52 Theological Studies of the principle of Anselm as it is outlined in the fourth and fifth forms. It is not an expression of thought which ends with the mere understanding of it. Rather, it is a constant spur to the student of Marian theology. The axiom has been an active force which eventually carried the theology of the Church to a position where it became clear that Mary’s privilege of being immaculately conceived was contained in the deposit of Faith Again, in the question of the doctrine of the Assumption, th principle has played its part, is still effective, and if this doc­ trine is defined in the future, it will have helped in this triumph for Mary. So too, it will have its deserved place and contribute its mighty force in the discussion of the Marian theses which are yet more fully to be worked out—her queenship, her interces­ sion, her place in the Mystical Body of Christ, and the complete theology contained in the Eve-Mary contrast. Nor need theo­ logians fear the heights to which their studies may guide their. In tradition the place of Mary under God is clear; but it re­ mains to investigate fully how near God the Queen of Heaven is. She is on a plane immensely lifted above that of other men— indeed so far above us is Our Lady that our eyes will ever neec to look up even when we arrive at the last station to which theological journeying will carry us. Γ SAINT THOMAS AND THE ULTIMATE PURPOSE OF CREATION PHILIP J. DONNELLY, S.J. Weston College Weston, Mass. OGMATIC theology treats many truths of momentous import, but there is not one of more fundamental importance than the question of the ultimate purpose or end of creation. For if the end holds the primacy among all causes and if, from it, all other causes depend for the exercise of their causality,1 then there can be no theological doctrine deal­ ing with the relations of creatures to God, whose objective truth is not dependent ultimately on the first of all causes, which is the ultimate end of creation. This truth is not merely basic in dogmatic theology but also constitutes the neces­ sary foundation of Christian morality and of all asceticism that is not chimerical. However, in common with similar problems concerning the relations of the finite to the infinite, this question, simple though it must necessarily be in its objective reality, contains many obscurities for the human intellect; and these inherent obscurities of thought can be multiplied easily by the very terminology intended to clarify them; a fact that will be conceded by anyone acquainted with the common terminology of modern dogmatic manuals and with the extraordinary diffi­ culties of students in comprehending the doctrine so proposed. The ordinary exposition of the purpose of creation in many modem manuals is based almost exclusively on the doctrine of Leonard Lessius? Summarily, it is proposed as follows: God’s extrinsic glory is the absolutely last end of creation, the supreme end, the ultimate finis-qui. Finis-qui is defined as bonum ipsum quod appetitur vel intenditur. The ultimate end is de­ fined as finis in quo ultimo sistit intentio agentis. The finis-cui D lCa*tre Gent. ΙΠ, It. !Dr Perfection ibni Moribrnquc Drvmis, Lib. xiv, cc. 1, 3. 54 w i Theological Studies ultimus of creation is God Himself and the finis-cui is defined as the subject or person for whom the finis-qui is intended; in addition most modern authors define finis-quo but do not apply it to the last end of creation; simultaneously with the above explanation and application of terminology, the same authors maintain that no created goodness could have been a motive determining God’s creative act and, consequently, that God’s intrinsic perfection is in no way changed by creation and is in no way intrinsically affected by His extrinsic glory.’ Now this method of explaining the Catholic doctrine on the last end of creation has been criticized severely by two out­ standing theologians of the present generation. In the opinion of the first, the Reverend Johann Stuffier, S.J., the affirmation of so many modern theologians that the absolutely ultimate end of creation, the finis-qui operis, is not God Himself, but rather a created good, namely, His extrinsic glory, is entirely untenable. The same author furthermore states that only by a noteworthy lack of logic can modern authors of manuals place the finis-qui operis in a finite entity such as extrinsic glory, since they admit in agreement with Saint Thomas that the Divine goodness is the sole ratio creandi and that God can only intend created things (and consequently His extrinsic glory which is finite) inasmuch as they are images of His in­ finite goodness.1 *4 Cardinal Billot was equally severe in his strictures of the terminology and method of exposition which would place the finis-qui in extrinsic glory. Of this method he states: "Indeed this first way (of understanding the problem) cannot even be considered. For thus the glory which is derived from creatures would be a means of God’s enrichment; it would be God’s purpose precisely as it is the purpose of worldly men who place their highest good in extrinsic glory and oi whom it is truly said that if, perchance, they receive the re1The following authors may be consulted in their treatises, De Deo Crera/e; Berazi Boyer, Huarxe, Mazella, Otten, Stentrup; confer also Pinard de la Boullaye, in Diet, it TbioL Ctib. m (2), sect, vii, colL 2165-2167, 2191. ♦Zeitschrift fûr katholische Théologie, 1917, pp. 698-699. Aquinas on the Purpose of Creation 55 ward sought for, they receive it in vain; whom Sacred Scrip­ ture chides and the unerring authority of the Saints reprehends, blaming them likewise for those actions which they perform and are otherwise excellent, generous and just, unless they be done for an end that is truly good and not for the windiness of human praise. Moreover, this method makes the goodness of human praise the finis-qui, intended by God, while God Himself would be nought but the finis-cui, namely, the sub­ ject for which God would will this glory, i. e., for Himself. And what else is this than to place in God love of concupis­ cence, to make Him greedy for His glory, despite the fact that Augustine says and says it most truly, most certainly and most evidently, ’by so much is each man more like God, by the degree in which he is freed from the desire of glory.’ Finally, nothing is more manifest than what Saint Thomas has in I, II, Q. 2, a. 3, where, showing that it is impossible for the good of man to consist in fame or glory from creatures, he says: 'The object known is in different wise proportioned to Divine and human knowledge. Whence the perfection of human good, which is called beatitude, cannot be caused by human recognition, but rather human recognition of the be­ atitude of another proceeds from and is in some way caused by beatitude itself, either inchoative or complete.’ Thus far the Angelic Doctor, excluding the goodness of fame or glory from a true good of man, and rightly. How much less there­ fore will the good which God has as the end of all His works consist in such glory?’” These lines sum up the objections against the terminology of Lessius’ followers. The basic difficulty with the terminology so strongly re­ jected by Stuffier and Billot is its logical implication that, if the principal and ultimate intention of God’s creative will is some­ thing finite (extrinsic glory as the finis-qui ultimus), then the ratio creandi or finis operantis, which motivated and deter­ mined the creative act, was something distinct from God’s in­ finite goodness. This apparently unavoidable logical impli5 Dr Deo Uw et Trino, (1926) p. 249. S6 Theological Studies cation is, of course, openly inconsistent with the affirmati® of all theologians that the finis operantis cannot possibly be finite or in any way really distinct from God.’ For it is cler that the absolutely last end of creatures, whose existence, nature and every action are principally due to the efficient activity of God, the First Cause of all things, must be identical vic His finis operantis, that is, His infinite goodness, which con­ sequently must be considered to be the sole sufficient reason of the creative act and at the same time the unique ultimo ' end or first final cause of everything finite, including of cows the operations of creatures, in which extrinsic glory conss principally. Nor is the difficulty with this terminology solve: as simply as some would imply, by insisting that, althouc something finite is the ultimate finis-qui of creatures (and, : logical implication, of the creative act itself), neverthels God Himself is the ultimate finis-cui for Whom extrinsic glc< is intended; for no entity whatsoever is a true finis excer inasmuch as its own intrinsic goodness exercises final causalir Hence, since the absolutely last finis-qui is placed in soffit thing finite and since nothing finite can in any way affect Gal intrinsic goodness, then, if God be the last end of creation on· inasmuch as He is the finis-cui, that is, the subject for whe: extrinsic glory is intended, it is very difficult to see how Get is in any way intrinsically and really the last end and first catf of all things. Now there can be no doubt that all Catholic theologiae no matter what terminology or method of exposition they for low, must and do hold that God Himself, in His own intrins.· and infinite goodness, is, by no means metaphorically, but, * a most real and true sense, the absolutely last end and the fii final cause of all finite being. For this truth is too dearb contained in revelation to admit of denial. ' On the other hai> it would be open heresy to deny that the world was creati Aquinas on the Purpose of Creation 57 for the glory of God,8 which all theologians understand as extrinsic glory, namely the finite manifestation of God’s in­ trinsic perfection and the finite communication of His intrinsic goodness. It is however equally clear that extrinsic glory, as a finite entity, cannot be the absolutely last end of creatures, since it is itself a creature, and hence is caused ultimately by God whose intrinsic goodness is the final cause of all things. Conse­ quently, though the terminology used so commonly seems in­ adequate to explain the fulness of Catholic doctrine, this by no means implies that the authors who make use if it are guilty of theological error, though they may, it seems, be rightly charged with logical inconsistency. This inconsistency, as already noted, seems due in large part, to a literal following of Lessius and a corresponding neglect of Saint Thomas. Now it is a rather startling fact that Lessius, in his entire treatment of the last end of creation, never cites or follows either Saint Thomas or Suarez, both of whom treated the question fully and with precisely the same terminology, which leaves no room for ambiguity and embraces adequately all the data of revela­ tion and sound philosophy. Consequently, the scope of this article is to propose syste­ matically the doctrine and terminology of Saint Thomas and to indicate briefly Suarez’ complete conformity. This mere exposition, with short comments will suffice, it is hoped, to show how much modern theologians have lost in clarity and effectiveness, by practically deserting these two recognized masters for the more subjective and anthropomorphic presen­ tation of Lessius. In other articles, it may be possible to show in greater detail the logical inconsistency of the treatment based on Lessius and the conformity of Saint Thomas and Suarez with the doctrine proposed in the Councils of Cologne and the Vatican. •"Eadem sancta Ecclesia tenet et docet, Deum, rerum omnium principium et finem, •Confer decree of the Council of Cologne, Collectio Locensn, Vol. V, coL 291. "Ego Alpha et Omega, principium et fini», dicit Dominus Deus; qui est et qui tr* et qui Tenturus est, omnipotens.” (Apoc. 1, I). The traditional exegesis of this text suststf the these on fait. natural: humanae rationis lumine e rebus creatis certo cognosci posse.” Concilium Vatica­ num, Sen. ΙΠ, cap. 2 (DB. 17SS). Confer also the third iftcButn in the ith Canon (DB. 1I9T): **Si quis aut mundum ad Dei gloriam conditum esse negaverit, A.S.” 58 Theological Studies Finis Operis et Operantis of Aquinas on the Purpose of Creation Creation According to Saint Thomas, the finis operantis is that whic an agent principally intends.9 Then in the same place, apply­ ing this definition to God’s creative activity, he continue “Whence—also in the case of God operating, the end of Hi action must be considered, which is the goodness of God:’ Himself.”10 The perfect agreement of this definition and application of Saint Thomas with the definition and applicatio: of the Council of Cologne, whose dogmatic value is very hig: because of the unrestricted approbation of the Holy See," evident from a cursory reading of the latter: “If the *··· operantis, or that which impelled God to create, be sought,: should be stated that nothing which is distinct from God cou.: have impelled Him, since, being self-sufficient, He could inten: nothing for Himself. Since, however, it is clear that God c: create and that, whatever He effects, He does it out of love c: His absolute goodness, we rightly maintain that God wt moved by His goodness freely to create the world. Moreovt' in this same sense Saint Augustine said: ’Because He is gowe exist’.”11 Saint Thomas never deviated from this definition of R operantis, but rather, in his later works develops more cor pletely the notion of voliti principalis. "The principal obje. desired is for everyone the cause of volition. For, when* say: 'I wish to walk for health’s sake’, we are conscious assigning a cause, and if it be asked: 'Why do you wish fc health?’ we proceed in the designation of causes until we retf the ultimate purpose which is the object principally intend which in itself is the cause of volition.”13 This is the fa operantis according to Saint Thomas’ definition. This passage shows clearly that Saint Thomas identifies r volitum principale, the finis iilthnus intentus and the finis C 59 erantis. This identity is made even clearer by the following citation: "Furthermore, for every person making an act of volition, the object principally intended is his last end; for the end is per se intended and that on account of which all other things are intended. The ultimate end, however, is God Him­ self, because He is the highest good. He therefore is the prin­ cipal object of His will.”14 From this citation, it is clear that God Himself intrinsically, and not something finite and totally extrinsic to Him, is at one and the same time the finis operantis and the ultimate end of all things finite which are intended by Him in the creative act. Certainly, no one could maintain that in this text Saint Thomas teaches that the last end of creatures is indeed some Divine good, but a good that is not intrinsic to and identified with the Divinity—a doctrine not uncommonly proposed in theological and philosophical manuals.15 If therefore the intrinsic goodness of God is the unique prin­ cipale volitum, it follows that absolutely nothing outside of God can possibly be His finis operantis. This is a truth which Saint Thomas proves many times from a further analysis of the volitum principale. “The object of an appetite is proportioned to the appetite as the object moving is proportioned to the sub­ ject that is moved; and likewise is the object willed propor­ tioned to the will, since the will belongs to the genus of ap­ petitive potencies. If therefore there be any other principal object of the Divine will than the very goodness of God, it will follow that there is something superior to the Divine will which moves it.”1’ The absolute and supreme unicity of God’s finis op­ erantis in no way conflicts logically with the concept of creation, as if God could not intend beings outside of Himself unless they were in some way His finis operantis, for this is a uIb»d. cap. 4. •II Sent., d. 1, q. 2, a. I. l5Confer. Ferd. Stentrup, S.J., Tractains de Deo Uno et Trino, (Oeniponte, 189J), l*Loc. rit. ρ. 2ίβ, Thesis LXX: "Supremus creationis finis aliquo bono ipsius Dei, non tamen interno ilCollectk> Lecenat, VoL V, col. 266-270. sed externo, externa scilicet divinae gloriae manifestatione, continetur.” liIbid. cd. »1. Grw/. I. 74, J. ’’Coefr* Gent. 1, 74, 1. Aquinas on the Purpose of Creation Theological Studies 60 61 stituted by its appetibility, which is the end, which, moreover, false and undemonstrable concept of creation; but it does im­ moves the agent to act. Wherefore goodness is said to be dif­ ply, on the contrary, that the finis operantis is the entire an: fusive of itself. But this diffusion is found in God; therefore sole sufficient reason for that intention of the Divine will whir God is truly good.”19 terminates in finite being. "It must be stated that in ώκ Hence the intrinsic goodness of God moves His things which we will on account of an end, the entire reasc: will to create, precisely inasmuch as it is difiusivum sui and for so willing is the end. And this is supremely clear in ths therefore it is not only God’s unique finis operantis, but is also things which we will solely on account of the end. Hen;, the unique ultimate end and first cause of all creatures, since since God does not will things other than Himself excepte according to St. Thomas: "It must be said that goodness is account of the end which is His goodness, it does not follow th called diffusive of itself in the precise way in which the finis something other than His goodness moves His will.... It mu is said to move and thus the axiom: 'because God is good, we be said that from the fact that Divine goodness is suffice exist’ is to be referred to the final cause.”20 The objection unto the Divine will, it does not follow that God wills nothin: maintained that the axiom referred to the efficient cause. else, but that He wills nothing else except by reason of HAre we, however, to understand the intrinsic goodness of goodness.”1T God, which is simultaneously and uniquely the finis operantis It is scarcely necessary to add that the volitum prim­ and supreme last end of creation, as the ontological, Le., essential pale, which according to Saint Thomas, moves God to vgoodness of God or His moral goodness i.e. the virtue of bene­ creatures and is the sole reason why He intends finite beinn ficence? Saint Thomas replies unequivocally that we should is not to be understood as a strict cause, but rather as the unk> understand it as the essential goodness of God: "Every good sufficient reason of the creative will and only mentally disti.n which is not its own goodness is said to be good only by par­ from it. "Whence, since the will of God is His essence, it is ticipation; but that which is predicated by participation pre­ moved by another, but by Itself alone ; after that fashion fc supposes an anterior being from which it receives its goodness. which intellection and volition are called motion; and * But this process cannot be infinite, because there is no infinite cordingly Plato said that the Prime Mover moves Himself· process in final causes. ... We must therefore arrive at some Thus far we have seen that St. Thomas maintains that ώ first good which is not merely good by participation in sub­ intrinsic and, therefore, infinite goodness of God is the unk ordination to something else, but which is, by its very essence, finis operantis of the creative act. We are now in a positions good. This being, however, is God.”21 show more intimately and precisely what he understood by From these last three citations, Saint Thomas so obviously intrinsic goodness of God and how it is identified with Γidentifies, in the intrinsic, essential and infinite goodness of God, absolutely ultimate finis operis. "The communication of en:the finis operantis, the supreme end of creatures and the first and goodness proceeds from goodness; a fact which is cb final cause of all finite being, that it is not a little strange how both from the very nature of goodness and from its inteà; so many modern authors can profess their adherence to the bility. For according to its nature, every being’s good is ·Angelic Doctor and, at the same time, assert that the supreme act [existence] and perfection. Moreover every being acts pfr cisely because it exists. By acting, it diffuses being and g*·: “Conir* Gnt. 1, 37, 4. Tbeol. I, q. J, ». 4, ad 2. ness into other beings. The intelligibility of goodness is c&17 18 nCoeto G«rf. 1, 38, 2. 17Sm«>w< Tirol- I, Q· 19, i. 2, id 2, id 3. 18Ibid- sd 3. IP 62 Theological Studies or absolutely ultimate purpose of all things, principally in­ tended by God in creating, is His extrinsic glory, which, » evidently, is a good only in virtue of its participation in the Divine goodness itself. How then does God’s goodness, as the sole sufficient reason or finis operantis of creation, move the Divine will? Saint Thomas replies that the creative will is moved by God’s good­ ness as it is apprehended intellectually by Him: "The will s moved to act by some apprehension (cognition) ; for, gooc apprehended is the object of the will. Hence every agent mus act accordingly as it possesses a similitude of its effect. But in every voluntary agent as such, there exists a similitude of the effect according to the apprehension of the intellect.”” This Divine apprehension, therefore, inasmuch as it is identi­ fied with God’s essential perfection, is the Divine goodnes apprehended: inasmuch as it is a similtude of every creature, actual or possible, it is called an idea. Whence is this ida derived? Saint Thomas replies: "Whoever knows an object per­ fectly, knows everything that is in it. But God knows Himse?. perfectly. Therefore, He knows all things which are in Him­ self according to His active potency. But all things according to their proper forms are in Him with respect to His active potency, since He is the first principle of all being. Therefor? He has a proper knowledge of all things. Whoever knows as' nature, knows whether that nature is communicable. But th Divine nature is communicable through similitude. God there­ fore knows in how many ways something similar to His essena can exist. God therefore has knowledge of things according ® their proper forms.”13 Inasmuch, however, as "God, in His essence, is the similitui of all things, whence an idea in God is nothing else but lb essence”,24 it follows that we must not attribute to God ide entitatively distinct from each other. Nevertheless we are jus- Aquinas on the Purpose of Creation 63 tified in predicating a certain multiplicity of ideas in God with respect to creatures. Furthermore, the fundament of such a predication is not derived from creatures; for according to Saint Thomas: "It must be said that these varying respects, according to which Divine ideas are multiplied, are not caused by finite beings, but by the Divine intellect comparing its own essence with them (creatures).”” Furthermore, "these respects which multiply ideas are not in created things, but are in God; they are not, however, real rela­ tions such as those by which the persons are distinguished, but they are relations comprehended by God.”2’ From this doctrine on Divine ideas Saint Thomas proves that God, that is, the ideas themselves which are identified with His essence, is the exemplary cause of all finite beings: "There must be in the Divine wisdom species of all things, that is, ex­ emplary forms existing in the Divine mind. And these, though multiplied with respect to created beings, are nevertheless not really distinct from the Divine essence, inasmuch as its simili­ tude can be variously participated by finite beings. Thus, there­ fore, God Himself is the first exemplar of all things.”” In answering the difficulty that, since every effect of an ex­ emplary cause must be a similitude of its exemplar and since no creature can bear a similitude to God, therefore God cannot be an exemplary cause, Saint Thomas replies: "It must be stated that although creatures do not arrive at a similitude with God according to His nature by a specific similitude, nevertheless they do attain to His similitude according to the representation of the form apprehended by God.”“ But, as we have seen, this form apprehended by God is in no wise derived from creatures; rather it is identified with His in­ trinsic goodness as known by the Divine intellect; it is therefore really identified with God’s finis operantis and with the ab­ solutely last end of all creatures. Tbeol. I. q. U, a. 2, ad J. i3Coittra Gmt. 2, 24, 1. •ftii. »d 4. -^Contre Gmt. 1, $0, 7-1. Theol. I, q. S, ». 4, ad 2. •ftid- ad I. TbttA. I, q. 44, a. 5, corp. 64 Theological Studies In addition, Saint Thomas gives a penetrating and exhaustive analysis of what is required that the Divine ideas, to which each creature is perfectly assimilated by way of finite representa­ tion, be truly an exemplary cause: "It is to be noted that some­ thing may imitate a form in two ways. First by the intention of the efficient cause, as a picture is produced by a painter precisely that it may imitate him whose figure is reproduced sometimes, however, the imitation is accidental, fortuitous an: quite removed from any intention. But that which imitates : form by chance cannot be said to be formed unto it, for unto implies finality. We see moreover that one may act on accoun: of an end in two ways; in the first way, so that the efficient cause determines the end for himself—sometimes, however, the end is determined for the agent by another principal efficient cause as in the motion of an arrow.... If, therefore, somethin: be produced in imitation of another by an agent which doe not determine its own end, the form imitated will not posses the attribute of an exemplar or an idea. For we do not say tha: the form of a man who generates is the exemplar or idea of the man generated, but we say this only when the agent acting on account of an end determines the end, whether the form in question be within or without the agent. This, therefore, is the proper notion of an idea that it be a form which something imitates because of the intention of an agent who determine for himself the end. Accordingly, it is clear that in the opini» of those who assume that all beings proceed from God by » natural necessity, Divine ideas cannot be postulated, because be­ ings which act from a necessity of nature do not determine for themselves the end. But this cannot be, for in the case of eve* being which acts for a purpose, if it does not determine the esfor itself, then the end must be determined by some super»* being; and thus there is some cause superior to the agent; which cannot be, because all who speak of God, understand Him to be the first cause of all being.. .. But, because an exemplary forte or idea possesses in a certain way the attribute of finis and be­ cause from it the artificer receives the form by which he acts Aquinas on the Purpose of Creation 65 if it be extrinsic to him; because moreover it is not proper to postulate that God acts on account of an end other than Him­ self and thus receives extraneously what is required for acting, therefore, we cannot place ideas outside of God, but in the Divine mind alone.”29 Therefore, according to the doctrine of Saint Thomas on exemplary cause, every creature arrives, by way of finite par­ ticipation, at a perfect imitation or representation of the Divine ideas. These Divine ideas are identified with the goodness of God intellectually apprehended by Him as communicable in vary ing degrees by finite communication. The goodness of God thus apprehended is, at one and the same time, God’s finis op­ erantis and the first final cause or absolutely last end of all creatures. We conclude with Saint Thomas, therefore, that the ‘i’Mi operantis is absolutely unique, namely, the intrinsic good­ ness of God inasmuch as it is communicable, even if God had freely chosen never to create; it is the principal object intended r y the Divine will in creation, because of which alone God free­ ly intends those beings which He actually creates, and hence it done is the unique absolute and ultimate end and the first final cause of everything finite without exception: "It must be stated that all beings intend God as their end, in intending whatsoever zood, whether by intellectual, sensible or natural appetite; for nothing has the attribute of the good, except in as much as it participates in the similitude of God.”30 The similitude, as we have seen, in the citation from the Summa, Part I, q. 5, a. 4, ad 2um, is identified with the essence of God. That the doctrine of Saint Thomas was held completely and identically by Suarez, is evident from the following citation: For any agent, the supreme end is that which constitutes for him the best and highest good; but for the First Agent, nothing except His own intrinsic goodness, is the greatest and highest zood; therefore nothing can be the last end of His actions and effects, except Himself, by reason of His own goodness. FurVtriMe, », a. 1. Tbetjl. L φ 44, a. 1, ad J. 66 Theological Studies Aquinas on the Purpose of Creation thermore, because the concept of final cause is perfect anc in itself pertains to unmixed perfection, therefore, it is prop: to God in the highest degree of perfection and because, since goodness is the reason of final causality and God is the higher good, it is necessary that He possess in the highest degree ώ attribute and perfection of final cause. . . . Finally the axior. that the order of ends is according to the order of efficien: causes, is here pertinent. For the more perfect and universi! the agent, the more perfect and universal is the end which be intends. But God is the most perfect and universal agen: therefore, He intends the most perfect and universal en: Therefore to the objection previously raised, 1 we answer that although God does not act on account of Himself, as on accour. of His own end [that is, final cause in a strict sense of causali? as opposed to sufficient reason], nevertheless, there can beb: one supreme end of all things, not because God seeks that end for His own satiety or that in this end He may possess a sus ciency of all goods, but, on the contrary, because He ahead' possesses in Himself all good and the highest perfection, b which alone He could be moved or attracted to benefit other· because of Himself. Whence, though it be true that among th beings created by Him, God orders some unto others as endsor rather, connects all in such a way that all in turn serve ea? other and in this way, under God, there can be assigned other universal ends to which each creature, apart from individui· ends, is ordained by the Creator, and in particular, to the order and beauty of the universe [ in which the highest degree ot extrinsic glory is found], nevertheless, absolutely nothing aptf from God can be called the last end toward which the Divi# intention or action tends.”35 The superiority of Saint Thomas and of Suarez, in excluding from God’s creative activity any semblance of acting to acqurand in excluding from creatures any semblance of being eit}g the finis operantis or the absolutely ultimate finis operis, is 3,The objection was that the last end of all things is the order of the universe in extrinsic glory, in the highest degree, consists. i3Mrtapb. Disp. 24, sect. I. (Edit. Berton, Vol. 21, 89J-Î94) 67 from the following citation of Lessius, whom most modern authors perpetuate: "The end which God intended in the crea­ tion and government of the entire universe must have been something extrinsic. . . . Although God most freely intends and most freely produces all being outside of Himself, neverthe­ less, if He wishes to produce something, He must necessarily will this effect out of a desire and intention of His glory. For even as He is necessarily the first and most eminent agent, so is he necessarily the last and most eminent end, for whom all things are. And hence in every operation ad extra He necessar­ ily intends some good of His own. 33 But there is no conceivable genus of goods which God can acquire for Himself, except extrinsic glory, which moreover is the most excellent of external goods.... It is clear that the end which God ultimately intends in all His operations ad extra is His own glory. . . . From this it is evident, how God is the ultimate end for whom all things exist;14 secondly what is the finis-qui [gloria extrinseca], which He intends to acquire for Himself; thirdly, in what the glory of God, for which He produced all things, consists.”35 Finis Operis of Creation More Specifically According to Saint Thomas: “Finis operis is that to which an effect is ordered by an agent.”3’ He understands, of course an intrinsic ordination, produced, it is true, by an extrinsic effi­ cient cause, but which consists in a permanent internal ten­ dency or appetite. Hence, as we have already seen generically, once the finis operantis is known, it is not difficult to find the absolutely ultimate finis operis in the case of an infinite agent who implants in his effects an intrinsic appetite for the ultimate end and is, moreover, the first efficient cause of every action of his creatures. It is indeed true that the creative will of God, as 33Ths good, according to Saint Thomas and Suarez, is God’s intrinsic goodness, which , ·.-.«, a* '-he principal object intended, moves God to create. ^’According to Lessius and many modern authors God is the finis-cni mtenditnr gloria ' ritriastci. ^Dr Prrftctionibns PAoribusqne Divmfa, Herder Edition, (1861) p. J16. »Π Sr·/. d. 1, q. 2, a. 1. moved by Hu mtnm* goodntv* mulleetuaily apprehended, » the Hbcamc uuw of every hru« bong and that all cmum corwquetxty. *rv peeuve commun* auum of the Divine, atrim* goudnew. it · equally true that, due to the Imutatw . of human language. the great SchdaeuCK including Smk Thoma*» senctunn ri prew th*i pruceM by uuog the foflowiq of equivalent term* regarding (xd i creative activity: aï rw■aMérrf. */ nw*»Ufude*i fowte/ra* ma·*, etc; bet et muet be moat careful, l«K. understanding thew ex pre» . merely m thru ordinary ayntactacal une. we interpret theta a meaning that the pawvc and finite communicatum of Donat gmidncM. which n eat nm* glory, and not the Divine. mtnau goodnew «twif. n the «m o>nn/n and the lupreme o>m or first final cause oi the world. The modern follower! of U> i um mually quote only those pawcagw of Saint Thomas wbet he use* thew cxpmejom and art thu» convinced that they in of one mind with the Angel* Doctor. However, that meh » interpretation of he mind i· clearly erroneous, Saint Thon» who « he own best interpreter, demonstrates beyond the p»nbdity of a doubt in the following objection and answer*. *14 The ultimate end of the Divine will is the communicatiofl # His goodness; for on account of the He produces creature, namely, that He may communicate His goodness. To 14. must be stated that the communication of goodness is not dr Ur/ rm/, but the Divine goodness itself out of whose love Goi wishes to communicate it; for He does not act on account ot His goodnew as one who deures what He does not possess, W as one who wishes to communicate what He poswuev been* He acts not from a desire of the end. but from love of th end/**’ It is obvious therefore that, according to Saint Thomas, * God were to act on account of the finite communication d His goodness and not on account of His goodness itself as th supreme end of creation, He would be acting on account of » good, previously not possessed but to be acquired for Htmsell , Therefore, it is to be noted that in the passages, in whid ”0* PefeW* q. }, *. If, sd. 14. Saint Thomas says that God acu r*/r* m order to com* ί municate His goodness. he by no means en pi xs that the brute communication ts either the supreme fines ofirrn or m am w the finis opertnhs, but he wishes eMy to exclude from God any motive by which He might even teem to be c reatmg. M to communicate, but to *r^«/rr some gxxdnrm not already Has from all eternity. Always presupposed in the phrase ·/ munieft is the /irwi itself. that η, Da wxrf tvdara/aJrw» ut communicet. That this is Saint Thomas* mind n clear from the fotU* mg passage; "Goodness in God implies the notion of fines, in which there ts the fullest perfection; the end however m»?vc· the altogether deficient and far removed from the infinite reality the supreme end, which is none the less actually acquired. T» deficient and limited communication, manifestation or ùjbp tion of the Divine goodness, which Saint Thomas design*» with one word, namely, an assimilation to the Divine gorxire» Aquinas on the Purpose of Creation nee it is, according to the degree freely determined by Divine providence, the ultimate intrinsic and finite perfection, by which each creature according to its nature obtains God the ibsclutely ultimate end, can be called and is truly the end of each creature and moreover the ultimate in the order of finite and created ends: "If every being tends toward a similitude of Divine goodness as an end; if a being is assimilated to the Divine goodness with regard to everything that pertains to its own goodness; if the goodness of a being consists not only in its existence, but in all things else required for its perfection as has been shown, then, it is manifest that creatures are ordained to God as their end, not only according to their substantial bemg, but also according to their accidental perfection and morecr according to their proper operation, which also pertains to the perfection of a being.”47 It is true that Saint Thomas frequently calls this created . initiation the last end of creatures, but he must be undertood as intending, not the absolutely last or supreme end, but rather the attainment or acquisition of the supreme end, for : he had intended to affirm that the supreme end consisted in a creature, he would have contradicted all the passages which we have seen in this section, and especially the place in his De Γ'-tentu, where he says that "the communication of goodness a not the last end, but the Divine goodness itself out of whose iove it is that God wishes to communicate it” (q. 3, a. 15, ad 14, ct. above 67 ff.) ; for then the finis operantis and the supreme opens would not be identical; God’s infinite goodness would not be the supreme final cause of all finite being; more­ rer St. Thomas would then have contradicted what we shall see immediately in the following section. Relation of Finis-Qui and Finis-Quo Saint Thomas teaches clearly that the unique ultimate finis;·Λί of all things is God Himself, whereas the ultimate finis-quo, aame.r, the finite attainment of the finis-qui, is neither unique GeW J, 20. ad wIW. I. 75 76 Aquinas on the Purpose of Creation Theological Studies 77 deputation we distinguished a two-fold end, the objective (finor even specifically the same for all creatures: ”Ccnc._-r and the formal (finis-quo), that God is not the ulti­ although God is the ultimate end of all things, neverS» mate formal, but rather, the ultimate objective end of creatures. there is not for men and for other creatures which lack And the reason is, because the formal end is not the absolutely the same last end as regards its attainment. It must be str..-, end, since it is ordained unto the objective. Likewise, the Philosopher says, that there is a two-fold division ot ··; though God be the summum bonum, nevertheless, namely, cuius and quo, that is, the object itself in which r creatures do not attain this summum bonum except by some ness is found and the use or attainment of it, for examp e. 2 ·, rt : participation; whence the attainment of the summum say . . . that the finis of a miser is either money as the .h ■■ is always something created. Whence, in passing is or the possession of money as use. If, therefore, we spe>. . Ived the objection put above, namely, how such a great the last end of man with regard to the object, which is th : met) of beings and natures can be ordained to the same last thus, all other beings share in the last end of man; for G end For the reason is that this same and identical last end is the last end of man and of all other creatures. But if we n : the nment itself, but the good attained. Different beof the last end of man, with regard to the attainment :?.<* . r.p. however, though they have in common the same ultimate in this end of man irrational creatures do not share. Foe rc •j. fiîfer in the attainment of it, even as they have the same and other intelligent beings attain their last end by k"· : principle, but differ in the mode or degree of their emanaand loving God, which is not proper to other creatures -ten from it.’’1* obtain the last end, inasmuch as they participate in some > F urthermore, Suarez asserts explicity that the extrinsic glory tude of God, accordingly as they exist, or live or posse» Gcd 5 not a finis-qui, but the finis-quo of creation, a posi­ sort of cognition.’*48 to exactly contrary to that taken by the modern followers What, therefore, is the relation between the objects'* c* t Lcsuus: "Thus, therefore, in answer to the difficulty, we (finis-qui) and the formal end (finis-quo), which in the c# cKtdc that the glory of God is something outside of Him; for of the ultimate end of creatures are infinitely distinct one fr* anrrtnaliy, glory, taken in its proper sense and likewise accord­ the other, both in entity and in goodness? In other words whe ât to primitive meaning, is a good that is extrinsic to him is the absolutely ultimate or supreme end? Saint Thomu œ it a. Nevertheless, God can intend His glory as an end, wers: "Since, as has been said above (previous citation). Λ became He does not intend it as a finis-qui but as a finis-quo, end is sometimes the object [ finis-qui] and sometimes the « ch not only is not repugnant but is necessary.”31 tainment [ finis-quo] of the object, even as for a miser tbeesi Therefore, according to both Suarez and Saint Thomas, the absolutely speaking, the ultimate end is the object itself; fa & .. ml s Ill ■Λ I frmi-quf* and the supreme finis operis are identified. 7^2.^ self.”* Suarez likewise insists that the finis-quo or formal end b and cannot be the absolutely last end of creatures, since it à χ· -riioro a absolutely identical and unique, not merely gen• ϋ*«Λ* LÀ ». cap. l. (Lût. Bertoa, VoL 9, p. 512) 78 Theological Studies Aquinas on the Purpose of Creation 79 goods can be desired as proximate ends, since all theu ?.· : urthermore, Saint Thomas frequently states that the order goodness has its source in Him as the first final cause, it «. ! the universe is a more primary intention of God than the beyond any possibility of doubt that, on the part of each rs vkiual perfections of single creatures: "Created things parrate creature, the intrinsic and created participation of c.z m the Divine goodness by way of similitude, inasmuch Divine goodness (extrinsic glory), inasmuch as it is a i s ii they are good. But that which is the greatest good in created entity and is specifically distinct in creatures of different sp« ·. ngv is the goodness which consists in the order of the uni­ and is, moreover, numerically distinct in all individual crer-verse. which is most perfect. ... It pertains to providence to whether of the same or different species, cannot be the rda;n things unto the end. But after the Divine goodness, bonum and hence cannot be the numerically identical la: which is an end separated from created beings, the principal of all creatures without exception. Therefore no one can c.~ good rus/ing in the being themselves is the perfection of the harmony with Saint Thomas and Suarez, if he holds tbit anivene.’”* The goodness of the order of the universe, therefore, is the finis-qui ultimus, the absolutely last end of all creatures b ' ghest end in the finite order of ends, precisely because, in this God Himself, but a good totally extrinsic to Him, name ly i .mverul order consists the highest communication of Divine extrinsic glory. ; odness; nevertheless, it is clear, both from the passage just Saint Thomas renders his mind doubly clear on this very . ted and from the one immediately preceding (P.I, q. 103, portant point by insisting that the supreme end of creature »2 . that the order of the universe (in which the definition of not merely extrinsic to each individual creature, but is ; - > ultimus is evidently verified, inasmuch as it is the to the entire universe of created beings: "Since the end • gheu created attainment or representation of the Divine responds to the beginning, it is impossible to be ignorant of à ci.dne«) is not the finis supremus or absolutely last end, but is end of things, once their principle is known. Since there: rdaitxd to the extrinsic end (finis-qui). For Saint Thomas the principle of created beings is something extraneous t :ut« dearly that the very perfection of the universe, which entire universe, namely God, it is necessary that the fa* * its order, is the last intrinsic end existing in creatures created beings be some extrinsic good. Whence that good •hr--.velvet and therefore finite, but that it is subordinated to the is the end of the entire universe must be distinct from the π “ ^jprene end, namely the Divine goodness. Hence, whenever universe. (To the second) Something extrinsic can be ant®* S* nt Thomas teaches that the created manifestation, communnot merely as an effect produced, as for example, the end $ · ,r imitation of the Divine goodness is the ultimate end, carpenter is not to build but the house itself, but also as * must be understood, as is clear from his own words, to be object possessed, obtained or even represented, as when we s»" :eak;ng of the f.nis-quo, not of the finis-qui, of the last end that Hercules is the finis of the picture which is made to reft • the order of created and finite ends, not of the supreme or sent him. Thus, therefore, it can be said that a good, extranet » au y ultimate end. Therefore those who would maintain to the entire universe, as a good to be obtained or represent the supreme end of creatures, their ultimate finis-qui is is the finis of the governing of creatures. (To the third) Indre 'a a good extrinsic to the entire universe, but is rather a there is an end of the universe existing in it, namely, the or# ” r.te good intrinsic to the created order, are in open variance of the universe. But this is not the list end, but is ordered ua· ·· .th the dearly expressed mind of Saint Thomas. an extrinsic good as the ultimate nW.** I. q. 1. i, >. L < M. t. ♦, eorp. 80 Theological Studies Aquinas on the Purpose of Creation 81 The Finis-cui of Creation $ f We have seen that, according to those who place the -t qui ultimus of created beings in the finite entity called extras glory, God Himself is only the finis-cui and that, by dus ar they mean that God is the subject for whom the created perfection of extrinsic glory is intended. By this termine, moreover, they sincerely wish to vindicate for God the fui perfection of final cause and of the ultimate end of all ώζχ in accord with the data of revelation and of sound phi».; But, despite all good intentions, the terminology is in \ defective, because extrinsic glory, as we know both from ’ and from reason, can in no wise affect God intrinsic!/- ε therefore it is metaphysically impossible that He be in anv E sense the last end of all things, precisely and solely, terminology contends, because He desires this finite ent::· ” Himself. Moreover, such terminology is entirely fore::' Saint Thomas. It is true that he never uses this technical T-3 of finis, as he does the technical terms finis-cuius and Λ but he never loses sight of the fact of paramount imponi'-' namely, that finis and final cause as applied to God a creatures are strictly analogical. Hence, he is never mnW · experience with created ends into attributing the imperfect* of finite ends to the infinite end of all things; conseque*: such an application of the term finis-cui as that made by b* sius and so many moderns is clearly excluded in the writing** Saint Thomas: An effect must tend toward the end in 0* way in which the agent acts on account of the end. But G* who is the first efficient cause of all things does not so act & by His action He acquires something; for He is solely in peffir ACT, whence He is able to bestow. Creatures, therefore. J? not ordered unto God, as unto an end for Whom something acquired, but, so that from Him they may attain Him sis He is the end.”^ Again, "The last end, on account ηί mv perfection. Whence, He does not wish to communicate His perfection to a creature in order that something may accrue to Himself from it.”* But, if God were the ultimate end only as a finis-cui, if He were the finis-cui only because He intends His extrinsic glory t c Himself, would He not, in these hypotheses, either depend upon those things which are ordained unto Him as the finis-cui, r w<>uld not this application of finis-cui to God, who can in no woe be intrinsically affected by extrinsic glory, be purely chunencal? In other words, according to Saint Thomas: "God, therefore, is liberal to the highest degree, and He alone can properly be called liberal; for every other being, except Him, - . acting acquires some good which is the finis intended.”31 This terminology which makes God the finis-cui because of a finite finis-qui (extrinsic glory) seems impossible, not merely because it logically deprives God of the intrinsic perfection of final causality’, but also because, according to Suarez, extrinsic ri n does not constitute a true good for God ; hence it seems 2 ub’.y impossible that He be truly and solely the last end (finis.u .because He intends for Himself a good which not only cannot affect Him intrinsically, but moreover is, in no proper