is in doubt is bound to divide with the other party, or to give satisfaction to that other in proportion to the doubt. This would be true if in the beginning he had taken possession, while doubting [the justice of his action]; for that sort of possession confers no kind of right. But if, on the other hand, he held possession at the beginning in good faith, if a doubt has arisen since that time, and if he has made diligent inquiries into the truth but has not been able to ascertain it, then he may, [with a] secure [conscience], continue in possession of the whole of the property in question; for the doubt remains purely theoretical, and such possession confers absolutely the right to the whole of the thing possessed, a fact which we have estab­ lished universally and more fully, in our discussion of conscience ([De Bonitate et Malitia Humanorum Actuum,'] Treatise III, disp, xii, §§5 and6).2 The same fact is stated specifically by Covarruvias(onSext, rule > possessor, Pt. II, § 7) and by Victoria (aforesaid Relectio [De lure Belli, \,· ,r·. no. 29]). Soto (Relectio: De Secreto, Memb. iii, qu. 2)3 does likewise. > ■·. Nevertheless, Victoria observes that a possessor of the kind in question is bound, when the doubt arises, to inquire diligently into the truth; and that, if he refuses to do so, he can be forced into this inquiry by the other party, even through war, for the principles of justice and right judgment do indeed demand that such an investigation be made. 4. Another aspect of the question regards the situation in which no one is in possession and the doubts and probabilities What should the balance each other. The more common opinion seems king do when neither side is in to be that either party has the right to seize first the possession? thing in dispute. In accordance with this opinion, the 810 1 [If cgrtainty of true ownership cannot be attained, the possessor, being in doubt, must relieve his conscience by giving the thing (possessed) to the poor (loc. at. i” punctum, secundo dico).—Réviser.] 2 (Not included in these Selections.—Tr.] 3 [Soto, De ratione tegendi et detegendi secretum, relectio theologica (Salamanca, 1574).—Reviser.] 830 The Three Theological Virtues: On Charity war would become just simultaneously, on both sides; but this point is of no importance, when ignorance intervenes. The reason, indeed, which is offered in support of this opinion is that in a similar case a judge could awrard the property by his own decision to either one of the parties to the litigation, as he might choose. However, I am unable to persuade myself that a judge may act thus in the case supposed. For certainly, under those circumstances, the judge is merely a distributor of property over which he personally has no right ; consequently, if the rights of the parties in question are at all times entirely equal, there is no reason which would allow him to allot the whole property to either party; and therefore, the judge is bound to divide the property. Or, if this cannot be advantageously done, it will be necessary to satisfy both sides, in some fashion. Hence, in a question involving war, the princes shall be bound to this same attitude. Accordingly, they must either divide between them the thing in dispute, or cast lots for it, or settle the matter in some other way. But if one party should attempt to seize the whole possession to the exclusion of the other party, by that very act he would be doing the other a wrong which the latter might justly repel, thus seizing, on this just ground of war, the entire disputed possession. 5. But the question may be asked whether, in cases of this kind, It is more probably sovereign princes are bound to submit the matter to true that in case of the decision of good men. This question, moreover, doubt as to the jus­ arises from the standpoint of natural law only, so that, tice of a war, a prince is bound to in our discussion, we shall not include the authority of submit the matter to the judgment of a the Pope, of which we have already spoken.1 good man. Indeed, I am of the opinion that the affirmative answer to this question is, in all probability, correct. For the said princes are bound to avoid war in so far as is possible, and by upright means. Therefore, if no danger of injustice is to be feared, the abovementioned [arbitration] is plainly the best means of decision, and consequently resort should be had to it. This opinion is confirmed as follows: it is impossible that the Author of nature should have left human affairs, governed as they are by conjecture more frequently than by any sure reason, in such a critical condition that all controversies between sovereigns and states should be settled only by war; for such a condition would be contrary to prudence and to the general welfare of the human race; and there­ fore it would be contrary to justice. Furthermore, if this condition prevailed, those persons would as a rule possess the greater rights who were the more powerful; and thus such rights would have to be measured by arms, which is manifestly a barbarous and absurd sup­ position. 1 [Cf. Sub-section 5 of Section II, supra, p. 808.—Tk.] Dis}. XIII: On War 831 6. In this connexion, however, we must observe, first, that a Concerning sovereign prince is not bound by the decision of those the decision that is whom he himself has not constituted as judges. Theregiven· fore, it would be necessary for the arbitrators to be chosen with the consent of both sides. Resort to this method, indeed, is a most rare occurrence, inasmuch as [these princes] seldom favour it ; for very frequently one or other of the princes holds the foreign judges in suspicion. Secondly, it should be noted that a sovereign prince, if he is acting Note 2 in good faith, may ascertain his own rights through prudent and learned men [of his own choice]; then he may follow their judgment (if by it his rights are made clear to him) ; and under these circumstances he will not be bound to abide by the judgment of other [and foreign arbitrators]. The reason in sup­ port of this statement is that the rights in question must be judicially ascertained in the same manner as a just decision of a court; and in the latter sort of decision, [only] two objectives are involved. One is an 811 examination of the cause and acquaintance with the rights of both sides ; for which process, not jurisdiction, but knowledge and discretion, are necessary. For since this decision is not sought through war, but, on the contrary, a substitute for war [i.e. a judicial inquiry] is employed, there is no occasion to call in any arbitrator. The other objective is the enforcement of the right after it has been made clear. For this, jurisdiction is indeed required; but such jurisdiction is inherent in a sovereign prince when in other respects he is sufficiently certain of his right. In that case, then, there is no reason binding him to await the judgment of another, although he ought to accept just settlements if they are presented to him. 7. Secondly, I hold that generals and other chief men of the The second conclu- Inngdom, whenever they are summoned for convul­ sion, in two parts.· tation to give their opinion on beginning a war, rating to generals. are j50unj t0 inqUfre diligently into the truth of the matter; but if they are not called, they are under no greater obligation to do so than others who are common soldiers. The first part of this conclusion is clearly true; because these generals, having been sum­ moned, are bound in justice to give a just opinion, for if they did not do so, any injustice that there might be in the war will be laid to their charge. The proof of the second part of the conclusion is the fact that, when they are not summoned [to give advice], their part in the affair becomes simply that of private soldiers, since they are merely set in action by others, but do not control action; while it is only inci­ dental (per accidens) that they are wealthy or of noble birth. Never­ theless, Victoria (De lure Belli, no. 24) adds that such generals are Victor, bound in charity to inquire into the justice of the war, in order to give Note i 832 Cajetan. Soto. Victoria. Sylvester. The Three Theological Virtues: On Charity warning when it shall be necessary. But if this obligation is derived from charity alone, it will exist only in case of necessity; and therefore, generally speaking, apart from these cases where there is such need, they will not be so bound. 8. I hold thirdly, that: common soldiers, as subjects of princes, are in The third conclu*n no wise w^se bound to make diligent investigation, sion: relating to but rather may go to war when summoned to do so, common soldiers. provided it is not clear to them that the war is unjust. This conclusion may be proved by the following arguments: first, when the injustice of the war is not evident to these soldiers, the united opinion of the prince and of the realm is sufficient to move them to this action; secondly, subjects when in doubt (i.e. doubt of a theoretical character) are bound to obey their superiors {Decretum, Pt. II, causa xxm, qu. i, can. iv, which is cited from Augustine, Against Faustus, Bk. XXII, chap. Ixxv). This last statement is based upon the best of reasons, namely, the fact that in cases of doubt the safer1 course should be chosen; therefore, since the prince possesses rightful authority, the safer course is to obey him. The assertion is confirmed by the fact that the official subSee Suârez in a ordinate of a judge may execute a sentence without similar passage in any previous examination, provided that sentence is torarvoi° aSee3Cen- not manifestly unjust. Such is the common opinion suris, Disp, in, of Cajetan (Summa, word bellum), Soto (De lustitia, sect.xv.fromno.9.2 Bk IV> qu art Victoria (De lure Belli, no. 25), and Sylvester (word bellum, Pt. I, qu. 9 [qu. 5]). 9. Nevertheless, Sylvester would seem to limit this conclusion. A limitation of the For says that, if the common soldiers have doubts, third conclusion ; they are bound to make inquiries in order to dispel by Sylvester. those doubts; but, if they cannot do so, it will be permissible for them to fight. Adrian (Quaestiones Quodlibeticae, II) indeed, absolutely denies that it is permissible to go to war with such Adrian likewise doubts; both because it is never permissible to act limits this conclu- with a doubtful conscience ; and because soldiers who ^Sy ; OT ^auSThe ^id act wou^ be choosing the [morally] more [absolutely] denies dangerous course, since they would be exposing themxt' selves to the peril of unjust slaughter and plundering; whereas, if they abstained from going, they would sin only by dis­ obedience, and justice imposes a more rigorous obligation than that of obedience. The reply to this objection, however, is that the doubt in such a case is not practical but speculative, and therefore Adrian is answered. joes renc[er the conscience doubtful. Further1 [Le. morally safer.—Tr.] 2 [Not included in these Selections.—Tr.] Disp. XIII: On War 833 more, it would not be safer to disobey; for as a natural result of such disobedience, it would become impossible for princes to defend their rights, and this would be a serious and general misfortune. With regard to Sylvester’s limitation, we should observe: first, Sylvester is that the doubt may be a purely negative one, namely, answeredthat the soldiers are entirely ignorant of the basis of the justice or injustice underlying the war; in which case they are in no wise bound to make inquiry, being sufficiently supported by the fact that they have relied upon the authority of their sovereign; secondly, that the doubt may be positive, having its source in conflicting argu­ ments adduced in favour of one side and the other. Indeed, if the arguments showing the war to be unjust were such that the soldiers themselves were unable to give a satisfactory answer, then they would be bound to inquire into the truth in some way. Even this obligation, however, is to be imposed, not readily, but only in case those argu­ ments render the justice of the war extremely doubtful, for in that case, it would seem that the soldiers have inclined towards a moral judgment that the war was unjust; otherwise, however, if they have probable reason for thinking that the war is just, they may legitimately conform their conduct to these reasons. io. A greater difficulty arises in connexion with soldiers who are The more common not subjects and who are called mercenaries. The opinion with respect opinion commonly held seems to be that these soldiers mercenarv r , . .·'.. ... r . to mercenary are bound to inquire into the justice of a war, before soldiers, who are not subjects. they enlist. This is the opinion of Sylvester (on Sylveter word bellum, Pt. I, qu. io), who even states definitely that such soldiers, when doubtful, cannot legitimately engage in the war. Cajetan {Summa, word bellum) holds almost the same view; although Gyna,·.. he makes this limitation: ‘Unless they receive their pay in time of peace also, and are bound to go forth to war whenever called.’ For in that case, [according to Cajetan], mercenaries may conduct themselves as if they were subjects, since they are really such, by reason of the pay which they receive. The basis of the foregoing opinion is The basis of the r^e ^act t^iat æ suc^ a situation it is safer for one who opinion above set is not a subject to abstain from fighting; because if he fortb· so abstains he does not expose himself to any peril; 812 whereas, if he does fight, he exposes himself to all the dangers enume­ rated by Adrian; and in doubtful matters the safer pan should be chosen. This assertion is confirmed, first, by the Sexi (Bk. λ, tit. xii, De _ Regulis luris, rule io) and the Digest \(L. xvii. J38 The first confirma- r tion from the rule of L3°D’ which states that he is not exempt from law and from Am- blame who thrusts himself, with peril to another, into affairs that do not concern him; wherefore Ambrose 1569.74 1 [In the Latin text *Cajetan’ is incorrectly placed before ‘Sylvester’.—Ti.] ξO 834 The Three Theological Virtues: On Charity (On Duties, Bk. Ill, chap, ix and cited in Decretum, Pt. II, causa xiv, qu. v, can. x) makes the general statement that no one ought to assist one party to the prejudice of another. It is confirmed secondly by the fact that, in a similar kind of doubt, The second conand for the reason set forth above, the laws hold that firmation· a spouse who is in doubt [as to the title to the act] may render the conjugal debt, but may not ask for it. By the same reasoning, it may also be said that princes who are kinsmen or friends may not assist one another until they have duly examined the cause. 11. However, such an opinion comes into conflict with the follow­ ing difficulties. First, it would be necessary for each individual mercenary soldier The first argument to inquire into the cause of the war. But such an against this opinion, investigation is contrary to all custom, and humanly speaking, is impossible; for, as I have said above, the reason for the war cannot be explained to all, nor are all capable of appreciating that explanation. Secondly, [if the opinion in question were valid,] even soldiers The second arguwho were subjects could not take part in a doubtful ment· war without examining the cause, save when they were under strict orders of such sort that they would be disobedient in not going; for in that case their obedience would alone excuse them. But as long as they wrere not under orders, it would be [morally] safer not to fight. However, this consequent is contrary to all custom, and that1 obligation [to investigate the cause of war] would be harmful to the state. Thirdly, if permanent mercenaries could, previously to a war, .. . bind themselves to fight even in doubtful cases by The third argument. . . . . . . . . . _ . / giving their consciences into the keeping of the pnnce s conscience, why could not those mercenaries do the same who enlist at the outbreak of a war? For, from a moral standpoint, the same principle is involved in the performance of an action and in binding oneself to perform it. The confirmation of this argument lies in the fact that just as one The confirmation *s not allowed to proceed to an unjust war, neither is of the third arguhe allowed to undertake the obligation of serving in such a war, nor even in any war indiscriminately, whether just or unjust ; and the reason for these restrictions is that to fight in an unjust war is to act unjustly. Therefore, conversely, if one is permitted to bind himself to service in a doubtful war, the obligation involved in such a case is not 'wicked ; and therefore, it would be permissible so to bind oneself for pay, here and now, although no previous obligation exists. Nor does it seem to be of much importance that a given ’ [Reading ilia for alia.—Reviser.] Disp. XIII: On War 835 [mercenary] was already regarded as a subject before the war, by reason of his pay. For one might say the same thing in the case of a contract made on the eve of the outbreak of the war, since, at such a time also, soldiers bind themselves to obedience in all matters in which obedience is legitimate ; so that it makes no difference from the standpoint of justice, whether this contract was made before the war, or whether it is made now, [at the moment when the conflict begins]. Fourthly, in a similar doubtful situation, any person is permitted The fourth arguto sell arms to these princes and to the soldiers; neverment· theless, if they do so, the same danger is present, namely, that the act may contribute to the injuiy of innocent persons, if by any chance, the war is in fact unjust. The antecedent is commonly accepted as true. The proof of the consequent is, that both kinds of co-operation are very pertinent to actual wars; and although soldiers seem, in a sense, to co-operate more immediately, nevertheless the persons who furnish arms are ordinarily able to do more harm. Fifthly, any individual is permitted to enter the service of a rv x merchant, on a wage contract, with the intention of co-operatmg with the latter m those of his contracts whose injustice is not manifest to the employee; neither is that em­ ployee under an obligation to examine the nature of the contracts; and accordingly one should adopt a similar view with respect to the case under discussion. Lastly, there is one argument that is commonly applicable to all the cases mentioned above, namely, in all of them, the The sixth argument. first and essential element is that one who is not a subject, submits himself to another for the sake of payment, and in so doing, inflicts no injury upon any person; neither, generally speaking, does he expose himself to the danger of any wrongdoing. And for the rest, he is [simply] exercising his right, when he sells his own property or his own labour, a right of which he certainly is not bound to deprive himself to his own detriment. With regard to these [mercenary] soldiers, there is, in addition, a special argument; for each of them has the authority of the prince and that of the whole state to support him, a fact which involves a great probability [that their conduct is just]. Hence, all the circumstances being weighed, it would by no means seem that mercenaries who serve in that contingency,1 are choosing the course that is [morally] less safe. 12. These arguments are clearly convincing; nor do I find any The author’s deci- difference in actual fact between subjects and nonsion: in two parts, subjects. So it is that Victoria (supra, in his Relectio Vk-tom. [De lure Belli], no. 24 [no. 25]), too, speaks simply of‘soldiers’, with­ out distinction. 1 (Le. when there is great probability that the war is just.—Revises. ] The Three Theological Virtues: On Charity 836 However, since the question is one of moral conduct, and in order that we may proceed with less risk of error, I lay down this conclusion: if the doubt [as to the justice of a war] is purely negative, With respect to a it is probable that the soldiers in question may [right­ negative doubt. fully] take part in that war without having made any examination of the question, all responsibility being thrown upon the prince to whom they are subject. We assume, to be sure, that this prince enjoys a good reputation among all men. This is clearly the opinion supported by Victoria and agreed to by other Thomists. 813 If, however, the doubt is positive, and if both sides advance plauWith respect to a sible arguments, then, in my opinion, [those who are positive doubt. about to enlist] should make an inquiry into the truth of the matter. If they are unable to ascertain the truth, they will be bound to follow the course of action which is more probably just, and to aid him who is more probably in the right. For when the case involves doubt with respect to a fact, such as loss affecting one’s neighbour, or with respect to the defence of the innocent, that course which appears to be more probably just should be followed, in accordance with the rules on conscience above set forth (Sub-sect. 6). To this end, indeed, it will be sufficient if the soldiers consult prudent and conscientious men upon the question of whether or not they are in an absolute sense able to take part in such a war. And if the soldiers in question form a single poli­ tical body, and have their own chiefs, the inferiors will certainly satisfy all requirements, if each person examines the question of the justice of the war, through his own chief or prince, and follows the judgment of that authority. Finally, if the arguments on both sides contain an equal [element of] probability, the soldiers may under such circumstances con­ duct themselves as if the doubt were purely negative; for the balance is then equal, and the authority of the prince turns the scale. Sylves­ ter, too (on the word bellum, Pt. I), has clearly suggested this conclusion. The foregoing may suffice for the question under discussion. SECTION VII WHAT IS THE PROPER MODE OF CONDUCTING WAR? Three periods must be distinguished [with respect to every war]: *ts inception ; its prosecution, before victory is tion of this ques- gained; and the period after victory. The three classes tMm* of persons already mentioned must also be distin­ guished, namely: the sovereign prince; the intermediate group of leaders; and the soldiers of the rank and file. All of these persons may be considered in certain specific relationA fourfold relation- ships. First, with respect to the enemy, that is to say: ship is outlined. how may these classes justly conduct themselves toI. Notes for the soiu- Disp. XIII: On War 837 ward the enemy? Secondly, with respect to their mutual relations : how should the king conduct himself toward his soldiers? Thirdly, [and again in connexion with their mutual relations,] how should the soldiers conduct themselves toward their kings? Fourthly, how should they conduct themselves toward other persons, for example, those per­ sons in whose houses the soldiers are quartered during the march? At present, we are dealing in the main with the first question; but we shall also treat briefly of the others. 2. With respect to the fourth relationship, then, we may repeat On the fourth reia- briefly the admonition of John the Baptist (Luke, Lût. ■. tionship. Chap, iii [, v. 14]): ‘Do violence to no man; [...] and be content with your pay.’ Hence, none of these soldiers may take anything from his hosts, beyond that which has been determined by the king; otherwise, he sins against justice and is bound to make restitu­ tion. The same is true if he does any other damage to houses, fields, &c. To be sure, the leaders [of intermediate rank] and the princes are bound, by virtue of their office, to prevent such acts in so far as they are able. If they fail to do so, the whole duty of making restitution falls upon them, in default of the soldiers. Concerning the third head, just as the kings are under an obligaOn the third reia- tion to give pay to the soldiers, so the latter are bound tionship. to discharge all the duties pertaining to their office. Hence, justice requires of them brave conduct, even to such a degree that they shall not take to flight, nor desert their stations or fortifica­ tions; a matter concerning which there are many laws (in XLIX. xvi). Cajetan, also, should be consulted in his brief treatise on the ejecta, subject (Opusculum, Bk. IV, last question but one [Bk. Ill, treatise ix: De Vinculo ObedientiaeJ) ; for he holds that commanders of forts are under an obligation not to surrender through any fear of death or starvation, since they have made a contract with the prince not to do so, and since they receive their payment because of this contract, whence there arises an obligation binding them in justice. Finally, with regard to the mutual relationship of the private soldiers, we may remark that, apart from the ordinary rules of justice, they are especially bound after victory to make a just distribution in sharing the booty. What that just distribution may be, however, it is not possible for us to determine; for in every kingdom the rules laid down by the monarchs or generals should be observed, or, at least, those rules which may have been established by usage and custom. Only the first head, then, still remains for discussion. 5. I hold, first that before a war is begun the [attacking] prince On the first relation- is bound to call to the attention of the opposing state tiro C°n" t^ie existence of a just cause of war, and to seek adeparts. ’ quate reparation therefor; and if the other state offers 838 Augustine. Major. Driedo. Cajetan. Sylvester. Deuteronomy, xx. The Three Theological Virtues: On Charity such adequate reparation, he is bound to accept it, and desist from war; for if he does not do so, the war will be unjust. If, on the other hand, the opposing prince refuses to give satisfaction, the first prince may begin to make war. This conclusion is commonly accepted in its entirety, and the latter part is clearly true because, assuming the obsti­ It is commonly accepted. The latter nacy of the opposing prince or state, and the other part of the conclu­ conditions specified, there is no [other] point that sion is clearly true. calls for consideration. The first part is derived from Augustine (in Decretum, Pt. II, causa xxiii, qu. i, can. iii [which is cited from The first part is Augustine, Letters, clxxxix, no. 4, To Boniface]', Decre­ proved by citing authorities and by tum, ibid., qu. ii, can. ii [cited from Augustine, On reasoning. Josue in Questions on the Heptateuch, Bk. VI, qu. 10, Migne ed.]). Moreover, this view is accepted by all Doctors: Major (on the Sentences, Bk. IV, qu. 20); Driedo (De Libertate Christiana, Bk. II, chap, vi); Cajetan (on the word bellum) and Sylvester (ibid., qu. iv, concl. 2 [qu. i, concl. 2]). And it would seem that the same principle may correctly be inferred from a passage in Deuteronomy (Chap, xx [, v. 1]) : ‘If thou go out to war [against thy enemies and see horsemen and chariots, and the numbers of the enemy’s army greater than thine, thou shalt not fear them : because thy God is with thee]’. The reason supporting this part of our conclusion is that any other manner of making war would be unjust, and therefore the cause of war itself would become unjust. For where a full and sufficient satisfaction 814 is voluntarily offered, there is no ground for violence; especially not, since reason demands that punitive justice be exercised with the least possible harm to all, provided, however, that the principle of equality be observed. Moreover, one sovereign has no coercive power over another sovereign, unless the latter acts unjustly, as is the case when he is unwilling to give satisfaction. 4. But Cajetan limits this conclusion by stipulating the following Cajetan’s limitation condition: namely, that the satisfaction in question of this conclusion, shall ke offered before the actual encounter in war. For after the war has commenced, he who brings it to a victorious conclusion is not bound to accept such satisfaction ; since, in that con­ flict, he is as a judge who, once the action has been undertaken, finds the cause within his jurisdiction, having acquired the right to proceed to the end, so that the vanquished party has only himself to blame, in that he did not offer satisfaction at the proper time. But, I ask, what does Cajetan mean by ‘actual encounter in warThis limitation is ex- fare?’ If he refers to the last actual battle in which ammed· the whole war is to find its conclusion, there is no doubt that, if the affair has already been entered into and victory is Disp. XIII: On War 839 beginning to favour the side of the just belligerent, the latter is not bound, under such circumstances, to accept any reparation short of complete victory; for such victory now seems to be in all probability close at hand, and, indeed, to treat of peace at that juncture is, to all intents and purposes, impossible. If, on the other hand, by actual encounter in warfare, Cajetan means a war in which several conflicts have occurred, I do not see how it may be asserted with any solid assurance that, under these circum­ stances, [the just belligerent] has the cause under his jurisdiction any more than he had before the commencement of the war. For pre­ viously, he had the same right to begin the war that he now has to proceed with it; and the sole difference is that the injury has grown greater, and that consequently an increased right to a greater satisfac­ tion has arisen. Moreover, the arguments set forth above apply equally to both of the situations in question. For the continuance as well as the beginning of the war ought to be dictated by necessity. And, in addition to all these considerations, there is the fact that, [in the wake of both situations,] similar wrongs against the general welfare follow, wrongs which should be avoided while preserving intact one’s indivi­ dual rights. These are preserved when satisfaction is offered, because nothing further than this satisfaction can be claimed even when vic­ tory is achieved, a point which we shall discuss below’.1 In short, the right to make war is prejudicial to others,2*and the punishment in­ flicted through war is of the severest kind; therefore, that punishment ought to be inflicted as sparingly as is possible. 5. Therefore, the opinion contrary to Caj etan’s appears to be in The [author’s] solu- everF respect nearer the truth, with the sole proviso tion, which is abso- that complete satisfaction shall include the following ci et7an’s°iùSion° conditions : all property unjustly withheld shall be reit is more fully ex- stored; secondly, reimbursement must be made for all plained. expenses due to injuries inflicted by the enemy, so that, once the war has been begun, a claim may justly be made for all its costs, to date ; thirdly, something may be demanded as a penalty for the injury inflicted, for in war, regard must be had not only for com­ mutative justice, but also for punitive justice; and finally, a demand may justly be made for whatever shall seem necessary to preserve and also to guard peace, in the future, since the chief end of war is to establish such a future peace. It should also be added that the state of war has its rightful source in justice and that, consequendy, if war is made contrary to justice, there arises from that fact an obligation to make reparation for this injury. 1 [Jnfra, P· 840, Sub-section 7.—Tr.] 2 [Jus belli odiosum. The expression has a legal connotation, namely, that one man’s right may restrict the action of another, and is, therefore, prejudicial to the latter.—Reviser.] 840 The Three Theological Virtues: On Charity 6. I hold, secondly, that after war has been begun, and during the whole period thereof up to the attainment of vic»on· tory, it is just to visit upon the enemy all losses which may seem necessary either for obtaining satisfaction or for securing vic­ tory, provided that these losses do not involve an intrinsic injury to innocent persons, which would be in itself an evil. Of this injury, we shall treat below, in the sixth conclusion. The reason in support of this conclusion is as follows : if the end is permissible, the necessary means to that end are also permissible ; and hence it follows that in the whole course, or duration, of the war hardly anything done against the enemy involves injustice, except the slaying of the innocent. For all other damages are usually held to be necessary for attaining the end to which the war is directed. 7. In the third place, I hold that after the winning of victory, a prince is allowed to inflict upon the conquered state The third conclu­ such losses as are sufficient for a just punishment and sion : commonly applicable, and satisfaction, and reimbursement for all losses suffered. undoubtedly true. This conclusion is commonly accepted and un­ doubtedly true, both because the exaction of such penalties is the object of war, and also because in a righteous judgment at law this same course of conduct is permissible. But it should be observed that in computing the sum required for this satisfaction, one should in­ clude all the losses by the state in question throughout the wrar, i.e. the deaths of men, conflagrations, &c. In the first place, however, the additional comment made by Sylvester (word bellum, Pt. I, qu. 9 [qu. 10]) and The first observa­ tion: An additional by λ ictoria (above-cited Relectio, no. 20 [De lure comment is not im­ Belli, no. 51]) is not unacceptable, namely, that mov­ properly attached to this observation, by able goods captured by soldiers during the war are not Sylvester and by Vic­ to be reckoned by the prince as part of the restitution. toria. For this rule has become a part of the ius gentium, through common custom. The reason underlying it is that, since the soldiers’ lives are exposed to dangers so numerous and so grave, they should be allowed something; and the same is true of their prince. Secondly, it is necessary to observe with regard both to this, and The second observa- the previous conclusions,1 that soldiers are not allow’ed t»00· to seize anything on their own authority, whether after 815 or even before the victory is won ; because they have in themselves no power, but possess it solely through their prince, as his agents, so that they may not justly take anything without his express or implied authorization. Thirdly: it follows from this conclusion that, if all the penalties The second conclu- 1 fie. the first conclusion, Sub-section 3 of this Section ; and the second conclusion, Sub-section 6 of the saine.—Tr.] Disp. XIII: On War 841 just enumerated seem insufficient in view of the gravity of the wrong, then, after the war has been entirely ended, The third observa­ tion, involving a certain guilty individuals among the enemy may also, twofold corollary with justice, be put to death; and, although the slay­ based upon this conclusion. ing of a great multitude would be thus permissible only when there was most urgent cause, nevertheless, even such slaugh­ ter may sometimes be allowed, in order to terrify the rest, as is indicated in the following passage from Deuteronomy (Chap, xx [, w. 13-14]): ‘When the Lord thy God shall deliver the city into thy hands, thou shalt slay all that are therein of the male sex, with the edge of the sword, excepting women and children,’ &c. And from this passage it follows that with much more reason the guilty who have been vanquished may be reduced to captivity and all their property seized. Fourthly, it is to be noted that one should interpret in accord The fourth observa- with this conclusion the civil laws which assert that, ouT lawT1^ardln' t^lrouS^1 t^Le gentium, it has been established that this conclusion are all the property of the enemy, both movable and immade clear. movable, passes to the victors. This fact is brought out in the Digest (XLIX. xv. 24, 28), the Code (VIII. liii. 36), and the Decretum (Pt. I, dist. 1, cans, ix and x). The same point is made by Ambrose (on Abraham, Bk. I, chap, iii), and by St. Thomas {De Regi­ mine Principum, Bk. Ill), while Covarruvias (on Sext, rule peccatum, Pt. II, § 13 [§ 11, nos. 6-7]) discusses the subject at length. More­ over, similar laws are found in Deuteronomy (Chaps, xi and xx), as Abulensis notes thereon [on Deuteronomy, Qu. 3]. But all of these passages must be interpreted in conformity with the rule previously laid down, namely, that a just equality must be preserved, and regard must be had for the future peace; a matter of which we shall treat below. For it is necessary to preserve in war the same quality as in a just judgment; and in such a judgment, the offender cannot be visited with every sort of punishment nor deprived of all his property without any restriction, but may be punished only in proportion to his fruit. 8. A doubt, however, arises; for it sometimes happens that among the goods of the enemy there are found many of which The first doubt: con­ cerning goods which they themselves are not the owners. May these goods, did not belong to the then, be seized, if they are necessary for reparation? enemy. The reply is, that if the property is immovable, [the victors] certainly cannot retain it; for those from First, a decision is whom it was taken were not the owners; therefore, the given as to immov­ victors themselves do not acquire any ownership there­ ables. in; and consequently, they must restore such goods to the true owners. This is the rule laid down in certain laws of the Digest (XLIX. xv. 20, § 1, XLI. i. 44). However, the civil laws apparently lay down the contrary rule in 1569.74 5 p Dtulemu^, Ambrose. St Tbomas. Covurovu*. tbriasn. 8^.2 The Three Theological Virtues: On Charity regard to movable property, as Covarruvias contends at length (on Sext, rule peccatum, Pt. II, § ii, nos. 6-7). But, putting secondly, as to mov- aside the positive law, if such property has been ables.fromthestand, ,r tie , , r .r, ' , point of the law of acquired through theft, so that the title thereto does nature. not vest in those in whose custody that property is found, but rather in its former owners, the reason stated above proves incontestably that the said property must be restored to those former owners. Nevertheless, the victorious soldiers may demand a just reward for their labours, and may exact it from the true owners of the property in question; or the victorious prince may make the demand, if it so happens that he has already recompensed his soldiers. The foregoing is, indeed, a provision of the natural law. 9. But positive laws in favour of those making war against the .. ... . enemies of the state could have granted to the soldiers given from the tnemselves the ownership of such property, when it tive^aw^ °f posi' ^as ^een found by those soldiers to be already in the peaceful possession of the enemy. Accordingly, the effect of these laws could have been to deprive the former owners of their title to the property, for the benefit of the state, to which such a practice may often be advantageous, particularly with respect to mov­ ables, the true ownership of which it is difficult to ascertain, while it is nevertheless desirable that the rights of ownership should in some other way be rendered unimpeachable. This is the case especially when the property in question comes into the hands of subjects, a practice which, according to Covarruvias, was allowed by the laws of Spain. For, as a general rule, it would be rather difficult to believe that this practice prevailed, since the laws of one country cannot bind [the citizens of] other countries, nor deprive aliens of their rights of owner­ ship. Thus the civil laws seem, in this respect, to have sprung from the unjust manner in which wars were at that time carried on. For The unjust mode of Romans believed that the wars which they waged war employed by the against the enemies of the state were just on both ancient Romans. sjdes. and in fact, they preferred to fight as if upon the tacit and mutual understanding that the conqueror should become absolute master. Hence, they were accustomed to consider that all property of the enemy, whatsoever its origin, passed absolutely to the captors; and that the latter would thus possess this property, whatever might be its source. This standpoint is clearly brought out in the Digest (XLIX. xv. 5, § 2). Accordingly, they thought it unnecessary to restore these goods to the former owners, since the enemies of the latter,1 as soon as they had taken the property, had acquired the title to it. Furthermore, arguing conversely, the laws deny this right [of postliminiumJ to pirates and robbers. On this point see the Digest A decision is given, 1 [Who had subsequently become the enemies of the Romans.—Tr.] Disp. XIII: On War 843 (XLIX. xv. 19). Assuming that all this is true, the question of whether or not such a practice would imperil the conscience is a matter which will be better explained below, in Sub-section 22 [of this Section]. 816 10. But another doubt remains, namely: whether it is equally _ j j v. allowable to inflict damages of this kind upon all those The second doubt: . , . ° / who on the enemy’s who are numbered among the enemy. In answering side are liable to this question we must note that some of these persons punishment? x. , , . T . Λ . are said to be guilty, and others innocent. It is implicit in natural law that the innocent include children, women, and all unable to bear arms ; by the ius gentium, ambassadors, and among Chris­ tians, by positive [canon] law {Decretals, Bk. I, tit. xxxiv, chap, ii), religious persons, priests, &c. And Cajetan (on Decretum, Pt. II, causa Cajetia. mu, qu. iv [causa xxiv, qu. iii, can. xxv, word bellum]) holds, indeed, that this provision of law has been abolished by custom, which should be observed. All other persons are considered guilty ; for human judgment looks upon those able to take up arms as having actually done so. Now, the hostile state is composed of both classes of persons, and therefore, all these persons are held to be enemies {Digest, XLIX. xv. 24). In this respect, strangers and foreigners, since they form no part of the state and therefore are not reckoned among the enemy un­ less they are allies in the war, differ from the persons above mentioned. ii. Assuming that the foregoing is true, I hold, fourthly,1 that The fourth if the damages inflicted upon the guilty are sufficient conclusion. for restitution and satisfaction, those damages cannot justly be extended to affect the innocent. This fact is self-evident as a result of what has already been said, for one may not demand greater satisfaction than that which is just. The only question that might arise is whether or not victorious soldiers are always bound to observe this order in their procedure, taking vengeance upon the guilty and their property rather than upon the innocent. The reply is briefly that, other things being equal, and within the limits of the same class of property, they are so bound. For the principle of equity clearly imposes this rule, a fact which will become moreevident from what follows. 12. Fifthly, I hold that if such a course of action is essential to The fifth conclusion complete satisfaction, it is permissible to deprive the and die reason un- innocent of their goods, even of their liberty. The ®eriyinglt· reason is that the innocent form a portion of one whole and unjust state; and on account of the crime of the whole, this _ part may be punished even though it does not of itself share m the fault. This argument is confirmed as follows: first, it is on this very ground that the children of the Saracens are made slaves by the 1 [The Latin reads: hoc posito, ii. Dico quarto-, Le. the new section actually begins after the phrase ‘Assuming that the foregoing is true.’—Tr.] 844 i Victoria. ί· The Three Theological Virtues: On Charity Christians ; secondly, a son is sometimes punished for a crime committed by his father, as we have said in the treatise on faith, in dealing with heresy (Disp. XXII, sect, v, and Disp. XXIV, sect, in, no. 3).1 In this connexion, the canon law (Sext, Bk. V, De Regulis luris, rule 23) states that, ‘No one is punished save for guilt or for a just cause’2; from which The opinion of Syl- one infers the falsity of the opinion expressed by ▼ester is expounded. Sylvester (word bellum, Pt. I, qu. 10 [qu. 11]) that, after victory is attained, the property of the innocent must be restored to them ; unless he is speaking of cases in which property has evidently been seized in excess of the amount required for satisfaction, for in that case, if anything is to be restored, reason demands that a beginning be made with what was taken from the innocent ; but if the property seized does not exceed the required amount, then, just as it was permissible to take such property, so also it is permissible to retain it, as Victoria has noted [Relectio, De lure Belli, no. 40]. 13. In this connexion, however, some [special circumstances] existThe first observa- ing among Christians must be noted. First: by the tion· ius gentium the custom has been introduced among Christians that prisoners of war are not to be made slaves by mancipiu m, although they may justly be detained until they are sufficiently punished or redeemed by a just ransom; a point which is confirmed by a royal decree ([Las Siete Partidas,] Pt. II, tit. xxix, law 1). But since this privilege was introduced for the benefit of the faithful, it is not always extended to apostates. Therefore, if war be waged against those baptized persons who have entirely forsaken the faith, as is the case with those who pass over to paganism, such persons may be made slaves by mancipium. This is the custom. For they themselves wholly deny Christ, and consequently, they may not reasonably profit by the privilege of Christians. However, it has been customary for heretics to enjoy this privilege, since in a sense, at least, they confess Christ. For [this privilege], inasmuch as it has been introduced by custom, is to be interpreted equally in the light of custom. Covarruvias (on Sext, rule peccatum, § 9, no. 4 [Pt. II, § 10, no. 3]), indeed, quoting Innocent The____ .j:™ made an^· ot^ers> seems not to have spoken truly with respect by Covarruvias con- to wars waged against apostate subjects, in which the cem^g war against latter, [according to him,] may not be enslaved by mancipium, ‘since’, says Covarruvias, ‘it is not properly war, but (as it were) an exercise of ordinary jurisdiction’. In the war against Granada, however, we see that the contrary The point made by procedure was adopted, with the approval of all the Covarruvias is re- most learned and conscientious men. Ayala, too, takes jected’ this stand ([De lure et Officiis Bellicis et Disciplina 1 [Disputations XXII and XXIV are not included in these Selections.—Tr.] 3 [This quotation, as given by Suarez, varies slightly from the text of the canon law.—Tr.] Disp. XIII: On War 845 Militari,Bk. I, chap, ii, no. 15). The argument in favour of such a view is that the apostates in question are subjects and that, therefore, they may justly be punished. Moreover, if [the practice in question] is permissible with respect to foreigners over whom there is less jurisdic­ tion, why is it not permissible with respect to subjects? Finally, it is false to assert that the action described above is not war; for when sub­ jects are rebels the ordinary mode of procedure is to subdue them anew through war. 14. Secondly, we must note that among Christians the immunity The second observa- of ecclesiastical persons and property has also been intion· troduced, both because of reverence, and because these persons or goods seem to form a kind of spiritual realm distinct from the temporal state and exempt from temporal jurisdiction. 817 F urthermore, Sylvester (word bellum, at end) adds that all property, How far the state- to whomever it may belong, if it is placed within a ment added by Syi- church, enjoys this same privilege; for consecrated ▼ester is true. places cannot be attacked. But this last statement is true only in a general sense. Therefore, if men seek retreat in such places solely to protect their own lives, they should enjoy ecclesiastical immunity; but if an enemy use a church as a citadel or as a defensive camp, that church may be attacked and burned, even if some dis­ advantages follow therefrom; for such disadvantages would be of an incidental nature. However, with respect to other temporal goods, there is no fixed rule; although, in such cases, the customary practice should be observed. 15. Sixthly, I hold that innocent persons as such may in nowise The sixth conclube slain, even if the punishment inflicted upon their sion: in two parts, state would, otherwise, be deemed inadequate; but in­ cidentally they may be slain, when such an act is necessary in order to secure victory. The reason supporting this conclusion is that the slaying of innoThe reason support- cent Persons intrinsically evil. However, one may ing the first part of object that this is true with respect to killing- upon this conclusion. private authority and without just cause, but that the case in question involves both public authority and a just cause. Nevertheless, such a plea must be rejected when the slaughter is not necessary for victory (a condition which we have already assumed to exist), and when the innocent can be distinguished from the guilty. The conclusion is confirmed by the difference existing between The first confirma- life and other possessions. For the latter fall under tionhuman dominion; and the state as a whole has a higher right to them than single individuals; hence, individuals may be deprived of such property because of the guilt of the whole realm. But life does not fall under human dominion, and therefore, no one Λ 846 Deuteronomy, xxiv. Exodus, xxiii. Decretum, Josue, vi. I Kings, xv. Judges, xx. Deuteronomy, XX. Deuteronomy, ix. Abulensis. The Three Theological Virtues: On Charity may be deprived of his life save by reason of his own guilt. For this reason, undoubtedly, a son is never killed on account of the sin of his father ; which is in accordance with the passage in Deuteronomy (Chap, xxiv [, v. 16]), and Exodus (Chap, xxiii [, v. 7]), ‘Do not put to death the The second innocent.’ [Another] confirmatory argument is that, confirmation. [f the innocent were able to defend themselves, they would act justly in so doing; hence, an attack upon them is unjust. The third confirma- There is a final confirmation of the same conclusion tion· in the act of Ambrose, who visited Theodosius with a major excommunication because of a like slaying of the innocent; a fact which is recorded in the Decretum (Pt. II, causa xi, qu. iii, can. Ixix). But one may ask, who actually are the innocent, with respect to .. . this issue? My reply is. thati theyi include not only the Who are the innoJ i -t 7 cent, with respect to persons enumerated above, but also those who are able tiie conclusions un- t0 bear arms if it is evident that, in other respects, they have not shared in the crime nor in the unjust war; for the natural law demands that, generally speaking,1 no one who is actually known to be free from guilt, shall be slain. But what shall we say, if certain persons are not known to have participated either [in the crime or in the unjust war], and if there exists only the presump­ tion that they were able to bear arms? On this point, I shall speak shortly. 16. However, there is an argument [opposed to the sixth concluAn argument from sion] which. runs as follows : In two passages of the Scripture against Old Testament {Josue, Chap, vi [, v. 17] and 1 Kings, this conclusion. Chap, xv [, v. 3]) the people of God were ordered to kill all of the enemy, not excepting the children. Again, according to the account in the Book of Judges (Chap, xx), as many as possible of the tribe of Benjamin were slain indiscriminately by the Israelites, even after victory.2 In Deuteronomy (Chap, xx [, w. 16-17]) we read that after a city had been captured authority was given to kill all the enemy, including the women and children. As to the first two passages cited, the reply must be that only The reply to the first God could have given such an order, and accordingly, two passages. that this command was a special judgment of God designed to terrify the nations in question and caused by their iniquity, as may be gathered from Deuteronomy (Chap. ix). In the event described in the third passage [, that concerning the slaughter of the Benjamites,] the children of Israel o e pA^ge. acted wrongfully. On this point, see Abulensis [Tostado] ([on Judges^ Chap, xv, qu. xxxvii). 1 [per se ; i.e. apart from specific cases in which such slaughter is needful, for incidental reasons.—Tr.] 2 [citra victoriam is a rather obscure expression, but the context appears to favour the translation given above.—Tr.] Disp. XIII: On War 847 St. Thomas (I.-II, qu. 105, art. 3, ad 4), explains the fourth pasSt. Thomas’s reply sage as meaning that permission was given to kill all to the fourth pass- who refused to accept peace; therefore he would seem “*** to conclude that this permission applied only to the slaughter of the guilty. Nevertheless, the commentaThe sense in which tors generally appear to think that it applied to the this passage is more slaughter of all adult males who might have been commonly taken. capable of bearing arms ; for the presumption of guilt existed with respect to all of them and therefore their destruction was lawful, if there was no proof of their innocence. Abulensis adds Refutation of the another reason [for the authority to slay, mentioned reason given by Abu- in this fourth passage], namely, that [otherwise] the thT^rSisÏJn men- enemies in question might renew the warfare against honed in Deutero- the Chosen People. But this reason, simply in itself, HOmy’ xx‘ is not sufficient ; and consequently, Abulensis (above cited, Qu. xxxvii) himself later refutes it on the ground that no one may be punished for a prospective sin, provided that he is not otherwise deserv­ ing of death ; this refutation being especially applicable because the pre­ sumption in question does not of itself seem to warrant the slaughter of human beings, since in a criminal trial particularly there should be sufficient proof, and since, furthermore, he who is not proved guilty is presumed to be innocent. Finally, it is practically certain that, among a whole multitude, some may be found who neither consented to the war nor gave any assistance in it, but who, on the contrary, urged the acceptance of peace; and therefore, all may not be indiscriminately slain. These arguments prove beyond a doubt that, after victory has A reply especially keen attained, those only who are clearly guilty may adapted to the first be slain. As for the law above referred to [see Josut, S°4^sion’e· ChaP· vi> ν· v; I &W Chap, xv, v. 3 and Judgts, Chap, xx], we may say that this was a positive law laid down by a special act of God’s will. What of the second With regard to the second part of that same law,1 part? indeed, we may even observe that it was given in time 818 of actual combat and upon an occasion of the kind when, according to the customary phrase, a rebellious city is justly handed over ‘to blood and to the sword’. For sometimes this is permissible, either on account of the enormity of the offence, or for the correction [by example] of other cities; since, to be sure, upon such occasions it is scarcely possible to distinguish the innocent from the guilty, except through age and sex. Hence, the slaughter of all those whose innocence is not dearly evident for reasons of age or sex is, in general, permitted, as long as the actual combat continues; but the case will be otherwise after the cessation of combat, and the attainment of victory. ][De posteriori veto parte illiusmet legis. This appears to be interpolated in the Lacn text.—Rtvisnt. 848 The Three Theological Virtues: On Charity 17. The latter part of the [sixth] conclusion is also commonly accePted> and is clearly true in the case of certain ing the latter part of means essential to victory, which, however, necessarily ^on *-sixthJ condu· involve the death of innocent persons, as in the burn­ ing of cities and the destruction of fortresses. For, absolutely speaking, whoever has the right to attain the end sought by a war, has the right to use these means to that end. Moreover, in such a case, the death of the innocent is not sought for its own sake, but is an incidental consequence ; hence, it is considered not as volun­ tarily inflicted but simply as allowed by one who is making use of his right in a time of necessity. A confirmation of this argument lies in the fact that it would A confirmation of be impossible, through any other means, to end the this argument, from war. In like manner, a pregnant woman may use the inconvenience medicine necessary to preserve her own life, even if that would other­ wise follow, and she knows that such an act will result in the death of from an example. her unborn child. From these arguments it is to be inferred that, save in time of necessity, the means in question are not legitimate. 18. On the other hand, one may argue, first: that in the case Arguments against described, one really co-operates, in a positive sense, sbrt^condusionfthe *n brmgmg about the death of an innocent person; The first argument. hence, one cannot be excused from sin. In the second place: it may be alleged that to The second argu­ ment. kill an innocent person is as intrinsically evil as to kill oneself; and to kill oneself in this manner, even incidentally,1 is evil; as, for example, when soldiers demolish a citadel and a w*all, although they know with certainty that they will be crushed at the moment [when the fortifications fall]. An indication of this fact is that Samson, who committed such an act [of self-destruction], is exonerated by the Fathers, Augustine (On the City of God, Bk. I, chaps, xxi and xxvi), Bernard (De Praecepto et Dispensatione [Chap, iii]), St. Thomas (II.—II, qu. 64, from no. 5 [art. 5], ad 4) only because he acted at the prompting of the Holy Spirit. In the third place: evil may not be done that good may ensue. The third argument. Fourthly: [in the parable of our Lord] (Matthew, The fourth argu­ Chap, xiii [, v. 29]) it is forbidden to pull up the tares ment. lest the wheat should be pulled up with them. The fifth argument. Fifthly : the innocent persons in question would be justified in defending themselves if they were able to do so; hence the aggression against them is unjust.2 Sixthly: the past] argument mentioned in favour of the sixth The reason support- Augustine. Bernard. St. Thomas. 1 [Per accidens, i.e. incidentally to the attainment of a justifiable end.—Tr.] » [According to the principle that war (or combat) cannot be justly waged on both sides.—Tr.] Disp. XIII: On War 849 conclusion may be reversed, to prove the contrary contention; for a mother is not allowed to use a particular medi­ es argument. cjne^ ·ρ certainty that it will cause the death of her unborn child, and especially not after the infusion into that child of a rational soul. This seems to be the opinion more com­ monly held by Antoninus ([Summa Theologica,\ Pt. Ill, tit. vi [tit. Antoninus, vn], chap, ii), Sylvester (word medicus, Qu. 4), Navarrus ([Surnwu,] Sylvester. Chap, xxv, no. 62). The reason supporting it is that, if help cannot be given to one person without injuring another, it is better to help neither person. On this point, see the Decretum (Pt. II, causa xiv, L can. i [Pt. II, causa xiv, qu. v, can. x]). 19. The reply to the first of the foregoing arguments is as follows : The reply to the first if .the matter be viewed from a physical standof the foregoing point, the victor does not really kill, for he is not the ar^uments· cause of the death in an essential, but merely in an incidental sense; and even in the moral order, he is not guilty of homicide, because he is exercising his own right, nor is he bound to avoid to [his own] great detriment, the resulting harm to his neighbour. As for the second argument, I deny that [the act in question] is The reply to the intrinsically evil, basing my denial on that same ground, second argument. namely, that the person described does not in fact kill himself, but merely permits his own death. The question of whether or not this may be allowed under such circumstances must be considered in the light of the order of charity ; that is to say, one must consider whether the good at stake in the case is to such an extent the common good,1 that there is an obligation to expose oneself in its defence to a peril so great. There are some who think that Samson's action may be excused from this point of view; but such a reason would not seem to serve as a sufficient excuse for that action, because, it the matter is looked at from a purely human standpoint, the punishment of one’s enemies would not seem to be a good so great as to justify Samson in killing himself therefor, even though his death would be only incidental [to the attainment of his end]. With respect to the third argument, it is true that morally evil The reply to the deeds may not be performed that good may ensue, third argument. but is permissible to inflict the evils of punishment [for that purpose]; though, [in point of fact,] in the present case, the evils in question are not so much brought about [with deliberation], as they are allowed to follow [incidentally]. As to the fourth argument : in the first place, I deny that the case The reply to the [set forth in Matthew, Chap, xiii, on the tares and fourth argument. wheat] involved a legitimate necessity [of pulling up rhe 1 [The Latin reads : an ibi intercedat tam commune bonum. If for tarn, we substituted tantum, the translation would be: * Whether the common good at stake is so great that, &c.’—Reviser.] 1569-74 5Q 850 Ambrose. The Three Theological Virtues: On Charity tares]. Moreover, there was no power to do so. Again, the pulling up of the tares was inexpedient to the end sought by the head of the household. To the fifth argument, some persons reply that, under such The reply to the fifth circumstances, the war may incidentally be just for argument. both sides. Excluding cases of ignorance, however, this seems impossible. Accordingly, my reply is that the innocent persons in question may indeed protect themselves in so far as mere self-defence is concerned: by preventing the burning of the city, for example, or the destruction of the citadel, &c. For such actions involve solely the protection of their own lives, and may lawfully be performed. I maintain, however, that they may not adopt an aggressive defence (so to speak) combating those who are justly engaged in the war; for, in point of fact, such combatants are doing them no injury. But these innocent persons may fight against those who are responsible for the war, since the latter are truly doing them an injury. As for the last argument, the judgment set forth above must be The reply to the understood to relate to a situation in which the medisixth argument. cine jg not indeed absolutely necessary to save the 819 mother’s life, but is perhaps necessary simply as an aid to her better health; for in such a case the life of the child should be given the preference. This would seem to be the teaching of Ambrose (on Duties, Bk. Ill, chap. ix). That same judgment must also be held to refer to medicine administered with the deliberate intention of killing the foetus. But otherwise, if a case of necessity coupled with a right intention be present, then without doubt it is permissible [to take the medicine]. This is clearly true, even apart from the arguments ad­ duced above; because, if the mother were allowed to die, then, in most cases, both she and the child would perish; therefore, it is prefer­ able, if possible, to save the mother’s life while permitting the child to die, rather than to allow the death of both. The matter would, indeed, be somewhat doubtful, if it involved a comparison of the mother’s physical existence with the spiritual life of the child; for possibly the latter could be baptized [if he were not deprived of physical life]. With respect to this question, however, the order of charity mentioned above must be observed. 20. Seventhly, I hold that, in addition to all the losses which The seventh conclu- have previously been enumerated and which may be Sion commonly held, claimed as necessary to satisfaction, a prince who has obtained a just victory may do everything with the property of the enemy that is essential to the preservation of an undisturbed peace in the future, provided that he spare the lives of the enemy. Therefore, if it is necessary, he may on this ground seize cities, provinces, &c. That is the doctrine supported by all, and the rational basis thereof is derived from the very purpose of an honourable war; since war is The rational basis of permissible especially for this reason, namely, as a way this conclusion. (so to Speak) to an upright peace. This reasoning is confirmed by the fact that within the state itself, . wrongdoing is punished in accordance with what is The confirmation. ° r i , i· i i it necessary for the public peace with the result that, frequently, some person is ordered into exile, or visited with a similar punishment, &c. From this example, one infers that, if a [precautionary] measure of this sort is taken under circumstances such that it may at the same time come into the category of a penalty, this step should be taken on both of these grounds1; nor is it permissible to multiply without cause the harm inflicted upon the enemy. 21. Finally, I hold that a war will not be unjust, if all the preThelast conclusion: cautions which we have enumerated are observed in m two parts. it, and if at the same time the other general conditions of justice are fulfilled; and yet, such a war may contain some evil element opposed to charity or to some other virtue. The first part of this conclusion is sufficiently proved by what has already been said (Sect, iv, sub-sect. 8). Some examples confirming the second part have been mentioned above, examples relating to cases in which a war is under­ taken in opposition to charity, but not in opposition to justice. Another illustration would be a situation in which the conditions above set forth are fulfilled, yet the war springs from hatred. 22. However, some doubts which need elucidation are attached The first doubt con- to conclusion. The first doubt is as follows: if ceraing this conclu- both sides voluntarily engage in war, without just aon' cause, should that war be considered as opposed to charity, or as opposed to justice; and does it give rise to a consequent obligation to make restitution? Covarruvias (on Sext, rule peccatum, Pt. The affirmative II, § 21 [§ 12]) indicates that a war of this kind is conanswer of Covarru- trary to justice ; for he says that goods captured therein nas. ms' must be restored, since an unjust war creates no right. But, while there is no doubt that in the sight of God such a war The author’s soiu- is, in its essence, opposed to justice, because of the tion of the doubt, homicides—actual or potential—which are involved in it, nevertheless, there would seem to be no injustice involved, in so far as regards the combatants themselves. For injustice is in no wise done to a person who knowingly consents e [to an action] ; and Γ, in the situation under discussion,] the two sides are voluntarily lighting with each other, since, as I assume, the war is waged by mutual agreement, and after proclamation. 1 [Le. the grounds of precaution in the interests of future peace, and punishment for past wrong­ doing.—Tr.J - 851 — Disp. XIII: On War 852 The Three Theological Virtues: On Charity In the second place, for the very reason that the parties in question . make this agreement, they surrender fas it were) their own rights, and join in a pact to the effect that the victorious party shall acquire the property of the vanquished; and once this compact—unjust though it is in the sight of God—has been made, the victors become the true owners of such property, since they possess it by the will of the former owners. Therefore, [the victors are not bound to make restitution for property thus acquired]. In the third place, for these same reasons, there exists no obligation _ . to make reparation, not, at all events, for the losses inflicted; and therefore, the conquerors may also re­ imburse themselves from the property of the enemy, at least to the extent of the expenses which those conquerors have incurred in the war. Finally, because of the mutual and voluntary agreement, there _ . arises in the case of a private duel which is voluntary on both sides, no obligation to make restitution, nor any act of injustice. Therefore, . . . These arguments, then, would seem to prove that there results no obligation of making restitution for losses inflicted—not, at least, in a war of the kind in question; but as to other questions of property, the case is doubtful. Nevertheless, it is extremely probable that the same rule holds with regard to this matter, also; just as a game which is in other respects wrong, but in which there is no injustice committed among the players, may result in the transference of property from one to another without any consequent obligation to make restitu­ tion. The same may be said of adultery, if a price is given in exchange for it ; however, we do not deny that the opposite opinion may perhaps be correct; and much less do we deny that it is [morally] safe. 23. A second doubt, according to St. Thomas (II.-II, qu. 40, art. 3), is whether stratagems are permissible in war. The second doubt : drawn from St. To this we must briefly reply, in agreement with him, Thomas. that they are permissible in so far as relates to the prudent concealment of one’s plans ; but not with respect to the telling of lies. Regarding this point, what we have said elsewhere (Disp. XIV, sect, iv)1 on the concealment of one’s religious faith should be 820 consulted. From the foregoing, another doubt is resolved a fortiori, the doubt Vide Bk. vi of the as to whether it is permissible in war to break faith Defensio Fidei, plighted with the enemy. For we must say that, cnap.ix.1 generally speaking, such an act is not permissible, since it involves patent injustice; and consequently, if the enemy suffers loss for this reason, full reparation should be made. However, all this is true only provided that the promise shall have been made _ 1 Not included in these Selections.—Tr.] Disp. Xlll: On War 853 from the beginning of the war, by a just and mutual agreement (as it were) in such a way as to be binding; and it is also necessary that this promise shall have remained and persisted in full vigour and force, since, if one side has perchance broken faith, the other side will be entirely freed from its own obligation. For the equity of law demands that this condition be understood to exist. The same holds true if any change in circumstances has occurred, such that the promises in ques­ tion cannot be hept without grave loss. In that event, the opposing side must be warned that it is not possible to keep the promise made to it; and, after [either side] has issued this declaration, it is freed from the pledge. However, such a declaration is seldom to be permitted. 24. A third doubt, also derived from St. Thomas (ΙΙ.-Π, qu. 40, art. 4), turns upon the question: is fighting permissible The third doubt : drawn from the on feast days? The reply is that such fighting is per­ same St. Thomas. The author treats of missible, in cases of urgent necessity. Cajetan adds this point more fully that, if mass is heard, there is no mortal sin involved in De Diebus Festis [inDe Virtute et Statu in fighting on feast days, even when there is no neces­ Religionis,'] Bk. II, sity for so doing; although such an act may be a chap, xxviii, no. 7.1 venial sin, because it is characterized by a certain lack of proportion, especially if the fighting could be postponed without detriment. Sylvester (word bellum, Pt. I) extends this permission to the season of Lent, relying on the canon law {Decretum, Pt. II, causa ΧΣΙΠ, qu. viii, can. xv; Decretals, Bk. I, tit. xxxiv, chap, i), but custom does not sanction that view, a fact which is noted in the Gloss on the passages above cited. 25. A fourth doubt concerns the question of whether or not a The fourth doubt is Christian prince sins in calling to his aid infidel soveresoived by means reigns, or, conversely, in giving them aid in a war of examples. which is otherwise just. We must answer that such an action is not in itself a sin, since it is not opposed to any virtue, and since examples [of this sort of conduct] are supplied by the Scriptures in the case of David (r Kings, Chap, xxviii) and the iMachabees (f 1 JTwip.'**·*· Macbabees, Chaps, viii and xi). tSlaAtl·**. Furthermore, it is permissible in war to employ the aid of wild *" animals; therefore, why not the aid of unbelievers? Jrlvedbyreasoni^g0 Conversely, it is permissible to sell arms to unbelievers for use in just wars; hence it is permissible to aid them. Sometimes, however, such a course of action may militate against charity, because it involves public scandal, or some peril to believers, or even lack of trust in divine aid. In this connexion, an example may be found in the Old Testament (2 Paraltpommon, Chap, xvi), where King Asa is gravely rebuked and is punished for having sought the x“ human aid of another and infidel prince, through his want of trust in 1 [Not included in these Seleciims.—Hl] «54 Abuiensis. The Three Theological Virtues: On Charity divine aid. Abulensis [Tostado] should also be consulted, in this con­ nexion (on i Kings, Chap, xxviii, qu. 17). SECTION VIII IS SEDITION INTRINSICALLY EVIL? I. Sedition is the term used to designate general warfare carried on within a single state, and waged either between two parts thereof or between the prince and the state. I The first conclusion. hold, first, that sedition involving two factions of the state is always an evil on the part of the aggressor, but just on the defensive side. The truth of the latter statement is self-evident. The truth of the former is proved by the fact that no legitimate authority to declare war is discernible in such a situation, for this authority, as we have seen (Section II [su'pra, p. 806]), resides in the sovereign prince. The objection will be made that, sometimes, a prince will be able The objection to the to delegate this authority, if urgent public necessity contrary is demands that he do so. In such a case, however, the enswered. prince himself, and not a part of the state, is held to be the aggressor ; so that no sedition will exist in the sense in which we are using the term. But what if one part of the state actually suffers injury from another part, and is unable to secure its right through the prince? My reply is that this injured part may do nothing beyond that which a private individual may do, as can easily be gathered from what we have said above.1 2. I hold, secondly, that a w’ar of the state against the prince, The second conclu even aggressive> not intrinsically evil ; but that sion, on which see the conditions necessary for a war that is in other rew^chap iv***’ Bk’ sPects just must nevertheless be present in order that this sort of war may be righteous. This conclusion holds true only when the prince is a tyrant, a situation which may occur in one of two Ways, as Cajetan notes (on II.-II, qu. 64, art. I, ad 3 [art. 3]). In the first place, the prince may be a tyrant in regard to his [assertion of tyrannical] dominion, and power; secondly, he may be so merely in regard to his acts of government. When the first kind of tyranny occurs, the whole state, or any portion thereof, has the right [to revolt] against the prince. Hence, it follows that any person whatsoever may avenge himself and the state against [such] tyranny. The reason supporting these statements is that the tyrant in question is an aggressor, and is waging war unjustly against the state and its separate parts, so that, in consequence, all those parts have the right of defence. Such is the opinion expressed by Cajetan What is sedition? Cajetan. 1 [Cf. Section II, sub-section 2, of this Disputation, supra, p. 806, especially the third paragraph.— * [Supra, p. 705.—Tr.] Tk.] Disp. Xlll: On War 855 (loc. cil.'); and this conclusion may also be derived from a passage in St. Thomas’s works (on the Sentences, Bk. II, dist. xhv, qu. 2, art. 2). John Huss upheld the same doctrine with respect to the second kind of tyrant, and, indeed, with respect to every unjust superior. But this teaching was condemned at the Council of Constance Comal <>f (Sessions VIII and XV). Consequently, it is most certain that no private person, nor any imperfect power, may justly begin an aggres­ sive war against this kind of tyrant, and that such a war would be sedition in the true sense of the term. The proof of these assertions is as follows : the prince in question is, we assume, the true sovereign; and inferiors have not the right of declaring war, but only that of defending themselves, a right which does not apply in connexion with this sort of tyrant; for the latter does not always do wrong to individuals, and in any attack which [these individuals] might make, they would be obliged to confine themselves to necessary self-defence. The state as a whole, however, may rise in revolt against such a tyrant; and this uprising would not be a case of sedition in the strict sense, since the word is commonly employed with a connotation of evil. The reason for this distinction is that under the circumstances described the state, as a whole, is superior to the king, for the state, when it granted him his power, is held to have granted it upon these conditions: that he should govern in accord with the public weal, and not tyrannically; and that, if he did not govern thus, he might be deposed from that position of power. [In order that such rebellion may justly occur,] however, the situation must be one in which it is observed that the king does really and manifestly behave in a tyrannical manner; and the other conditions laid down for a just war must concurrently be present. On this point, see St. Thomas (De Regimine Principum, Bk. I, chap. vi). st-Tbon»» 3. I hold, thirdly, that a war of the state against a king who is The third conclu- tyrannical in neither of these two ways, is sedition in aon· the truest sense and intrinsically evil. This is certainly true, as is evident from the fact that, in a such a case, both a just cause and a [rightful] authority are lacking. From this, conversely, it is also evident that the war of a prince against a state subject to himself, may be just, from the standpoint of rightful authority, if all the other required conditions be present, but that, in the absence of those conditions, that same war is entirely unjust. 821 LAST SECTION [SECTION IX] IS A PRIVATE WAR, THAT IS TO SAY, A DUEL, INTRINSICALLY EVIL? I. A private contest of this sort, which in Greek is called μονο­ μαχία (single combat), may be entered into, in one of two ways : either ——1 856 Cajetan. Torquemada. Henry of Ghent. The Three Theological Virtues: On Charity suddenly (as it were) and by chance, and viewed in this light, the treat­ ment of such contests is part of the subject-matter of homicide; or else, by the agreement and consent of both parties. In the latter case, if certain public conditions are satisfied, the contest is called a duel {duellum) ; but if the affair is conducted privately, it is termed a diffidatio1 or single combat, that is, in our common tongue,2 a desafio. I hold, first : that if a just cause be lacking, a duel is always wicked. . Thi£·. · is clearly true, since such a contest .is a kind of The first conclusion. , . J tvar, and since it is even possible that in the course of that contest the dèath of a human being may occur. Again, a duel tnay be fought in order to display prowess and courage ; or in order.to win a reputation, as is wont to be the case, from time to time, among soldiers during a war. Duels fought for such reasons are also evil, because the participants rashly expose themselves both to the peril of death and to the peril of killing another. This view is confirmed by the fact that a sham battle3 is a mortal sin, if it involves evident danger of death; for those who die therein are denied the right of ecclesiastical burial, in accordance with the canon law {Decretals, Bk. V, tit. xm, chap, i) ; therefore, . . . For a like reason, the same opinion should be held with respect to duels fought for the sake of revealing some truth or clearing oneself of some charge. This is the doctrine laid down by Cajetan (on II.-II, qu. 95, art. 8 [, ad 3]), and supported by Decretals (Bk. V, tit. xxxv, chap, i), by the Decretum (Pt. II, causa 11, qu. v, can. xxii), by Torque­ mada thereon, and by Henry of Ghent {Quodlibeta, IX [V], qu. 32). The reason supporting this view is that such contests are not really a means of revealing truth and innocence, seeing that sometimes an innocent man is slain in a duel. Neither, [in situations of this sort,] is there sufficient reason to justify killing another; and therefore, there is not sufficient reason for making an attack. Furthermore, such conduct See the author *s contrary to the charity due to oneself; for if the [Suarez,] De irreii- person who issues the challenge is innocent, he exposes fritteetsiatu^Rdi- himself to the peril of death; and, on the other hand, gionis, Tract, ill, if he is guilty, his sin is far greater in that he attempts Bk. I, chap. iu].4 t0 c]ear jn a superstitious manner. Finally, in these contests, God Himself is tempted, since His aid is hoped for, through unfitting means. 2. I hold, secondly: that every private duel, that is, [every contest The second conclut^s sort] that is not characterized by all the consion and the proof ditions of a just war, is intrinsically evil. This is the common opinion of the Summists (on wrord duellum). r [An impromptu armed combat following a challenge—Tr.] 3 [fulgo ; in this case, Spanish.—Tr.] 3 [Bellicum exercitium (a warlike exercise). Or Suarez may have had in mind a tournament, to which his canon law reference applies.—Tr.] 4 [This treatise is not included in these Selections.—Tr.] Disp. XIII: On War 857 Regarding the challenger to a duel, indeed, the truth of such an . assertion is admitted without any limitation or dis[ rs pom . tinction, and may be proved as follows: the killing of any man on mere private authority is intrinsically wicked, except in the necessary defence of one’s own person and property; and the chal­ lenger to a private duel sets out to kill upon his private authority; 822 therefore, . . . Secondly, the same proof applies in regard to one who accepts a . x challenge ; .for in his veryr acceptande he wills to.. under- , . A second point. . ° ’ . . J . r take the slaying of that other person who issues the challenge. > This argument is confirmed by the fact thL· such duels are, in Confirmation from general, condemned by the law, « laid down in the both forms of law.1 Code (XL xliv. i); while the Council of Trent (Session XXV, De Reformatione [, chap, xix]) has also imposed the penalty of excommunication, and many other penalties, upon those who fight, counsel, participate as spectators, &c., in connexion with these duels. In a certain Bull of Pius IV [Contra Pugnantes in Duello, &c., Nov. 13, 1564],2 such excommunication is reserved [for absolution] to the Pope, save with respect to the persons of the emperors or kings [who are not included in the penalty]. And although these laws may seem to refer only to public duels, Gregory XIII [Bull Ad Ίollendum, Dec. 5, 1582]3 nevertheless extends such duels to include single combats between individuals; but he does not reserve [to himself the absolution of] the excommunication. 3. It is to be noted, indeed, that some writers have limited this conclusion with reference to the person who accepts A limiting clause the challenge, if he does so in order to defend his which some writers impose upon this honour and for the reason that, otherwise (that is, if conclusion. he did not accept the challenge received), he would incur disgrace. An argument in favour of this stand is based upon analogy: for The basis of their a nobleman attacked by another is not bound to flee, limitation. but may lawfully stand his ground and kill his aggressor in self-defence ; and this merely to protect the honour befitting his rank; therefore, in like manner,... This is the point of view suggested byNavarrus in one passageof his work {Summa [Enchiridion sive Manuale Confessariorum,] Chap, xv, at end) ; although in another Chapter (Chap, xi, no. 39), he expresses a different opinion. However, the contrary is in every respect true, as is evident from 1 [Le. civil and ecclesiastical.—Tr.] 2 [Bullarium Romanum VII, p. 85 (Turin, 1862).—Réviser.] 3 [Bullarium Romanum VIII, p. 400 (Turin, 1862).—Reviser.] 1569.74 5 R Council of Trot. BdloIPnaFV. Gregory xu: 858 The Three Theological Virtues: On Charity the laws above cited, and especially from the Bull of Pius IV, in which the following words are to be noted: ‘To allow is rejected: first, by [duelling], for whatsoever cause, even for one not citing authorities. disapproved by the [civil] laws, or on whatsoever pretext’, &C.1 The reason, a posteriori, for such a stand is derived from nature;234 Furthermore, it is f°r> 3n t^ie judgment of every prudent person, each rejected by reason- of the combatants in the situation described, chooses, ing' contrary to right reason, to smite his adversary. Furthermore, I maintain that the alleged disgrace is not truly such, although the ignorant crowd may judge it to be disgrace. The reason, a priori for this same opinion, is clear, to wit : [acceptance of a challenge] is not an act of defence but one of aggression, since there is occasion for The reply to the defensive acts only when force is repelled by force and bases of the asser- sjnce no force has entered into the case in question.3 bons made by those . .. . , who offer this 1 herein lies the difference between this case and the opinion. analogous one that was adduced. For in the latter instance, the nobleman suffers actual violence, and is forced into an action which would not otherwise be permissible to him; whereas, in the former instance, [as we have said,] there is no use of force. More­ over, in that [supposedly analogous] situation, a man is provoked to an act of simple defence ; but in this matter [of the duel], one is provoked to an act of aggression, and such a challenge may be refused, for a righteous reason. Such is the stand taken by Cajetan (on II.-II, qu. 95, art. 8, ad 3) and in his Summa (word duellum), and Armilia thereon ([on word duellum,'] no. 1). See also Soto {De lustitia, Bk. V, qu. i, art. 8, clause quod si hinc), and Abulensis [Tostado] (on 1 Kings, Chap, xvii, last qu.). 4. Secondly, there is an exception to the conclusion in question,4 a second limiting in the case of an innocent person who is unjustly dause· accused and condemned—or who, at least, is going to be sentenced to death—if that person is challenged by his accuser to a duel, and wishes to substitute the peril of such a contest, for the certain death to which he must shortly submit as the result of a judicial decision. For, under these circumstances, his agreement to undertake the duel would seem to be an act of just [self-]defence. This is the opinion held by de Lyra (on 1 Kings, Chap, xvii), Navarrus {[Summa or Enchiridion], Chap, xi, no. 39 and Chap, xv, no. 9), and Cajetan (on II.-II, qu. 95, art. 8 and [Summa,] on word duellum). This limiting clause Cajetan. Armilia. Soto. Abul ensis [Tostado]. de Lyra. Navarrus. Cajetan. 1 [The words are not in the Const, of Pope Pius IV (1560), but very similar words are found in the Const, of Pope Julius II [Regis pacifici, Feb. 24,1509).—Reviser.] 2 [naturalis.—Tr.] 3 [i.e. the case in which a given person has been challenged to a duel.—Tr.] 4 [i.e. the second conclusion : * Every private duel that is not in every way characterized by the con­ ditions of a just war is intrinsically evil.’ Supra^ sub-section 2 of this Section.—Tr.] Disp. XIII: On War 859 The latter, however, adds a provisional clause to the effect that this duel shall be undertaken, not upon one’s ovn , . , 1 r r · authority, but upon that of the prince. The proof of the second limiting clause is as follows: the accuser in question attacks an innocent man with the sword The proof of the second limiting of justice; therefore, self-defence is permissible to that clause, as drawn from the authorities innocent person; and consequently, it is also permisdted above. sible for him to avail himself of the means of defence, which in the case supposed is none other than the duel. This argument is confirmed by the fact that, occasionally, as we _ . have said above,1 what is material aggression is formal A confirmation. , r , 1 · r l ·j 1 · defence; so that this fact, too, must be considered, :n connexion with the situation described. 5. But this [second] exception is not established to my satisfaction. The [second] limit- Moreover, it is rejected by Sylvester (word duellum), ing clause is Abulensis [Tostado] (supra), and Antoninus ([Summa rejected. Theologica,] Pt. Ill, tit. iv, § [chap.] iii), with other authorities there cited. Soto (De lustitia, Bk. V, qu. 1, art. 8, near end) appears to hold the same view. If, indeed, we put aside [the cases sanctioned by] the authority of _ the prince, we may argue that, ini reality, the act in with respect to ·· /· j /· [casesnot sanctioned question is not one of defence but one of aggression, by] the authority of ρΟΓ defence is possible only where force is applied by the prince. . r , / . , . r.r an actual aggressor; and the accuser, in this instance, does not resort to force, since he does not compel the other to fight, but merely invites him to do so, being an aggressor, strictly speaking, „, , only in his false accusation ; whereas calumny is repelled Salon also agrees J , . , , , , · z 1 with this, on 11.-11, not by violence, but by the manifestation of trurn. qu. 64, art. 3, Moreover, if the latter course of action cannot be controvers. 3. r ,, .... . · , followed, it is in no wise permissible to resort to irregular means which are not truly means. On the contrary, death must be patiently endured just as if an innocent person were found guilty because of false witnesses. This argument is confirmed [, first,] by the fact that, if the accepA confirmation de- tance of a duel under these circumstances had a defenrived from a three- sive character, then, surely, the challenge also would fold absurdity. have the same character, provided no other means [of exonerating oneself] were available. For this act [of challenging, on the Cajetan adds a proviso to this second limiting clause. Sylvester. Aboleasè [Tostado]. Astomous. of the- violence, inflicted with the sword of/justice. .And. , . r therefore, such a challenge [on the part of the accused] to a duel [of this sort] would be permissible; a proposition which, how’ever, the very authorities cited above deny. [Secondly,] a further The first absurdity. * [Cf. Section I, sub-section 6, of this Disputation.—Ta.) I 86o The Three Theological Virtues: On Charity consequent [of the assertion which we are rejecting] would be that the The second accused, should he be able to do so, might legitimately kill his accuser in secret, if he hoped thereby to escape 823 death. This consequent would clearly follow, since in a just defence it is allowable to anticipate a future situation. Another [and third] conse„ ,. Λ quent of the assertion in question would be that one The third. ±ιτι··ι i in · ·· τ could licitly accept the challenge in question m order to prevent any other person from depriving him through a judicial decision of his reputation or his entire fortune. For not only in defence of one’s life, but also in defence of one’s external possessions, it is per­ missible to kill another. This consequent is rejected by Cajetan, who argues as follows: armed defence is permissible only Cajetan’s evasion [of these argu­ when one person makes an armed attack upon another; ments]. in a criminal action, however, while the aggressor does not attack with his own weapons, still he does attack with the sword of the judge; but this is not true of a civil action, wherein the sole weapon employed is an unjust judgment. However, this point is of no signiThis evasion is re- ficance; for in the first place, as far as the moral quesjected. tion jg concerned, such a distinction is wholly of a material nature, and consequently has no application to upright conduct. Therefore, other authorities make an assertion which, even if it is less probably true, is nevertheless more logical; since Among these autho- they admit that the same reasonin? holds for both nhes are Molina, . , ' —,, . . . _ ° . Treatise in, De iusti- sides. Inis assertion is that, when an innocent per­ it? Commutativa, son pe condemned, even if it be [merely] to serious Disp. XVII, no. 7; , 2, L and sinchez, with loss of reputation or or fortune, he may accept or issue others whom he a challenge to a duel. Furthermore, Cajetan even cites, Decalogue, Bk. , J3. r .r J 1 n,chap.xxxix,no.8. makes a false assumption; for if some unarmed person should attempt to steal my property, and if I were unable to ward off the injury without arms, it would be entirely per­ missible for me to use weapons for that act of self-defence; and there­ fore, in like manner, it would be allowable for me to avert by armed defence the above-mentioned loss of reputation or property, while accepting my calumniator’s challenge to a duel. There are some, how­ ever, who deny that the cases are similar, on this ground, namely, that no one is allowed to expose himself to the peril of death for the sake of external possessions. The denial which they rest upon such a basis is erroneous. For, indeed, as was pointed out in Sub-section 3 [of this Section] the nobleman [in the case supposed] is not bound to flee, although, by awaiting the aggressor in order to protect the honour befitting his rank, he exposes himself to the danger of death. 6. Finally, the defendant who is thus falsely accused may not slay his accuser; and therefore, he may not attempt to do so by means of Disf. XIII: On War 861 a duel. The truth of the consequent is evident; for it is not per­ missible to attempt that which it is not permissible The second and to do. The truth of the antecedent also becomes dear, principal rejection of the limiting both from what has been said above, and from the clause. following example: if Peter, for instance, knew dial Paul had given money to another person in order that the latter might slay Peter, it would not be permissible for Peter, acting on his own authority, to slay Paul, even if he believed that there was no other way in which he could escape death at the hands of that third person; and this would be true for no other reason than that Paul would not, in his own person, be inflicting violence ; therefore, and in like manner, one who has been falsely accused before a judge may not for that reason slay his accuser. In fine, the foregoing is confirmed by the fact that much unjust e slaughter would undoubtedly result, to the great, A confirmation. .9 r , r J detriment of the state, from the acceptance of the contrary opinion. For any one might easily persuade himself that he was being unjustly accused in court and that there remained no other means of protecting his life, honour, or property, than that he should slay his accuser. It would also follow that, if one person should, out of invincible ignorance, accuse another—in good faith, to be sure, but nevertheless falsely—the accused could slay that innocent accuser, in order to protect his own fife or reputation. For even such an accuser attacks another person with the sword of the judge, no less than if he were making the accusation out of malice; since, in point of tact, he also is about to take from that other, through a false accusation, his life or his good fame. Consequently, although the opinion opposed ro that which we are defending may seem convincing from a theoretical point of view, still, it is by no means admitted in practice. 7. Cajetan’s statement, indeed, that it is permissible to accept the .. . , challenge in question, at least, with the permbiion the limiting clause, of the prince, does not seem to be sufficiently sound, as qualified by Ca- por a prince may not justly give such authorization, jetan s proviso. sjnce according to the allegations and the proofs, he is certain either that the accused person is innocent or that he is guilty, or that neither the one nor the other fact [is manifest]. If the first alternative be true, then the sovereign is bound to acquit the accused and cannot righteously involve him in the peril of a duel. In the third case, exactly the same assertion applies. For the laws and the principle of justice demand that when the accuser does not prove his charge, the defendant shall be discharged; and in case of doubt, the defendant is to be favoured. If, however, the second alternative shall prevail, the judge is bound to condemn the accused, according to the ordinary law. Moreover, if it be argued that a sovereign prince, out of the 86z The Three Theological Virtues: On Charity plenitude of his power, may set free even a convicted person, especially if Evasion is preprivately he knows that person to be innocent, we say duded· in rebuttal, not even then may he permit the duel; for if the prince has the power to acquit, right reason demands that he shall wholly acquit this person and not expose him to the peril of a duel. There is the additional consideration that, with respect to the accuser, an injustice would be committed. For, even though the prince may be able to acquit an innocent person who has been found guilty, still he may in no wise punish a guilty person who has not been con­ victed of guilt ; and the accuser, in his turn, even though he may be in fact a calumniator, nevertheless has not been convicted of this offence in court ; and if, eventually, he is punished, it will at least be through a just punishment, and not through a duel. It may be urged that the 824 contest in question is not a punishment nor a wrong, because, so we assume, the duel is voluntarily sought or accepted. I reply, indeed, that The reply is over- it is true that on this account no wrong is done to the thrown. private person involved; but a wrong is nevertheless done to the state and to good government, whenever, in violation of due process of law, any person is exposed to the peril of death without sufficient public cause. Finally, if it should be contended that in any given situation, the The final argument sovereign may allow such a duel in order to avoid is refuted, and the greater evils, just as in actual fact prostitutes are defended as genetolerated; even so, he can in no way confer the right rally applicable. and the power to engage justly in this practice of duelling, although he may not have been sinful in permitting it [, in a particular instance]. For the innocent or accused person in the case has no right, acting for himself and on his own authority, either to slay or to attack the other ; and consequently, the prince cannot grant such power to innocent persons of this sort. The truth of the consequent is evident, since the sovereign may not grant that any one shall, with­ out sin, kill another person, unless the latter has previously been legally convicted and condemned, circumstances which do not exist in the situation supposed. Therefore, the conclusion propounded above1 is applicable in general without qualification. 8. Thirdly, I hold that a private armed contest—that is, one The third conduby two or by a few individuals—is not intrinsision: commonly held cally wicked, if engaged in by public authority; on and consisting of two the contrary, if in other respects the contest in ques­ tion comprehends the conditions of a just war, it may be justified, for in that event it has the nature of war;—at least, war of a limited sort—rather than that of a duel. This is the commonly accepted conclusion. 1 [i.e. the second conclusion. See Sub-sections 2 and 4 of this Section.—Th. Disp. XIII: On War 863 The prior part of the conclusion is proved, in the first place, as follows: slaying on public authority and for a just Provedcause is not intrinsically evil; hence, it will not be evil to resort to the means necessary in order to effect that slaying (in which means there is included the [private armed] contest in question.) This argument is confirmed by the fact that a war in which many T persons are iengaged, andi which is characterized bv the Confirmation I. r ,. . · i j , . it conditions laid down above, may be just; and there­ fore, the same assertion holds true of a contest carried on among a few persons ; for a mere difference in the number of persons involved does not affect the righteousness or the justice of a cause. Secondly, the argument in question is confirmed as follows: any „ „ . „ one condemned to capital punishment may legirimately, on the authorization of the pnnce, be put to death by any private person whatsoever, if it shall prove necessary for such an authorization to be given; and under these circumstances, the private agent will not be guilty of any sin in such killing, since he acts as a minister of justice; therefore, in the case described, the same procedure will be permissible. 9. Now the latter part of [this third] conclusion may be estabThe proof of the fished, in the first place, from the [special] use of the latter part. word duel {duellum). Ordinarily, indeed, the term refers to a combat which is entirely private, i.e. undertaken solely upon private authority and on account of a private matter. Such a duel, to be sure, is intrinsically wicked. But the combat of which we are speak­ ing, although it may in appearance be private, because it involves only a few persons, is nevertheless held to be public in point of fact, for the reason that it is undertaken under public authority and for a public cause; and therefore, it is not characterized by the intrinsic wickedness of the duel, but has, on the contrary, the true character of war. Accord­ ingly, in order that such a contest may licitly be undertaken, it mu>t be clothed with the conditions characterizing a just war; and this may come about in either one of two ways. First, the whole business of a war may be reduced to an armed . contest among a few combatants. No, doubt exists The first way in . r - · which this kind of a on the question of whether or not such [a cause] is S αΐΛ7 h* righteous, provided that, in addition to the fact that the war is just, precaution is taken by the prince not to make victory more doubtful than it would have been in case of actual warfare. Cajetan [on II.-II, qu. 95, art. 8, comment, x], indeed, maintains that the prince is not allowed to reduce a war to an engagement among a few combatants, unless he is sure that he would be defeated in the general war. But the rule already laid The first part is 864 Navarros. Caje tan. The Three Theological Virtues: On Charity down1 is more widely applicable and contains more truth. For when the hope of victory is not diminished and does not become less sure because the war has been reduced to a duel, no harm or wrong is done to any one, and for the rest, a great deal of slaughter is avoided. Accordingly, [the arrangement in question] will be righteous and just. However, since this sort of advantageous transformation of the war is a rare occurrence, prudence must be used in allowing it. For if the prince does perchance allow such [a procedure] rashly and without sufficient cause, he will not sin, to be sure, against the justice owed to the enemy state, provided that, in other respects, he is waging a just war ; but he will be sinning against the due rights of his own state, for which, by virtue of his office, he is bound to make careful provision and take careful thought; and he will also be sinning against those subjects whom he exposes to the peril of a duel without reasonable cause. In a second way, the contest in question may be righteous. Not _ . because the entire war is (so to speak) virtually conwhich this kind of tamed therein, but because it is a portion of a war, duel may be justi- justly undertaken and begun, which it is perhaps expedient to carry forward in this fashion to the attain­ ment of victory, inasmuch as the act of reducing the war to a duel deprives the enemy of certain of their bravest soldiers or else dis­ heartens that enemy, while, on the other hand, one’s own men may be heartened ; or there may be other, similar reasons, which will possibly arise. Thus Navarrus taught ([Summa,] Chap, xv, at end). However, the true reason [for the legitimacy of the contest] is that a lawful cause and power underly it, in this case. Moreover, if the war as a whole is legiti­ mate, the same is true of a part thereof; and this armed contest is (as it were) a certain portion of the whole, and a portion, so w’e assume, which is necessary or useful to attaining the end of the war in its 825 entirety; therefore, . . . The foregoing argument proves that it is as permissible to pro­ pose such a contest as it is to accede to the proposal; for if that contest is allowable in itself, it will also be allowable to obtain the authorization to engage in it, from the possessor of authority. Cajetan (word duellum), however, seems to hold an opinion opposed to this one regarding the second manner [in which the contests in question may be justified]. But Navarrus explains the statement of Cajetan as referring to those occasions when the war is confined to a few comba­ tants, without justice and without cause. 10. Now it is maintained in opposition to the above conclusion, The first objection to first, that whoever offers a challenge to such a duel, Hnsinnregoing C°n” Pæ^ed he is waging a righteous war, consequently 1 [i.e. the rule that the prince may resort to such a procedure, if the chance of victory is not rendered more doubtful thereby.—Tr.] Disp. Ill: On War 865 invites and incites another to an action which the latter cannot without sin accept ; hence the challenger himself sins by the act of The second objec- provocation. ϋοη· Secondly, he exposes innocent people to the peril of death, an act which in its very essence would seem to be evil. ... . Thirdly, he binds himself not to defend his own The third objection. , ./ ; · t j l · j people, if they are vanquished by their adversaries orare in most evident danger ; yet, to bind oneself thus seems to be opposed to natural law, which places us under the obligation of protecting the innocent. In reply to the first objection, we must say that the prince in The reply to the first question provokes not to evil [as such], but to a lesser objection. [alternative] evil; for he is directly concerned with seeking his own rights; and he may, on the ground that the other side is sinning, and for the purpose of preventing war on a large scale, seek to substitute for that war a lesser evil, such as this engagement involving peril to only a few persons. To the second objection, one may reply that sometimes it is The reply to the permissible to endanger the fives of innocent per­ second objection. sonSj for the sake of the common welfare. For in the general engagement, also, innocent persons—in much greater number— are exposed to the peril of death. In individual cases, however, care must be taken that these single combats be entered into only with serious reason and that, as far as possible, the peril be diminished. To the third objection it may be replied that, just as the The reply to the duty of defending the innocent is a precept that third objection. binds, not without intermission, but only when it can advantageously be carried out; so, conversely, to bind oneself in a given situation to refrain from defending the innocent, is not intrinsi­ cally wicked, and may be allowed when such an obligation is entered upon, under circumstances that to the prudent mind may render the defence of the innocent impossible for the reason that it would clearly involve grave and general disadvantage; these being, indeed, the cir­ cumstances assumed in the course of our argument. We might deal at this point with the penalties inflicted for duelling, Vide Suârez, Vol. De as well as with the punishment of those who encourage ™s,rns’LDis?* the practice; matters which are, however, more suitii ; Disp. xxxi, ably discussed in connexion with censures, Here, then, sect, iv, no. 48. we may conclude the entire treatise on charity, written for the glory of God and of His Virgin Mother. PRAISE BE TO GOD 1 [This work is not included in these Selections.—Ti·] 1569.74 53