THE DOCTRINE OF THE COMMON GOOD OF CIVIL SOCIETY IN THE WORKS OF ST. THOMAS AQUINAS A Dissertation Submitted to the Graduate School of the University 0/ Notre Dame in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy by Jaime Velez-Saenz Department of Philosophy Notre Dame, Indiana April, 1951 > ‘ j * > Λ / \ ' > i » J Lithoprinted in U.S.A. t % ; .EDWARDS · > 1 , J ‘ t - ΛNN BROTHERS, ARBOR, MICHIGAN 1951 INC. Cu *Ί ι *μ.·^· ·, '=>!'■ ~... Wh ■'- iw xj CcrJ Q ξ V * 4PREFACE The question of the common good, of civil society was never devel­ oped or discussed in a systematic manner by Saint Thomas, but the theses which he expounded in relation to it, while treating other sub­ jects, can be summarized in a doctrinal body, which could be re­ garded as the “theory of the common good” of Saint Thomas. To or­ ganize these theses to the extent that is warranted by the condition in which they appear in his works, as well as to examine what is needed to complete the theory, which is not included explicitly in those works, is the main purpose of this dissertation. The fragmentary and scat­ tered character of materials bearing· upon this cpiestion in Saint Thomas’ writings requires a considerable amount of interpretation, inference, and even some times harmonizing of those texts which at least appear contradictory. This we have tried to do in writing this dissertation. Moreover, we have taken special pains to remain within the limits of what, historically, are the personal teachings of Saint Thomas, as distinct from what has been a development of Thomism from his time up to the present. On the other hand, since it is not always easy to distinguish between what he actually declared or in­ timated, and what is merely implicit in his teaching, it has not been possible to avoid completely recourse to Cardinal Cajetan and John of St. Thomas, two of his greatest commentators. We have tried to use their commentaries only in an instrumental way, so to speak, toward ascertaining what Saint Thomas’ own thought actually was, without in­ troducing elements unwarranted by those texts. Recent discussions among the disciples of Saint Thomas concerning the common good of civil society have made apparent the confused and undeveloped condition of this question in current Thomistic philosophy. Accordingly, before proceeding to integrate into a new synthesis what­ ever may have been gained in these discussions, it would seem advis­ able, as a preliminary task, to settle the state of the problem such as it can be determined on the basis of what is contained in the writings of Saint Thomas. The primary sources for this dissertation have been chiefly the Summa Theologica, the Summa contra Gentes, the Commentaries on the Ethics and Politics of Aristotle/and the De Regimine Princfpum~ It has been unquestionably established by scholars that of the Commentary on the Politics only the first four books and, of the De Regimine, the first book and the first five chapters of the second book iii 1V PREFACE other four booksoTthe^^m^nt^r”138’ f^Ithough u seems that the faithful disciple of Saint~Thorn»—F"n —Politics were written by a hence represent the Xr's ±Τ"<· notes °f «« master, and them in this dissertation for wp ha0^*’ *ittle Use has been made of Thomas personally wrote as an add,? Strictly to what Saint of others be attributed to him The r safeguard lest the thoughts Principum is known to have r^mainmg part of the De Regimine ®iFT5H-many PZts from to! T. by PtolemT of ----- Consequently, no use at all has teen made^fït™ ®^η1 Th°“aS· TABLE OF CONTENTS sources: some of tte Qwata^’n·1’®®?’ Of course> used as basic the De Veritate and Dè^CarîtateT· tï^T^^’ f°r instancef especially a«d eveiT^Fki suchTs th on the Sentences, totle, in which one would Metaphysics of Arisof the common good, but which in fact to obtain that which they think good.”48 Such a tendency must always be present in every social body; and the mutual arrangement of its parts as well as the working of the whole thus constituted and in motion toward the end—in short, both the structure and the dynamism of the social body--depend upon that end and are measured by it, for the end governs the entire system of things which tend toward it.49 Furthermore, the structure and operations through which every community 46. Cf.In Met., VII, 17, #1672; passage quoted above - note 34. 47. I-II, 1, 2: “aliquid sua actione vel motu tendit ad finem dupliciter: uno modo sicut seipsum ad finem movens, ut homo; alio modo sicut ab alio motum ad finem... Illa ergo quae rationem habent, seipsa movent ad finem... Et ideo proprium est naturae rationalis, ut tendat in finem quasi se agens, vel ducens ad finem.” Ibid., ad 1; “quando homo per seipsum agit propter finem, cognoscit finem.” 48· poL Ir *' 1252 a ί· i/ di ; 49. II-II, 87, 2, ad 3: “ea quae ordinantur in finem sunt judicanda secun­ dum quod competunt fini.” I-II, 102, 1: “oportet quod id quod est ad finem, sit proportionatum fini; et ex hoc sequitur quod ratio eorum quae sunt ad finem, sumitur ex fine; sicut ratio dispositionis serrae sumitur ex sectione, quae est finis ejus, ut dicitur in 2 jPhys., text. 88.” ' SPECIFICITY OF COMMON GOOD Of POLITICAL SOCIETY 19 displays its own activity participate in that kind of finality which is proper to rational creatures. Accordingly, the activity which most formally expresses the finality of social beings is not of a physical type, nor even biological, as in the vegetable and animal organisms. Social phenomena transcend the physical sensible order to which they are subject on account of the matter--both bodies and space--by means of which they exist. Knowledge of social facts comes, of course, through sensible things, but social facts inasmuch as they are social belong to a completely different order; they possess a dimension by means of which they are orientated towards ends that are knowable only through reason. This is why the knowledge of social facts cannot be resolved into sensible data; their explanation can be provided solely by their end.50 We must remark here that the end of a society need not be always present to the minds of all its members. It does not even have to be known by all of them. What is more, it is not always easily formulable in statements which are precise and beyond controversy. It is not necessary either, in order that every human community be truly said to aim at some end, that each of its members always act with an actual view to that end. The real meaning of this truth is that the dif­ ferent forms and organizations through which the entire social ac­ tivity is carried out are objectively referred to ends, which explain them and make them comprehensible. In other words, those forms of social dynamics move themselves, as it were, in virtue of what they are and according to their own inclination, towards their respective ends, even if these ends may not be actually known or rightly viewed by many of the individual agents who are the ultimate subjects of that social activity, or even if the motives of some of these individuals may be at variance with the objective social ends.51 The fact remains 50. That which specifies a thing and constitutes it as such and such makes it thereby intelligible. Now, human actions are specified by their ends: “actus humani, sive considerentur per modum actionum, sive per modum passionum, speciem a fine sortiuntur. ...actus dicuntur humani, inquantum procedunt a voluntate deliber­ ata; objectum autem voluntatis est bonum, et finis; et ideo mani­ festum est quod principium humanorum actuum, inquantum sunt humani, est finis: et similiter est terminus eorumdem." (I-II, 1, 3). Cf. Ibid., ad 1: “finis non est omnino aliquid extrinsecum ab actu, quia comparatur ad actum ut principium, vel terminus.” 51. Just as with regard to an action the “finis actionis” and the “finis agentis" need not be identical, so the end of any association or any social institution does not necessarily coincide with the particular motives that an individual acting through them intends to attain. The intrinsic end of an institution or a community specifies it and gives it its objective form. It can be considered as a kind of “finis actionis,” which, unlike the “finis agentis,” gives an act its proper species and nature. Cf. I-II, 18, 4. 20 SPECIFICITY OF COMMON GOOD OF POLITICAL SOCIETY SPECIFICITY OF COMMON GOOD OF POLITICAL SOCIETY 52. Contra impugnantes Dei cultum et religionem, 2, c. 8. - Fr. Engel­ bert Kurz rightly criticizes as erroneous the idea, often held, that this formula is the definition of civil society in Saint Thomas. (See E. Kurz, O.F.M., Individuum und Gemeinschaft beim Hl. Thomas von Aquin). Such a formula is too generic to constitute a complete definition; an army, a society, a family, as well as any other form of collective human action, are all of them an “adunatio hominum ad aliquid communiter agendum.” What specifies society is not included here. On the contrary, it is much more exact to say that civil society is “multitudo adunata ad totam vitam” (Π-ΙΙ, 48, art, unie.), although this formula is applied in the same article to the family, also. But then both family and civil society are set off in contra-distinction to any kind of “multitudo adunata ad aliquod speciale negotium," such as, for instance, an army is. In a com­ plete definition of civil society a further specification would be needed so as to have the expression “tota vita” mean not only “vivere” but also, and chiefly, "bene vivere," --as it will be ex­ pounded in Chapter II. 53. In Eth., I, 1,#5: “tractus navis est operatio multitudinis trahentium navem. " 21 function is to direct society toward that in which its common good con­ sists and to procure unity of action whenever there is no ground for unanimity. In fact, it cannot be expected that all individuals, even if agreeing upon the end, should also agree upon the way to attain it, es­ pecially when different ways of action can lead to the same results. In such cases authority is indispensable in order to choose the course to follow and to prescribe that course. Its precepts constitute the law, in the most general sense of the word. Authority is thus both a result of the end-seeking activity of every community and a necessary condition for success in such activity. In order to determine the nature of the order whereby a society is one, we have thus far considered that the components of society have rational nature, and, consequently, that society essentially aims at some end. The next point concerns the relationships which exist among the members of society. In any society whatever these rela­ tionships are necessarily implied by the degree of organization and mutual arrangement of parts which its activity requires. It makes no difference how complex and varied the relationships may be from an empirical point of view. What is relevant here is the ontological meaning which relationships have in the table of the Aristotelian cate­ gories. According to this schema, they belong to the category rela­ tion, so that this category is necessarily present in the essential constitution of any social being as such. Since a society does not and cannot exist in such a manner as to be itself a substance, its sole possible manner of being is to be simultaneously many substances in­ asmuch as these are interwoven into one body by the category relation. In other words, the social ens has real existence independently of any • mental representation, but it does not exist like a substance; rather it exists insofar as, and in the manner and condition in which, the ac­ cident relation exists among substances. This is the meaning of Saint I Thomas’ teaching when he writes: “licet multitudo praeter multa, non est nisi in ratione; multitudo tamen in multis est etiam in rerum natura.”54 But just as a society is not a collection of individuals, it cannot be considered as a mere sum of relationships among indivi* duals; if it were such, the unity of the whole would disappear. The fact is, however, that those relationships are integrated into a system which is unified by its over-all reference to the common social end. ( Furthermore, they have a place in, and a relevance for, the entire common operation and functioning only insofar as they are called for by the end. Thus, it is from the end that the unity of the system orig­ inates. Now, a body of relationships which are unified into a system that the finality of any society whatever cannot but share in the nature of human finality, and, therefore, social ends can not only be known by rational beings but can also be held as the rule and measure by which to adjust the individual’s conduct in his social life. As to the way in which the entire operation of a social body is ac­ tually carried out, the fact is that the final goal to be attained implies some basic agreement among all the individual members and some amount at least of ultimate convergence and congruity in their com­ mon action. It is to this that Saint Thomas refers when he speaks of the “adunatio hominum ad aliquid communiter agendum.”52 From this very formal point of view of the “communiter agendum” it makes no difference whether the group in question is a small and transitory one, like the one formed by a few men drawing a boat (“trahentes navem”),53 or on the contrary an old, complex society: the end can in both cases · —and in all cases intermediate--be attained only by means of some kind of collective action converging towards it. Thus, beyond any con­ crete or historically given forms of common social activity, and re­ gardless of the particular ends a society sets out to pursue, a mini­ mum of cooperation of all concerned is at the root of the very exis­ tence of a society, and below that minimum the society simply could not subsist. It can be said then that the very existing of any society lies in the actual finalistic cooperating of all its members. At this point it becomes clear why authority is necessary, since its essential s 54. De Pot., 3, 16 ad 16. 22 SPECIFICITY OF COMMON GOOD OF POLITICAL SOCIETY SPECIFICITY OF COMMON GOOD OF POLITICAL SOCIETY 23 by their ultimate referability to a supreme end is an “order.”55 There­ calls democracy). He further remarks that the name used for this fore, that which really causes any human community to be one is an species of regime is the generic name given to all constitutions, or “order of relations;” and so, the “unitas ordinis” by means of which politias.58 a society is one is an “ordo relationis.”5S The reality designated by This generic use of the term constitutes its second sense. Here this expression “ordo relationis” is what Saint Thomas, following politia denotes the general arrangement or organization of a society; Aristotle, calls politia. This word has two senses in Aristotelianit is the “ordering of those who live in a city” (a “civitas”), and the Thomistic politics, however. In one sense politia is applied to that intercommunication, or body of mutual bonds, “communicatio,” among mixed regime which consists in a combination of different elements its members.59 In modern terms, politia is the system of those in­ of oligarchy and democracy, and which is often called respublica by stitutions which shape a social matter~and are embodied in it, es­ Saint Thomas. In Aristotle’s classification of regimes according to pecially insofar as they are the expression of an actual way of social the number of persons--either one, or a few, or many--who exercise and political living. The politias or constitutions of the Greek citythe political power in the city57politia is the name which denotes the states, studied by Aristotle, are spoken of in this sense. Note that regime of the many, provided that their rule is intended for the bene­ here the word constitution is given a meaning wider than the current fit of all; (otherwise, the regime becomes the perversion which he and technical one of source or foundation of the system of positive law of a nation. The politia has, with regard to its community, a func­ tion similar to that of the form in a substance; it makes a society be such and such, while distinguishing it from all others. The identity of I 55; For an “order” to exist among things, there are two requisites: a a society depends upon the politia to such an extent that, if the politia criterion, or principle, --which in practical things is an end--, and changes, the society ceases-to~be formally the same, even if it remain the arrangement and disposition of the things to be ordered, ac­ materially identical through the sameness of its parts.60* cording to the measure set up by the end. Saint Thomas writes: “Ad hoc quod aliqua sint ordinata, duo requirunter: primo quidem, quod aliqua ordinentur ad debitum finem, qui est principium totius ordinis in rebus agendis;... Secundo oportet quod id quod est ad finem, sit proportionatum fini; et ex hoc sequitur quod ratio eorum quae sunt ad finem, sumitur ex fine.” (I-II, 102, 1). 56. This expression does not seem to have been used by Saint Thomas in connection with society. Whenever he speaks of the “civitas” as made one by a “unitas ordinis,” he does not go further to specify what kind of order it is. In fact, the expression “ordo relationis” is used by John of Saint Thomas when he comments on Saint Thomas’ In Metaphysicorum; he then writes (Logica, II, 16, 2): , “distinguitur unitas ordinis in numero ab unitate exercitus vel t civitatis, quae sunt entia per accidens, eo quod in istis solum in­ venitur ordo relationis, qui non sufficit ad unitatem per se.” Cf. note 36 above. ’ 57. The criterion of the number of rulers is not the only one used by Aristotle to draw the distinction among the different forms of gov­ ernment. Political regimes are bad or good according as the com- · mon good is, or is not, their aim, but, even for two constitutions, the aim of which is not the common welfare, the distinction ac­ cording to the number of their governing bodies does not suffice. ί In fact, “the real difference between democracy and oligarchy is 1 poverty and wealth. ” (Pol., III, 8, 1279 b 40. See also same chap­ ter, passim). j 58. Pol., ΙΠ, 7, 1279 a 39: “when the citizens at large administer the state for the common interest, the government is called by the generic name--a constitution” (or politia). - For Saint Thomas’ use of respublica (politia) in this sense, the following text can be mentioned: "oportet quod in republica aliquo modo appareat pau­ corum status et popularis. " (In Pol., IV, 8, #7). See also Ibid,, lect. 7, passim, for Saint Thomas’ commentaries on the politia. 59. “ordo inhabitantium in civitate” (In Pol., III, 7, #1); “ordo civitatis (ibid., IV, 10, #3); "communicatio civium" (ibid., III, 2, #3); “vita civitatis” (Ibid., IV, 10, #3). 60. In Pol., Ill, 2, #3: “non potest dici eadem civitas, si mutetur ordo politiae : cum enim communicatio civium, quae politia dicitur, sit de ratione civitatis, manifestum est quod mutata politia non rem­ anet eadem civitas... Et ita etiam videmus in omnibus aliis quae consistunt in quadam compositione vel communione, quod quandocumque alia est species compositionis non remanet identitas... manifestum est quod civitas est dicenda eadem respiciendo ad ordinem politiae; ita quod mutato ordine politiae, licet remaneat idem locus et iidem homines, non est eadem civitas, quamvis materialiter sit eadem.” - Understood in its second meaning, politia can be applied to two different aspects of the same reality. (Cf. Marcel Demongeot, Le meilleur regime politique selon saint Thomas, in which there is an analysis of the notion of politia in Saint Thomas). Under one of these aspects, the politia is the or­ ganization of public authority; it is then variously called “ordo / 24 SPECIFICITY OF COMMON GOOD OF POLITICAL SOCIETY SPECIFICITY OF COMMON GOOD OF POLITICAL SOCIETY 25 Let us now make, in the manner of definition, an enumeration of the elements of the “ordo relationis” which unifies a society. This “ordo” is the one which exists necessarily, and to the exclusion of any other, among the components of a whole whenever these components are substances in actu endowed with a rational nature, and consequent­ ly mutually bound by relationships which imply rational knowledge and will--and which imply, correspondingly, ends which can be known and pursued as such; in the pursuit of these ends the components of the whole--that is, the individuals which make up a society--organize into different structures and functions, all of which possess an objective reference to ends, and finally to a supreme end.61 On thé other hand, this ordo which unifies a society has two dimen­ sions*, first, the relationships of the parts among themselves; and second the relationships which all of the parts have to their common end;® this latter relationship determines and measures the relation­ ships among the parts.63 The dependence of the entire social activity upon its end is what makes a multitude of interrelated individuals to be one whole—which is to say that the supreme end is the formal constitütïve of both the unity and being of a society, because in the things which move towards an end the formal and specifying ratio comes from the end, and all things receive their unity as well as their very existence from the form which is proper to them.64 The unity of so­ ciety is grounded in its teleological character. 6Û. Continued——————— At this point it is appropriate to consider the immanent order of principantium” (in Pol., IV, 12,#1); “ordo dominantium in civitate” society in relation to the good. For the immanent order of society is (ibid., Ill, 6,#2); “ordinatio civitatis quantum ad omnes principatus nota static structure but a dynamic and teleological organism, and so qui sunt in civitate, sed praecipue quantum ad maximum principa­ it is related to an end. But whatever has the ratio of end has also the tum" (ibid., Ill, 5, #2). The other aspect, which is the one chiefly : ratio of good: an end as such is always the term for a tendency; and, considered in the text of this dissertation, is the organization im­ whatever fulfills a tendency, or is sought as desirable for it, as its manent to society itself. There is evidently a mutual acting of both completion and satisfaction, has by that very fact the ratio of good for aspects upon one another, since the general organization and moral it. A thing is said to be a good precisely because it is perfective of orientation of a society influence the form of its governing authori­ ties, and are in their turn influenced by the latter. another thing by way of final causality ,65 61. These various forms of organization and activity are the social in­ stitutions, in the most general sense of the expression. AH of them > are at least mediately directed toward an end which is not sought for the sake of anything else. About the subordination of lower to higher ends Saint Thomas writes: “unus finis propter alium desideratur. Aut ergo est devenire ad aliquem finem, qui non desideratur propter alium, aut non. Si sic, habetur propositum. Si autem non est in­ venire aliquem talem finem, sequitur quod omnis finis desideretur propter alium finem. Et sic oportet procedere in infinitum. Sed hoc est impossible, quod procedatur in finibus in infinitum: ergo necesse est aliquem esse finem, qui non sit propter alium finem desideratus.” (in Eth., I, 2, #20). The “cooperation” which is spoken of in the text must be under­ stood in a very formal way. So understood, it does not necessarily imply a universal agreement of wills; the conflicts and tensions within a society are quite obvious. But in order for a purposive common working to exist it is sufficient that these conflicting ten­ dencies do not go so deeply as to break a certain minimum of basic agreement on the ultimate ends. Such a minimum exists beyond the reach of any dissension whenever the moral totality of a society- ac­ cepts at least a small number of principles and values to be respec­ ted in the solution of political and social conflicts. In Saint Thomas’ theory of the political regimes, the minimum of unity corresponds to the democratic regime, in which government is distributed according to the freedom which the citizens have to act on their own initiative and discernment, without receiving from others the rule of their actions. Cf. Marcel Demongeot, op. cit., about unity in the different political regimes. έΖ/Τη Eth., I, 1,#1: “Invenitur duplex ordo in rebus. Unus quidem par­ tiurn. alicujus totius seu alicujus multitudinis ad invicem, sicut partes domus ad invicem ordinantur. Alius est ordo rerum in finem. " 63; II-II, 47, 10, ad 2: “bona dispositio partium accipitur secundum habitudinem ad totum.” I-II, 102, 1: “ratio eorum quae sunt ad finem, sumitur ex fine.” 64. II-II, 47, 11: “Ratio formalis omnium quae sunt ad finem attenditur ex parte finis.” Concerning the existence and unity which a being enjoys as coming from its form, Cf. _δ·£·Τ, II, 58: “Ab eodem ali­ quid habet esse et unitatem; unum enim consequitur ad ens. Quum igitur a forma unaquaeque res habeat esse, a forma etiam habebit unitatem." Even if not actually written by Saint Thomas himself-who is believed to have written only the first four books ofthe Com­ mentary on Politics-~the following text, probably from one of his immediate"disciples, contains good Thomistic doctrine: “Unitas ordinis in finem facit civitatem unam." (in Pol., V, 2, #18). ‘65. I, 5, 1: “Ratio enim boni in hoc consistit quod aliquid sit appetibile; unde Philosophus in I. Ethic., in princip., dicit quod bonum est quod omnia appetunt.” De Ver., 21, 2: “cum ratio boni in hoc con­ sistat quod aliquid sit perfectivum alterius per modum finis; omne id quod invenitur habere rationem finis, habet et rationem boni.” I 26 SPECIFICITY OF COMMON GOOD OF POLITICAL SOCIETY SPECIFICITY OF COMMON GOOD OF POLITICAL SOCIETY 66. I-II, 102, 1; “Ad hoc quod aliqua sint ordinata, duo requiruntur: primo quidem quod aliqua ordinentur ad debitum finem, qui est principium totius ordinis in rebus agendis... Secundo oportet quod id quod est ad finem, sit proportionatum fini.” 67. In Met., XII, 12, #2627: “Bonum enim, secundum quod est finis alicujus, est duplex. Est enim finis extrinsecus ab eo quod est ad finem, sicut si dicimus locum esse finem ejus quod movetur ad locum. (This example is taken from the Aristotelian physical sys­ tem). Est etiam finis intra, sicut forma finis generationis et alterationis; et forma jam adepta, est quoddam bonum intrinsecum ejus, cujus est forma. Eorma autem alicujus totius, quod est unum per ordinationem quamdam partium, est ordo ipsius: unde relinquitur quod sit bonum ejus.” This doctrine is derived from a passage of the Metaphysics in which Aristotle inquires “in which of two ways the nature of the universe contains the good and the highest good, whether as something separate and by itself, or as the order of the parts. (Met., IX, 1075 a 12). And he answers: “probably in both ways, as an army does; for its good is found both in its order and in its leader, and more in the latter. " 68. I-II, 111, 5, ad 1: “bonum multitudinis, sicut exercitus, est duplex: unum quidem quod est in ipsa multitudine, puta ordo exercitus; aliud autem est quod est separatum a multitudine, sicut bonum ducis; et hoc melius est, quia ad hoc etiam illud aliud ordinatur." The good of the leader is explained as his will of victory, and the organization of the army is for victory’s sake--its extrinsic good: “magis est bonum exercitus in duce, quam in ordine: quia finis patior est in bonitate his quae sunt ad finem: ordo autem exercitus est propter bonum ducis adimplendum, scilicet ducis voluntatem in victoriae consecutionem; non autem e converso, bonum ducis est propter bonum ordinis. ” (in Met., XII, l2,#2f>30). 27 A difficulty may be raised here by the simple remark that a society can have existence while in a bad state of organization and activity , or while in pursuit of wrong ends. A society exists only through a form which is an order, but insofar as it is badly organized or wrongly or­ ientated, it does not really have an order and form, and therefore, it cannoteven be said to have existence. However, the difficulty van­ ishes when one considers what good is and the different modes accor­ ding to which a thing is said to be good. The ratio of good consists, as briefly mentioned above, in that a thing perfects or completes another thing in the manner of a final cause. Now, the order of society is something that perfects it, and this in a twofold way. First, insofar as the order of a society is the form whereby it comes into existence; in this sense, the order is always good, since it is both the act which gives that society its very existence, and that society itself as exis­ ting; now, a thing is good insofar as it is, “intantum est aliquid bonum, inquantum est ens.”09 Second, order is a good for a society if it con­ stitutes an improvement of any kind along the line of what is added to the mere existence of that society; if, more specifically, that order consists in bringing about a better condition of organization and ac­ tivity of the social body: in this sense there exists always the possi­ bility for a society to reach higher and higher levels of perfection. Thus, if a society is considered from the point of view of its existing, that is to say, of its being an ens in actu, then its order cannot but be a good for it, for exactly the same reason that actual existence is a good for whatever has a mere possiblity of existence. But if, on the other hand, a society is considered from the point of view of that which, added to its existence, could be for it either a further perfection, along an always open avenue of possible improvement, or just the opposite, then the order of a society becomes subject to a judgment by virtue of which this order can be said to be either good or evil, according as it is, or is not, in agreement with those ultimate ends every society must pursue. These ends preside, as it were, over all ideal patterns of so­ cial organization; they are, above all, the object of an ethical know­ ledge—in a very general yet proper sense--and constitute, according­ ly, ethical criteria to judge of a social order. All this amounts to say­ ing that both “immanent order” and “intrinsic good” are expressions which, applied to a society, can be taken either in an ontological sense or an ethical one. Thus, immanent order, inasmuch as it gives a so­ ciety its act of existence, is always a good; inasmuch as it must con­ form with the true ends at which a society must aim, it can be either good or evil, and in divers degrees. Because society is an “unum per accidens,” the distinction between the two lines of perfection, ontological and ethical, holds true of so­ ciety in a peculiar manner, rather different from the manner in which It follows from this that a society’s immanent order, or politia, is re­ lated to some good for the very reason that it refers to an end; and that order will be good if the end at which it aims is good, and if, moreover, it is adequately proportioned to this good end. Only under these conditions can an order really and truly be said to be such.60 Just as there is a twofold order in things—as recalled above--that which is good as an end for something is also twofold. There is first a good which is extrinsic to that which is ad finem; and then there is a good which is intrinsic to a thing, namely, its form. Now, the form of a whole which is one through an ordering “per ordinationem,” is the order itself, which is therefore the intrinsic good of that whole.66 67 This is why the immanent order and the intrinsic good of civil society are equivalent expressions. In like manner, the intrinsic good of an army consists in its good organization and functioning- -its immanent order. Its extrinsic good is victory.68 69. I, 5 28 SPECIFICITY OF COMMON GOOD OF POLITICAL SOCIETY SPECIFICITY OF COMMON GOOD OF POLITICAL SOCIETY a good has not only impregnated the external relationships of the mem­ bers but has also penetrated into their souls and achieved in them the unifidation of all their tendencies. Being identical in this manner with peace, unity can be considered in the line of ethical perfection. It is indeed a high ethical excellence fora community to achieve the harmony of all wills--and of all ap­ petites—in the love of common ends. This is social unity in its moral sense. And from the point of view of existence, it is an absolutely necessary requisite for a society to be one in order to exist, because everything is insofar as it is one: “unumquodque intantum est, in­ quantum unum est.”74 Furthermore, unity belongs to the ratio of goodness: “Unitas pertinet ad rationem bonitatis.”75 Thus, the transcendentals being, goodness and unity are also present--and necessar­ ily, of course,-in any society; they mutually imply each other and are realized analogically, in the form which befits the nature of society. We must again insist that in every community there is a continuity and a mutual implication between its existential and its ethical lines. At the lowest stage of its existence some sort of action--actually, a beginning of “cooperation,” as shown above—is already present. At the height of an intensely united common living, society, not being a substance by itself, requires indispensably for its maintenance in ex­ istence such actions of the individuals as insure unity and peace. Thus, there is in social life a gradation of increasing actuality of both exis­ tence and moral perfection. In every act of “communicatio,” of civic living together, there appear two aspects of one and the same reality, the social being. The entire system of those acts, inasmuch as the very existence of a society becomes real through them, is its imman­ ent order, or form, in the ontological sense. And insofar as those same acts are carried out in a true direction towards right social ends, they are morally good, and they constitute the immanent order in the moral sense. And in both senses the immanent order is identi­ cal—as already noted—with the intrinsic common good, which Saint Thomas compares to such organization of an army as is adequate to attain victory, which is the extrinsic good. There is an extrinsic or separate good for civil society also. In contrast to the immanent common good, the extrinsic is, as it were, outside of society; it is a good external and superior to the order which is inherent in society, and society should serve it. For Saint Thomas, the question of concretely identifying that extrinsic end is dominated by these two principles: that the end which suits every man is twofold, one natural and one supernatural; and--as enunciated in De Regimine Principum--that one and the same judgment should be it applies to substances. In a substance, existence can be conceived as completely stripped of any operation, as put in extra mental reality in a state of absolute inactivity, as bare and sheer existence. On the contrary, existing as “unum" requires necessarily for an “unum per accidens” a minimum of operation of its parts, a minimum which in a society would probably consist in the mere consensus, however im­ plicit and tacit it may be, of all its members to live a common life.70 This consensus is a “cooperating,” it is an acting with a view to a common end, so that for society to exist is for men to cooperate. In­ sofar as cooperation becomes more intense and reaches more areas in the life of a community—the “communicatio” among its members thus becoming deeper--the “unum per ordinationem” which society is rises to a higher degree of existence, because then the degree of actuality in the cooperation among its parts is also higher. This higher degree depends not so much on the complexity and number of social relationships as on the intensity and depth with which the members of a community engage their personal inferiority in the common living. If, for that sort of “unum per ordinationem” which a society is, to ex­ ist is for its members to cooperate, then the intensification of their cooperating—of their civic “communicatio”—constitutes an increase in the actuality of the society’s very existence, while at the same time it is a perfection along the ethical line; it is indeed a good which a community ought to strive to acquire. Such a perfection is, in con­ crete terms, that unity which is called peace, which Saint Thomas de­ clares to be the goal intended by the ruler of a multitude: “id ad quod tendit intentio multitudinem gubernantis, est unitas, sive pax.”71 Peace is not only the concord of all wills in a common object, but also the harmony of all tendencies within each soul.72 Peace can exist only if related to an authentic good;73 it is the state of a society when such*12 70. This consensus is not the acquiescence given to a compact which has been agreed upon for utility’s sake alone, but which freely could have not been formed--as is held by some of the so-called social compact theories on the origin of society--; it is rather the > expression at the level or reason, and through it, of a fact of nature: f the natural need of social life for man. 1 1. I, 103, 3. · 2. II-II, 29, 1: “pax includit concordiam, et aliquid addit...Concordia enim proprie sumpta est ad alterum: inquantum scilicet diversorum i cordium voluntates simul in unum consensum conveniunt...concor­ dia importat unionem appetituum diversorum appetentium; pax autem, supra hanc unionem, importat etiam appetituum unius api petentis unionem.” 1 Ibid., 2, ad 4: “cum vera pax not sit nisi de bono," etc. Ibid., ad 3; ’‘pax vera non potest esse nisi in bonis et bonorum. ” Peace will be | considered with some thoroughness in Chapter II, which deals with ’ the content of the common good. 29 74. I, 103, 3. 75. Ibid. 30 SPECIFICITY OF COMMON GOOD OF POLITICAL SOCIETY SPECIFICITY OF COMMON GOOD OF POLITICAL SOCIETY 31 formed about the end of the whole society and the end of one man.76 natural authorities but to the priesthood.79 For this reason the Christ­ ian Church is present in the midst of the temporal city. However, a doctrine of the extrinsic natural good of the multitude is not found elaborated in his works. It is not strange that Saint Thomas But it is precisely by applying the principle stated in the De should have deemed it superfluous to develop a purely natural moral Regimine that one can learn what the extrinsic end of the city in the philosophy:77 whatever the supreme good to which man may naturally natural order is. This end, which society is to serve after it has acattain, the fact is that in his concrete situation after Christian Reve­ I quired its own immanent unity, order and harmony, cannot be other lation he is supernaturally destined to enjoy God in the eternal life. than the highest good that man can obtain by his natural powers alone, It is only through comparison with an army's double end that Saint namely, “the happiness of which the philosophers spoke/ “felicitas Thomas refers to what would in reality be society’s natural extrinsic de qua philosophi locuti sunt.”80 Of this happiness Aristotle says: “If common good, but he never ventures a further specification. On the happiness is activity in accordance with virtue, it is reasonable that it other hand, he is very explicit when he deals with the supernatural should be in accordance with the highest virtue... This activity is con­ extrinsic good of society. Here his starting point is the principle, templative.”81 Saint Thomas also considers the contemplative life the above mentioned, that one and the same judgment should be formed highest form of life.82 If this holds true for every man, it holds for about the end of the whole society and the end of one man; it follows society also, since, according to the above-enunciated principle of the from this, as he clearly teaches, that the multitude is also destined De Regimine, one and the same judgment should be formed about the for fruition in God. It would seem, he begins, that the end of civil end of the whole society and the end of one man; and therefore con­ society is virtuous life, since men congregate with the object of living templation is the extrinsic end of civil life. Now, even if this extrin­ properly, and they would not secure this object if each man lived apart sic end of society and the extrinsic end of each single man are identi­ from the rest. But the multitude has the same end as any of its mem­ cal—and indeed they are, both in the natural and in the supernatural bers, and each man is destined through virtuous life for the divine orders—society and the individual do not refer to them in the same fruition; it follows, therefore, that the ultimate end of the multitude is manner. This interpretation seems to be supported by an important not the virtuous life itself but the possession and enjoyment of God text of the De Regimine Principum. It is the passage in which Saint attained through the virtuous life.78 And because that end is superior ) Thomas says that living according to virtue is the end for which men to all human power and shall be fully consummated only in the King­ dom of God, the office of leading to it was not entrusted to the city's 79. Ibid.; “quia finem fruitionis divinae non consequitur homo per Reg'· 1’ 14; “Idem oportet esse judicium de fine totius multi; tudinis, et unius. ” The reason for this statement can be found in In Pol., VII, 2, #2, where it is said; “manifeste apparet felicitatem < unius hominis et civitatis esse eamdem et unius rationis... Et hoc ) rationabiliter contingit; quoniam quorum est una natura, eorum est unus ultimus finis. Unus autem homo et omnes cives civitatis sunt ( unius speciei: ergo unius et omnium civium est unus ultimus finis.’’ j 77. Cf. E. Gilson, Le Thomisme, p. 421, 5th edition. 78. De Reg., I, 14: "Videtur finis esse multitudinis congregatae vivere ( secundum virtutem. Ad hoc enim homines congregantur, ut simul bene vivant, quod consequi non posset unusquisque singulariter ) vivens; bona autem vita est secundum virtutem; virtuosa igitur vita ' est congregationis humanae finis... Sed quia homo vivendo secun­ dum virtutem ad ulteriorem finem ordinatur, qui consistit in fruii tione divina, oportet eumdem finem esse multitudinis humanae, qui , est hominis unius. Non est ergo ultimus finis multitudinis con­ gregatae vivere secundum virtutem, sed per virtuosam vitam perj venire ad fruitionem divinam. ” > 76. virtutem humanam, sed virtute divina, ...perducere ad illum finem non humani erit, sed divini regiminis. Ad illum igitur regem hujusmodi regimen pertinet, qui non est solum homo, sed etiam Deus, scilicet...Jesum Christum. ... Hujus ergo regni ministerium ...non terrenis regibus, sed sacerdotibus est commissum.” 80. De Ver., 14, 2. In the Ethics Aristotle had already declared that happiness is the supreme end: “We call that which is in itself worthy of pursuit more final than that which is worthy of pursuit for the sake of something else, and that which is never desirable for the sake of something else more final than the things that are desirable both in themselves and for the sake of that other thing, and therefore we call final without qualification that which is always desirable in itself and never for the sake of something else. “Now such a thing happiness, above all else, is held to be; for this we choose always for itself and never for the sake of some­ thing else.” (Eth., I, 7, 1096 a 30, Page 31: If.). 81. Eth.» X, 7, 1177~i 11, ff. 82. Of the two possible forms of life for man as such, the contem­ plative life is the higher; “vita contemplativa simpliciter melior est, quam activa." (II-II, 182, 1). 32 SPECIFICITY OF COMMON GOOD OF POLITICAL SOCIETY congregate in society;83 and they would not be able to attain this end if they did not congregate: “virtuosa vita est congregationis humanae finis.”84 The perfection of human activity secundum virtutem can thus be achieved in the community and only in the community, but the subject in which virtue resides and by which it is practiced is the in­ dividual, and it is the individual also who is the term in which the act of association finally redounds in perfection of virtue. The (super­ natural) extrinsic end of both society and individual is materially one and the same thing: the possession and enjoyment of God through the highest activity according to virtue, that is, through contemplation. This is the extrinsic end of society inasmuch as virtue can be ac­ quired only in and through society. It is the extrinsic end of the indi­ vidual man inasmuch as he alone is the radical and ultimate subject of the vision of God, to which he is directed by virtue. One might ask whether there is not an incompatibility between the principle that the judgment is one and the same with regard to the end of the whole society and the end of a single individual, and the thesis, on the other hand, that society’s common good differs formally from the good of the individual. No real difficulty can be found here, how­ ever. With regard to the extrinsic common good which is materially one and the same for both society and individual, the fact that they at least are diversely related to it--as already said—means that the same end is a good for both of them under different respects, and this agrees with the principle of the specificity of the common good. Furthermore, this principle concerns primarily the intrinsic or im­ manent good. In the first place, this principle means that the common good is formally distinct from the private good because it alone befits the nature of an *unum secundum quid,” like the social being, in which alone that good is realized as in its own and proper subject. This is equivalent to saying that such a good is identical with the good structure and functioning of the social body. The principle means also—as explained at the beginning of this chapter—that the total con­ tent of goods that can be realized in civil society transcends in kind and not only in degree the goods which the domestic community is capable of giving to man. It must be remarked, however, that the good of a whole society at least partially coincides materially with the private good, that is, insofar as it is also a good for each individual; if this were not so, the common good would not be truly common. But even so, the common good preserves its formal difference in that it is a good for each individual without ceasing to be the very good which is simultaneously common to many, whereas the private good as such excludes any other: it is this individual’s own good and for that reason is not the good of another. 83. De Reg., I, 14, the same passage quoted above in note 78, p. 30. 84. ibid*: SPECIFICITY OF COMMON GOOD OF POLITICAL SOCIETY 33 All these considerations lead to the problem of ascertaining in what consists that good which is realized in civil society. This as­ pect of the doctrine of the common good is more concerned with eth­ ics than have been the aspects thus far discussed. The object of this chapter has been to investigate the specificity of society’s common good considered only as befitting society inasmuch as it is a com­ munity, that is, an “unum secundum quid,” and in contrast to the good which befits a being “unum simpliciter.” To this purpose a line of reasoning more ontological than ethical has been followed. The gist of the reasoning has been to show that the kind of “whole” that so­ ciety is consists essentially in an order, and that this order is its good, the good which is common to the individual members. Now, when the principle is applied that the ratio of whole differs formally from the ratio of part, the conclusion follows that the good of the whole cannot but differ from the private good, as a quality formally irreduc­ ible to it. At the same time the argumentation has made it manifest that, because of the nature of the being which has only that “unitas ordinis” which is proportionate to a human community, the minimum existence of any community whatsoever implies already some amount of cooperation towards one end; and, by virtue of such mutual impli­ cation in all human communities of the entitative and of what may be called the ethical aspects, it is in their very constitution or ontologi­ cal structure that the specificity of every common good has its roots. The question now arises: what is the content of that good which the societas perfecta alone—not the family or any other human commun­ ity—procures for man? It will be the object of the next chapter to an­ swer this question. Chapter Π THE CONTENT OF THE COMMON GOOD That civil society should be the only environment proportionate to the realization of the highest human good does not depend on the onto­ logical constitution of that society but on the fact that it is the only society that can be self-sufficing for living well, which is the highest among human goods. For this reason civil society is designated by Saint Thomas as the societas perfecta, and it is a societas perfecta at least de jure, although the ideal of giving to man the highest good he can reach on earth may be far from realization in fact. But civil society is destined for that consummation and it is in this form of community alone that the good of living well could be attained. And so it is said that society is necessary for man. In the exposition of this classic doctrine of the politics of Saint Thomas and Aris­ totle it is often insinuated, and sometimes openly stated, that accord­ ing to these philosophers society is necessary for man inasmuch as it succors the individual in his purely vital needs, and that it is con­ sequently like a useful invention of which the individual avails him­ self to compensate for his incapacity to achieve subsistence by him­ self alone. But if reasons of this kind are all that is said in order to explain the necessity for living in society, clearly such an exposition gives to the doctrine of Saint Thomas a coloring of utilitarianism which it is very far from having. It is true, and Saint Thomas teaches it very explicitly, that the individual when isolated can do little or nothing to provide for his vital needs, and therefore requires the assistance of the others, organized in society, as a supplement to the deficiencies and limitations of his nature.1 The need for supplying these deficiencies is one of the reasons which, according to Saint Thomas, explain the appearance and existence of society. But man 1. Not only through the assistance of his fellows but also by use of his reason man procures that which animals obtain with the biological means with which they are by nature endowed: “Aliis animalibus natura praeparavit cibum, tegumenta pilorum, defensionem, ut dentes, cornua, ungues... Homo autem institutus est nullo horum sibi a natura praeparato, sed loco omnium data est ei ratio, per quam sibi haec omnia officio manuum posset praeparare, ad quae omnia praeparanda unus homo non sufficit, Nam unus homo per se sufficienter vitam transigere non posset. Est igitur homini naturale, 34 i j i ’ ) ‘ 5 THE CONTENT OF THE COMMON GOOD 35 needs the help and collaboration of his fellows not only in the lower order of the physical means necessary for the conservation of life,1 2 but also in the order of spiritual life; society is necessary for the moral and intellectual culture of man.3 But there is in the teaching of Saint Thomas a more profound rea­ son than all this to explain why man is a social animal. This reason is that the ultimate and radical foundation for life in society is man’s rational nature, not inasmuch as reason supplies him with those means of biological defense with which nature did not endow him, but formally because it constitutes him in his character as a person. The multiple forms of communication which social life implies are above all forms of the communication of intelligent beings. Only the person as such is made by nature to transcend itself in the manner of ration­ al intentionality, and only this transcending, thanks to which man can in a certain way open himself to others, makes him social in an authen­ tic sense, in the sense of participating consciously and voluntarily, with the inwardness of his person, in a common life. Saint Thomas, following Aristotle, remarks that the word, that is, the sound charged with intentionality, is proper to man alone, who is capable through it of communicating with his fellows in what is useful and in what is 1. (Continued) quod in societate multorum vivat." (De Reg., I, 1). Although Saint Thomas assigns to reason the role of a substitute for the biological means which man, unlike many irrational animals, does not pos­ sess, he does not, in the explanation of sociability as natural to man, reduce the function of reason to that of a mere instrument of biolog­ ical life. This will be shown later in this dissertation. 2. This is the sphere that could be called in modern terms “the divi­ sion of labor”: Saint Thomas refers to this in the following words: “Est igitur necessarium homini, quod in multitudine vivat, ut unus ab alio adjuvetur, et diversi diversis inveniendis per rationem oc­ cuparentur, puta, unus in medicina, alius in hoc, alius in alio.” (De Reg., I, 1). And in In Pol., I, 1,#17: “[civitas] componitur ex pluri­ bus vicis, in quorum uno exercetur ars fabrilis, in alio ars textoria, et sic de aliis. ” (]01n Eth., I, 1,#4: “juvatur homo a multitudine, cujus est pars, ad vitae sufficientiam perfectam; scilicet ut homo non solum vivat, sed et bene vivat, habens omnia quae sibi sufficiunt ad vitam: et sic homini auxiliatur multitudo civilis, cujus ipse est pars, non solum quantum ad corporalia... sed etiam quantum ad moralia.” In Pol., I, 1,#17: “ex ejus [civitatis] esse provenit, quod homines non solum vivant, sed quod bene vivant, inquantum per leges civi­ tatis ordinatur vita hominum ad virtutes." De Reg., I, 14: “Ad hoc homines congregantur, ut simul bene vivant, quod consequi non posset unusquisque singulariter vivens.” 36 THE CONTENT OF THE COMMON GOOD THE CONTENT OF THE COMMON GOOD 37 it is on the ground not of an insufficiency but, on the contrary, of an excellence of his nature that man forms a society with his fellows. It is to be remarked, however, that the insufficiencies which man overcomes by living in society, are due to the fact that personality is realized in him in the most imperfect degree. If the person is the most noble thing to be found in nature,8 it is from consideration of the concrete state of its realization in man, and not of the ratio itself of person, that Saint Thomas frequently says that man in several ways needs the society of others. Thus, for instance, he needs them for his intellectual and moral perfection,9 and for happiness in the present life.10 It is in this same sense that Saint Thomas can say that the diverse forms of human living together communicationes”), which will be surpassed in the future life, were instituted because of the in­ sufficiency of each one by itself.11 In sum, the existence of all social life is based upon two different orders of reasons: an order of rea­ 4. In Pol., I, l,#20: “loquutio est propria hominibus; quia hoc est pro- ; sons, on the one part, according to which society follows naturally from what is most formal in human nature, namely, its character as prium eis in comparatione ad alia animalia, quod habeant, cognitio­ person; on the other part, an order of reasons which are derived nem boni et mali, ita et injusti, et aliorum hujusmodi, quae sermone from the concrete condition and imperfect degree of realization of the significari possunt. Cum ergo homini datus sit sermo a natura, et ratio of the person in man and which are revealed in the insufficien­ sermo ordinetur ad hoc, quod homines sibi invicem communicent in cies that reach from the level of his animality to the core itself of his utili et nocivo, justo et injusto, et aliis hujusmodi; sequitur, ex quo natura nihil facit frustra, quod naturaliter homines in his sibi com­ moral and spiritual life: these latter reasons do not move man any municent. Sed communicatio in istis facit domum et civitatem. , less to association. harmful, in good and evil, in the just and the unjust. This is what causes a community to be, and what makes human social communica­ tion much more profound than, and in reality essentially different from, the association which is found among gregarious animals such as ants and bees.4 Much more: even on the supposition that the individual would not require the help of others to provide for his various needs, society would exist as a logical result of man’s rationality and spirit­ uality. For, inasmuch as the individual by his rational nature is cap­ able of communion with others in the knowledge and love of the same ends, of devotion to the good of the community more even than to his own life,5 of preferring life with others to living in solitude even should he lack nothing in that solitude,6 inasmuch--in brief--as he is capable of loving the good of the city secundum se, in order that it be preserv­ ed and diffused, and not in order that it may be of profit for himself,7 Igitur homo est naturaliter animal domesticum et civile.” Develop­ ing the same theme in the De Regimine Principum (I, 1), Saint Thomas concludes: “Magis igitur homo est communicativus alteri quam quodcumque aliud animal, quod gregale videtur, ut grus, for­ mica et apis. ” 5. I, 60, 5: “Naturaliter pars se exponit ad conservationem totius corporis... Et quia ratio imitatur naturam, hujusmodi imitationem invenimus in virtutibus politicis. Est enim virtuosi civis ut se ex­ ponat mortis periculo pro totius reipublicae conservatione." 6. In Pol., III, 5, #4: “homo naturaliter est animal civile; et ideo homines appetunt ad invicem vivere et non esse solitarii, etiam si in nullo unus alio indigeret ad hoc quod ducerent vitam civilem." 7. De Car., 2: “Amare bonum alicujus civitatis contingit dupliciter: uno modo ut habeatur; alio modo ut conservetur. Amare autem bonum alicujus civitatis ut habeatur et possideatur, non facit bonum politicum; ...quod est amare seipsum magis quam civitatem; sibi enim ipsi hoc bonum concupiscit, non civitati. Sed amare bonum civitatis ut conservetur et defendatur, hoc est vere amare civitatem, ...intantum quod aliqui propter bonum civitatis conservandum vel ampliandum, se periculis mortis exponant, et negligant privatum bonum.” --Owing to his limitations, however, the individual cannot help loving the common good with “love of concupiscence” (Cf. I, 60, 3), though loving it at the same time with “love of friendship.” 8. I, 29, 3: “Persona significat id quod est perfectissimum in tota natura, scilicet subsistens in rationali natura.” 9. Il-Il, 188, 8: “solitudo competit contemplanti, qui jam ad perfec­ tum pervenit. Quod quidem contingit dupliciter. Uno modo ex solo divino munere, sicut patet de Joanne Baptista... Alio modo per exercitium virtuosi actus... Ad exercitium hujusmodi juvatur homo ex aliorum societate dupliciter: uno modo quantum ad intel­ lectum, ut instruatur in is quae sunt contemplanda; ...Secundo quantum ad affectum, ut scilicet noxiae affectiones hominis repri­ mantur exemplo et correctione aliorum ... Et ideo vita socialis necessaria est ad exercitium perfectionis.” 1 10. I-II, 4, 8: “si loquamur de felicitate praesentis vitae,...felix indi­ get amicis, non quidem propter utilitatem, cum sit sibi sufficiens; 1 nec propter delectationem, quia habet in seipso delectationem per. fectam in operatione virtutis; sed propter bonam operationem, ut scilicet eis benefaciat, et ut eos inspiciens benefacere delectetur, et ut ab eis in benefaciendo juvetur. Indiget enim homo ad bene operandum auxilio amicorum tam in operibus vitae activae, quam ' in operibus vitae contemplativae.” i 11. Sent., Ill, 34, 3, 2, qla. 3, in 1: “hujusmodi [ad alterum) communi­ cationes non erunt in patria, quia omnes sufficientiam ibi a Deo i , accipient. Propter insufficientiam enim uniuscujusque in se intro* ductae sunt communications, ut patet per Philosophum in V Ethic." 38 THE CONTENT OF THE COMMON GOOD THE CONTENT OF THE COMMON GOOD Now, that total good which only civil society, “societas perfecta” and no other form of community, can give to man, is the one which at the same time succors the individual’s deficiencies and limitations and brings to realization the most noble human faculties. The two tenden­ cies, first of seeking in society a help and a supple ment and, second, of expressing and unfolding in it the excellences of the individual being, are like two aspects of the same imperfect human nature in search of its culmination and perfection in the possession of its high­ est object and good. What is this supreme good? Its nominal definition has already been mentioned; it is that which consists in living well, bene vivere. This is nothing else than the right exercise, according to reason, of man’s appetitive and cognitive faculties. And only such living pro­ duces “a life of true happiness and goodness.”12 But this supreme human good is the end of politics, the science which deals with the right arrangement of the city.13 On that account, “the good life” is the rule and measure of the common good of the city and the intelli­ gible key to its content. Consequently, society should be proportioned to that dual excel­ lence in which happiness consists: the good operation of reason itself, and the acts of the will as regulated by reason. Of these two aspects of the good which civil society offers to man, Saint Thomas never hesitates to assert that virtuous life is the superior; that living well is only living according to virtue;14 and, consequently, that the common good is primarily the moral health of society, the environment in which the individual begins and develops his own moral life, and in which one person helps another to live well. The common good is a vital store to which all virtuous men contribute, and from which all receive beneficent influx; it surrounds men, as it were, with an interchange of aids, examples and incentives for well doing. This good is the object of the city in such a way that only those who com­ municate mutually in living well deserve to be called parts of the city.1516 Such is the concept of the content of the common good which Saint Thomas expounds in unmistakable terms especially in the De Regimine | Principum, but which appears also quite clearly throughoutrevelant ( discussions in his other works. ! At this point a difficulty arises. It is well known that Saint Thomas, I following Aristotle, teaches the primacy of the contemplative life over ’ 12. Pol., Ill, 9, 1281 a I. 13. in Eth., I, 2, #29: “finis politicae est humanum bonum, idest optimus in rebus humanis." 14. De Reg., I, 14: “bona vita est secundum virtutem.” Ibid., 15: “virtus enim est qua bene vivitur.” Cf. I-II, 55, 4. 15. Ibid, I, 14: “hi soli partes sunt multitudinis congregatae, qui sibi invicem communicant in bene vivendo. ” i 1 . 39 the active, that happiness consists chiefly in the operation of specu­ lative reason, and that the intellectual virtues, which perfect reason, are more noble than the moral virtues, which perfect only the appe­ tite.18 How is it possible then that the common good of society, the only good which measures up to the supreme (naturali end of man, the good about which the same judgment must be formed as about the good of a single individual, how is it that this good is above all a mor ­ al good, a life according to virtue and according to moral virtue, which is the most proper meaning of this latter word?17 The answer is that, although the intellectual virtues--and with them the contemplative life--are more noble, because of their object, than the moral virtues, yet the moral virtues are more necessary for human life, and it is only by reason of them that a man can be called good simpliciter. A man is not called good because he is learned.18 Moreover, the final cause of society is, according to Saint Thomas, a moral end: in the De Regimine Principum, while surveying the ends which may move men to congregate in society, he says that it is not the knowledge of truth—nor corporal health nor the acquisition of wealth—but living virtuously, which moves men to attain through virtue their fruition in God: Idem autem oportet esse judicium de fine totius multitudinis, et unius. ...si quidem talis ultimus sive unius hominis, sive mul­ titudinis finis esset corporalis, vita et sanitas corporis, medici esset officium. Si autem ultimus finis esset divitiarum affluen­ tia, oeconomus rex quidam multitudinis esset. Si vero bonum cognoscendae veritatis tale quid esset, ad quod posset multitudo pertingere, rex haberet doctoris officium. Videtur autem finis esse multitudinis congregatae vivere secundum virtuten. Ad hoc enim homines congregantur, ut simul bene vivant; ...bona autem 16. I-II, 66, 3, Sed contra: “Virtus moralis est in rationali per parti cipationem; virtus autem intellectualis in rationali per essen­ tiam... Ergo virtus intellectualis est nobilior virtute morali.” (in II-II, 182, 1, following Aristotle in Eth., X, 7 and 8, Saint Thomas sets forth reasons why the contemplative life is better than the active). 17. I-II, 66, 3: “quia virtus dicitur ex eo, quod est principium alicujus actus, cum sit perfectio potentiae, sequitur quod ratio virtutis magis competat virtutibus moralibus, quam virtutibus intellectuali­ bus.” 18. I-II, 66, 3, ad 2: “secundum virtutes morales dicitur homo bonus simpliciter, et non secundum intellectuales virtutes, ea ratione qua appetitus movet alias potentias ad suum actum." I-II, 56, 3: “non dicitur simpliciter aliquis homo bonus ex hoc, quod est sciens, vel artifex, sed dicitur bonus solum secundum quid, puta bonus grammaticus, aut bonus faber.” 40 THE CONTENT OF THE COMMON GOOD THE CONTENT OF THE COMMON GOOD vita est secundum virtutem. (...) Sed ...homo vivendo secundum virtutem ad ulteriorem finem ordinatur, qui consistit in fruitione divina.19 In recognizing the preeminence of moral virtue in the content of the common good Saint Thomas does not contradict his doctrine of the primacy of contemplation. Rather he sets forth this doctrine as valid ' in the natural order and he insists that there could not be lasting so­ cial good without the knowledge of truth and the profession of wisdom. But Saint Thomas reserves the complete realization of the superiority of contemplation for the supernatural life in Heaven, in which alone man attains his highest beatitude, which is the contemplation of God.20 Virtuous life is necessary for man in this life, precisely for obtain­ ing possession of God in the next. There is no doubt, on the other hand, that the contemplation of truth has an essential part in the con­ stitution of the common good, and that the common good cannot per­ dure in a society which professes fundamental errors with regard to man’s nature, his destiny and his situation in the universe. The multitude’s living properly and according to virtue is, above all, what defines the common good for Saint Thomas. Although it is true that this expression comprehends in reality diverse levels of the good organized in a hierarchical order of means and ends - as will be explained later in this chapter - the living well of the city is the highest and determinative level of the total content of the common good; it is the common good par excellence, and the end to which are ultimately subordinated all the other goods which in some way may be called common to the city. Social institutions of every kind, and corporeal possessions have worth and are justified only insofar as each of them in some way within its own sphere, corresponds to, or con­ tributes toward the existence, preservation and promotion of the city’s good moral condition. Before showing in detail that this is the central idea in Saint Thomas’ conception of the content of the common good, it is well to explain briefly the sources of that conception in Aristotle. Repeated­ ly and unequivocally the Philosopher says that the true end for which the polis is instituted is not mere living but living well.21 And in pas­ sages which constitute an advance rebuttal to social theories promin­ ent in the last three centuries, he states that “it is not the end of the state to provide an alliance for mutual defense against all injury, or to ease exchange and promote economic intercourse.*22 Nor is it the 19- De Reg., I, 14. 20. S.c.G., III, 37: "ultima felicitas hominis non consistit nisi in con­ templatione Dei.” 21. Pol., I, 2, 1252 b 30. Cf. Ibid., Ill, 9, passim. 22. Pol., Ill, 9, 1280 a 35. , 1 | ‘ 41 end of the polis simply to prevent injustices in the course of inter change with other nations, as cities which trade among themselves du. This intercourse through trade does not constitute these communities, a single city, since they have neither laws nor magistrates in com­ mon, and “neither of the parties concerns itself to ensure a proper quality of character among the members of the other; neither of them seeks to ensure that all who are included in the scope of the treaties shall be free from injustice and from any form of vice.”23 With this distinction Aristotle clearly implies that the end of every true state is the proper living of its members according to a high quality of character and virtue. And the conclusion explicitly stated is that “any polis which is truly so called, and is not merely one in name, must devote itself to the end of encouraging goodness.”24 But to attain this state of affairs is to realize happiness, which is “the energy and prac­ tice of goodness.*25 For Aristotle, then, it is evident that this excel­ lence is the supreme end of the polis. Whence it follows that in order to attain this high state of happiness, mutual help, the communication of friendship among men, is necessary, because however noble the form of life a man may lead he never succeeds in becoming wholly self-sufficient; even the philosopher may need companions in the very contemplation of truth; and in any case the virtuous man requires per­ sons toward whom and for whom he may exercise his virtue.26 As a faithful interpreter of Aristotle’s thought, Saint Thomas makes these ideas central points in his philosophic speculation on the nature and end of society and on its political regime. In his Commentary on the Politics he expounds in the following terms what may be con­ sidered a full and clear definition of civil society: “Civitas enim est communicatio bene vivendi composita ex generibus diversis et gratia vitae perfectae et per se sufficientis. Hoc autem est vivere feliciter: bene autem vel feliciter vivere in politicis, est operari secundum optiman virtutem practice.*27 The unity and thereby the being of the city depend solely on the communication of several families in the common purpose of proper living; it is neither military alliances nor trade pacts of any kind which make a city one. The two causes which specifically define the constitution of a being are the formal and the * i Ibid., 1280 b 2. Ibid., 1280 b 6. Ibid·.VU» 13> a 8· Eth., X, 7, 1177 a 32: “The just man needs people towards whom and with whom he shall act justly, and the temperate man, the brave man...but the philosopher, even when by himself, can con­ template truth, and the better the wiser he is; he can perhaps do so better if he has fellow-workers, but still he is the most selfsufficient." 27. In Pol., Ill, 7 ,#14. 23. 24. 25· 26. 42 THE CONTENT OF THE COMMON GOOD THE CONTENT OF THE COMMON GOOD 43 Thus, the good ruler as such is capable of discerning the good and the final; and, Saint Thomas observes, for society these two causes are eril, the just and the unjust, the profitable and the harmful, not only respectively the communication in living well, “communicatio bene for himself but also for the whole of a community; and so is capable vivendi,” and the intending of the perfect life, “gratia vitae perfec­ tae.”28 In Chapter 14 of Book I of De Regimine Principii m—one of the ! of presiding over the others. The man well endowed for ruling is he who hy the high perfection of his moral virtues ---interlocked and barmost important sources for the thought of Saint Thomas on the end and good of society—he states that the good king should chiefly see to J monized by prudence--is capable of directing the moral conduct of the community under his care. If the good ruler then is the one who it that the multitude subject to him leads a good life; and this solici­ can habitually give good moral precepts, the good which he secures tude should extend not only to instituting the proper living of the mul­ for the community through good government will consist formally in titude, but also to preserving what has been instituted, and to cease­ its good moral condition. For Aristotle—and for Saint Thomas, who lessly perfecting what has been preserved. And in agreement with adopted this conception and developed it in a Christian sense in his Aristotle, he writes that the true motive for congregating into a so­ ciety is not mere living and attending to the needs of physical life; De Regimine Principum--the ruler is a sort of moral leader, a wise nor is it the securing of wealth—otherwise, all merchants would be­ and prudent man who by his virtue towers over the rest and is, thus, long to a single society.29 The criterion for judging the goodness of the one best fitted to guide them along the paths of moral life. The virtue of the one who not only governs himself but can also govern political systems is precisely the degree in which they are apt to at- , tain the virtuous life of the city; and according to this the two best ( others is accordingly of a surpassing excellence. If greater virtue is systems simpliciter are royalty and aristocracy, because they are di­ required for ruling the household family than for governing oneself, rectly ordained to and fitted for such purpose.30 much greater must be the virtue necessary for the rule of a whole Even if Saint Thomas did not frequently state that the end of the city or a kingdom. Exercising properly the king’s office requires city is the virtuous life, his insistence that the ruler be a “vir bonus” therefore an outstanding virtue, the more so if one considers that the would sufficiently intimate this thought. Politics is an art which I doing of a greater good demands a greater virtue; but the good of the requires a high species of prudence, and so the good ruler will be a [ community is precisely better and more divine than that of an indivi­ man endowed with prudence to an extraordinary degree--and there; dual.32 In conclusion, the good legislator is he who is engaged in mak­ fore virtuous without qualification, since it is according to prudence, j ing his subjects virtuous; and law is nothing else than the precepts of upon which all moral virtues depend, that a man is said to be virtuous.31 i the virtuous man who presides over the community. Now, Aristotle says that the virtue of the good citizen consists 28. Ibid., #13: “per hoc quod [Philosophus] dicit, ‘communicatio bene precisely in his observance of the constitution and the laws under vivendi,’ innuit causam formalem; ...per hoc quod dicit ‘gratia which he lives; his virtue is therefore relative to those laws.33 The vitae perfectae etc.’ tangit causam finalem. ” just man, on the other hand, is called just on account of an absolute 29. De Reg., I, 14: “Si propter acquirendas divitias [homines conven­ excellence, which is superior and prior to any written law, and not irent], omnes simul negotiantes ad unam civitatem pertinerent: sicut videmus eos solos sub una multitudine computari, qui sub eisdem legibus et eodem regimine diriguntur ad bene vivendum.” 30. In Pol., III, 16, #7; “cum sint tres politiae recte ordinatae, ... illa inter alia optima est, quae regitur et dispensatur ab optimo viro vel ab optimis viris, quia ad optimum finem ordinatur: sem­ per enim quod fit ab optimo agente, ad optimum finem ordinatur per se.” Ibid., IV, I,#8: “Adhue consideratum est in praecedenti­ bus de regno et de statu optimatum. Idem enim est considerare de his quae significantur per ista nomina et de optima politia: utraque enim istarum duarum intendit principaliter in finem, qui est secundum virtutem, et ad ipsam virtutem multam et perfectam existentis. ” 31. In Pol., III, 3, #1: “aliquis dicitur virtuosus secundum unam virtu­ tem perfectam, scilicet secundum prudentiam, ex qua omnes vir­ Non dicitur tutes morales dependent. ” And further on (ibid., #2): 31. Continued. aliquis esse bonus princeps, nisi sit bonus per virtutes morales et prudens. Dictum est enim in sexto Ethicorum quod politia est quaedam pars prudentiae; unde oportet politicum, idest rectorem politiae, esse prudentem, et per consequens bonum virum.” 32. De Reg., I, 9: “Est praecipua virtus, qua homo aliquis non solum se ipsum, sed etiam alios dirigere potest ...Sic igitur major vir­ tus requiritur ad regendum domesticam familiam, quam ad regen­ dum se ipsum, multoque major ad regimen civitatis et regni. Est igitur excellentis virtutis bene regium officium exercere” ... (··.)· “majoris virtutis esse videtur quod majus bonum per eam aliquis operetur. Majus autem et divinius est bonum multitudinis quam bonum unius." 33. Pol., ΙΠ, 4, 1276 b 30: “the virtue of the citizen must be relative to the constitution of which he is a member." 44 THE CONTENT OF THE COMMON GOOD THE CONTENT OF THE COMMON GOOD 46 relative to any constitution; this excellence is virtue without qualifi­ Now, even in the case in which the virtue of each and every citizen cation. This is the reason for the distinction made by Aristotle be­ does.not realize perfectly the ideal of virtuous life which the system tween a good man and a good citizen. The Philosopher wonders proposes, there will always be an equivalence between the rommon whether the excellence of the just man and that of the good citizen are good which a city attains and the virtues of the citizens composing it. identical or different; and his answer is that, because the citizen as This equivalence consists of this, that the moral atmosphere in the such is a part of the city, his virtue is defined with regard to the city—the common good in its noblest aspect--depends materially on politia or constitution according to which he lives; but tnai politia such virtues. The countenance of the common good depends on fTie may not be the best. But in defining the virtue of the good man simplivirtue of the members making up the city, although ordy with the de­ citer there is no reference at all to a special political system, but pendence of material causality. The reason for this is, first, that as only to the absolute criteria of virtue. The good citizen's excellence ) regards its nature the happiness of a man and that of the city are of is identical with the good ruler’s only when the citizen in the best the same ratio;36 and second, that the actions of an individual redound system possible has the virtue which would be required both for ruling in some way upon the social whole of which he is a part. Society is a and for being ruled. In such a system, which would be the only one composed whole and depends therefore, in a material way, to a high adequate for a community of free men, one man or several exercise degree on its parts; and the action of the parts has an influence upon government not despotically, in the manner in which the master exer­ the whole.37 In the intention of its author an action may well not be cises it over the slave, but politically, that is, over free and equal directed to the good or evil of another individual or of society; never­ people, who are capable both of governing, and of being governed by, theless, objectively, that is to say, in consideration of the finis opecis, their equals.34 This thesis means that only in the best system is it it redounds directly or indirectly to the good or evil of society. For possible for the excellence of the just man and that of the good citizen this reason the life of the just conserves and promotes the common to coincide, for only in such a regime is the bene vivere in all its full­ good, because they are the principal part of the multitude; they are ness the ideal of common life embodied in the constitution. Saint that part of the social whole which realizes most perfectly the city’s Thomas makes these theses his, but, with Aristotle, he warns that ( end and which with its virtue produces, conserves and promotes the even in the best city it is nevertheless impossible that all the citizens good moral environment which spreads its benefit to the whole multi­ be equally virtuous, or even simply virtuous; but for the good of the ) tude.38 city it suffices that each one does well what falls to him as a part of ' But if the common good depends, chiefly in the order of material the social whole. Yet even with these exceptions, it is always true causality, upon private virtues, private virtues are submitted in turn that only in the best system is it possible for the virtue of the good [ to the common good as to their final cause: “bonum partis est propter citizen as such to coincide perfectly with that of the honest man.35 i bonum totius,”39*“bonitas cujuslibet partis consideratur in proportione 34. Cf. Pol., III, 4, passim. What is expounded in the text is the substance of Aristotle’s thesis developed in this chapter of the Politics. ' 35. In Pol., Ill, 3, #1 : “Contingit aliquem esse bonum civem, qui tamen non habet virtutem secundum quam aliquis est bonus vir; et hoc in politiis quae sunt praeter optimam politiam... (...) impossibile est, quantumcumque sit bona politia, quod omnes cives sint virtuosi: ) sed tamen oportet quod unuscuisque faciat opus suum quod ad civitatem pertinet, bene... in optima politia oportet quod quilibet ! civis habeat virtutem boni civis. Per hunc enim modum civitas ( erit optima: sed virtutem boni viri, impossibile est quod omnes habeant.” However, in another place (In Eth., V, 3, #926) Saint Thomas writes thus: “Sunt enim quaedam politiae, non rectae, secundum quas aliquis potest esse civis bonus, qui non est vir I bonus; sed secundum optimam politicam non est aliquis civis bonus, qui non est vir bonus. ” This text identifies the virtue of every citizen with that of the good man in the optimum system; the text quoted from the Commentary on the Politics maintains | > / ί ' 35. Continued the distinction between the two. The position exposed in the last work seems to be the one which is truly representative of Aristotle’s thought--and Saint Thomas' as well--since a little earlier in the Commentary on the Ethics it is announced that this theme will be treated in the Politics. The Ethics speaks rather casually about what is examined closely in the Politics. 36. De Reg., I, 14: “Idem oportet esse judicium de fine totius multi­ tudinis et unius." 37. J-Π, 21, 3: “unusquisque in aliqua societate vivens est aliquo modo pars, et membrum totius societatis; quicumque ergo agit aliquid in bonum, vel malum alicujus in societate existentis, hoc redundat in totam societatem: sicut qui laedit manum, per consequens laedit hominem.” 38. II-II, 64, 6: “Vita justorum est conservativa et promotiva boni communis, quia ipsi sunt principalior pars multitudinis.” 39. I-Π, 1°9’ 46 THE CONTENT OF THE COMMON GOOD THE CONTENT OF THE COMMON GOOD 47 virtue,44 but also indicate the circumstances in which that act should ad suum totum.”40 Thus, private virtues are referable to the common be executed. Furthermore, it can also occur that an act. which, abs­ good in two ways: either as integral parts of it, in the measure in tractly considered according to its kind, is morally excellent ought which each virtue is a good; or as subject to the rule which an end common to the virtues imposes upon them. Under the first aspect, to i not however to be executed hic et nunc, because, in view of the conbe referable to the common good means to contribute to the constitu­ j crete circumstances, the common good requires otherwise. Contemting and increase of the good of the whole society; it might be said that j plation, for example, is superior by its very essence, simpliciter, to virtue then acquires one more title of justification, namely, that which ! active life, but general justice can, nevertheless, in consideration of is derived from its being thus a positive contribution to the common the particular circumstances in a given situation--in cases of extreme good; (its other title is the value which it has by itself, in its sub­ disturbance of public life, for instance--decide that it is more accorstance or content as virtue). It is also under this aspect that the com­ ) ding to virtue to cease contemplating and to come to the rescue of mon good, in its most elevated form, may be considered materially one’s fellow-beings in their spiritual and temporal needs.45 It falls, (materialiter) equivalent to the virtues of the good men, in the sense thus, to general justice to so intervene in the very exercise of virtues in which a society is what its component elements make it. According as to demand such exercise, to regulate it, and even to suspend it in to the other viewpoint, for virtues to be referable to the common good favor of a different act of more immediate urgency. If the species of means that the common good, as the end of all virtues, demands the ■ a virtue and its particular acts are not distinguished the role of gen­ acts of all as something which is owed to it, and adapts to its exigen- | eral justice and its relation to the common good cannot be under­ cies the exercise of the virtuous life. In accordance with its essence, | stood. The expressions which Saint Thomas uses are very explicit re­ every virtue orders its act to its proper end; but it does not belong to | garding this distinction. the essence of a virtue to be ordered to an ulterior end.41 This ulter- i If the acts of all the virtues are the matter or field of application ior ordering of the acts of all the other virtues to the good of society ; of general justice, it follows that general justice has an architectonic is carried out by legal, or general, justice.42 The goodness of an act I character, for it embraces the entire domain of doing secundum virtu­ of virtue does not depend entirely on its species, but also on some| tem and determines the how, the when, and the other circumstances of thing else which is added to the species as circumstances necessary j the virtuous acts, according to a general order or plan and in consid­ for the rectitude of the act.43 By reason of what is owed to the good of eration of the good of the political community. In an architectonic the social whole, general justice may not only demand a certain act of !■. way, general justice exists par excellence in the ruler; but it exists also in the citizen, although"only secondarily, namely, insofar as the citizen contributes actively and of his own inclination to the realization 40. I-II, 92, I, ad 3. of this general order, in conforming his conduct to what the ruler has 41. II-II, 58, 6, ad 4: “quaelibet virtus secundum propriam rationem prescribed for the common good.46 In an analogous way, prudence is ordinat actum suum ad proprium finem illius virtutis; quod autem also architectonic in the ruler, since it is his function as such to coun­ ordinetur ad ulteriorem finem, sive semper, sive aliquando, hoc sel, to judge and to rule rightly concerning those means through which non habet ex propria ratione." 42. II-II, 58, 5: “pars id quod est, totius est; unde et quodlibet bonum partis est ordinabile in bonum totius. Secundum hoc ergo bonum cujuslibet virtutis, sive ordinantis aliquem hominem ad seipsum sive ordinantis ipsum ad aliquas alias personas singulares, est referibile ad bonum commune, ad quod ordinatur justitia. Et secundum hoc actus omnium virtutum possunt ad justitiam pertin­ ere, secundum quod ordinat hominem ad bonum commune. Et quantum ad hoc justitia dicitur virtus generalis.” 43. I-II, 18, 3: “plenitudo bonitatis ejus [actionis] non tota consistit in sua specie, sed aliquid additur ex his, quae adveniunt tamquam accidentia quaedam: et hujusmodi sunt circumstantiae debitae: unde si aliquid desit, quod requiratur ad debitas circumstantias, erit actio mala. ” 44. II-II, 58, 6: “justitia legalis dicitur esse virtus generalis, inquan­ tum scilicet ordinat actus aliarum virtutum ad suum finem, quod est movere per imperium omnes alias virtutes.” 45. II-II, 182, 1 ad 3: “ad opera vitae activae interdum aliquis a con­ templatione avocatur propter aliquam necessitatem praesentis vitae.” Sent., III, 35, 1, 4, sol. 1: “Vita contemplativa non ordina­ tur ad aliquid aliud in ipso in quo est; quia vita aeterna non est nisi quaedam consummatio contemplativae vitae...; unde non restat quod ordinetur ad aliud, nisi secundum quod bonum unius hominis ordinatur ad bonun^ multorum, ad quod propinquius se habet vita activa quam contemplativa." 46. II-II, 58, 6: “[justitia legalis] est in principe principaliter, et quasi architectionice; in subditis autem secundarie, et quasi administrative. ’’ 48 THE CONTENT OF THE COMMON GOOD J the good of the community under his care is attained. Political pru­ dence exists in the ruler in an outstanding degree; in the .abject, in a lower degree and as an auxiliary to the prudence of the prince.4748 49 Political prudence in its most excellent form, the prurience which rules, the regnatiya, is one of the bases for general justice, inasmuch as it utters the practical judgment according to which the will, the seat of justice, moves all the virtues to the common good fi Saint Thomas says that general justice may be had without virtue in common and virtue in common may be had without general justice, for they are not essentially the same: “non est eadem justitia genera­ lis cum virtute communi; sed una potest sine alia haberi.'J’ ft does not seem that they can in fact be had one without the other except in the lower and initial state of virtuous life, or in regimes which pur­ sue an ideal of life which is not the best and most perfect. In such cases it may be that the citizens will have the virtue of générai justice, inasmuch as they accommodate their conduct to the requirements of the common good in that particular regime, and yet they may not be purely and simply virtuous men. But, on the contrary, it is impos­ sible that general justice and virtue in common do not coexist in the ruler, because the virtue of the prince and that of the good man are i one and the same:50 as a ruler, he should possess general justice in s its highest degree; but it is only through the aggregate of all the vir| tues that he is a good man. In the same way that good citizen and good \ man are identified at the apex of the city’s life—in the ruler of the I best regime—so, at that apex and there only do the highest virtue and j the fullest general justice join and sustain each other mutually. The meaning of these two distinctions51 and of their final resolution to unity at the peak of the community is that there is among the total of the virtuous acts and the exigencies of the common good a growing j assimilation, which reaches the point of absolute identification in the : one who presides over the best of the politias. In the just man, ' 47. II-II, 47, 10: “prudentia non solum se habet ad bonum privatum unius hominis, sed etiam ad bonum commune multitudinis, ” Ibid., 50, 2, ad 2: “Eadem agenda considerantur quidem a rege secun- J dum unix'ersaliorem rationem quam considerentur a subdito, qui obedit...Et ideo regnativa comparatur ad hanc politicam, de qua loquimur, sicut ars architectonica ad eam, quae manu operatur.” 48. II-II, 47, 10 ad 1: “sic se habet prudentia politica ad justitiam legalem, sicut se habet prudentia simpliciter dicta ad virtutem moralem. ” 49. II-II, 58, 6, Sed contra, 50. In Pol., Ill, 3, #4: “virtus boni viri est quae est virtus boni principis/’"' 51. These two distinctions are: between the “bonus civis” and the “bonus vir,” and between virtue in common and general justice. I f ! ( / i ) ! Î ' THE CONTENT OF THE COMMON GOOD -19 virtue tends, upon becoming more perfect, to coincide more and n.orp with the requirements of the common good, as intimated by in.? gcner al justice. At the same time, the citizen whose viriue has come to I coincide with the virtue of the good man, becomes worthy to smern I and preside over the others. ; And there is evidence more cogent that general justice cannot in I tact be possessed without the other virtues, nor the virtues without general justice, at least beyond a certain degree of perfection in the I virtuous life. For the effect of law is, according to Saint Thomas, to cause men to be good; but law contains precisely the precepts of general justice. The actions prescribed by general, or legal, justice resuit therefore in virtuous life. Just ice is called general when it orders the acts of all the virtues to the common good, and since orderbig to the common good belongs to law, general justice may be also called legal,52 because through it man conforms with the law which orders his acts to such an end. Thus, the theme of law appears in close relation with the common good and general justice. As noted above, the effect of the law is to cause men to be good. This is Saint Thomas’ reasoning: the law is a judgment of the ruler’s practical reason, and the virtue of the subject or citizen consists in obeying that judgment. And as laws are given to be ooeyed, it follows that it is a property of the law to induce those subject to it, to exercise that virtue which pertains to them, namely, to obey the law. And virtue being by definition that which causes the one possessing it to be good, the effect of law will be to make good those subject to it. (That goodness, however, can be an authentic goodness, or it can be merely the habit of adjusting oneself to a law which has for end, not the common good such as natural and divine laws call for, but the mere profit or pleasure of the legislator, or even what conflicts with God’s law; a man can thus be called a good thief, inasmuch as he observes the rules of his trade. It can also happen that the law in question is not the one of the best or regimes, but rather, for example, the law of the “status popularis.” In such cases, the law certainly does not cause men to be good simpliciter and according to virtue, but only secundum quid).53 But when the 52. II-II, 58, 5: “actus omnium virtutum possunt ad justitiam pertinere, secundum quod ordinat hominem ad bonum commune; et quantum ad hoc justitia dicitur virtus generalis; et quia ad legem pertinet ordinare in bonum commune, ...inde est, quod talis justitia, praedicto modo generalis, dicitur justitia legalis; quia scilicet per eam homo concordat legi ordinanti actus omnium virtutum in bonum commune.” 53. I-II, 92, 1: “lex nihil aliud est, quam dictamen rationis in praesidente, quo subditi gubernantur. Cujuslibet autem subditi virtus est, ut bene subdatur ei, a quo gubernatur... Et per hunc modum j ’ I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I t [ / I I I I I I I I .■ ■ ■ I I ■ B ■ B H H B B B M B B B 50 THE CONTENT OF THE COMMON GOOD effect of the law is to produce virtue in men simpliciter - that is, in accordance with the precepts of natural and divine laws - it is pre­ cisely then that the end which the law proposes is at the same time the common good in its highest genuine form - although with the re­ striction, already mentioned, that perfect virtue in those who govern and the mere obedience of citizens to the mandates suffice for the good of the community. It has been said53 54 that Saint Thomas has developed two theses on the end of law - that law is for the common good,55 that law is for the happiness of the individual person - that these theses are in conflict, and that Saint Thomas either did not find or did not expound the form­ ula of their reconciliation. But this is not a question of the end of the law, but rather a question of the two different aspects under which the law’s end may be considered; and these aspects are perfectly compatible with each other. Furthermore, the ambivalent character of the end of the law shows that the common good in the mind of Saint Thomas is a condition and at the same time a result of the happiness 53. Continued virtus cujuslibet subjecti est, ut bene subjiciatur principanti, ut Philosophus dicit in I.Polit. Ad hoc autem ordinatur unaquaeque lex, ut obediatur ei a subditis; unde manifestum est, quod hoc sit proprium legis, inducere subjectos ad propriam ipsorum virtu­ tem. Cum igitur virtus sit,‘quae facit bonum habentem,’sequitur quod proprius effectus legis sit bonos facere eos, quibus datur, vel simpliciter, vel secundum quid. Si enim intentio ferentis legem tendat in verum bonum, quod est bonum commune secun­ dum justitiam divinam regulatum, sequitur quod per legem hom­ ines fiant boni simpliciter. Si vero intentio legislatoris feratur ad id, quod non est bonum simpliciter, sed utile, vel delectabile sibi, vel repugnans justitiae divinae; tunc lex non bonos facit homines simpliciter, sed secundum quid, scilicet in ordine ad tale regimen. Sic autem bonum invenitur etiam in per se malis; sicut aliquis dicitur bonus latro, quia operatur accomode ad finem. " 54. In the Bulletin de Théologie Ancienne et Médiévale, II, #418, (1933-36), Dom O. Lottin, O.S.B., writes thus: “Quand, dans la2ae, q. 90, a. 2, S. Thomas se demande utrum lex ordinetur sem­ per ad bonum commune, on voit clairement dans sa réponse se juxtaposer les deux solutions : l’une individualiste (la loi est faite pour acheminer l'homme à sa fin dernière, la béatitude person­ nelle, si fermement établie au début de la Ia-2ae), l’autre sociale (la partie est faite pour le tout). II faut se demander jusqu’à quel point la synthèse a été faite par S. Thomas et donc si, dans sa pensée, la première solution est subordonée a la seconde." 55. I-II, 90, 4: “flexj nihil est aliud, quam quaedam rationis ordinatio ad bonum commune, ab eo, qui curam communitatis habet, promul­ gata. ” THE CONTENT OF THE COMMON GOOD 51 which those persons who participate in the common good attain by living virtuously. The question is rather whether Saint Thomas really believed that the two viewpoints differed so much as to require a formula of conciliation. It does not seem that he did. Still, the diffi­ culty which this dualism might involve was removed in advance when Saint Thomas says that the law’s effects are to cause men to be good. One of the objections in that article states: that the law is given with respect to the common good; but there are some who, behaving fitly in that which pertains to the common good, conduct themselves badly ' in matters of their own private good; consequently, it does not belong to the law to make men good.56 Saint Thomas answers that, on the one hand, the goodness of each component element is considered in relation to its whole, so that for the part to be really good it must be measured by the good of the whole; but the whole, on the other hand, cannot exist properly except through parts proportionate to it. Again he answers that in a community in which either the whole citizenry, or at least those who rule, are not virtuous, there cannot be a com­ mon good.57 There is, therefore, as observed above, an interdepen­ dence between the whole and its parts, between the common good and the virtues of the citizens. In this interrelation, however, the charac­ ter of the dependence is not the same for each term. The good of the whole depends on the good of the parts in a way similar to the way in which a body depends, for its being, on its integral parts. On the other hand, the perfection, in each concrete case, of the virtuous ac­ tivity of each citizen comes from the accommodation of his conduct to the prescriptions of the law for the common good. The specific distinction between the common good and the individual good (here understood as the life of virtue) is not made principally on the ground of the matter which causes the common good to be good. That matter is, so to speak, virtuous matter for both kinds of good, and thus in that matter a high individual virtue and the common good par i • i ( 56. I-II, 92, 1, obj. 3: “Lex ordinatur ad bonum commune...; sed quidam bene se habent in his, quae ad commune pertinet, qui ta­ men in propriis non bene se habent; non ergo ad legem pertinet, quod faciat homines bonos.” 57. Ibid., ad 3: “bonitas cujuslibet partis consideratur in proportione ad suum totum; ...cum igitur quilibet homo sit pars civitatis, im­ possibile est, quod aliquis homo sit bonus, nisi sit bene proportionatus bono communi: nec totum potest bene existere, nisi ex partibus sibi proportionatis; unde impossibile est, quod bonum commune civitatis bene se habeat, nisi cives sint virtuosi, ad minus illi, quibus convenit principari. Sufficit autem quantum ad bonum communitatis, quod alii intantum sint virtuosi, quod principum mandatis obediant. ” 52 THE CONTENT OF THE COMMON GOOD THE CONTENT OF THE COMMON GOOF 53 excellence come to coincide. Society and the individual are rather to moral law. Some less grave vices, faults and sins are to be iid.erabe opposed on the ground of other categories of the good, such as the ted by human law, which prohibits only the vices which are most sei existence of the individual and all that relates more or less directly ions and those which, if left unrestrained, could endanger the very ex­ to this existence. In this order there can be, and often are, cases of istence of society.6061 62Therefore, human law must try to induce men t I .1 I j Ί I 60 THE CONTENT OF THE COMMON GO. Hl THE CONTENT OF THE COMMON GOOD sense which is surely authentic, but yet different from (he sense according to which the common good is synonymous with· roe common happiness of the multitude. Justice is an authentic cmmnon good be­ cause inasmuch as it is realized within a society, it consists in the good social organization on the basis of what is due to each part andto the whole, and such a social condition is a good for ail the members of that society. Justice in this way proves to be an element of the allembracing common good of society; and it is such an element, both in its character as an upright external operation of the individuals and, mainly and formally, when it insures to the community a certain number of moral conditions without which the community could not survive. This interpretation agrees with Saint Thomas' teaching that the intention of the legislator is directed first and primarily to the conimon good and secondly to the order of justice and virtue, bv means of which the common happiness is achieved.81 In speaking of peace and justice, one cannot fail to mention friendship. Whereas justice is essential as a foundation for any right soI cial structure, and is measured in accordance with the things by means of which persons are related, friendship manifests itself I rather in the mutual benevolence which normally arises among those I who are united under any form of grouping or any common possession I (“communicatio”) ,35 As a sentiment of this kind, friendship facilitates I the cohesion of all who are in the group. To each type of communiI catio, from the most simple to the largest and most comprehensive, I which is civil society, there corresponds a different sort of friendship. I 64. Ι-Π, 100, 8: “intentio legislatoris cujuslibet ordinatur primo quidem et principaliter ad bonum commune; secundo autem ad ordinem justitiae, et virtutis, secundum quem bonum commune conservatur, et ad ipsum pervenitur.” Cf. I-II, 100, 9 ad 2: “intentio legislatoris est de duobus: de uno quidem, ad quod intendit per praecepta legis induce re : et hoc est virtus; aliud autem est, de quo intendit praeceptum ferre: et hoc est, quod ducit, vel disponit ad virtutem, scilicet actus virtutis; non enim idem est finis praecepti, et id de quo praeceptum datur; sicut neque in aliis rebus idem est finis, et quod est ad finem.” - The inclusion of virtue with justice in this passage means that virtue can be a subject matter for the law, and in such a case it becomes an object of legal justice. The “order of justice and virtue” is then the same as the total content of the positive law. 85. Π-Π, 23, I; “non quilibet amor habet rationem amicitiae, sed amor qui est cum bene volentia; quando scilicet sic amamus aliquem ut ei bonum velimus... Sed nec benevolentia sufficit ad rationem amicitiae, sed requiritur quaedam mutua amatio, quia amicus est amico amicus. Talis autem mutua benevolentia fundatur super aliqua communicatione. ” for instance, the friendship which unites fellow-soldiers .is aifferent from the one which links the members of a family, and this friendship differs, in turn, from the friendship which unites fellow-citizens.’** Each communicatio (xoivovm, for Aristotle) proves to he, in its dual character as an interrelation of individuals and as the special feeiingof friendliness which unites them in the group, a specific and I more or less complex unit both of the structure and of the functionI ing of the social organism. In general, friendship is a manifestation of the natural sociability (“omnis homo naturaliter omni honiini est amicus”)86 87 by means of which men constitute their communities; but itisalsoa conscientious and voluntary cultivation of this human tendency. Considered in this latter sense, friendship is a virtue, and its acts are owed to the other persons on account of the delight which it affords and which is necessary for man’s life?’8 This is why friendship, with the affection it generates, completes and perfects in a sense the work performed by strict justice. But whereas friendship is essentially personal, justice is impersonal by nature, since ii. depends on certain proportions among things and makes no acceptance of persons.89 Finally, it can be said of friendship, as of peace, that it is rather the result of virtue than itself a virtue.90 On a level lower than that of intersocial relations--justice, peace, friendship, etc.--and subordinated to them are the things required in the third place, according to the De Regimine, for the good living of 86. In Eth., VIII, 9, #1661: “ostendit [Philosophus] diversitatem amicitiarum secundum diversitatem communicationis. Videmus enim quod fratribus et personis ita conjunctis sunt omnia communia, puta domus, mensa et alia hujusmodi. Aliis autem amicis sunt quaedam discreta. Et quibusdam plura et quibusdam pauciora. ” Cf. Eth., VIII, 9, 1159 b 27. 87. II-II, 114, 1 , ad 2. 88. II-II, 114, 2, ad 1: “sicut non posset homo vivere in societate sine veritate, ita nec sine delectatione.” 89. Jacques Maritain, The Person and the Common Good: “society... cannot subsist without...civil amity, which is the animating form of society and essentially personal. However, the relations which make up the structure of society concern, as such, only justice, which is essentially impersonal because it is measured on things, and does not make acceptance of persons.” 90. II-II, 23, 3, ad 1: “potest dici, quod [amicitia] non est virtus per se ab aliis distincta: non enim habet rationem laudabilis, et honesti, nisi ex objecto, secundum scilicet quod fundatur super honestatem vir tutum... unde amicitia virtuosa magis est aliquid consequens ad virtutem, quam sit virtus.” bf 1 I h i 61 i F I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I I / . I ■ B B I I i· ■ ■ I I ■ ■ ■ ■ ■ ■ ■ 62 THE CONTENT OF THE COMMON GOOD THE CONTENT OF THE COMMON GOOD the multitude.91 A certain amount of “corporeal goods” is necessary for virtuous activity, both for the decorum of happy1 life and as instruments which virtue utilizes for doing good.92 These goods occupy the lowest level of all those comprehended in the expression “common good,” and this expression fits them least properly. They form an order of purely instrumental goods, the order of wealth, that is, of those things “exterior to man, the use of which is necessary or favorable to the support and expansion of human life.”93 In the order of nature, the instrumental goods are inferior to man and were made for him, “infra hominem, et propter hominem facta.”94 They might rather be called common utilities. They are common in the sense that an entire society needs them, and can consequently give laws for their use, employment, distribution and enjoyment by each and every one of the citizens, in accordance with justice and with a view always to the highest ends on which the common good depends. It must now be asked which of the three levels in which the total content of civil society’s common good is organized--namely, the level of happy activity, that of social structure and functioning, or that of the instruments favorable to human life—corresponds strictly to the immanent good as discussed in the first chapter, and there de­ clared to be the good which most properly specifies the social being. At once the goods of the lowest level may be excluded from such a concept; it is obvious that they, although objects of use, are external to what is social. On the other hand, just as the immanent good of an army is its organization, so the immanent good of a society is the 1 ' I ' j ! 91- De Reg·. I> 15: “ad bonam vitam multitudinis instituendam tria requiruntur... Tertio vero requiritur, ut per regentis industriam necessariorum ad bene vivendum adsit sufficiens copia." 92. In Eth., I, 14, #173: “Felicitas non est a fortuna... Concurrunt au­ tem ad felicitatem quaedam alia bona, in quibus fortuna aliquid operatur. ...eorum quaedam necessaria sunt ad decorem quem­ dam felicitatis. Quaedam vero instrumentaliter cooperantur ad felicitatem.” Ibid., 16, #194: “felicitas indiget exterioribus bonis, vel ad decorem, vel inquantum sunt instrumenta operationis secundum virtutem. ...usus exteriorum bonorum est bonus et virtuosus, inquantum scilicet virtus utitur eis, ut quibusdam instru­ mentis ad bene agendum." 93· Yves Simon, “Work and Wealth,” Review of Politics, 2 (1940), 2. 94. I-II, 2, 1: “in ordine naturae omnia hujusmodi [divitiae] sunt infra hominem, et propter hominem facta.” We add here that Saint Thomas in the Commentary on the Ethics, observes on his part that between the Stoics and the Peripatetics there is the difference that the latter recognize that just as the virtuous man can be af­ fected by sadness, so also he depends on external property up to a certain point for his felicity. Cf. In Eth., I, 16, #196. ; 63 good condition of its structure and functioning. But the qualities of that condition are, precisely, justice, as realized in social life; unity; peace; friendship; and everything which these imply in the institutions, habits and social customs which make living together possible, arid which are the means and the form of the flow of social life. Thus, any good quality of organization or of activity which is capable of reali­ zation only in a social being as such, is a part of society’s immanent common good, in the most proper meaning of that term, because that which is essentially relative ad alterum, — such as justice, peace, friendship, concord, social unity, — can exist only among several. But the righteous operation in which the happy life of the community consists is also immanent in the community, although not in exactly the same way as the virtues ad alterum. Common activity according to virtue resides, by analogy~with the individual person’s acts of vir­ tue or knowledge, in the collective subject--“manet in ipso operante” —in the measure in which this activity by itself and not its object, constitutes happiness. That operation perfects society in the line of What is moral, and it adheres to it in a way similar to the way in which a virtue dwells in its individual subject. Thus, it may with all propriety be said that the collective moral conscience and the com­ mon patrimony of virtue and good living which nourish the moral life of each individual dwell in society itself. However, unlike unity and justice, which when objectively realized in a community are qualities essentially inherent in its very structure, and, therefore, necessarily imply relations among persons, the good living of the multitude re­ sides in each one of the good men as in its ultimate subject; the virtue of each of them is afterwards made common to many by diffusing it­ self through its own action.95 Thus, the totality of the immanent good of society comprises a range of qualities which extend for what is most impersonal, socialized and “relational” in its structure, through I the diverse states of the collective moral conscience--in different i degrees of interdependence with the virtue of individuals—up to the most personal acts of virtue of good men as diffused through the com­ munity. That this good is common means that all the component parts of the community enjoy and share in it. Being the good of a whole, it is thereby in an effective way common, or at least communicable, to its y parts. Such communicability belongs to the essence of any common good, whereas it may be entirely lacking to some individual goods: ! personal existence, for example, cannot, under the same ratio of goodi ness, be shared by more subjects than its own. Now, the common 95. S.c.G., III, 69: “bonum unius fit multis commune, si ab uno in alia deTivatur; quod non potest esse, nisi in quantum diffundit ipsum in alia per propriam actionem." 64 THE CONTENT OF THE COMMON GOOD good is not only communicable, but, owing to the ouioj^ical structure of society, it cannot be completely separated nor m^Mutely distin­ guished from the good of the singular individuals: order different respects--materialiter on the part of the citizens, am; finaliter on the part of the common good--there is an interdependence ..md^mutual in­ fluence between the two terms. The common good m not, then, pecul­ iar to the social body as an entity separated from the. parts of the so­ cial body; it is likewise a good for the parts precist lv insofar as they are parts.96 Whence it follows that he who seeks the common good, simultaneously seeks a good for himself. Saint Thomas likes to quote the saying of Valerius Maximus to the effect that the ancient Romans preferred to live poor in a rich empire than rich in a poor empire, which indicates that the common good is for each of the mem- , bers of the city a good even greater than his private good,97 The highest and most perfect form of communicability is that of a good which, remaining wholly identical, can be enjoyed and shared simultaneously by many individuals; this is precisely the communica- I bility of the objects of spiritual and moral life; objects of this kind are not submitted to quantity and so their communicability is not subject to any form of distribution.98 i 96. De Car., 4, ad 2: “Est quoddam bonum commune quod pertinet ad hunc vel ad ilium inquantum est pars alicujus totius; sicut ad militem, inquantum est pars exercitus, et ad civem, inquantum est pars civitatis.” 97. 11-11, 47, 10 ad 2: “ille qui quaerit bonum commune multitudinis ex consequenti etiam quaerit bonum suum, ...quia bonum proprium non potest esse sine bono communi vel familiae vel civitatis aut regni. Unde et Valerius Maximus dicit de antiquis Romanis quod “malebant esse pauperes in divite imperio quam divites in paupere imperio. " 98- Saint Thomas speaks of a common good of intellects, which consists in the order of the intelligible objects: “bonum cui intellectus speculativus conjungitur per cognitionem, est communius bono cui conjungitur intellectus practicus, inquantum intellectus specu­ lativus magis separatur a particulari quam intellectus practicus, cujus cognitio in operatione perficitur, quae in singularibus con­ sistit.1^ Sent., IV, 49, I, 1, sol. 3 ad 1). This common good is “separated,’’ in a way analogous to the way in which God is the separated common good of the universe. Maritain remarks (The Person and the Common Good) that the common good of the intel­ lects can be understood in two ways: either as the supratemporal order of truth and beauty, or as the treasure of culture accumu­ lated in the course of a civilization and in which minds participate as in a truly common good. THE CONTENT OF THE COMMON C-Oôf) 6 A lower manner of communicability is that of tne- goods which submitted to any form of distribution or of use by a multitude, in a way as to imply either division of the goods themselves accord! quantity, or at least a reciprocal exclusion among those who enjoy the I goods. It may be said of none of these things that it is simply the “common good,* but rather it may be said that they are common goods, I in the plural. They are common, however, in the sense, either that no ! individual is assigned in advance to enjoy them privately, and to the exclusion of the rest, or that, because of tne end for which they exist, society has over them a supreme dominion, which is superior to all individual appropriation or adjudication. In the totality of the common good everything which may be com­ municated through some form of distribution is a subject matter for distributive justice. The fact that when discussing distributive jus­ tice Saint Thomas often uses the expression “bona communia,’ (plural), is significant, because only goods which are several can be distributed in a strict sense. Just as it belongs to distributive justice to assign the various burdens and tasks which each one owes to the community, in accordance with what each can contribute in equality of proportion, so it also belongs to it to distribute the goods which are common, which as such are owed by the whole to the part." Concern­ ing the nature of these goods, sufficient light is shed both by the ob­ jection that to distribute the common goods to many is harmful to society’s common good, and Saint Thomas’ reply which recommends moderation in the distribution. Saint Thomas would not have given this answer if the expression “common goods” concerned only spiri­ tual and moral goods, which are neither exhausted by their being shared by many,nor even subject to moderation when it is a question of realizing them.100 99- II-II, 61, 2: “in distributiva justitia datur aliquid alicui privatae personae, inquantum id quod est totius, est debitum parti: quod quidem tanto majus est, quanto ipsa pars majorem principalita­ tem habet in toto; et ideo in distributiva justitia tanto plus alicui de bonis communibus datur, quanto illa persona majorem habet principalitatem in communitate.” 1Û0. II —II, 61, 1, obj. 1: “non enim potest esse justitiae species, quod multitudini nocet, cum justitia ad bonum commune ordinetur. Sed distribuere bona communia in multos, nocet bono communi multi­ tudinis: tum quia exhauriuntur opes communes: tum etiam quia mores hominum corrumpuntur.” And Saint Thomas’ r eply :( Hoid., ad 1): “sicut in largitionibus privatarum personarum commen­ datur moderatio, effusio vero culpatur; ita etiam in distributione communium bonorum est moderatio servanda, in quo dirigit jus­ titia distributiva.” 66 THE CONTENT OF THE COMMON GOOD As a result of the foregoing discussions two things must be pointed out: the complexity of the content of the common good, and the fact that however complex it may be, the content of the total social good is a hierarchical order which is commanded by the supreme end of human happiness. This end is essentially a moral good, and whatever is contrary to moral law will fail to attain this good- in fact, to con­ travene moral law is at the same time to attempt against human hap­ piness. Now, several questions arise from the consideration that the good of the whole must be shared by its parts. It might be asked, for in­ stance, whether this sharing means that the good of the whole com1; munity is worthy only because it is useful to each individual, and so | is on that account subordinated to each individual, or whether, on the 11 contrary, the good of the whole is worthy by itself, not as a means I but as an end. And if this latter is the case, it may further be asked whether the good of the entire community prevails over that of a sin) gle person. These and similar problems are set by the general rela|l tionship between society and the individual, common good and private 1 good, and their solution is not given by merely stating the constitutive I elements of the entire good of society. The solution to these problems I is found, as will be shown in the next chapter, in the doctrine of the t primacy of the common good. I i ) II; I i Chapter III j THE PRIMACY OF COMMON GOOD OVER PRIVATE GOOD Saint Thomas makes frequent and varied application of the prin­ ciple of the primacy of the common good over any private good, now, for instance, to find the justification for capital punishment; now to establish the excellence of the Eucharist over the other sacraments; in another place, to subordinate private virtue to the common happi­ ness, or again, to teach the duty of renouncing contemplation at least in part, in order to tend to the spiritual good of the Church, or even the urgent temporal needs of a multitude. In these, and in many other different cases, he never hesitates to uphold the superiority of a com­ mon good—whatever it may be in each particular case. Historically, the principle of the primacy of society’s common good may be traced to the political thought of the ancient world. In the prevailing tendency of this thought, as represented mainly by Plato and Aristotle, the state, or polis, was believed to have an in­ comparable influence in shaping the”moral life of the citizens ; and since the end of the state is above all moral perfection, the good and virtuous citizen is he alone who conforms his life to the constitution and laws of his city. On the other hand, the relationship between so­ ciety and individual often assumes, on a purely practical level, the form of disagreement and even of acute conflict between their respec­ tive interests. The solution for such conflicts has generally been found in subordinating all other interests to that of the community. The community was acknowledged to have a good of its own; this fact was clearly expressed in such notions of the Roman Law as “res publica” and “bonum publicum,” which designated those values of a political order to which was given absolute predominance over all private goods. With these and similar formulas of the Roman Law there arises a second element in the formation of the doctrine of the primacy of society’s common good. A third element comes from Patristic literature. The Fathers of the Church introduced into the incipient Christian philosophy many formulas of the Roman jurists concerning the hegemony of the “res publica,” but at the same time they made the decisive and far-reaching reservation that although the city is what is most eminent in the temporal human order, there is nevertheless something superior to it for which man is ultimately destined, namely, the order of divine things. Such a reservation will, in the long run, modify the general perspective of the problem. 67 68 PRIMACY OF COMMON GOOD OVER PRIVA 7Έ GOOD Saint Thomas embodied this reservation—as a C.·!,· L theologian could not help doing—together with the Aristotelian ,νκι Roman legacy, in the elaboration of his political doctrines. That nc'-v datum--that is, the new meaning and value acquired by man’s person..! ny with his supernatural destination--appears unequivocally in Thomas’ statement that grace in a single soul is worth more than the natural good of the whole universe. Thus, the final and decisive stage in the formation of the problem known as “the primacy of dr. common good of the civil society” must be ascribed directly to Patristic sources and to the Fathers’ interpretation of formulas of Roman Law? It was in this state of historical development that the problem reached Saint Thomas. In his writings the statement, in varied but more or less equivalent formulas, of this doctrine is usually that “the common good prevails over the private good.” Whatever may be said concerning die terms or the post-Aristotelian conceptualization in which Saint Thomas ex­ presses the principle, it is certain that he rightly finds an authority for the principle in the passage of the Nicomachean Ethics in which I. What is stated above about the sources for the problem of the pri­ macy of the common good of civil society follows what Fr. I. Th. Eschmann, O.P. writes in his article “A Thomistic Glossary on the Principle of the Preeminence of a Common Good” (Medieval Stud­ ies, V). Fr. Eschmann presents here a collection of numerous passages concerning the primacy of the common good of civil so­ ciety in the works of Saint Thomas. In addition to the sources for those texts in Aristotle, in Roman Law and in some Fathers of the Church, especially Saint Augustine, Fr. Eschmann points out that in Saint Thomas the elements of the problem show a development and, above all, a juridical style which they are very far from hav­ ing in their Aristotelian sources. It would be wrong, Fr. Eschmann goes so far as to say, “to believe that we are faced here with an Aristotelico-Thomistic doctrine. Nothing is further from the truth ... Historically speaking the principle of the superiority of a com­ mon good and related doctrines are a legacy to Scholasticism from a Roman and patristic heritage. ” And, further on: “The authority of Aristotle is only, if at all, in a very limited sense a source for the Scholastic axiom [that “bonum commune praefertur bono pri­ vato”]. ” And also: “The word and notion of bonum commune are Roman” (p. 125). If such, historically, is the case, as Fr. Eschmann assures us, there is no doubt on the other hand that, philosophically, Saint Thomas is right in finding in a passage of Aristotle’s Nicomachean I Ethics (I, 2, 1094 b 7) a sufficiently explicit basis to support the i docTrTne of the primacy of the common good, and that his interpre[ tation of the passage is wholly warranted by the words which f PRIMACY OF COMMON GOOD OVER PRIVATE GOOD 69 Aristotle says that “even if the end is the same for a single man and fora state, that of the state seems at all events something greater and more complete whether to attain or to preserve; though it is worthwhile to attain the end merely for one man, it is finer and more godlike to attain it for a nation or for city-states.”2 This sentence is for Saint Thomas, as it was for his medieval predecessors, a dic­ tum authenticum.3 Before examining the conditions for the validity of this dictum it is necessary to take as a starting point what it pure ­ ly and simply affirms. A quite typical formulation,is the following: ‘bonum multitudinis est maius quam bonum unius qui est de multitudine.”4 The principle contained in the dictum is, then, that the good belonging to a society as such is worth more than any of the private goods of its members; the former possesses more dignity and eminence than the latter and, consequently, should be granted an effective preference in the order of the social and political life rightly constituted. The general scope and meaning of this preference may well be gathered from its appli­ cation to certain typical cases. Sometimes, for example, that pre­ eminence can be such that a private good may have to be sacrificed for the sake of the common good. There is then a true conflict be­ tween what is good for the community and what is good for the indivi­ dual. Thus, in the case of a just war, the good, both spiritual and temporal, of the community can extend so far as to require the loss of many individual goods, even of life itself.5 There is also a conflict 2. The Thomistic texts in which the common good is called “divinius” are inspired by this passage: Eth., I, 2, 1094 b 7. 3. A dictum authenticum is in the Middle Ages a proposition whose truth is considered ascertained because it belongs to an author· whose works make “authority." If its application to different cases presented difficulties the only thing possible was to interpret it or to fix the conditions of its right application, since its truth had to be preserved at all events. The dictum referred to here appears sometimes in the objections (argumenta in contrarium) to the thesis of Saint Thomas. For the manner in which Saint Thomas uses this dictum consult Fr. I. Th. Eschmann, O.P., “Bonum commune melius ësTqûàm bonum unius " - Eine Studie ueber den Wertvorrang des Pe’r'sonalen'bei' Th’omas von Aquin, Medieval Studies, VI. 4. iT-TÎ?"39, 2~ acT'2. The texts containing this principle are so numer­ would be impos s ible --as well as useless--to cite them ous that a collection of texts concerning the primacy of the common good, see Fr. I. Th. Eschmann, loc ■ cit. 5. II-II, 31, 3 and 2: “pro bono communi reipublicae vel spirituali vel temporali virtuosum est etiam quod aliquis propriam vitam exponat periculo.” II-II, 26, 3: “quaelibet pars habet inclinationem princi­ palem ad actionem communem utilitati totius. Apparet hoc in poli­ ticis virtutibus, secundum quas cives pro bono communi et dispen­ dia propriarum rerum et personarum interdum sustinent.” 70 . PRIMACY OF COMMON GOOD OVER PRIVATE GOOD of goods whenever the service of the community demands sacrificing, or at least deferring, individual goods such as health, one’s own com­ fort, the repose of the philosopher or the scientist. A conflict of an­ other sort, though no less actue, is that which exists in the case of the criminal condemned to death; here the common good is in conflict not only with the criminal’s life, but also with the private good of his fam­ ily, which needs that life. If for the common good the malefactor’s death is necessary, it is without doubt an evil for him and for his fam­ ily.6 Something similar happens whenever any penalty-—which is al­ ways the deprivation of some good: life, bodily integrity, liberty, ma­ terial property—is imposed on anyone who lacks fondness for virtue, in order to restrain him from sinning.7 Now, if it is simply in order that the common good be preserved that it is sometimes necessary to sacrifice private goods, it is pre­ cisely on that account that justice--legal justice, that is, whose object 6. I-II, 19, 10: “judex habet curam boni communis, quod est justitia; et ideo vult occisionem latronis, quae habet rationem boni secundum relationem ad statum communem; uxor autem latronis considerare habet bonum privatum familiae; et secundum hoc vult maritum lat­ ronem non occidi.” 7. In the question devoted to the licitness of vindication, Saint Thomas writes: “vindicatio fit per aliquod poenale malum inflictum peccan­ ti.” (II-II, 108, 1). And further on: “vindicatio intantum licita est et virtuosa inquantum tendit ad cohibitionem malorum. Cohibentur autem aliqui a peccando, qui affectum virtutis non habent, per hoc quod timent amittere aliqua quae plus amant quam illa quae pec cando adipiscuntur; alias timor non compesceret peccatum. Et ideo per substractionem omnium quae homo maxime diligit, est vindicta de peccatis sumenda. Haec autem sunt quae homo maxime diligit: vitam, incolumitatem corporis, libertatem sui, et bona exteriora, puta divitias, patriam et gloriam.” (ibid., 3). In his Commentary on the Politics (In Pol., I, 4,#5) Saint Thomas explains how, accor­ ding to Aristotle, it is licit, for the good of the community, that even a learned person be submitted to slavery by the conquerors in a war. In fact, allowing them to make themselves the owners of the conquered, “homines incitantur ad fortius pugnandum: et quod sint aliqui fortes pugnatores expedit conversationi humanae ad prohiben­ dum multorum malitias.” Even if it is not just simpliciter that the learned man be made a slave of the ignorant one, “tamen servandum est hoc etiam homini virtuoso secundum mentem, quia cum bonum commune sit melius quam bonum proprium unius, non est infrigendum quod convenit bono publico quamvis non conveniat alicui pri­ vatae personae." PRIMACY OF COMMON GOOD OVER PRIVATE GOOD 71 is the common good8--requires that such sacrifice be imposed only in the measure in which it is necessary for securing such an end. To go beyond that measure would be contrary to justice and consequently harmful to the good of the community. This is why it is not because he would attribute an absolute and despotic power to the state over the individuals that Saint Thomas acknowledges that it is lawful for the public authority to inflict the death penality, but for the very different reason that the common good must be protected when the existence of malefactors within a society endangers it. Saint Thomas uses for this purpose terms which are particularly explicit and energetic: “Omnis pars ordinatur ad totum ut imperfectum ad perfectum. Et ideo omnis pars naturaliter est propter totum. Et propter hoc videmus quod si saluti totius corporis humani expediat praecisio alicuius membri, puta cum est putridum vel corruptivum aliorum membrorum, laudabil­ iter et salubriter abscinditur. Quaelibet autem persona singularis comparatur ad totam communitatem sicut pars ad totum. Et ideo si aliquis homo sit periculosus communitati et corruptivus ipsius propter aliquod peccatum, laudabiliter et salubriter occiditur, ut bonum com­ mune conservetur.”9 ' A superficial and erroneous interpretation of this text would conI sist in using it to justify the sacrifice of human life or of bodily in! tegrity without any consideration other than public usefulness. But I that is certainly not the concept of the common good which, in the eyes of Saint Thomas, makes capital punishment just. What common good is referred to in this text? Undoubtedly it refers on the one hand to those goods without the protection of which social life cannot be con­ served.10* But it is not only that category of good which is to be proftected by the malefactor’s punishment, but also the moral health of the community, its life secundum virtutem. This interpretation ap­ pears as the only one possTbïëïf proper attention is given to the fact that in the text quoted Saint Thomas speaks of sin. It is necessary to recognize what this word means to the theologian and Christian moral­ ist. Sin is nothing else but the conscious and voluntary infraction of the moral law;11 consequently the concept of sin refers essentially and Î i i I 8. II-II, 5é, 6: “justitia legalis est quaedam specialis virtus secun­ dum suam essentiam, secundum quod respicit commune bonum ut proprium objectum.” Cf. also Ibid., a 5, passim, 9. II-II, 64, 2. 10. I-II, 96, 2: “lege humana non prohibentur omnia vitia... sed solum graviora, a quibus possibile est majorem partem multitudinis ab­ stinere; et praecipue quae sunt in nocumentum aliorum, sine quo­ rum prohibitione societas humana conservari non posset; sicut... homicidia et furta et hujusmodi.” Ji, l-II, 71, 6: “peccatum nihil aliud est quam actus humanus malus. Quod autem aliquis actus sit humanus, habet ex hoc quod est 72 PRIMACY OF COMMON GOOD OVER PRIVATE GOOD directly to the moral order, and only secondarily and by its effects to social usefulness. According to Saint Thomas, then, it is because of the sin which a man commits that his punishment is justified; it is only because a malefactor has endangered the moral health of a com­ munity (“si aliquis homo sit...corruptivus communitatis propter ali­ quod peccatum”) that it is licit to deprive him of life in order that that good be conserved. Moreover, the malefactor, says Saint Thomas, has made himself by his sin unworthy of sharing in the society of the good.12 It is precisely in the consideration of the concept of sin that this above-quoted text is seen quite otherwise than as tim justification of an absolute and despotic power of the state over the individual. Only after a man has sinned is there reason in justice t;> impose a penalty on him; this penalty may be death if that is the only effective means for protecting the common good against the malefactor.13 Saint Thomas teaches very clearly that in no case may an innocent be le­ gitimately deprived of his life, and no argument can ever he drawn ’ 1 , r i ( |ί ( 1 i ' I 1 I 1 I 1 i j I , 5 E I i i • j i Fit'" ί’· ' I 1 1. Continued voluntarius." In the same article Saint Thomas adopts Saint. Augustine’s definition of sin: “Peccatum est dictum, vel factum, vel concupitum contra legem aeternam.” Ibid., ad 5: “a theologis consideratur peccatum praecipue secundum quod est offensa contra Deum; a philosopho [Dionisio] autem morali, secundum quod contrariatur rationi.” 12. II-II, 64, 2, ad 3: “homo peccando ab ordine rationis recedit; et ideo decidit a dignitate humana... Et ideo quamvis hominem in sua dignitate manentem occidere sit secundum se malum, tamen hominem peccatorem occidere potest esse bonum, sicut occidere bestiam.” Cf. II-II, 108, 4: “secundum rationem poenae, ...poena non debetur nisi peccato.” 13. Cf. X. Basler, “Thomas von Aquin und die Bergriindung der Todesstrafe," Divus Thomas, Freiburg i. d. Schw., (1931), pp. 173-202. Basler states that, according to Saint Thomas, it is solely propter peccatum that punishment is imposed on a malefactor. Basler brings out the character above all moral, not utilitarian, of the penalty imposed by the public authority, and he rightly declares as contrary to the doctrine of Saint Thomas the attempts made by some authors in Germany to seek a moral ground for the sterilization of idiots in the Thomistic thesis of the superiority of the common good over the private good. Basler points out that in II-II, 65, 1 (“Et ideo sicut per publicam potestatem aliquis licite privatur totaliter vita propter aliquas majores culpas, ita etiam privatur membro propter aliquas culpas minores”), the basis for im­ posing as a penalty the deprivation of a corporal member is also a moral guilt: propter aliquas culpas minores. In regard to the measure of the~penalty, there is no other way to determine it than the consideration of the needs of the common good: “...das Mass PRIMACY OF COMMON GOOD OVER PRIVATE GOOD 73 I from the common good against the life of an innocent person.13 14 Since precisely the life of the just conserves and promotes the common good, it would be contradictory to say that in the name of the common good capitalpunishment—or any other punishment—can justly be inflicted on one who has not committed sin. In summary, what should be stressed here is that the character of the common good such as Saint Thomas conceives it when he recognizes its primacy over all private in­ terests, is quite clearly implied in the assertion that the malefactor’s I sin makes him corruptive of the community; it is because Saint ThomI as considers the common good above all in terms of a virtuous life I that he teaches that a grave sin makes the one who commits it a dan' ger for the good of the community in which he lives. The good which possesses by right and requires in fact primacy over all Others is, in Saint Thomas’ mind, primarily the patrimony of virtues of a society which are shared, practiced and lived in common and for the mutual benefit of the members of that society. This primacy, being in accor­ dance with the moral order, does not warrant the attribution to public authority of the power to dispose of lives and private properties with­ out reference to the attainment of ethical ends and solely for pragmat­ ic considerations of political success. In the conception of Saint Thom­ as, political life, and consequently the government of society, are not regulated by laws independent of morality; on the contrary, he never would have admitted--nor perhaps even have conceived as a possible position--that the good of the community can be attained as something other than precisely the highest realization possible in this life of one and the same order which, maintaining itself identical, regulates at the same time both public and private life.15 13. Continued der Strafe wird sich immer richten müssen nach dem Gemeinwohl und dessen Interessen." In fact, from conceiving the penalty as the expiation due for a guilt it cannot be deduced that the penalty for such a species of guilt must be precisely death. The mere idea of the penalty as punishment is not sufficient for determining its mea­ sure in the great majority of cases; the measure must be deter­ mined by taking into account the requirements of the common good, which are nothing else than the defense of the community’s moral health through the malefactor’s death if the conditions of a society make it necessary to resort to that. 14. II-II, 64, 6: “occisio peccatoris fit licita per comparationem ad bonum commune, quod per peccatum corrumpitur. Vita autem justorum est conservativa et promotiva boni communis, quia ipsi sunt principalior pars multitudinis. Et ideo nullo modo licet occi­ dere innocentem." 15. The unity of political and moral order is clearly set forth by Saint Thomas in the Introduction to his Commentary on the Ethics. All the operations in which the human will may be concerned are 74 PRIMACY OF COMMON GOOD. OVER PRIVA TE GOOD This is the place to point out that it belongs to political prudence to determine the right application of the primacy of the common good in particular social conditions. It is the role of prudence to know the singular in order that general principles may be applied to action. Now, Saint Thomas tells us, prudence exists not only in relation to the good of a single man but also with regard to the good of a whole so­ ciety. This latter is political prudence.15 16 By meant- of its judgments alone can be known, with the highest degree of approximation to con­ crete circumstances, what is conducive and what is harmful in a given case to the good of the community. That is why it is proper to this prudence to establish the laws, to be “legum positiva.”17 Law, in fact, is the practical judgment of the legislator when he decides which actions are due or conducive to the common good and which are not. Law is given with a view to the common good,18 and consequently it is through the laws that the primacy of the common good comes to be concretely established in a particular society. 15. Continued considered by moral philosophy as belonging to one order: “Ordo quadrupliciter ad rationem comparatur... Tertius est ordo quem ratio considerando facit in operationibus voluntatis........... ad philo­ sophiam naturalem pertinet considerare ordinem rerum quem ratio humana considerat sed non facit; ita quod sub naturali philo­ sophia comprehendamus et metaphysicam.. .Ordo autem actionum voluntariarum pertinet ad considerationem moralis philosophiae... Sic ergo moralis philosophiae...proprium est considerare opera­ tiones humanas, secundum quod sunt ordinatae ad invicem et ad finem.” (In Eth., I, 1,#1 and 2). 16. II-II, 47, 10: “quidam posuerunt quod prudentia non se extendit ad bonum commune, sed solum ad bonum proprium... Sed haec aestim­ atio repugnat charitati. ... repugnat etiam rationi rectae, quae hoc judicat, quod bonum commune sit melius quam bonum unius: quia ergo ad prudentiam pertinet recte consiliari, judicare, et praeci­ pere de his, per quae pervenitur ad debitum finem, manifestum est quod prudentia non solum se habet ad bonum privatum unius hominis, sed etiam ad bonum commune multitudinis. ” And in article 11 of the same question, that prudence whose object is the common good of the city is called political; “prudentia politica, quae ordinatur ad bonum commune civitatis, vel regni,” whereas prudentia oeconomica is concerned with the family’s common good, and prudentia monastica, or prudence simpliciter, is related to the i individual good. 17. II-II, 47, 12, Sed contra. 18. I-II, 90, 3: “lex proprie primo et principaliter respicit ordinem ad bonum commune." In The Summa contra Gentes, however, the per­ fection of the individual person is the end of the law; “finis cujuslibet legis, et praecipue divinae, est homines facere bonos" j PRIMACY OF COMMON GOOD OVER PRIVATE GOOD 75 All that has been stated, however, holds true only when private good and common good are of the same kind oi' species. If such is not the case, it may happen that the good of a single individual is higher than the good of the community to which he belongs. This hap­ pens in a most outstanding way with regard to supernatural grace, which is of greater worth, even in a single soul, than the natural good I of the whole universe.19 Supernatural grace is so superior to any I other good that in the extreme, and purely hypothetical, case of an I absolute opposition arising between them in such a way that the conI servation of the one would require the sacrifice of the other, it would I be the natural good of the universe which it would be necessary to I sacrifice. Thus, to the principle of the primacy of the temporal com! mon good, as it comes down to him from Aristotle, Saint Thomas I adds the important and decisive specification that it is valid only if [ common good and private good belong to the same order. And this he could not help doing, since Christian faith and ethics, with their doctrine of man’s vocation to a supernatural life which shall be rea­ lized after this one, profoundly modify any statement of the problem made in merely Aristotelian terms. It was to be expected that Aris­ totle, who lived before the coming of Christianity and who was, as a philosopher, doubtful about the destination and even about the sur­ vival of the soul after death, could not conceive for man a greater good than that which he can attain by living in the polls. But, in the actuality of the Christian Revelation, the temporal “city” no longer possesses incontestably the supremacy over all the goods in which man can participate. With Christianity there is made manifest a 18. Continued (III, 116): “intentio cujuslibet legislatoris est eos quibus legem dat facere bonos; unde praecepta legis debent esse de actibus virtutum" (III, 115). Dom O. Lottin says (“Bulletin de Théologie ancienne et médiévale," V,#475, 1947), that these are two differ­ ent viewpoints, and that Saint Thomas never developed a formula reconciling both. Such a formula, it is true, is not found in his works, but the conciliation is implicitly contained in his concept­ ion of the common good as a moral life in common, which virtu­ ous men at once both enjoy and contribute to, as shown above in the second chapter. 19. Speaking about the justification of the impious man (which belongs to the order of grace and is greater than the creation of the uni­ verse, as it is achieved in the eternal good of divine participation), Saint Thomas says, in answer to an objection based on the principle of the primacy of the common good: “bonum universi est majus, quam bonum particulare unius, si accipiatur utrumque in eodem genere; sed bonum gratiae unius majus est, quam bonum naturae totius universi." (I-II, 113, 9, ad 2). 76 PRIMACY OF COMMON GOOD OVER PHÏVATe GOOD truth, unknown to Aristotle, which permits man, while living in time, to surpass absolutely the destiny of the temporal socseiy, since through grace the supernatural vocation of man has its beginning in this life. It is then the fact that grace is a good greater than all na­ ture which leads Saint Thomas to recognize that there can be in in­ dividuals perfections which are superior by their kind to the good of the whole of which those individuals are parts. But it is not only with regard to grace that Saint Thomas speaks about the superiority of a good ex genere suo, although, on the other hand, he dne< not always appear~tô~grânt a~final and definitive supremacy over ihe common good to private goods which are by their species higher than the com­ mon good. There arises then the problem of knowing for what reason and under what conditions the common good eventually prevails over those private goods which are higher ex genere suo. Saint Thomas does not formulate the solution nor even the problem as such, in any systematic way, but the elements of the question and, with them, the general orientation toward the solution, may readily be drawn out of his works. It is necessary, first of all, to know what the expression kind (genus) of a good means. We are told in the De Veritate that there are two ultimate genera of good for man, namely: the supreme good pro­ portionate to human nature, in which consists the happiness of which the pre-Christian philosophers spoke; and the good of the supernat­ ural order, which man can obtain only with Divine help.20 But at other times, in comparing the worth of two goods according to kind Saint Thomas refers not to these two ultimate orders but, rather, simply to goods which pertain to the order of what is accessible to human pow­ ers alone; this does not, however, prevent there being between the two goods a difference in value and consequently a subordination of the one to the other. This occurs, for instance, in the case of the contemplative life, which is in itself, without necessarily involving a relation to revealed truths, superior to the active life; the contem­ plative life thus judged superior to the active may well involve simply contemplation of objects of the purely natural order, since contem­ plation befits man according to an attribute with which he is naturally 20, De Ver., 14, 2: “Est autem duplex hominis bonum ultimum... quorum unum est pr opor tionatum naturae humanae, quia ad ip­ sum obtinendum vires naturales sufficiunt; et haec est felicitas de qua philosophi locuti sunt... Aliud est bonum hominis naturae humanae proportionem excedens, quia ad ipsum obtinendum vires naturales non sufficiunt... sed ex sola divina liberalitate homini repromittuntur. ” PRIMACY OF COMMON GOOD OVER PRIVATE GOOD 77 endowed; namely, his intelligence.21 Thus, within the enure genus of natural goods the contemplative life is superior to the active, and ή is superior by reason of what, specifies it as such, that is, by its kind. This is the meaning which Saint Thomas gives to genus when hi? says that, taking genus for species, the goodness of the mural act is speci­ fied try its object, or, as some say, by its genus, "ex genere, genere pro specie accepto.”22 On the other hand it happens sometimes tJiat the preeminence of one good over another because of its genus--even when it is not a question of the double final good of man, of which the De Veritate speaks implies a relation of some sort to the supeγ­ ι' natural order, as, for instance, a favorable disposition, or condii ion I for attaining the life of grace. It is thus that virginity is superior ex genere suo to matrimony, because virginity provides for the spirit' ual life and good of the soul, while matrimony inclines by nature to the good of the body and the cares of this world.23 And a reason for the superiority of the contemplative life over the active life is that it re­ sembles more that state which both by contemplation and action we strive to reach.24 By understanding the genus of a good in the sense just explained Saint Thomas solves the difficulties which the principle “bonum 21. II-II, 182, 1: “vita contemplativa simpliciter melior est quam ac­ tiva.” Contemplation befits man according to what is best in him, that is, the intellect. This is the first and most important reason of the eight that Saint Thomas gives in favor of the contemplative life over the active life in the same article. 22. I-II, 18, 2. In his commentary on the article about the preemin­ ence of contemplative life (the article referred to in the preceding note), Cajetan writes: “Melius simpliciter appellatur quod est melius ex suo genere, hoc est, ex sua propria et substantiali na­ tura." In other words, genus is that which constitutes a particular good as such and such, and is thereby the reason for its superior­ ity or inferiority with regard to another good. 23. The proof that virginity is a good greater than matrimony is given not only by the example of Christ and the teachings of the Apostle, but also by reason, says Saint Thomas, “tum quia bonum animae praefertur bono corporis: tum etiam quia bonum contemplativae vitae praefertur bono activae. Virginitas autem ordinatur ad bon­ um animae secundum vitam contemplativam, quod est ‘cogitare ea quae sunt Dei.’ Conjugium autem ordinatur ad bonum corporis, quod est corporalis multiplicatio generis humani; et pertinet ad vitam activam... unde indubitanter virginitas praeferenda est con­ tinentiae conjugali.” (II-II, 152, 4). 24. Sent., Ill, 35, I, 4, sol. 1: “vita contemplativa simpliciter melior est quam activa, inquantum magis as similatur illi vitae ad quam per activam et contemplativam nitimur pervenire.” 78 PRIMACY OF COMMON GOOD OVER PRIVA TE GOOD commune melius est quam bonum unius” meets in the case of the spiritual perfection of a singular man: a good which seems less than the common good because it belongs to a sole individual, but which, because it refers in its content and substance to the supernatural destination of man, is greater than the temporal happiness of an en­ tire society. The solution to the difficulty lies in the qualification of the principle by the formula “si utrumque in eodem genere.” Now, in order to systematize in this regard the total doctrine ox Saint Thomas, a further distinction within the qualification is necessary. For, with­ out such further distinction, it can be inferred from this qualification that a private good may be superior ex genere suo to the common good, even to the good of the whole universe--and, a fortiori, to the good of the temporal society. But such superiority is absolute and unreserved only when the individual good belongs to the supernatural order and is compared to a good belonging to the natural order. God’s grace is the example par excellence of such an individual good. On the other hand, if the comparison is made within the order of purely human goods, the common good is always higher than the good of any single individual. But there are some private goods which, although not belonging to the supernatural order itself, are yet related to it as means to an end. On this account they are higher than the temporal common good; yet, they may sometimes, for the community’s sake, have to be ranked below goods which are actually inferior. The above mentioned cases of matrimony and of a virginity dedi­ cated to God, of the active and the contemplative life, are good illus­ trations of this point. Virginity, which is ordained to the spiritual good of the one possessing and preserving it rather than to the per­ petuation and conservation of the human species, is superior ex gen­ ere suo to carnal fecundity,25 which matrimony procures and which society needs in order to subsist. Concerning this point it seems to be the doctrine of Saint Thomas, according to Cajetan’s interpreta­ tion, that in time of need for the conservation of the human species, the precept of natural law -- namely, thé multiplication of men through matrimony -- would prevail over the vow of virginity,26 provided this 25. II-II, 152, 4, ad 3: “bonum commune potius est bono privato, si sit ejusdem generis: secj potest esse quod bonum privatum sit melius secundum suum genus: et hoc modo virginitas Deo dicata prae­ fertur fecunditati carnali. ” 26. In his commentary on the article cited in the preceding note, Cajetan writes: “comparatio rerum in bonita^p non est consider­ anda secundum casus et eventus, sed absolute... optime Auctor dixit quod finis virginitatis secundum genus suum est simpliciter melior quam multiplicatio hominum, quae est finis conjugii." And, further on: “in casu quo speciem humanam oporteret conservari, PRIMACY OF COMMON GOOD OVER PRIVATE GOOD 79 row were not solemn.26 27 And as regards contemplation and action, Saint Thomas writes in his Commentary on the Sentences that the ac­ tivé life can often refer more directly to the common good than does the contemplative, which, however, is desirable by itself and more worthy than the active; but the active is more useful and better se­ cundum quid, and as such should be preferred sometimes, ad tempus, because of the needs of the present life. From this the conclusion must be drawn that contemplation should be interrupted and deferred in the service of fellow-beings whenever any grave need of life in so­ ciety so requires. This agrees with the assertion that the contem­ plative life is not ordained to anything other than itself except in the manner in which the good of a man is ordained to the good of the mul­ titude.28 Thus, even in cases in which one private good is superior secundum genus suum to another which, although less worthy, is more useful, because more directly related to the common good in concrete circumstances, the more useful good should then be preferred, and must determine the main course to be followed; the reason for this preference is precisely the superiority of the good of the multitude over that of an individual person.29 But this preference which is 26. Continued praeceptum juris naturae praevaleret voto virginitatis... licet simpliciter melior sit virginitas matrimonio, tempore tamen nec­ essitatis melius est nubere... Et universaliter dicitur quod dispen­ satio voti continentiae potest fieri non solum propter melius secun­ dum suum genus, sed propter melius ex circumstantia; puta hic in tali eventu." 27. II-II, 88, 11; “in voto solemizato per professionem religionis non potest per Ecclesiam dispensari: et rationem assignat Decretalis, quia castitas ‘est annexa regulae monachali’." 28. Sent., Ill, 35, I, 4, qla. 3: “Duplex est ratio boni. Aliquid enim dicitur bonum quod propter seipsum est desiderandum. Et sic vita contemplativa simpliciter melior est quam activa... Unde et con­ templativa est finis activae et fini ultimo vicinior. Aliquid vero dicitur bonum quasi propter aliud eligendum: et in hac via vita activa praeeminet contemplativae. Vita enim contemplativa non ordinatur ad aliquid aliud in ipso in quo est; quia vita aeterna non est nisi quaedam consummatio contemplativae vitae quae per con­ templativam in praesenti quodammodo praelibatur. Unde non restat quod ordinetur ad aliud, nisi secundum quod bonum unius hominis ordinatur ad bonum multorum, ad quod propinquius se habet vita activa quam contemplativa. Unde activa quantum ad hanc partem quae saluti proximorum studet, est utilior quam con­ templativa. Sed contemplativa est dignior, quia dignitas significat bonitatem alicujus propter seipsum, utilitas vero propter aliud.” 29. In connection with the common good of the Church, Saint Thomas, on answering the question whether it is licit to refuse the 80 PRIMACY OF COMMON GOOD OVER PRIVATE GOOD PRIMACY OF COMMON GOOD OVER PRIVATE GOOD 81 I contemplation the time which he should give to the service of the mulgiven ad tempus and ex circumstantia to a lower good for the sake of I titude. Neither is it licit to reject the episcopate when imposed, in­ the common good, is licit only when the good of a superior kind is not junctum; this would be to prefer one’s private good to the necessities so connected with the acquisition of grace that its disregard would in­ of the Church. If the good of the community licitiy requires it, vows volve the loss of supernatural life; or, in other words, when the higher of religion and of continence may be dispensed. The examples are good thus forgone is not a necessary means to supernatural life, but many. The determination of the circumstances when, how far, and in only a natural condition favoring it. Again using examples previously what manner one must so act as to choose what is more useful rather cited, it is clear that in the cases considered by Cajelan the dispen­ than what is more worthy depends on prudence, in all its range, from sation from the vow of continence for the sake of the common good, the prudence which bears upon the individual good up to the prudence and provided the vow is not solemn, does not imply loss of the life of which cares for the good government of a multitude. grace nor, consequently, does it contradict the principle “bonum The second distinction which must be made here arises from the gratiae unius maius est quam bonum naturae totius universi,” since use of the idea of “genus” in these problems. This is the distinction the acquisition and conservation of grace are compatible with the existing between the content, substance or nature of a good—its state of matrimony. Neither is this principle violated in the case in “genus”—and its greater or less proximity to the good of a multitude. which the leisure of contemplation has to defer to the needs of the mul­ The relation between this distinction and the first can be formulated titude: because the active life is not incompatible with the state of I by saying that the degree of dignity of a good depends on its genus; grace—far from it; furthermore, the active life does not entirely I the effective preference granted to it depends on its greater or less prevent the exercise of contemplation.30 I propinquity in a concrete case to the common good. The two terms In summary to this discussion, various distinctions must be made. of this second distinction constitute two criteria for evaluating the The first distinction is between the inherent dignity of a good, con­ ethical excellence of a good. The criterion of the “genus” answers sidered objectively and absolutely, and the preference which must in the question which of two goods is better absolutely (simpliciter mel­ fact be granted to that good in the concrete situations of a properly constituted social life. The greater objective dignity of a good does 1 ius), and decides the question from the point of view of the objective value of that good. With reference to this criterion, a good will be so not always coincide with the requirement to prefer it, in an effective way, in the orientation if conduct; the preference is granted in specI much higher the nearer it is by its nature, ex genere suo, to the su­ ial cases (ad tempus, ex circumstantia) to goods of minor ethical I preme end of man, which is the happy life according to the order of dignity which happen to be closer (propinquius) to what the good of the I reason. The second criterion, that is, the degree of propinquity hie multitude at any given moment requires. Such preference then agrees I et nunc of a particular good to the common good, resolves the prob­ lem of ascertaining to which of two goods, of which one is superior with, and is demanded by, the requirements of right conduct; in final simpliciter but inferior secundum quid, must be granted the predom­ analysis it is in such situations more virtuous to labor for the good inance in the practical and effective orientation of social and private of the multitude in the exercise of the active life than to repose in life. As has already been stated, one must in such a case choose the contemplation. A ruler, for example, could not licitiy devote to I good which, according to prudential knowledge, is closer,· propinquius, 29- Continued to the common good, for the reason that the common good enjoys a episcopate, says expressly that, if ordered, injunctum, it must not definitive primacy, always provided that such a choice does not in­ be rejected with the excuse that one may not abandon contempla­ which, by itself, absolutely transvolve the loss of that personal good ............................... tion: “ad inordinationem voluntatis pertinet quod aliquis omnino, cends the natural order: it is not licit to seek, nor is it in fact possicontra superioris injunctionem, praedictum gubernationis officium ble to attain, the temporal happiness of the multitude through the sac­ [episcopatum] finaliter recuset” (II-II, 185, 2). Ibid., ad 1: “quam­ rifice of the state of grace in an individual soul. vis, simpliciter et absolute loquendo, vita contemplativa potior sit There is a question here of two different criteria, which by them­ quam vita activa, et amor Dei, quam dilectio proximi; tamen ex selves correspond to two different problems. This is seen clearly if alia parte bonum multitudinis praeferendum est bono unius. ” There­ one considers that to determine conduct in a concrete case with re­ fore, the episcopate to which one has been elected must not be ab­ lation to the common good, it is not sufficient to know simply that, solutely refused. of the two goods which are possible objects of that conduct, one is 30. II-II, 182, 1, ad 3: “ad opera vitae activae interdum aliquis a con­ simpliciter better than the other. Rather it is necessary to know templatione avocatur propter aliquam necessitatem praesentis further which good to choose as the end of conduct; for conduct to be vitae; non tamen hoc modo quod cogatur aliquis totaliter contem­ virtuous it is necessary that one choose that which, in the circum­ plationem deserere.” stances, best serves the good of society. 82 PRIMACY OF COMMON GOOD OVER PRIVATE GOOD The ultimate reason one must at times prefer a good which is more useful to a good which is more worthy is the plurality of aspects and, in short, the imperfection of the human condition in it me. This is the thought which runs more or less expressly through the texts of the Sentences and the Summa Theologica quoted in the previous pages. Saint Thomas is very well aware that the necessities of this life ab­ solutely prevent that all the occupation of man should be a solitary exercise in the heights of spiritual life; rather, the major part of man’s existence in time is taken up in diverse forms of the active life and of relations with his fellow-beings. The social nature of man, justice and charity demand solicitude in many forms for the spiritual as well as the temporal needs of others, in order that everyone may finally reach to some measure, however small it may be, of contem­ plation and spiritual perfection in the present life. The result of these analyses confirms the statement, made above, that the maxim *si utrumque in eodem genere” is unreservedly valid only when the terms of the comparison are the two supreme kinds of good--supernatural grace and the natural good of the whole universe --or, a fortiori, supernatural grace and any of the goods included in the good of the universe. Otherwise, it is not always true that one natural good which is higher ex genere than another is in a given case closer than that other to the requirements of the common good. This shows that the primacy of the common good cannot be sufficiently ex­ plained through the argument that the goods which are simpliciter highest by reason of their genera are realized in it, for this is not always what actually occurs. Although these goods cannot be disre­ garded, a total explanation would require some other arguments in addition. This qualification will be expounded shortly. But first, this point must be distinguished from another with which it may otherwise be confused. The question is asked whether, in or­ der to preserve the principle of the primacy of a common good, it must be held that an individual good, greater by its kind than the tem­ poral good of the community, is greater precisely because it depends / upon a common good higher than that of civil society. For instance, to the objection that the sacrament of matrimony is worth more than the Eucharist, because it is ordered to the common good, Saint Thomas answers that the Eucharist is the common spiritual good; in fact it is the separated common good of the whole Church, God made man; whereas matrimony is only ordered to the common good aci cording to the body (corporaliter).31 Saint Thomas answers the 31. Ill, 65, 3, ad 1: “matrimonium ordinatur ad bonum commune cor­ poraliter. Sed bonum commune spirituale totius Ecclesiae continetur substantialiter in ipso Eucharistiae sacramento.” PRIMACY OF COMMON GOOD OVER PRIVATE GOOD 83 objection which states that the practical reason is higher than the speculative reason because the former serves the good of society di­ rectly, by saying that, on the contrary, the speculative reason adheres to a good more common than the one which practical reason serves, and that this indicates that speculative reason is the higher.32 These answers are true, but it must be pointed out that the formal reason why the Eucharist is higher than the sacrament of matrimony is not that it makes present a good which is more common but th it it is a good which, being also common, is of a more excellent nature than the corporeal one. A similar thing can be said about the speculative rea' son. In reality, the fact that one good is more common than another is not the reason why it is more excellent; the relation is rather the inverse: it is because a good is better according to its species and content, that its attraction and influence as a final cause is extended to more beings, and so it is, on that account, more common. Now, even if all this is true, a different answer must be given to the spe­ cific question why the good of the temporal community predominates even over private goods which belong by their genera to a higher level of goodness--or, more exactly, why it is that of two singular goods, it is not the one greater in its genus but rather the one closer ex cir­ cumstantia to the common happiness which should be chosen and fol­ lowed as a course of conduct. In sum, the different degrees of super­ iority which are found among private goods, although entirely depend­ ent on their genera, can be associated with diverse levels of goods which are more and more common, but the primacy of the common good of civil society is not sufficiently explained by the mere criterion of the genus of a good. It is time now to ask what is the foundation for this primacy. [The primacy of the common good is closely associated in Saint Thomas’ mind with his conception of society as a totality composed of human individuals. The parts exist for the whole and for its good, and when the existence of any part endangers the whole it must be sacrificed for the sake of the whole. Thus, there is a teleological re­ lation as well as a complete metaphysical dependence of part with respect to whole. There are several reasons for this. First, because the part is what it is on account of its existence within the whole. For this reason the hand severed from the body is only by equivocation a hand in the manner in which, say, a hand of stone is a hand; it is only when joined to the rest of the organism that a hand is alive and real.33 32. Sent., 4, 49, I, 1 sol., 3, ad 1: “bonum cui intellectus speculativus conjungitur per cognitionem, est communius bono cui conjungitur intellectus practicus, inquantum intellectus speculativus magis separatur a particulari quam intellectus practicus." 33. In Pol., I, 1 ,#21 : “destructo toto homine, non remanet pes neque manus nisi aequivoce, eo modo quo manus lapidea posset dici manus. ” 84 PRIMACY OF COMMON GOOD OVER PRIVATE GOOD But the point at stake is not only nor is it principally that the parts depend in a utilitarian way upon the whole for their existence; on the contrary, they expose themselves naturally, even without any deliber­ ation, for the conservation of the whole, even as the hand does, for example, to protect the body.34 This demonstrates that the whole has value in its own right and not simply because the parts exist in de­ pendence upon it. Thus, the parts belong to the whole and exist prin­ cipally in order to integrate it. Whence it follows that in cases of accidental incompatibility between the existence of the whole and that of the part--the case of a member, for instance, which it not isolated could cause death to the entire organism--the part must be sacri­ ficed. The whole is that which nature principally wants to exist, and the parts exercise the functionings necessary for this existence. The autonomous existence of a part as such has no sense : it is by itself something incomplete which seeks completion through integration with a higher entirety, which is the end for which the part exists. The preeminence of the good of society is founded on this principle. This preeminence is accordingly valid in the measure in which human society is a whole with regard to the individuals existing in it. Now Saint Thomas says repeatedly that the singular man is related to so­ ciety as a part is related to its whole.3^ Besides, he says, it is mani­ fest that civil society is not only a whole but is also the most vast and comprehensive whole of its kind.36 Consequently, it is true for 34. I, 60, 5: “Videmus quod naturaliter pars se exponit ad conserva­ tionem totius corporis; sicut manus exponitur ictui, absque delib­ eratione, ad conservationem totius corporis.” In his commentary on this article, Cajetan writes: “ratio quare pars exponitur pro toto, non est identitas quae est inventa inter partem et totum. Et hujus manifestum signum habetur ex hoc, quod pars exponitur ad perdendam identitatem cum toto, ut salve­ tur esse totius. Non ergo ratio inclinationis talis est identitas, aut ut salvet seipsam in toto; sed ut salvet esse totius secundum se, etiam cum non esse ipsius partis.” 35. II-II, 64, 2: “quaelibet persona singularis comparatur ad totam communitatem, sicut pars ad totum." The same statement is found in many other passages in his works. Eor instance: “[per­ sona] comparatur ad communitatem, sicut pars ad totum” (II-II, 61, 1); “ipse totus homo ordinatur ut ad finem ad totam communi­ tatem cujus est pars” (II-II, 65, 1). 36. In Pol., I, 1, #2.: “Manifestum est quod civitas includit omnes alias communitates. Nam et domus et vici sub civitate comprehenduntur; et sic ipsa communitas politica est communitas principalissima." I PRIMACY OF COMMON GOOD OVER PRIVA’iE GOOD 85 I society also that the whole has a metaphysical preeminence ever its I component elements, and therefore that the law winch subjects the .>x! istence of the parts to the good of the whole--“esse partis est pi'opler I esse totius’37--is not affected by the fact that human society is a whole of the moral order. Now, in accordance wiui the character as ' an end which is immanent to the whole--which character is correla­ tive to the fact that the parts exist for it--the common good becomes the end and therefore the measure of the particular goods/’8 And just as a member cannot live separated from its organism, neither can the private good exist without the common good,39 and, accordingly, it is not possible that a man be virtuous if his conduct does not conform towhat is required in justice for the good of the community.10 Now, it is evident that because the good of society is a moral one, the criteria according to which the subordination of the parts to the whole is regulated in a human society, are necessarily different from the corresponding regulative criteria of an organism. Thus, for in­ stance, an individual cannot for merely biological considerations be put to death in order to conserve the social whole in the manner in which a hand may be cut off for the body’s sake. In order for a man to be subjected to punishment there must first, as a necessary con­ dition, be moral malice in him; and to condemn an innocent to death because of physiological degeneration, abnormality or imperfection would be illicit and harmful to the common good. Now, owing to the fact that the moral good is the end to which all other goods are sub­ ordinated, it is never licit to contravene a moral principle in order to obtain and insure the existence of any of those other goods. The moral good is of such a nature that it can be attained only through morally licit means; if the means used are not licit, the good of the city, which is before all else a moral good, will suffer detriment in 37. J5.C.G., Ill, 17. 38. Ibid.: “bonum particulare ordinatur in bonum commune sicut in finem.” This text precedes immediately the one referred to in the preceding note. 39. II-II, 47, 10, ad 2: “bonum proprium non potest esse sine bono cornmuni vel familiae, vel civitatis; ...cum homo sit pars domus, vel civitatis, oportet quod homo consideret, quid sit sibi bonum ex hoc quod est prudens circa bonum multitudinis.” In Eth., VI, 7, #1206: “proprium bonum uniuscujusque singularis personae non potest esse sine oeconomia, idest sine recta dispensatione domus, neque sine urbanitate, idest sine recta dispensatione civitatis; sicut nec bonum partis potest esse sine bono totius." 40. Ι-Π, 92, 1, ad 3: “bonitas cujuslibet partis consideratur in propor­ tione ad suum totum; ...cum quilibet homo sit pars civitatis, im­ possibile est, quod aliquis homo sit bonus, nisi sit bene porportionatus bono communi.” . / f 86 PRIMACY OF COMMON GOOD OVER PRIVATE GOOD what is most essential to it. Moreover, such moral goods as justice, peace, social unity, all of which are related to the existence and con­ servation of social living, would never be reached if morally wrong means were used, since the observance of the moral law is the con­ dition most necessary and indispensable for the very existence of community life. Since it is the only self-sufficient temporal community, the civil society is an end for all the other communities which compose it.41 It is principally under the formality of final cause that Saint Thomas assigns to the common good--and to the good in general-~its essen­ tial property of diffusing itself. If it is true, he says, that the notion of “diffusing itself” appears to signify the operation of the efficient cause; it can nevertheless be understood in a more ample sense as the proper operation of the final cause. Still more; it can with great­ er fitness be said that the good as such implies essentially the dif­ fusion which belongs to the final cause, and not to the efficient cause. The efficient cause is in fact only the initiation or beginning of what is caused, whereas the final cause is the measure and perfection of all the being that is under its influence, and it is precisely in this latter that the intelligible character of the good consists.42 The more power a good has to diffuse itself from some beings to others, that is to say the more capacity it has as a final cause, the more common will it be for the beings among which it is diffused. The common good is a final cause par excellence, and insofar as a cause is higher it extends its causation to more beings.43 There is then a direct 41. In Pol., I, 1, #18: “cum civitas sit communitas habens per se suffi­ cientiam vitae, ipsa est finis praemissarum communitatum." 42. De Ver., 21, 1 ad 4: “Diffundere, licet secundum proprietatem vo­ cabuli videatur importare operationem causae efficientis, tamen largo modo potest importare habitudinem cujuscumque causae si­ cut influere et facere, et alia hujusmodi. Cum autem dicitur quod bonum est diffusivum secundum sui rationem, non est intelligenda effusio secundum quod importat operationem causae efficientis, sed secundum quod importat habitudinem causae finalis; et talis diffu­ sio non est mediante aliqua virtute superaddita. Dicit autem bonum diffusionem causae finalis, et non causae agentis: tum quia effi­ ciens, inquantum hujusmodi, non est rei mensura et perfectio, sed magis initium; tum quia effectus participat causam efficientem secundum assimilationem formae tantum; sed finem consequitur res secundum totum esse suum, et in hoc consistebat ratio boni.” 43. In Eth., I, 2, #30: “Manifestum est quod unaquaeque causa tanto prior est et potior quanto ad plura se extendit. Unde et bonum, quod habet rationem causae finalis, tanto potius est quanto ad plura se extendit." In Met., VI, 3,#1205: “quanto aliqua causa est altior, tanto ejus causalitas ad plura se extendit. Habet enim causa altior proprium causatum altius, quod est communius et in pluri­ bus inventum. ” PRIMACY OF COMMON GOOD OVER PRIVATE GOOD 87 proportion between the diffusion of the common good as a final cause and the plurality of the beings which its causation reaches. It is pre­ cisely in this that Saint Thomas sees the reason why Aristotle should say that it is more divine to love the common good than the individual good, since the common good, by extending itself to many beings, imi­ tates much more perfectly the divine causation, whose influence reach­ es all things.4445Even as above, in the treatment of the specificity of the common good, the notion of order is closely connected with the notion of social whole, and with the notion of end thereby implied, but here the connection is on the ethical plane and under a fresh aspect. This is the aspect of order as a harmony which must be reached among elements like those of a community, which are not necessarily in accord but in fact underlie a well-ascertained conflict of tenden­ cies. An idea often expounded by Saint Thomas is that the universal order is not only composed of parts unequal among themselves, but also that the presence of evil contributes to it in its own way, and that one of the manifestations of evil is the conflict which results from the fact that each creature acts only in accordance with its respective I nature.43 This general conception of the situation in the universe can I be perfectly applied to society, although in an analogous way; Saint I Thomas suggests this application when he says that a prudent ruler must tolerate defects and inequalities in the parts for the good of the whole.46 Since in any community there is a plurality of parts, there is also a conflict which results necessarily from the diversity of tenden­ cies among the integrating elements, each following its natural in­ clination. Nevertheless, one essential difference must be noted: the order of the universe exists already, previous to any consideration by the reason; the order in society is, on the contrary, an order which 44. In Eth., I, 2, #30: “Pertinet ad amorem, qui debet esse inter hom­ ines, quod homo conservet bonum etiam uni soli homini. Sed multo melius et divinius est, quod hoc exhibeatur toti genti et civitati­ bus... Dicitur hoc esse divinius, eo quod magis pertinet ad Dei similitudinem, qui est ultima causa omnium bonorum.” II-II, 31, 3, ad 2: “bonum multorum commune divinius est, quam bonum unius. " 45. S.c.G., III, 71: “Multa bona sunt in rebus, quae, nisi mala essent, locum non haberent... Si ergo malum totaliter ab universitate re­ rum... excluderetur, oporteret etiam bonorum multitudinem dimin­ ui.” Ibid.: “esset contra rationem divini regiminis si non sineret res creatas agere secundum modum propriae naturae. Ex hoc autem quod creaturae sic agunt, sequitur corruptio et malum in rebus; quum, propter contrarietatem et repugnantiam quae est in rebus, una res sit alterius corruptiva.” 46. Ibid. : “Ad prudentem gubernatorem pertinet negligere aliquem defectum bonitatis in parte, ut fiat augmentum bonitatis in toto.” 88 PRIMACY OF COMMON GOOD OVER PH1V, i fc GOOD must be created according to right reason.47 But the e\ H which is present in both orders is due to the same cause, namd). the conflict which may arise within a plurality of creatures when. they act accor­ ding to their respective natures, thus entailing almost inevitably a contrariety of goods. Consequently, it is in the Iasi analysis because of the primacy of the whole over the parts that it is necessary for the component elements to restrain, limit, and even sacrifice the natural development or exercise of their tendencies and potentialities, so that the order indispensable for its existence may prevail in the whole. In this way it is clear how this aspect of the notion of order is insepar­ able from the notion of a social whole and from the character of the social whole as end for the parts of society. Not all of the doctrine of the common good in Saint Thomas can however be built around the notions of whole, parts and their mutual relations, insofar as these notions are applicable to the social being. These notions are at times presented with a certain crudeness, as in the frequent comparisons in which man is related to the community, as a member is related to the animal organism of which it is a part. But there are sufficient elements in the ontology (cf. chapter 1, above) and in the ethics of Saint Thomas to correct whatever may be unilateral in these comparisons, and also to reestablish the equilibrium in his social philosophy. These elements, most of which Saint Thomas re­ ceives from Christian Ethics, converge upon the characteristics of autonomy and value which the individual person possesses in himself, by virtue of his being destined to enjoy eternal life in God. Whence he has said that “man is not ordained to the political community accor­ ding to all that he is and has,”48 but rather all that man is and can be must be ordered to God. Once this has been remarked, it is no longer possible merely to say, as a principle which would embrace all truth in this regard, that a singular man is related to society as part to whole. And, apart from this, one may ask whether in elaborating, hy­ pothetically, a moral philosophy which had not been informed by Christian Ethics, Saint Thomas would also have assigned to the indi­ vidual person the realization of ends which are within the temporal and natural order but higher than what is social as such. If he did not dis­ cuss this problem, or thought it superfluous to do so in view of the ac­ tual supernatural destination of man, it can at least be said that such a problem does exist in his philosophy; in fact, it arises once it is granted, in accordance with his teachings, that in each individual man 47. As stated by Saint Thomas in the introductory lesson to his Com­ mentary on the Ethics. See note 15, page 74 in this chapter. 48. ΐ”ΎΪ7~2Ι, 4, ad 3: “homo non ordinatur ad communitatem politicam secundum se totum, et secundum omnia sua; ...totum quod homo est, et quod potest et habet, ordinandum est ad Deum.” PRIMACY OF COMMON GOOD OVER PRIVATE GOOD 8b I there exist natural conditions which enable him to aci.ieve al·.,it p< r| fections of which the social whole as such--a whole with a mere unity I of order--is incapable. Only the creature whicn in its substantial unity possesses reason is able to attain the highest good, eapax summi noni, not only in the supernatural order with the vision of God, out Ji.-o m the natural order with the acquisition of natural happiness - - wit d. m and virtue--the highest good within the reach of hmman power m each of the two cases, the highest good can be achieved and reside only in the individual person, not in the collective entity, as in its proper and immediate subject.49 Society can oe said to reach natural happi­ ness only in the sense that, within society itself, in the organization and inspiration of civil life, due acknowledgment is given to the su­ preme human values and man is assured the possibility of reaching a life secundum virtutem. The fact remains, however, that, in accor­ dance with their~different ontological constitutions, soeieiy and the individual person attain the highest good in characteristically distinct ■yays; but, on the other hand, it is erroneous to use that difference to set in opposition the common good and the good of the individual per­ son. We agree entirely with the assertion that “there is nothing more illusory than to pose the problem of the person and the common good in terms of opposition.”50 As has been shown above, in the discussion of the content of the common good, the good life of the multitude and that of each person coincide and are mutually implied in that which is most excellent in both. And even in the extreme case in which the in­ dividual has to die for the city’s sake he is performing a virtuous ac­ tion, thus heightening his moral perfection and his value as a person.51 Insofar as the highest human goods are achieved in the city, and blos­ som there into a civilization which is determined by them in all its manifestations, the common good is so much more human; and so much less in the breach which may separate the requirements of com­ mon happiness from those of the individual good. As for all those matters other than virtue in which the singular in­ dividual is related to the community, the case of the sacrifice of life in a just war shows at the same time both the coincidence of common I 49. Defining the modes according to which the different beings have a resemblance to God, Saint Thomas says that only intellectual creatures as such are images of God in a proper sense; “Ea quae non habent intellectum, non sunt ad imaginem Dei.” (I, 9 3, 2, Sed contra). Ibid., ad 3: “universum est perfectius in bonitate quam intellectualis creatura, extensive et diffusive. Sed intensive et collective similitudo divinae perfectionis magis invenitur in in­ tellectuali creatura, quae est capax summi'boni. ” 50. Jacques Maritain, The Person and the Common Good. 51. Ibid. 90 PRIMACY OF COMMON GOOD OVER PRIVATE GOOD good and personal perfection on the level of moral values, and the possible opposition between individual life and community interest on the level of the good of existence, itself not properly a moral value. Not far removed from this ambivalent relationship is Saint Thomas’ statement that spiritual goods can be possessed simultaneously by many, but corporeal goods cannot.52 In general it can be said that op­ position between individual interest and social requirements is possi­ ble whenever the goods in question are not such as virtue and wisdom but rather those whose possession and enjoyment cannot be diffused among many subjects, because the goods themselves arc either ex­ clusively proper to each subject, or cannot be shared indefinitely without decrease. On the other hand, it is evident that the total good of a society is as a whole so much better, the fewer restrictions com­ mon happiness secundum virtutem requires regarding non-moral goods. A general doctrine about the relationship between society and indi­ vidual would include in a coherent synthesis the truths that every in­ dividual man is merely a part of the social body and yet that this part is a suppositum of rational nature, which, unlike the community, is alone capable of attaining the highest good. The synthesis of all those elements was not so well elaborated by Saint Thomas as to exclude possible divergent interpretations of his thought.53 A complete formu­ lation of the relationship between the community and the individual must be made, first, in ontological terms which define what, according 52. Sent., HI, 30, a. 1, ad 4: “Bona temporalia·..possunt se invicem in diversis impedire, quia prosperitas unius inducit adversitatem alterius... Sed...spiritualia bona [simul] a pluribus integre possi­ deri possunt." The bona temporalia spoken of here seem to be mainly those related in one way or another to corporeal things, since they are opposed by Saint Thomas in this text to bona spirit­ ualia. - Contra impugnantes Dei cultum et religionem, 4:“'Quod dat aliquis, iam non habet’: patet esse falsum in spiritualibus, quae communicantur non per translationem alicujus dominii, sicut accidit in rebus corporalibus, sed magis per modum emanationis cujusdam effectus a sua causa: sicut qui communicat alii scientiam, non propter hoc scientiam amittit.” 53. Cf. the authoritative opinion of Dorn O. Lottin, (Bulletin de Théo­ logie Ancienne et Médiévale, II, #418, 1933-36): “La pensée de saint Thomas sur le rapport individu-société est malaisément définissable... c’est une question de savoir si s. Thomas s’est posé explicitement ce problème des rapports entre le bien commun et le bien privé." (See the remarks made above, chapter 2). It can be added here that this latter relation is a most important as­ pect of the larger problem of the relationship between society and individual. PRIMACY OF COMMON GOOD OVER PRIVATE GOOD 91 to the nature of things, is permanent and invariable in the mutua! posi­ tion of the social body and its parts. But a purely metaphysical solu­ tion is insufficient for a problem which essentially involves ethical questions, since these belong to the dynamic aspect of the community­ individual relationships. In fact, the relationships between community and individual are worked out in terms of human conduct, and, conse­ quently, it is only according to ethical criteria that principles for the solution of the tension between man and society can be found. The re­ lation between the two terms is manifested as tension and can be sol­ ved only in motu.54 Now, aside from man’s ontological position with respect to society and whatever the metaphysical preeminence he may be granted over it once their interrelationships have been carefully defined, a paramount ethical principle undoubtedly stands out: namely, that the moral dis­ position of the individual person toward the common temporal good must always be, not the love of possession but that other love of which Saint Thomas also speaks in the De Caritate; not the inclination to take advantage of society’s good, but theTnclination to serve it and to promote its conservation and diffusion. A man who acts this way heightens his spiritual perfection much more than he would by pur­ suing his own good, for it is more godlike to seek the happiness of a whole city than to seek one’s own happiness. A summary and, at the same time, a conclusion of this exposition on the Thomistic doctrine of the political common good can be set forth in the following propositions: 1. When there are two goods of the same kind, one of which is com­ mon to many, the other private, the common good always prevails. 2. An individual good which belongs to an order higher than the whole natural order, is always and under all circumstances superior to any common good of the natural order. 3. A private good which by its nature belongs to the temporal and natural order and is superior simpliciter to another private good, must at times be renounced in favor of that other, for the sake of the common good. 4. The primacy of the common good—understood in all its all-com­ prehensive range--is due formally not to its content or genus simpliciter, but to the fact that it is the good of the whole, to which the parts are metaphysically subordinated. 5. At their highest level--the happy life secundum virtutem--the common good and the good of the individual person coincide, at least in a relative and imperfect way; on lower levels, an incompatibility may truly exist between the two, but the primacy belongs always, and must be accorded always, to the common good. 54. Jacques Maritain, op. cit. CONCLUSION Out of the numerous teachings of Saint Thomas concerning the common good of civil, society there arises a coherent conception quite definite in its principles and general fundamental outlines according to which the common good in its broadest sense is an orderly struc­ ture of different kinds and levels of goods under the supreme rule and measure of one end, the happy life of man in the exercise of his ra­ tional powers. The dominating position accorded to this end, which is always present to the mind of the good legislator, and which the laws are to promote, gives to the totality of social life, as Saint Thomas conceives it, an accentuated moral orientation, since this end is the supreme criterion as to the extent and manner in which it may be licit to seek and enjoy other goods, or as to what should be or should not be done, for the sake of common happiness. And common happi­ ness cannot be attained automatically through the striving of every one to reach his own private good; the common happiness in its widest con­ tent is a good which, as an autonomous quality, is formally diverse from the singular goods of the parts taken collectively, and it does not result from the separate pursuit of these particular goods without a view to the common end. The belief here rejected is common to the doctrines vaguely and unprecisely called “individualistic.” Rather than constituting a rigorous doctrine, they are a certain ideal of politi­ cal and social organization which, if it does not absolutely deny what is specific in the social good, does at least tend to overlook it. Such tendencies have appeared historically sometimes in association with hedonistic ideas about happiness, and sometimes together with a con­ ception of society as organized merely for the acquisition of wealth. But such a society would not truly be one, in the Aristotelian-Thomistic sense of the word; it might well be self-sufficient in an economic sense, but not in the sense that it procures for its members the great­ est human good which can be attained in the course of time, happiness in accordance with virtue. This is why, in civil societies organized for economic benefit--if indeed there have ever been any in the strict sense of these words--such expressions as common good or the like are to be understood as meaning prosperity and material well-being-something very different from what Saint Thomas thought and taught. In public life the end of civil society is more often completely over­ looked than misconceived. The State is so entirely concerned with what are really only ways and means that one may wonder whether an end is thought to exist at all. The end is completely lost sight of, and so the means become emancipated, as it were, and are granted an CONCLUSION 93 entirely autonomous consideration. One example of this non-subor­ dination of means is the regime, often proposed, in theory as well as practice, for the economic life, which would enjoy an autonomous reg­ ulation, subject not to human aims superior to the economic system, but to laws which are presumed immanent to the system itself and suf ­ ficient for its regulation. In a similar way, the conception of the whole social activity as intended to build a super-individual entity to which the supreme value under all respects is attributed, and of every hu­ man being as a mere instrument of that activity, without any recog­ nition of his final autonomous value as a subject of moral goods, is completely foreing to Saint Thomas’ thought on the common good. It is, on the contrary, to the superior human goods that every social ac­ tivity or common task should be subordinated. Now, since, according to Saint Thomas, the highest goods a human being can attain by living in society are virtue and contemplation, which have, as their proper subject, the individual person, there is no doubt that, his entire politi­ cal thought is orientated concretely and in the last analysis to the hu­ man person and his destiny. This, as we hope we have shown, does not oppose the person to the common good or to the primacy of the common good: there is, rather, an interchange between the noblest aspects of the common good and the excellences of personal perfec­ tion; every man must love the common good not in order to possess it and make use of it, but in order that it may be preserved and pro­ moted. Although the individual person is called to a destiny superior to the destiny of temporal society--which will as such finally perish —the good of temporal society is not simply a means or instrument whereby man may more easily attain his supra-social vocation; the good of society is of such a nature that it deserves to be loved for itself. In other words, man should love the social good not as a “bonum utile,” but rather as a “bonum honestum”--because it is a “bonum honestum.” In truth, the good which a community attains by being self-sufficing cannot be a merely useful one. “Self-sufficiency is,” according to Aristotle, “that which by and of itself makes life desirable and lacking in nothing? The happy life, which is not de­ sired for the sake of anything else, is what constitutes the self-suffic­ iency of the civitas perfecta. Therefore, a good like the bene vivere of the multitude, which as supreme end (in the temporal order) has its complete justification in what it is itself, cannot be a bonum utile. The common good of civil society cannot be other than a bonum honestum. Not every bonum honestum is necessarily self-sufficing; but a good which, because it is self-sufficing, is not desirable for the sake of anything else, can only be a bonum honestum. It must be borne in mind that Saint Thomas’ doctrine of the com­ mon good is placed at a high level of philosophical abstraction, and 1. Eth., I, 7, 1097 b 15. 94 CONCLUSION that therefore many contingent circumstances are to be taken into ac­ count in order to apply the principles of this doctrine to political life. It is legitimate and normal that, under different circumstances, these principles should find expression in diverse views and programs des­ tined for political and social action. But these views and plans of ac­ tion, even if more concrete than the philosophical principles which they intend to apply, are still at an intermediate stage between these principles and its immediate application to a particular society by the prudence of the ruler. BIBLIOGRAPHY I. Primary Sources Aristotle Politics Nicomachean Ethics Metaphysics Physics “The Works of Aristotle,” translated into English under the editorship of W. D. Ross. Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1908-31. Saint Thomas Aquinas Summa Theologica Summa contra Gentiles Leonine ed., Rome, 1882-1930 In duodecim libros Metaphysicorum expositio Cathala ed., Turin: Mariettl, 1935 In decem libros Ethicorum expositio Pirotta ed., Turin: Marietti, 1934 Opera Omnia In libros Politicoruip expositio In octo libros Physicorum expositio Quaestio Disputata De Caritate Quaestio Disputata De Potentia Quaestio Disputata De Veritate In quatu<>r Libros Sententiarum De Regimine Principum Contra impugnantes Dei cultum et religionem In I ad Corinthios Vives ed., Paris, 1875 95 96 BIBLIOGRAPHY Π. Secondary Sources A. Books Cajetan, Thomas de Vio Cardinal. In Summam Theologicam. Leonine ed,, Rome, 1895. Demongeot, Marcel. Le meilleur régime politique selon saint Thomas. Paris: A. Blot, 1929’ Gilson, Etienne. Le Thomisme. 5 ed., Paris: J. Vrin, 1944 John of Saint Thomas. Logica. Reiser ed., Turin, 1930. Kurtz, O.F.M., Fr. E. Individuum und Gemeinschaft beim Hl. Thomas von Aquin. MunchênTjTKosel &T? Pustet^Ï932. Lalande, André. Vocabulaire technique et critique de la Philosophie. 2 ed., 2 vois. Paris: F. Alcan, 1928. Maritain, Jacques. The Person and the Common Good. Translated by John J. Fitzgerald. New York: Scribner’s Sons, 1947. B. Articles Basler,. X. “Thomas von Aquin und die Begründung der Todesstrafe,’ Divus Thomas, Freiburg d. Schw., (1931). Eschmann, O.P., Fr. I. Th. “A Thomistic Glossary on the Principle of the Preeminence of a Common Good,” Medieval Studies, V, (1943). “ ‘Bonum commune melius est quam bo­ num unius’ - Eine Studie ueber den Wertvorrang des Personalen bei Thomas von Aquin,” Medieval Studies, VI, (1944). Lottin, O.S.B., Dom O. Bulletin de Théologie Ancienne et Médiévale, Π, (1933^36), #418; V, (1947), *4Ί5. Simon, Yves. “Work and Wealth,” Review of Politics, Π (1940), 2. VITA Jaime Vélez-Sâenz, born in Manizales, Colombia, attended “colegio de bachillerato” (secondary school) in Manizales and after­ wards studied law at the National University of Bogota, where he took his degree in 1939. He was a student of philosophy at the Grad­ uate School of the University of Notre Dame from 1944 to 1946, and a Spanish instructor at Notre Dame and La Salle College, Phila­ delphia, from 1946 to 1949. After his re­ turn to Colombia, he has been teaching phil­ osophy at the “Escuela Normal Superior” and the National University of Bogota.