92 Chapter II To sum up: The external criteria of Divine Revela­ tion are of greater apologetic value than the internal signs for the following reasons. 1. They manifest the divine origin of an alleged revelation with greater certainty than the internal cri­ teria. ’ As stated above, under certain circumstances, the posi­ tive internal criteria beget certitude; but they exert this influence only on those who, by reason, of their greater intellectual powers, are able to examinethe cônientof the doctrine m till'it^'aspects and properly to evaluate it. On the other hand, there is always the danger that va&rÇs judgment of a given doctrine, especially as regards its sublrmity and its capacity for satisfying the innermost needs of man, may be toosubjective, The positive external criteria, on the contrary, can b'e appreciated by all, even the ignorant and unlettered, because they rest upon historical facts which are easy to ascertain. For the same reason (namely, because there is question of objective facts) the danger of deception is practically excluded.43 2. They can be known also more easily. In applying the external criteria it suffices to investigate a few historical facts, whereas the application of the in. ternal criteria demands a careful analysis of the entire 1 content of the doctrines said to bè divinely revealed. It is obvious, however, that the more varied and comprehensive the subject-matter to be examined, the easier it is for error to creep in. 3. The fact of Divine Revelation can be known more quickly_by means of the external criteria. This is plain from the fact that, instead of the many truths which constitute/the subject-matter of an alleged revelation, only one needs to be considered, that is, the question relative to the Fact of Divine Revelation. Once this has been proven with certainty by the application of the external signs, there can be no doubt as to the divine origin of the content of the Revelation. The whole inquiry is focused on the question of the credibility of the witness 48_) J. Brunsmann, S. V, D., Lehrbuch der Apologetik. St. Gabriel bei Wien. 1924, I: "Religion und Offenbarung”, p. 149; English adap­ tation, "A Handbook of Fundamental Theology", by A. Preuss, St. Louis, Mo. 1929, Π, p. 71. The Subjective Criteria of Protestantism 93 of the alleged revelation, that is to say, the divine mission of the legate and the divine origin of his message.43 At the same time, however, it must be admitted that the internal criteria, per se, are in many respects superior to the external signs. They lead the inquirer into the essence of the subject in question, and are calculated to awaken a more joyful mood or attitude, since they demonstrate not only that Christianity is a Revealed Religion, but also open up its intrinsic value and its content of truth. Moreover, they are perhaps more congenial to the character and mentality of the “m oderiiTman, who"l^êdïïcated in the thought of natural science1and wr whom Miracles are, often enough, a difficulty and an obstacle rather than an aid to Faith. Nevertheless, despite these advantages the application of the external criteria may not be dispensed with. For their proving force is far more conclusive. The sublimity of the doctrine and the world renewing power of Christianity do not disclose its divine origin so palpably as Miracles do, since it is very difficult to establish the precise measure of achievement, which the power of man, relying on his native resources alone, can attain in spiritual and moral respects. Therefore, the proper method to be employed is' that which seeks to combine the external and the internal cri­ teria into a harmonious unity.44 Chapter III THE SUBJECTIVE CRITERIA OF PROTESTANTISM From the earliest Christian times to the present, there Historical Retro·prêt. have been advocates of an internal proof “of spirit and power” for the truth of Christianity, based on a higher intuition and an experience of the_fegart The external proof oT fact—namely, Àüracles and Prophecies—, so it has been said, ought either to be wholly abandoned or48 48) Brunsmann, S. V. D; ibid., I, p. 149; Brunsmann-Preuss, ibid., II, pp. 71, 72. 44) Fr. Sawicki, Die Wahrheit des Christentums. Paderborn. 1920 (4'ed.), p. 342; cf. Ad. Tanquerey, Synopsis theologiae dogmaticae. Romae, Tornaci, Parisiis. 1922 (19’ed.), I, PP- 134-137. 94 i i 1 1 ί lj ’ ί >| j i Chapter III . relegated to a subordinate position. Christianity must manifest itself, above all else, as a religion of salvation and a saviour religion for the inner man; it must prove itself, by means of a spiritual vision, and an emotional bliss,. As such, it'must1"autheÎ?f StT"îts * u''cïm^^fôr'uhiim who does not yet believe, but far more for the believer who lives by Faith and experiences its truth within him­ self. Thus, theaprimapv of value belongs to the subjective , and the mystic criteria. ' T”m”My9tfc>. There is hardly a more ambiguous term than the word * “mystic”. In general, it denotes something hidden,, mysferious. In the objective sense we call everything mystic, which by reason of its nature or origin is mysterious, whether relatively, that is, for this or that person, or abso­ lutely, for each and every person. In the subjective sense all activities are' termed mystic, which are mysterious. Thus, we speak of a mystic life of man, a mystic vision, feeling, striving, a mystic vital operation, accordingly as that .life is enigmatical or mysterious in its quality or. cause, whether it be natural, diabolical or, supernatural. .. In the matter under discussion, the problem is whether there is a natural mystical experience, which may serve as the medium for arriving at the1 supernatural/ Whether there is an intellectual experience of the supernatural, or an emotional and volitional experience of. the satisfying power and efficacy of the supernatural, which may function as an internal subjective criterion of its objective truth.1 Rjstor^ testifies that the different tendencies, which have sprung from the attempts to demonstrate the truth of * theT Christian Religion’by means of “these mystical criteria, have issued either in a kind of Rationalism, in that they have made the content-of Christianity the sub­ ject of a natural intuition and an emotional experience of the spiritual man, thus appearing as theosophical Gnosticism, a higher empiricism, or have ended in an exaggerated Supernaturalism, which sought to accredit the content of Christian doctrine by means of an internal testimony of God, thus anticipating the future bliss of the life to come. ϊ) Al. v. Schmid, Apologetik als speculative Grundlegung der Théologie. Freiburg i. B. 1900, pp. 174, 175. Protestantism 95 In direct opposition to these tendencies we note an­ other tendency, which has -also been active from the earliest Christian ■ times to the present, and which has sought5'to preserve, unimpaired'the spiritual "Mysticism of Christianity., It likewise strove 'for a proof of .the Christian Faith on ..internal mystical intuitions and ex­ periences, but carefully avoided the extremes of Ration­ alism and an exaggerated Supernaturalism.2 " Space, will not permit.us to review all these divergent tendencies.3, We.-shall restrict our study to three modern applications of these subjective, mystical criteria, which the apologist .may not ignore, namely, the Protestant, Pragmatist and Modernist evaluation. ' · PROTESTANTISM * From the very beginning of the so-called Reformation, orthodox Protestantism-made-light of and, to a certain extent, even repudiated the objective, especially the ex­ ternal, criteria-of Divine-Revelation. It championed a subjective and senrimentaj .apologetics»I. Luther did not indeed absolutely reject the external E«îy Reforme», criteria, but he did look upon “such vain, trifling and almost childish tokens” merely as signs for 'the ignorant and' urn­ believing crowd, for whose sake they have still to be per­ formed. But the. faithful, who already .know them, .have no further need of them. Miracles are wrought for the benefit of the heathens; but Christians require higher and heavenly sighs in comparison with which visible Miracles are still earthlyi It is not surprising, then, that such signs have ceased, now that the Gospel has been preached every­ where. Those who were ignorant of God had to be drawn and enticed to Him by means of external signs, just as one 2) Schmid, ibid., p. 175. ' ? ·) For the Patristic Period the student might consult Schmid, ibid., pp. 176-180; also Chas. M. Sauvage, art.. “Mysticism”, CE. X, p. 664; for St. Augustine’s position cf..Erich Przywara, S. J.,Religionsbegründung. Freiburg, i. B. 1923," pp. 258 sq. For the Middle Ages cf. Schmid, ibid., pp. 180-186. For the Post Middle Ages up to the twen­ tieth century, cf. ibid., pp. 186-194 ; also J. Pohle, Natur u. Übematur, in RCK, I, pp. 393-397. For. the Modern Period, cf. Schmid, i6id., pp. 194-200. t 96 Chapter III casts “apples and pears” before children, in order that God might be able to perform within them the really exalted Miracles, that is, the spiritual wonders. We, on the con­ trary, ought to praise and extol the great and glorious miraculous deeds, which Christ performs daily in His Christianity, in that if overcomes the power and might of the devil, and snatches so many souls from the jaws of death and Hell. For Christians and believers these are the really great Miracles, which Christ’s divine and almighty power, namely, preaching, prayer, baptism, etc., effect unceasingly in Christianity. These Miracles are the casting out of devils, the chasing away of serpents, the speaking with new tongues, of which we read in Mark xvi, 20. * This same viewpoint recurrs in the Lutheran dogmatic theologians of the early Reformation period.5 Starting with the basic conception that fallen man finds himself in a relation of contradiction as regards supernatural and Christian Revelation, orthodox Prot­ estantism, both Lutheran and Reformed, ^concludedJhat Ar-^man is, for the most natural knowledge^of^credibility, and unable to acquire a fides humana, wlucJlUrm andrela­ tive to the divine origin of Reveïæ ion and of the Sacred Scriptures, as the documents of God’s revealed message. But neither does man require such a natural knowledge, since he is able to arrive at a fides divina in God’s Reve­ lation and in the Holy Scriptures (both being generally regarded as identical) upon the testimonium Spiritus Sancti. For, when man hears the consoling and blissful word of the Gospel, that is, the glad tidings that he is able to find justification (forgiveness of sin), regener­ ation and divine sonship by Faith alone, or by a simple trust (fides fiducialis, specialis), he can look upon that experience of salvation as the testimony of the salvific spirit of God, and thus acquire a certain Faith, free from Teettmonfum sJwti.' *) Luthers Werke, ed. Erlangen, XII, Abtl. 1, pp. 218-221; cf. XII, Ablt. 2, pp. 235-238; ed. Weimar, X, Abtl. 3, pp. 144-147; cf. also Bretschneider’s summary of these teachings in “Luther an unsere Zeit”, p. 197 sq. δ) Quenstedt, Theol. didactico-polemica, I, p. 97; Baier, Compen­ dium theol. positivae. Lipsiae, 1680, p. 106; Gerhard, Loci theol. 23, c. 11 (vol. XI, p. 319 sq.) Protestantism 97 doubt, regarding the divinity of the content and origin of the Sacred Scriptures. Thus, for the individual, the objective ground, of. justifying failli (ultima ratio propter thp Holy Spirit ; the s ubj ectiye gr o uiiamBrfiï^t^^mmzmystm^g^^^Îcq , of this testimony? Accordingly, the early Reformers looked upon the rational substructure of Faith, which had hitherto been so strongly emphasized by traditional apologetics, as absolutely useless. The divine origin of Revelation was now held to be knowable solely through the divinely in­ spired Scriptures, and the divine inspiration of the Scriptures was said to be discernible upon the internal testimony of the Holy Spirit, Who, when we read the Bible, recognizes His own work.7 Therefore, the thread binding objective Revelation with the subject who re­ ceives it, is again a supernatural Revelation. This thread between the believing soul and objective Revelation ’ can ? •not be spun by human reason ; for reason is utterly inca­ pable of performing such an act. Indeed the Reformers stigmatized, as godless and wicked, the thought that things spiritual and divine (hence, Faith also) can be acquired through human activity. “The reason is obvi­ ous; namely, because, according to them, the hereditary evil (original sin) consists in an obliteration of the di­ vine image from the human breast : and this is precisely the faculty capable of co-operating with God. Accord­ ingly, they teach, that map remain and God is exclusive! vaehvpJ f8 For in man', everything in an upward (lirecfion,Tn religious matters, is dumb ; there is no voice that speaks for God; nothing bears witness to Him. Hence, the teaching that, if a religious voice is audi­ ble within man, it is the voice of God and the parallel e) Al. v. Schmid, Apologetik, p. 210. 7) cf. D. Fr. Strauss, Die christliche Glaubenslehre. I, p. 354. 8) John A. Mohler, Symbolik. Regensburg. 1921 (10’ed. by F. X. Kiefl), p. 107; English transi. “Symbolism” by James Burton Robert­ son. London. 1906 (5’ed.), p. 88. 98 Chapter III teaching that the Sacred Scriptures, of themselves alone, are the norm and judge in matters of Faith.9 Calvin writes : “The Scripture exhibits as clear evidence of its truth, as white and black things do of their color, or sweet and bitter things of their taste . . . Let it be con­ sidered, then, as an undeniable truth, that they who have been inwardly taught by the Spirit, feel an entire acquie­ scence in the Scripture, and that it is self-authenticated, carrying with it its own evidence, and ought not to be made the subject of demonstration and arguments from reason; but it obtains the credit which it deserves with us by the testimony of the Spirit ... We seek not arguments or probabilities to support our judgment, but submit our judg­ ments and understandings as to a thing concerning which it is impossible for us to judge”.10 Luther’s antipathy to the co-operation of reason'in matters of Faith is too generally known to require elab­ oration.11 If, nevertheless, there arose among Protes­ tants a rational theology, and, the catch-word * ‘ pure doc­ trine” came into vogue, it was largely due to the efforts of Melanchthon.12 9) A. Gisler, Der Modernismus. Einsiedeln. 1913 (4’ed.), p. 243. 10) Institutiones, I, c. 7, nn. 2, 5 ; English transi. "Institutes of the Christian Religion" by John Allen. Philadelphia, Pa. 1841 (3’Amer­ ican ed.), pp. 77, 79, 80. 11) Luther (In Genes, c. xix) delighted in comparing fallen man to a pillar of salt, a block, a clod of earth, incapable of working with God. He sarcastically calls reason “Lady Hulda, the mad fool” from Mount Venus (Luthers Werke, ed. Weimar, XXIV, p. 516; ed. Erlan­ gen, XXXIV, p. 138) ; “the clever prostitute, whom the heathens fol­ lowed, since they wished to be most wise” (ibid., X, p. 295, reap. XVI, Abtl. 2, p. 532) ; “the devil’s harlot”, that can do nothing save blas­ pheme and dishonour everything that God says and does (ibid., XVIII, p. 164, resp. XXIX, p. 241).—Luther’s spirit gained so complete a vic­ tory that his views, nay his very expressions, were adopted into the public formularies^ For example, Konkordienformel, Solida Declaratio, I, De peccato originis (ed. C. A. Hase, Lipsiae. 1827, p. 640; English transi. "The Book of Concord or the Symbolic Books of the Evangelical Lutheran Church", by Henry E. Jacobs, Philadelphia, Pa. 1912, p. 542), states: “That we all have by nature inherited from Adam such a heart, feelings, and thoughts as, according to their highest powers and the light of reason, are naturally inclined and disposed directly contrary to God and his chief commands"; II, De libero arbitrio (ibid., p. 657, resp. p. 553) : “The more diligence and earnestness they (namely, who do not yet believe) employ in order to comprehend, with their reason, these spiritual things, the less they understand or believe, and before they become enlightened, or taught of the Holy Ghost, they regard this only as foolishness or fictions”. 12) Gisler, ibid., p. 243; cf. Mohler, ibid., 44, 59, 66. Protestantism 99 The Lutheran and Reformed theologians of the seventeenth century systematized this fundamental conception of their founders. The le^mox^^^the^Holy^Spi^iyaud of His interior, mystic experience together wilh the * power of be­ getting certitude, exterffisvaccording to them, first, to the consoling article of justification by Faith alone in the exclu^•^me^s^f^}irist ~^^ÎhT^hief^onteri^ô^.thê^acrÆd * then reaches out also to all the remaining content of the Bible, according as this content is interpreted by the sym­ bols of both the Lutheran and Reformed confessions; moreover, it .jembrac^g all in the Sacred Scriptures, a: iHREwaffarii divine revelation, in the Bi atxoï^Oh^acré^S^^tÏÏ^^^f'^^a^ prmcrpIFoFtÎhrîstmrTFaiti?). IiL'the minds of many, this divine inspiration of the Sacred Scriptures extended not only to the content {real inspiration), but also to the very last syllable and point in the text {verbal inspiration), as well as to the origin of the canonical, divinely inspired Scriptures. Upon the foundation of such a Faith- rested also the science of Faith or Theology. To reason was conceded only a formal, instrumental use (usus organicus, instrumentalis) relative to the truths of Faith. Consequently, the basis of Faith and of Theology was a kind of mysticism, and from this coin of vantage the early theologians sought to combat all pseudo-mysticism. They looked upon the power and efficacy of the Holy Spirit as joined to the word of the Sacred Scripture and bound to it, precisely inasmuch as the word of the Bible appeared to them to be true and genuine in the light of the interpretation set down in the symbols of Faith. They regarded the word of the Bible, thus interpreted, as a weapon of defence, to combat the pseudo­ mysticism of the so-called enthusiasts and the theosophical mysticism of Valentin Weigel, J. Boehme, J. G. Gichtel and others. On this mystic foundation of the testimony of the Holy Spirit was reared the Pietism of a Spener and a Franke, with this difference, however, that Pietism, in con­ trast with orthodoxy, regarded a pious life operative in charity and good works, and an interpretation of the Holy Scriptures in harmony with such a life, as the essence of Christianity, without holding strictly to the letter of the formulated confessions. It was only at the turning-point of the eighteenth century that this conception, which made Divine Faith rest upon the mystic basis of the testimonium Spiritus Sancti, was abandoned, and in its stead was intro­ Teaching sy·- 100 sumimrjr. 7 γ/ Criticism. Chapter III duced, through the school of Wolff and Storr, a rationalhistorical, or a biblico-historical, foundation.13 To sum Up ; Orthodox Protestantism either under­ estimated the value and power of external Miracles, as compared with the spiritual Miracles wrought by God in man’s heart, or, in place of the criteria always in vogue in the Church, appealed rather to a new mystic testimony, which can.,be termed an internal criterion only in that it manifests itself, not through an external, but rather an internal Miracle. Moreover, since the Miracles of Christianity bear witness solely to the Church, Prot­ estants denied all extra-evangelical Miracles and, in their polemics against the Church, were obliged to invoke 4 ‘ the interior testimony of the Holy Spirit”, “the interior experience of the individual”, and similar mystical cri­ teria.14 Thus, for the early Reformers the credibility of the mysteries of faith signified their aptitude for belief, inasmuch as under private inspiration they appear as divinely revealed.1516 * It is, indeed, true that external physical Miracles possess less value and power than internal spiritual Miracles; however, the latter cannot prove the divine origin of Revelation, since/they are invisible. The ques­ tion at issue is : Whether this interior testimony is really the testimony of God, or merely .the testimony of a wicked spirit, or of our own spirit. Hence, we must judge whether the interior experience is a divine inspiration, or simply the expression of our own subjective feelings. And so, after all, we are obliged to appeal to another criterion. Moreover, as we shall show in detail below, this testi­ mony of the Holy Spirit, this internal experience, is a very indefinite and dubious concept.18 13) A. v. Schmid, ibid., pp. 210, 211; IDEM, Untersuchungen Uber den letzten Gewissheitsgrund des Offenbarungsglaubens. Mün­ chen. 1879, pp. 111-131. 14) Gutberlet, Lehrbuch der Apologetik. Münster i. W. 1904 (3’ ed.), II: “Von der geoffenbarten Religion”, p. 100. 16) P. Fr. Reg. Garrigou-Lagrange, Ο. P., Theologia Fundamen­ talis secundum S. Thomae Doctrinam. Romae et Parisiis. 1918, I, p. 519; (3’ed.), p. 269. 16) Gutberlet, ibid. II, p. 100. Protestantism 101 2. This theory of credibility leads to false conse­ quences. For, in the first place, if it is an internal reve­ lation of the Holy Spirit, which enables one to recognize an external revelation as divine, the court of last appeal, and the highest principle of supernatural truth and cer­ titude, is not Revelation, but rather this same internal testimony of the Holy Spirit. Thereby every vagary of visionary mysticism would be justified and religious truth, stripped of its objective dignity, would be at the mercy of every fantastic opinion.17 Thus, George Fox, the founder of the Society of-Friends (Quakers), taught, as the central dogma of his sect, the tenet of “the inner light”, which is supposed to be commu­ nicated to the individual soul directly by Christ, “who enlighteneth every man that cometh into the world”. To walk in this light, and to obey the voice of Christ speaking within the soul, was for Fox the supreme and sole duty of man. Creeds and churches, councils, rites and sacraments, were discarded as so many outward things. Even the Sacred Scriptures were to be interpreted by the inner light.18 Secondly, apart from this questionable immediatë in­ ternal revelation of the Holy Spirit, the divinity of this 17) Hettinger-Weber, Lehrbuck der Fundament alt heolo g ie oder Apologetik. Freiburg, i .B. 1913 (3’ed.), pp. 190, 191. 18 ) cf. James F. Loughlin, art. "Society of Friends", in CE. VI, p. 305 sq. Robert Barclay, one of the ablest apologists of the society, writes: “Unum addam argumentum ut probem hanc internam imme­ diatam et objectivam revelationem solum esse immobile et certum fidei fundamentum. Illud, ad quod omnes christianitatis professores ultimo recurrunt, cum ad extremum pressi sunt, et cujus causa certa omnia fundamenta commendantur et creditu digna habentur, et sine quo rejiciuntur, oportet esse solum, certissimum, immobile fundamentum omnis fidei christianae. Sed interna immediata Spiritus revelatio illud est; ... ergo est solum certissimum immobile fundamentum”. (Apologia theologiae vere christ., thes. 2. London. 1676); cf. Confession of the Society of Friends, Commonly called Quakers, A. D. 1675, in Phillip Schaff’s "The Creeds of Christendom", N. Y. 4’ed. revised and enlarged, vol. Ill, pp. 789, 790 ; also Mohler’s Symbolik, p. 492 sq., English transi, by Robertson, p. 390 sq. Neither Barclay nor Wm. Penn have been able to explain successfully, in what respect the “inward light” differs from the light of reason; neither have they been able successfully to recon­ cile the doctrine of the supreme authority of the “inner light” with the “external” claims of the Bible and the historic Christ. In fact, these doctrinal weaknesses were the fruitful germs of dissensions in later times.—For the modern viewpoint, cf. Rufus Matthew Jones, "Why I am a Quaker", in "Twelve Modern Apostles and Their Creeds", N. Y. 1926, p. 110 sq. 102 Chapter III testimony has, as its witness, something or other in the human spirit, namely, either the feelings or thought. Modern liberal Protestants, championing the former al­ ternative, Have substituted for this private inspiration the criterion of the natural religious sense, with the con­ sequent naturalistic disintegration of the content of his­ toric Christianity. On the other hand, if thought or rea­ son is made the witness, the lapse into Rationalism is not far removed.19 Therefore, the definition of credibil­ ity proposed by the early so-called Reformers, while minimizing the rights of reason and materially exagger­ ating the supernatural character of faith (pseudo-super­ naturalism), actually leads to Naturalism and Rational­ ism20 Modwn Π. As the older orthodox Theology of the Lutheran and Reformed confessions, so, too, Protestant Theology of the past century, which took the field against vulgar and speculative Rationalism, sought to ground the Chris­ tian Faith and its science chiefly upon a mystic basis, but partly also upon a biblico-historical foundation. Here we are concerned only with the former of these ten­ dencies, as championed by some of its principal repre­ sentatives. Difference be­ First, however, let us outline the characteristic differ­ tween Early and Modern Protes­ ences between Protestant Theology of the last century, in tent Theology. so far as it seeks to ground the Christian Faith through the medium of an inner, mystic experience, and the ortho­ dox Theology of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. The older Theology answered the question: Why do you believe?, by the statement: Because the Holy Spirit bears witness to, and guarantees the truth of the content of the Sacred Scriptures. Modern Protestant Theology, on the other hand, has come to realize that one cannot make the testimony of the Holy Spirit the ground of the certitude of Christian Faith without, at the. same time, assuming and holding as true the genuine divinity and credibility of that testimony; in other words, without a petitio principii. Hence, it recognizes that this certitude can be obtained only by means of an inner experience, which is perceived ie) cf. D. F. Strauss, Die christliche Glaubenslehre, I, p. 136. 20) Garrigou-Lagrange, Ο. P., ibid., I, p. 519, (3’ed.), p. 269. Protestantism 103 through the blissful impressions or effects exerted upon our emotional and volitional life. Therefore, modern Prot­ estant Theology proclaimed, as the ultimate ground of the certitude of Christian Faith, the impressions of consola­ tion and joy experienced within the soul, which the saving Gospel message produced in the individual. Through these impressions the individual becomes aware of. God, as the primal source of these feelings, and thus the truth of God’s testimony is rendered credible by means of the testimony of one’s inner spiritual experience. Thereby the doctrine of fiducial faith received a greater subjective motivation, inas­ much as the genesis of that faith was thrust into the fore­ ground. Moreover, modern Protestant Theology, in contrast with the earlier form, also set a greater value upon the powers of fallen man and, in consequence, also upon the measure of philosophical and apologetic knowledge, and the eviden­ tial value of the criteria externa et interna credibilitatis, although it still refuses to ground the fides fiducialis et salvifica upon these motives. As regards the content of Faith, modern Protestant The­ ology no longer conceives Revelation so strictly according to the meaning of the older confessions of Faith, particu­ larly since the State (in Germany) endeavored to bring about a union of the Lutheran and Reformed churches, on the occasion of the three hundredth anniversary of the Reformation. Modern Protestant Theology appears partly as a “medi­ ating” theology ( Vermitt lung st heologie), which no longer acknowledges the supernatural in its strict theological con­ notation, partly as a theology of repristination or restora­ tion, which, in so far as it continued to rest upon a con­ fessional basis, very often undertook a revision of the Lutheran and Reformed symbols, or asserted that the sym­ bols were obligatory only in so far as they were in har­ mony with one another, or finally, ascribed normative value to the Bible alone, variously interpreted in a positive be­ lieving sense. Still claiming that subjectively the inner spiritual experience of the individual is the ultimate ground of faith, modern Protestant Theology, now in a neo-Kantian, now in a Pietistic guise, has strayed into the many and multifarious paths of a “liberalized” Christianity, even with respect to the Apostles’ Creed. It differs from the earlier Theology finally, in that it makes a more careful distinction between Revelation and-the documents of Reve­ lation, the content of Revelation and the content of the Sacred Scriptures, the inspiration of Revelation and the I " 104 ‘ I 1 I * I’ 1 I [' ! · I Β ■ if I I I I I 9 Chapter III inspiration of the Bible; moreover, it no longer asserts that the proof that a doctrine is in conformity with Sacred Scriptures, is eo ipso the proof of its truth; lastly, it subjects not merely the genuinity and integrity of the biblical writings, but more so even their inspiration, to the in­ quiries of “untrammelled” criticism, and no longer admits strictly verbal inspiration, nay even surrenders the real inspiration of many or even of all the biblical writings and thus, for various reasons, opens the way to a more liberal interpretation of the Bible.21 In point of fact, so-called “Modern Christianity”, “Progressive Christianity”, “the New Theology”, as it is variously termed, retains very little of primitive traditional Christianity.22* The Illuminism of the eighteenth century had rudely shaken men’s faith in dogma, but its own efforts at spreading a rationalistic religion had met with scanty success. Protestant Theology, so Fr. Aug. B. Nitzsch writes,28 faced new tasks. Among other things the posi­ tion of religion, in the spiritual life of the individual and of history, had to be re-investigated and theoretically defined in accordance with the temper of the age, with its predilection for the vital, personal and affective element of man’s nature. On the other hand,'Theology had to be harmonized with the most recent results of criti’ cism, as applied to the Bible and the history of dogma, idealism. Modern Protestant Theology found an important Romanticism, · λ · schieiermacher. preparation for its new tasks, on the one hand, in German Idealism, which made the high-tensioned inner life . of man the fountain-head of a new philosophy and ideal of life. In place of mere reason it proclaimed the, rights of the immediateness, oneness and individuality of man. On the other hand, Theology joined hands with the Ro­ manticism of the earlier period of Protestantism. And out of the fusion of Kantian and romanticist impulses • issued a new philosophy, which, in its attempts to domi­ nate all the spheres of life and knowledge, naturally also 21) A. v. Schmid, ibid., pp. 213, 214. 22) cf. Errett Gates, The Development of Modern Christianity, in A Guide to the Study of the Christian Religion, ed. G. E. Smith. Chicago, Ill. 1917 (2’ed Impression), pp. 431-482. 28) Lehrbuch der evangelischen Dogmatik, ed. by Horst Stephan. Tübingen. 1912 (3’ed.), p. 38. Protestantism 105 included religion, and thus became of primal significance in the development of modern Protestant Theology.24 This is not the place to trace in detail the Various efforts that were made in the past century, to translate “inher­ ited doctrines into modern philosophical form with as little disturbance to faith as possible”.25 The attempts to intermingle the older religious attitude with modern philosophy inevitably led to confusion. A third and most important factor in the develop­ ment of modern Protestant Theology is the influence of Friedrich Schleiermacher, whose definition of Theology as the interpretation of the experience of Christian men, introduced a new epoch in the history of religious thought. Ever since his day this appeal to Christian experience, as the test of the truth of religion and mor­ ality, has become increasingly predominant in Protes­ tantism.26 The influence of Schleiermacher in this respect is ex- °!Jh^1do^ew pressed by, a recent Protestant writer in the following 600 words: “For the type of theology which finds the content of doctrine in an authorized system the primary question must be as to the validity of this authority. Thus, the au­ thenticity of Scripture must be established by orthodox theology before one is scientifically justified in deriving doctrines from Scripture. If, however, we regard doctrines as the creations of religious thinking for the purpose of interpreting religious experience, the first task of the the­ ologian must be to inquire concerning the nature of re­ ligious experience. This approach to the study of theology was initiated over a century ago by Schleiermacher, whose famous Discourses on Religion are today as stimulating as anything which one may read on the subject of religion”. Hence, the student of Protestant Theology is urged to “real­ ize that his primary task is to understand the vital nature and function of religion. If interest is once aroused in this direct subject-matter, many of the formal topics of the­ ological controversy—such as discussion concerning the exact location of 'authority’—cease to be of importance”.27 24) Nitzsch, ibid., pp. 38-40. 25) Gerald Birney Smith, Systematic. Theology and Christian Ethics, in A Guide to the Study of the Christian Religion. Chicago, Ill. 1917 (2’Impression), pp. 504, 505. 26) Ibid., p. 499. 27) G. B. Smith, ibid., pp. 508, 509. 106 Conclusion. Chapter III In the light of this brief historical survey of modern Protestant Theology, the tendency to divorce religion from reason and to unite it, on the one hand, with the will, and on the other hand, with the emotions, the move­ ments of the heart, is not difficult to understand. This will become clearer, if we study the writings of some of the more representative advocates of Voluntarism, and Emotional Religion in modern Protestant thought. At the same time, the relative value of the subjective and mystic criteria of Revealed Religion, as understood by the great majority of modern Protestants, will appear in clearer light. I I. K»nt. VOLUNTARISM 1. For Protestants “one of the principal fountains from which the main stream of modern theology has flowed”28 is Immanuel Kant (1724-1804). The primacy of value, which the “will” enjoys in religion and faith among large sections of present day Protestantism, is mainly due to his influence. For clarity’s sake, we must remind the student that we are not concerned here with the question as to the influence of the will in the exercise of religion and faith; for doubt­ less in this practical respect, the will does occupy the pri­ mary and most important position. For us the problem is rather this: What is the extent of the will’s influence in the matter of religious convictions? Or more precisely: What value attaches to the will as a criterion of the natural knowability of Divine Revelation?29 Pascal had already emphasized in a one-sided fashion the motives of the will or the heart, which “has its rea­ sons that the mind knows not of”.30 But it was Kant who proclaimed the perfect independence of practical reason ; upon it and the will only, so he insisted, devolves the task 28 ) Errett Gates, ibid., p. 455. 29 ) J. Mausbach, Die Religion und das moderne Seelenleben, in RCK, I, p. 62. 30) cf, J. Lataste, art. “Blaise Pascal”, in CE. XI, p. 512. I Voluntarism 107 of giving to a philosophy of life that final consumma­ tion, which speculative reason must despair of attaining. For Kant the existence of God is not a truth of knowl­ edge, but rather a practical assumption on the basis of the moral consciousness, a postulate, which becomes a reality through the medium of the moral will. This “faith” fills in the lacuna which the abdication of rea­ son produced in man.31 Kant’s ideal is a religion of pure reason, which pre- Kant’· Philosophy cinds from every positive Revelation and statute. Its doc- of RelIeion' trinal content is meager, being limited essentially to the existence of God, the immortality of the soul, and the moral law. Kant does not indeed absolutely reject a belief in Re­ vealed Religion resting on historical facts; he is inclined to concede to it a provisional significance, even though he does not acknowledge its supernatural origin. However, he is willing to tolerate such a faith only under certain limited conditions. It may not lay claim to any unique value; it may serve only as a means of visualizing the truths of natural reason. Neither may this faith be regarded as an essential condition of salvation. Its explanation is to fol­ low the spirit of the religion of reason, as its highest norm ; that is, its individual doctrines are to be interpreted as the investiture of ethical ideas: “The reading of these sacred writings or the inquiry into their content has as its final end, to make better men ; but the historical element, which does not contribute anything thereto is, in itself, something entirely indifferent, which one can regard as one wills”.32 Kant himself transmutes the central dogmas of Christianity in this spirit. Thus, for him the eternal Logos is simply the divine idea of morally perfect man. Inasmuch as this idea proceeds from God’s essence, the Logos is God’s only begotten Son. Christianity rightly recognizes the highest realization of the ethical idea in a man, who, despite the strongest temptations and the greatest sufferings, remains steadfast in the faithful performance of duty until death. Union with this ideal man guarantees salvation.33 Mean­ while, however, one may not tolerate the idea- that this faith even in its present form will last forever; in the course of Mausbach, ibid., p. 64. Die Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der blossen Vernunft. ed. Reclam. Leipzig, p. 118. 33) Ibid., p. 62 sq. 31) 32) 108 i ■ ■ i I I t Chapter III time it must give way more and more to the faith of pure and unveiled Reason. Religious action, in so far as it is justifiable, consists only in the fulfilment of ethical duties. Religion and mor­ ality are really identical. Moral life becomes religion, when the moral law is acknowledged as the law of God. Hence, the definition: “Religion (looked at subjectively) is the acknowledgment that our duties are divine command­ ments”.3435This definition precludes the erroneous concep­ tion, which would make religion a complexus of particular duties immediately directed to God, and prevents our accept­ ing court service in addition to the ethical and civil duties of man.85 The religion of pure Reason, at least, limits itself to moral conduct. In the existing religion, side by side with moral laws, there are still “statutory” laws, which impose on man particular duties in respect of God and impel him to perform particular religious practices. Kant regards these as grounded in human nature and is unwilling to condemn them, so long as they remain subordinated to ethical pur­ poses or ends. But just as soon as the idea obtains, that such exercises are pleasing to God, they become an abuse..36 Kant goes so far as to reject absolutely every prayer as divine worship in the proper sense of the term.87 God has no need of “court service” and cannot be moved by flattery J1 and prayers. He sees our needs and of Himself gives us what His goodness wishes to bestow. As regards the religious community, Kant is of the opinion that it results, like religion itself, from ethical con­ siderations. The full domination of the good can be realized by “the establishment and spread of a society according to the laws of virtue”, by the organization of a “kingdom of God”, a ‘‘church”. Kant’s ideal church is an “ethical repub­ lic”, which discards all dogmatic definitions and accepts “rational faith”, as its guide in all intellectual matters, and establishes the reign of the kingdom of God on earth by bringing about the reign of duty. In this church there will be no external authority and human statutes any more.88 In harmony with Kant’s Agnosticism, the criteria of Mira­ cles and Prophecies are, of course, rejected as unknowable. 34) Ibid., p. 164. 35) Ibid., p. 164. 36) Ibid., pp. 184, 186. 37) ibid., p. 213 sq. 38) Ibid., p. 130. cf. Franz Sawicki, Lebensanschauungen moderner Denker. Paderborn. 1920 (2’-3’ed.), pp. 40-44; Wm. Turner, art. “Philosophy of Kant*’, in CE. VIII, p. 603 sq. Voluntarism 109 2. Arthur Schopenhauer (1788-1860)39 also championed Schopenhauer the primacy of the will over knowledge in the apprehension w** of the Absolute. According to him the will itself is the Absolute ; the basic essence of all things is a blind striving and willing, to which the intellect associates itself merely later on, in a secondary, ancillary capacity. This predomi­ nance of willing, as compared with thinking, manifests itself in all the details of life; men’s judgments, whether they believe or doubt, love or hate, yes, even when they err in computing or counting, are according to Schopenhauer dominated by their interests and their individual advan­ tages.4,0 3. Many modern thinkers gratefully acclaimed this v»iue-judgm»nts. voluntaristic tendency as a defence against bold Material­ ism, as a means of rescue from the faintheartedness of subjective Idealism, and incorporated it into their own system. In the deepest problems of life, so they claimed, the decisive factors are not ‘4 judgments of exist­ ence”, but rather “judgments of value” and “feelings of value”, which express the tendency of man’s personal will. If there is still a metaphysics, the most that it can accomplish is to lead one to an absolute ground of the world, but not to God, as the content of the good, that is, not to the God of Theism. It is the will, the practical need, that decides one’s philosophy of life in the latter sense; we cannot “live” without God; we cannot sustain our personality, in the face of Nature’s forces, without God (Paulsen, Windelband, K. A. Lipsius, Tolstoi). The underlying thought of this philosophy of religion may be summarized thus : I hold fast to my religion, not be­ cause it is the true religion ; but it is the true religion, because and in so far as it corresponds with my needs. Accordingly, faith has no “objective validity, but only a subjective inevitableness”. This voluntaristic concep­ tion finds its logical expression in so-called Pragmatism; also in the school of Ritschl with its aversion for meta­ 39) Die Welt als Wille und V orstellung, 1819, II vol. 1844, with essays “Parerga,” and “Paralipomena”. English transi. “The World as Will and Idea” by Haldane and Kemp. London. 1886. *9) J. Mausbach, Die Religion und das moderne Seelenleben, in RCK, I, p. 64; cf. A. B. Sharpe, art. “Pessimism”, in CE. XI, p. 740 sq. Fr. Sawicki, ibid., p. 59 sq. 110 Balfour. Chapter III physics and its theory of faith closely akin to Luther’s; finally, in certain Modernists, for whom, however, the purpose of this practical need is simply to create the right disposition for religion; religion itself, the real faith in God, rests rather upon an experience of the feel­ ings.41 We shall treat of the pragmatic, Ritschlian and modernistic viewpoints more in detail below. 4. Arthur James Balfour expounds a characteristic theory of belief on the equivocal grounds, that it is no less certain than scientific theory and method. Our be­ liefs are largely determined by non-rational causes, and, even when evidence is their motive, what we regard as evidence is settled by circumstances altogether beyond our control.42 Starting with Kantianism and Positivism he questions the value of metaphysics; the existence of God, the immortality of the soul, and the freedom of the will are inaccessible to rational demonstration ; the prac­ tical reason, faith, must step into the breach.43 Balfour strives to show “how, in the face of the com­ plex tendencies which sway this strange age of ours, we may best draw together our beliefs into a comprehensive unity, which shall possess at least a relative and provisional stability”.44 The logical use of modern speculative reason on the data of experience, which he labels “Naturalism” (that is, Positivism, Idealism, Rationalism), in his opinion leads to the negation of religion and morality—to Agnosti­ cism. Their principles or methods rest upon indemonstrable and inevident postulates ; and yet, men cannot and will not and ought not to abandon religious and moral beliefs. Hence, an adequate motive for these beliefs must be found. “Not reasoning, inductive or deductive” lies at the basis of “the immediate beliefs of experience”, but rather nonrational processes, especially authority, by which Balfour understands, “a convenient collective name for the vast «) Mausbach, ibid., I, pp. 64, 65. Balfour, Defence of Philosophic Doubt. London, 1879,chap. xiii. cf. G. Fonsegrive, Le catholicisme et la vie de ΐesprit. Paris, 1906, p. 52. Renouvier takes a similar stand. Every proposition, in order to be affirmed with certainty, demands an act of the will ; science is the result of an act of faith and the whole of science accordingly rests upon faith (cf. Fonsegrive, ibid., p. 45). 44) Balfour, The Foundations of-Belief. Being Notes introductory to the Study of Theology. London, 1919 (1 l’impression), p. 345. 42) 43) Voluntarism 111 multitude of psychological causes of belief, not being also reasons for it, which have their origin in the social environ­ ment, and are due to the action of mind on mind’*. 45 Thus, the immediate cause or motive for man’s beliefs is the com­ bined influence of all the factors, which constitute a man’s social environment and make up the “psychological atmos­ phere”, in which his mental life is steeped and'formed. But, then, man cannot and does not live (his intellectual, moral, religious life) on reasons alone; “certitude is found to be the child not of reason, but of custom”. Man must hold to his beliefs despite the “rational” negations of Agnosticism, not by attempting the hopelessly difficult, if not impossible, task of rationalizing these beliefs; nor by attempting the equally hopeless task of finding adequate rational grounds for the authority of the various social institutions, whether civil or religious, which propound these beliefs to him as true. Since the beliefs of which Naturalism is composed must on its own principles have a non-rational source, there is no contradiction if in other spheres, for instance, in the­ ology, the same condition prevails. Hence, it is only right and proper and natural for man to trust the instinctive “non-rational” impulses and yearnings of his soul, and so to hold firmly to moral and religious beliefs,—beliefs which so obviously harmonize with all that is best and noblest in man’s nature, and the loss of which would degrade man to an unnatural condition of mere animality.* 46 “If no better ground for accepting as fact a material world more or less in correspondence with our ordinary judgments of sense perceptions can be 'alleged than the practical need for doing so, there is nothing irrational in postulating a like harmony between the Universe and other Elements in our nature, ‘of a later, a more uncertain, but of no ignoble growth’ ”.47 Balfour then contends that his argument shows “that the great body of our beliefs, scientific, ethical, aesthetic, and theological, form a more coherent and satisfactory whole in a Theistic than in a Naturalistic setting”. Press­ ing the argument further, he maintains that these depart­ ments of knowledge, or any of them, are more coherent and satisfactory in a distinctively Christian setting than in a purely Theistic one.48 He thinks that it can be shown that the central doctrine of Christianity, the doctrine which essentially differentiates it from- every other religion, «) 46) 47 ) «) Ibid., p. 390. cf. P. Coffey, Epistemology. London. 1917, vol. II, pp. 345, 346. The Foundations of Belief, pp. 391, 392. Italics inserted. Ibid., p. 397. ft 112 Chapter IΠ namely the Incarnation, “has an ethical import of great and even of an increasing value”. He enumerates three aspects of this doctrine “in which it especially ministers as nothing else could conceivably minister, to some of the most deep-seated of our moral necessities”. a) “The whole tendency of modern discovery is neces­ sarily to magnify material magnitudes to the detriment of spiritual ones. The insignificant part played by moral forces in the cosmic drama, the vastness of the physical forces by which we are closed in and overwhelmed . . . in’ crease (on the Theistic hypothesis) our sense of the power of God, but relatively impoverish our sense of his moral interest in his creatures. It is surely impossible to imagine a more effective cure for this distorted yet most natural estimate than a belief in the Incarnation”.49 b) “Again, the absolute dependence of mind on body ... is of all beliefs the one which, if fully realized, is most destructive of high endeavor. Speculation may provide an answer to physiological materialism, but for -the mass of mankind it can provide no antidote ; nor yet can an antidote be found in the bare theistic conception of a'God ineffably remote from all human conditions, divided from man by a gulf so vast that nothing short of the Incarnation can adequately bridge it”.50 c) “A like thought is suggested by the ‘problem of evil’ . . . Of this difficulty, indeed, the Incarnation affords > no speculative solution, but it does assuredly afford a prac­ tical palliation . . . Christianity brings home to us, as noth­ ing else could do, that God is no indifferent spectator of our sorrows, and in so doing affords the surest practical alleviation to a pessimism which seems fostered alike by / the virtues and the vices of our modern civilization”.51 summary. To sum up : The advocates of Voluntarism, divorcing the reason from the will, closely associate the origin, and the essence of religion and faith with the volitional part of man’s nature and with the exigencies of practical life. Repudiating the traditional apologetics of reason, they seek to ground religious faith upon voluntaristic motives of credibility. Accordingly, by the credibility of the truths of religion and ethics, they mean their aptitude for belief, inasmuch as they appear conformable with the 4») Ibid., p. 398; cf. pp. 333-338. 60) Ibid., p. 398; cf. pp. 338-341. 61) Ibid., pp. 398-399. Voluntarism 113 dictates of practical reason, or with the practical needs of man’s religious and moral life.6263 64 1. We are not now concerned with the problem as to CritIciam the measure of influence, which the will exerts on knowl­ edge, especially in the sphere of religious faith.53 Neither is this the place to enter upon a criticism of Kant’s theory of knowledge in its application to voluntaristic faith. The stüdent is referred to philosophy, especially to epistemol­ ogy, for an ex professo discussion of these questions.54 This much, at least, is certain : Whoever separates theoretical from practical reason, builds upon a precarious foundation. Faith is powerless to reconstruct the beautiful world which critical reason has deliberately demolished. Doubtless the natural and moral tendency of the will is of the greatest value, in the matter of inspiring and promoting thought activity and of giving to it earnestness and profundity. But if the will neglects this task, if it surrenders thought activity to a false propensity or inclination to individual­ istic self-disintegration, it is impotent to create a certain religious conviction. There is a natural connection between the true and the good, between “judgments of existence" and “judgments of value"; in the good is contained an in­ tensified truth and reality; in a judgment of value there is contained the acknowledgment of the excellence and dignity of existence.65 Hence, it is not surprising that ih the history of modern ethics Kant stands almost alone, when he asserts that the categorical imperative (the moral legislation of practical reason) is the primary, a priori truth, which.evi­ dences itself to every one without proof, and which gives to the whole realm of conscience, to morality, its uncondi­ tional validity and unction. This undervaluing of the vital· tasks, of the pregnant and inspiring purposes, of morality, has finally been rejected almost universally as an artificial and impotent formalism.66 2. The question that interests us here is : "What is the vohmjuffetie^chvalue of this voluntaristic criterion as regards the Problem of cernatural knowability oî Divine Revelation? And in this tItude U1MOIved* respect Voluntarism, in common with other subjective systems of thought, makes “the common mistake of leavG2) Garrigou-Lagrange, Ο. P., ibid., I, p. 619; (3’ed.), pp. 269, 270. 63) cf. Mausbach, ibid., I, pp. 65-72; Chas. R. Baschab, A Manual of N eo-Scholastic Philosophy. St. Louis, Mo., 1924 (2’ed.), pp. 177-184. 64) cf. P. Coffey, Epistemology. London. 1917, Π, pp. 330-344. 56) Mausbach, ibid., I, pp. 75, 76. G6) Ibid., p. 74. 1 114 Chapter III .ing the problem of certitude without solution. Sceptics themselves admit this more or less necessary impulse of our nature to assent to certain truths. But the whole point at issue is to ascertain whether this impulse is blind or justified. If any claim is made to justify it, recourse must be had in the last resort to some other motive than the nature of the subject, to a motive whose foundation the intellect can itself perceive, in a word, to a criterion which is objective”.All anti-intellectualistic theories, which would ground certitude ultimately on non-rational motives, produce not assents of certitude, but only of a prudent probabilism. An appeal to subjective feeling or sentiment, to the “will to believe”, must show its cre­ dentials before the bar of reflecting reason. An appeal to such extrinsic influences as are not directly rational, influences that are motives or causes, but not reasons (Balfour), of assent, cannot lay claim to my submission, until I know that what they prompt me to do is true. It is indeed proper for me-to believe ; to trust my faculties ; to trust the moral and religious promptings of my na­ ture. But only, when I convince myself that there are reasonable grounds for my doing so; but not sooner. It 1 is wrong for man to abdicate his dignity as a rational· being by trusting or believing blindly. He must use his reason to discover satisfactory objective grounds for be­ lieving; such grounds will be the ultimate test of the truth of what he is to believe; they will be the ultimate motive of his certitude ; then his belief will be a reason­ able belief, an obsequium rationabile. When the indi­ vidual holds beliefs “because he is rationally convinced, rationally certain, that he has adequate grounds for their credibility, for the truth of what they propose to him, then and then only does he believe rightly and rationally. For, as St. Thomas says, “Ea, quae subsunt fidei . . . aliquis non crederet nisi videret ea esse credenda’; and not only would the individual de facto refuse, but he would be 67) Cardinal Mercier, A Manual of Modern Scholastic Philosophy. Authorized translation and eighth edition by T. L. Parker and S. H. Parker. London & St. Louis, Mo. 1916, vol. I, p. 366. Emotional Religion 115 right in refusing, to ‘believe them unless he saw them to be credible’ The man of average intelligence can de facto easily see both within him and around him, in his own nature, in the world of experience, and in the light which those truths throw both on his own nature and on the world around him, adequate objective evi­ dence of the credibility of the truths to which he assents, for truth makes to Ihe human intelligence an objective evidential appeal, which is not forthcoming in the case of error. He can finally meet and settle all satisfactorily, according to the measure of his capacity and oppor­ tunities, such difficulties as may de facto happen to arise against the credibility of what he believes. Thus, the certitude of his belief is a reflex, reasoned and reason­ able certitude”.®8 The voluntaristic criterion is, there­ fore, insufficient to enable us to arrive at a certain knowl­ edge of Divine Revelation. r ? \ * II. EMOTIONAL RELIGION Protestant Theology, for the., most part, still looks upon the inner experience of the power and efficacy of God’s revealed word to satisfy our feelings and our striving for happiness as the primary criterion of the Christian Faith. It regards this criterion not as an in­ tellectual, but rather as an emotional experience, an experience of the sentiments or the heart. Hence, the ground of the certitude of salvific Faith, and of the sci­ ence upon which it rests, is not an inner experience in the sense of an intellectual intuition or perception, but an inner experience in the sense of a feeling of that, which satisfies our striving for bliss and of whatever goes to make up our happiness. This criterion is said to be an adequate sign of certitude, even apart from previous metaphysical or apologetical proofs, and without in the end needing Kant’s proofs of the moral reason. We have already called this criterion “mystical” and so, too, B8) Coffey, ibid., Π, pp. 346-348. r. 116 Chapter III many Protestants term it.59 For obvious reasons we are obliged to restrict our study to some of the more typical representatives of this viewpoint. 1. Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi (1743-1819)60 protested most vehemently against Kant’s ethical faith in God and religion. To it as well as to Lessing’s and Herder’s pan­ theistic concepts of God and religion, he opposed a sentir mental religious faith and was, therefore, like Rousseau be­ fore him, the protagonist of a sentimental religious Illuminism. For him religion was not merely a mediate postulate of morality, not only an adjunct of ethics, but rather some­ thing original, immediate, something that could be grasped by a. sentimental rational faith, no matter how imperfect it might appear to the understanding. He visioned man as caught between the devil and the deep blue sea: in heart man is a Christian, but in understanding a heathen, an atheist and a pantheist.61 Jacobi created a complete philosophy of Revelation. For him Revelation like Faith is the term or expression for the irrationality of the world. Accepting the conclusion of Kant’s “Kritik der reinen Vernunft”, namely that human “understanding” (Verstand) cannot transcend the limits of sense experience and arrive at a knowledge of the “nourrienon” or essence of things, Jacobi maintained that our con­ viction concerning the existence of things rests upon Reve­ lation and Faith. It is especially the irrational powers with­ in ourselves, the basic impulse of the true, the good, and the beautiful, the sentiments of reason (Vernunftgefühle), which must be ultilized as God’s Revelation ; by their means God becomes immediately present within us.62 In other words, ‘‘he proclaimed that man is endowed with a higher69 69 ) A. v. Schmid, ibid., pp. 236, 237. Other Protestant theologians, however, designate as “mystic” only those tendencies, which assume an immediate union of the soul with God and Christ in the formal mean­ ing of that term, or which unduly dissociate the inner Christian experi­ ence from the external, objective basis of the Person of Christ, as He continues to live in the community and appears to us in the Bible. Others call only that experience mystical, which emanates from ex­ ceptionally vital and intensive emotions (Pietism, Methodism etc.), or from an immediate ecstatic absorption into the Divine, etc. To that extent it is only a quaestio vocis. (Schmid, ibid., p. 237, foot-note) cf. R. H. Fisher, Religious Experience. The Baird Lectures for 1924. N. Y., pp. 48-70. 60) Werke, 6 vols., Leipzig. 1812-1825; Briefwechsel, 2 vols., 1825-1827. 61) Schmid, ibid., pp. 75, 76. 62) Nitzsch-Stephan, Lehrbuch der evangelischen Dogmatik, pp. Emotional Religion 117 faculty than this ‘understanding’, which reasons logically from the data of sense. This higher faculty (Vernunft: ‘reason’) works in a hidden, mysterious way in the suprasensible domain of the true, the good, and the beautiful, as a sort of spiritual feeling or sentiment (Geistesgefiihl). It is prior to, and deeper than, all reasoning : we cannot seize or analyze it: we simply believe in it and accept its dic­ tates. It has nothing to do with the phenomena but gets us into contact with noumena, with reality. Through it we escape scepticism and rise superior to all the doubts and limitations of the mere logical faculty, the understanding. Thus, human certitude is based ultimately not on any in­ telligent apprehension of reality as the object of the human understanding, but on an inevident dictate of sentiment or feeling”.9* The following study will show how this “phil­ osophy of sentiment”—sentiment or feeling variously de­ scribed as “rational”, “moral”, “esthetic”, “religious”, “spiritual”,—as contrasted with the so-called “reasoned” systems with their claims for the supremacy of intellectual evidence as the basis of certitude, permeates a very great portion of modern Protestant Theology. Jacobi’s Christianity is certainly not a positive, but rather a deistic sentimental Christianity. And even for the latter form of Christianity he had no certain scientific cri­ terion, because of its basic irrationalism.64 2. Modern Protestantism hails Friedrich Schleiermacher (1786-1834) as its great theologian and the founder of the so-called “mediating” theology (Vermittlungstheologie), which sought to reconstruct the bridge between supernaturalism and rationalism, Reve­ lation and nature, faith and science, orthodoxy and ideal­ istic philosophy.*65 He made a clean sweep of Melanchthonism and poked fun at the “finished plaything” of “natural theology”.66 “In an age which was inclined to hold religion in contempt, and to array scientific knowl­ edge and philosophical reflection against it”, says a mod­ 68) P. Coffey, Epistemology, vol. II, pp. 318, 319. «<) Schmid, ibid., p. 76. 65) w. Koch, art. “Schleiermâcher”, in Buchbergers Kirchliches Handleæikon. Freiburg i. B, 1912, vol. II, colls. 1969, 1970; IDEM, art. “Vermittlungstheologie”, II, col. 2584, ββ) Gisler, ibid., p. 243. Schlelermacher. 118 < Chapter III ern Protestant writer,67 “he sought a defense for it. To this end he prepared the epoch-making ‘Reden’ for the ‘cultured despisers of religion’ ”. Banishing meta­ physics from Christian philosophy, Schleiermacher “finds Religion, as Kant had found the fundamental moral law, in the human consciousness as such—it is a necessary and inalienable constituent element of human experience in its highest interpretation. It cannot, there­ fore, be a product of thought (it is not to be identified with a doctrine or sum of doctrines or to be viewed as the effect of such) ; or of moral action (it is not an in­ ference from moral principles or a belief involved in the subjection to a universal moral law) ; but it is an original human endowment. Indeed, in human experience it is antecedent to all knowledge and action, for it ap­ pears in that rudimentary consciousness in which the distinction of subject and object, self and not-self, had not yet appeared. In- this priority, religion is exhibited as superior to knowledge and morality. Here the soul is the subject of the action of the universe; it is wedded to infinity”.68 Subjectively, religion consists in feeling, that is, much more than sensation; “it is that sense of oneness with the whole of existence which is peace and blessedness. It comes into vivid consciousness in those deep emotions which are aroused by, or ex­ pressed in, elevated discourse or poetry or song. It does not submit itself to minute analysis or theological process. It is an immediate possession”.69* Philosophi­ cally, “it is the universe expressing itself in the human consciousness. Therefore, it occurs in and with man’s relationship to the world. In one aspect it may be desig­ nated as the human self-consciousness itself in its high­ est interpretation, and in another aspect as a function of the universe, the universe coming to self-conscious­ 67) Errett Gates, The Development of Modern Christianity, in A Guide to the Study of the Christian Religion, ed. by G. B. Smith, Chi­ cago, ΙΠ. (Second Impression), 1917, p. 455. 68) Geo. Cross, The Theology of Schleiermacher. A Condensed Presentation of his chief work, "The Christian Faith". Chicago, Ill. 1911, pp. 106, 107. 6») Ibid,, p. 107, Emotional Religion 119 ness in man”.70 “Religion is an immediate, or original, experience of the self-consciousness in the form of feel­ ing”;71 “in the feeling of absolute dependence God is immediately given to the religious man”.72 Thus, religion is not knowledge, but feeling and the science of faith is fundamentally different from rational science. Whoever possesses this feeling is according to Schleiermacher pious, religious, even though he does not know that this sentiment is religion, and does not realize and acknowl­ edge the Infinite as a personal something, but views it merely as something living and operative in the uni­ verse.* 78 As the feeling of dependence upon the Infinite is the Groaadof ground of religion in general, so, too, the feeling of the chrUttan Faith· need of redemption and the certainty that the influence of Christ has put an end to the state of being in need of redemption, or the experience of redemption, are the ground of the Christian Religion, the Christian Faith. This faith is merely a sentimental faith. It is “the in­ cipient experience of the satisfaction of that spiritual need by Christ” and is, therefore, an emotional, experi­ ential faith. Even though it is acquired under the im­ pulse of the Holy Spirit and the ecclesiastical symbols, still it cannot be demonstrated11 by means of the Miracles, which He performs, or the Prophecies which predicted Him, or the special character of the testimonies orig­ inally borne to Him, regarded as the work of divine in­ spiration”. “From all this it follows that, if faith in the Revelation of God in Christ, and in redemption through Him, has not already arisen in a direct way through experience, as the demonstration of the Spirit and of power, neither Miracles nor Prophecies can pro­ duce it, and moreover this faith would be just as un­ movable even if Christianity had neither Prophecies nor Miracles to show”. The New Testament writings in par­ 70 ) Ibid., p. 108. Π) Ibid., p. 119. 72) Ibid., p. 315. 78) Schleiermacher’s Werke, 30 vols. 1834/64, vol. I, pp. 254-257; 269; 279-281. His “Reden uber die Religion an die Gebildeten unter ihren Verdchtem”. Berlin. 1799, has been rendered into English by John Oman under the title “On Religion*’, London. 1893. 120 Chapter III ticular have been inspired by the Holy Ghost only in the sense that He is “the common spirit of the Church, and hence the source of all spiritual gifts and good works”; and “all thinking, so far as it pertains to the kingdom of God, must be traced back to and inspired by the spirit”. These writings are authentic inasmuch as they are the genuine products of this common spirit, even though they come from other and later authors than those whose name they bear on their face.74 Thus, Schleiermacher divorced faith from science and made a judgment of credibility impossible. And yet, despite this valedictory to traditional apologetics, he was > unwilling to forego every defense of Christianity ; there­ fore, he sought a new approach to apologetics, namely, through the philosophy of religion. He regarded apolo­ getics as a branch of philosophical theology, and aimed at showing how Christianity is deduced from the uni­ versal concept of religion. By the help of his philosophy he hoped to establish thé peculiar essence of Christianity, as contradistinguished from other kinds of faith, by pre­ senting the differences, on the one hand, and by offering * an insight into the details, on the other hand ; thus, he hoped to strengthen the conviction as to the truth and divinity of the whole. This procedure, however, is not a proof, but merely an exposition, a characterization, of Christianity by means of the science of comparative re­ ligion. The sum-total of such an apology is not the unique character, the absolute truth, of Christianity, but only its relative value and excellence. A very meager result indeed; but whoever assumes with Schleiermacher that one’s religious philosophy of life is not an objective mirror of real cosmic conditions, but purely the subjec­ tive product of one’s own feelings and will, cannot accomplish more as an apologist.7576 74) Schleiermacher, Der christtiche Glau.be nach den Grund· sdtzen der evangelischen Kirche im Zusammenhang dargestellt. Berlin. 1843, l’Abt. Zur Théologie, I, §14; §130. 131. English translation of the second German edition. Edited by H. R. Mackintosh and J. S. Stewart. Edinburgh (T. & T. Clark), 1928, under the-title: "The Christian Faith". 76) Gisler, ibid., p. 244. Emotional Religion 121 3. The first attempt to establish a formal “System of Frank. Christian Certitude”, on the basis of interior spiritual experience, was made by Franz H. R. Frank (d. 1894), a Lutheran theologian of the more conservative type. In his opinion the Reformation practically laid hold of the reali­ ties of the Christian Faith, but it left “unsolved” the ques­ tion as to the subjective certitude of that Faith. His work seeks to come to the rescue.76 Therefore, it claims to be the ground-work of the “System of Truth” and of the “System of Morality”, hence Fundamental Theology. As such, how­ ever, it is not identical with apologetics, as some recent theologians 'would have it. Apologetics cannot ground the fides divina scientifically ; it can only defend it against the attacks of adversaries. For Christianity is “foolishness” to the natural man and the convictions, to which natural reason can attain, are not only inadequate as compared with the Christian conviction, but also more or less in contradic­ tion with it.77 To make apologetics the science which grounds theology is in contradiction with the spirit of “evangelical -theology”.78 Hence, apologetics is only a prac­ tical theological science. Not so the “System of Certitude”. Its aim is not to beget the fides divina; rather it presup­ poses it, in order to raise it to gnosis. What, then, is the ultimate ground of the fides divina? Frank answers : It is not the testimony of the Holy Spirit ; rather it is the spiritual experience of regeneration together with conversion as a change of the old man into the new; hence, the “testimony of ourselves relative to our condition as Christians”. That this new, spiritual man has the Holy Spirit, as efficient cause, must first derive its certainty from that effect.79 It is possible that the new Ego of regen­ eration is already present before conversion, especially in the case of minors. It is only regeneration with conversion that is the ultimate ground of the certitude of the Christian Faith. According to Frank this spiritual experience is just as little subject to deception as the experience of bodily con­ valescence. And granting that instances might occur where the feeling of convalescence is deceptive, still they would constitute no valid argument against the feeling of genuine convalescence.80 Finally, in and through this fundamental fact, namely, regeneration and conversion, all those facts and objects, which are implied and assumed in it, also 76) System der christlichen Gewissheit. Erlangen, 2’ed. 1881,1884, I, 12. English transi. “System of Christian Certainty" by M. J. Evans. Edinburgh, 2’ed. 1886. W) Ibid., I, 20-26. 7») Ibid., I, 37. 7») Ibid., 138-143 . 80) Ibid., I, 120-129. 122 I I : J 1 r Chapter III acquire certitude.81 In other words, starting with “Chris­ tian Certitude” in the same sense as Schleiermacher, Frank essays the absolutely impossible task of deducing therefrom all the objects of Faith; in a very uncritical way he at­ tempts to reconstruct the whole Lutheran dogmatics from the fundamental fact of regeneration and conversion.82 4. Isaac Aug. Domer (d. 1884) is also opposed to an external, authoritative and philosophical authentication of the Christian Faith, and seeks to ground it rather on inner mystic experience. He is not a Lutheran theologian like Frank, but a representative of the so-called “mediating” theology. He differs from Frank likewise in regard to the manner of grounding the fides divina. According to Frank the experience of regeneration and conversion guarantees the central certitude upon which all other Christian certi­ tude depends ; but regeneration and conversion—so Dorner objects—is continually in the making, and is not like justi­ fication “something entire and finished in its nature” ; more­ over, that principle is still too closely akin to Schleier­ macher *s conception and too subjective, since the consci­ ousness of regeneration would be “semblance and fancy” only, unless it also directly contained God and Christ and the Holy Spirit bearing witness to Himself in us, as its objective ground: “There is an immediate knowledge of God, not only a secondary knowledge, which is first deduci­ ble by way of conclusion from effect to cause . . . We are not therefore certain of God, because we are conscious of ourselves (as regenerated and converted), but because we experience and know that God is in Christ for us, therefore, we know ourselves as redeemed”.83 A proximate ground for this difference of viewpoint is, that Dorner—obviously in stricter adhesion to the Reformation principle—regards salvific Faith as grounded upon the experience of regenera­ tion as a mere forgiveness of sin, and not upon the experi­ ence of regeneration, conversion, sanctification, which fol­ low upon it. Then too, Dorner conceives the fundamental certitude of the experience of salvation in an ontologistic and a more intellectualiste manner than Frank. “Without the Absolute”, says Dorner, “there would be not only noth­ ing infinite any more for man, but likewise there would be no knowledge of the finite as such, since without the con­ trast of the infinite the finite cannot be known”.84 If natural 81 ) Schmid, ibid., pp. 215, 216. 82) Nitzsch-Stephan, ibid., p. 49. 88) System der christlichen Glaubenslehre. Berlin, 1886 (2’ed.), I, 40-41. English transi. “System of Christian Doctrine” by Prof. C. M. Mead and Rev. R. T. Cunningham. N. Y. 1887. 84) Ibid., I, 213. Emotional Religion 123 experience already has the experience of God as its presup­ position, likewise also in a higher sense the spiritual ex­ perience of Christ’s saving Revelation. Religion is not a mere feeling, but also knowing and willing; there is need of an “objective norm” to which piety, to be perfect, must conform itself. This norm is to be sought for in knowledge ; hence, feeling without knowledge is not 'religion, even though this knowledge must not be conceptual and scien­ tific.86 While this more intellectualistic conception of re­ ligion is doubtless superior to a mere emotional conception, its ontologistic background is decidedly of inferior value for the objective grounding of religion. Hence, the more recent Protestant theologians generally are opposed to Domer’s theory of Faith.86 5. More recent writers insist that “Christian experi­ ence covers the entire Christian life, and not merely the initial act of conversion. It includes the operation in the Christian of all the incentives to activity and spiritual growth, the consolations in sorrow, the motives which lead to the broadening and deepening of the spiritual life, and the hopes for the future, which flow from the peculiarly Christian mode of regarding life and the world”.87 Its essential elements are said to be “1. The act of the will involved in repentance and faith; 2. the object of faith, God as revealed in Jesus Christ, Who is inwardly made known to the believer through the Holy Spirit; 3. the re­ sults in religious adjustment, moral reinforcement and intellectual peace. All these elements are not equally pres­ ent in all experience”, yet “conversion as thus analyzed is the great generic type and norm of religious experience”.88 Religious experience known as the new birth is the product of supernatural forces; these forces are personal; Jesus Christ as the Revealer of God to man actually works the change within man’s nature; and the inner power and wit­ ness which he employs for this purpose is the Holy Spirit of God.89 If one inquires: How may Christian experience be veri­ fied?, Mullins replies that “this confirmation will in large measure consist of further experiences, rich and manifold in character . . . Sometimes the confirmation will refer to the new birth itself, at others to the divine forces which 86) Ibid., I, 545. 86) Schmid, ibid., p. 217; cf. Geo. M. Sauvage, art. “Ontologism”, in CE. XI, p. 257 sq. 87) E. Y. Mullins, Why is Christianity True? The American Baptist' Publication Society, Philadelphia, Pa. 1905, p. 266. Italics inâdrtod 88) Ibid., p. 273. 89 ) Ibid., p. 287. Uullin·, I 124 Chapter III produce it, and sometimes to all these aspects together”.90 There is, in the first place, the principle of contrast. “In conversion one of the most radical and striking contrasts is introduced into experience”. Secondly, Christian experi­ ence is verified through reflection, which “makes reasonable the idea of the forgiveness of sin”. Assurance is another phase. Through the new birth doubts, misgiving, and fears, cease and give way to a “deepening conviction and growing intensity of Faith”. “Reflection also inevitably affects the Christian’s view as to the creative cause of experience, the Person of Christ”. Another test is the workableness of Christian experience in practical life. “Christian experi­ ence actually raises to a higher plane of moral power and attainment”. It enables “its subject to rise above the ills of life”. Prayer is a further verification. Then, too, Chris­ tian experience is verified by the experience of other Chris­ tians; also by “comparison with the earliest literature of the distinctively Christian experience, the New Testa­ ment”. Finally, the verification through the witness of the Holy Spirit”, “Every ray of the Spirit’s light in the soul can be traced to Christ as the Revealer of God”. “All the methods of the verification of Christian experience are pro­ gressive. Each re-inforces the other. The cumulative effect of them all produces immovable conviction. The gross re­ sult in moral and spiritual attainment is itself the solid basis of outward fact, which fortifies us against any im31 putation of self-deception. The inner basis of fact is our own experience of spiritual realities operating as causes. There is a mysterious, an unexplained side of these inner realities. But the result is as tangible and real to us as that of a tree whose growth we observe, while every particle of material addition to it is as mysterious as life itself”.91 Mullins repeats these same ideas in a later writing. “We accept the deity of Christ along with His humanity, not by authority, but by discovery. The lordship of Christ “has come to us by way of experience of His Grace working in us”.92 Baptists accept the authority of the Scriptures “by the testimony of the Scriptures themselves and by the re­ sponse of their own spiritual life” ; they find that the Scrip­ tures are the word of God. The Bible becomes a spiritual authority “by a spiritual process in which the whole relig»0) Ibid., p. 287. 91 ) Ibid., pp. 287-303; cf. also R. H. Fisher, Religious Experience. The Baird Lecture for 1924, N. Y., especially pp. 48-92. 92) Mullins, "Why I am a Baptist * ’, in Twelve Modem Apostles and Their Creeds. N. Y. 1926, pp. 92, 93. Emotional Religion 125 ioua nature of man is active, and in which the self-authen­ ticating power of the Bible is felt”.93 6. Julius Kostlin, a representative of the “mediating” κ*«« η· theology, assuming that reason as such cannot acquire a firm, undoubting knowledge of the existence of God,84 con­ tends that'the ground of each and every ethical and relig­ ious conviction is inner experience, apart from metaphysical knowledge. It is a “mystic” experience of an emotional kind, “an immediate moving (Berührtsein) and stirring (Ergriffensein) of our inner self by the Divine, which is present to us in actual, historical Revelation, a perception of the Divine, an immediate consciousness of the impres­ sions received here and now, and of the Divine, which now operates in them, a feeling, which, however, is wholly dif­ ferentiated from the ordinary feelings of pleasure and pain, an experience, which has the characteristic of immedi­ ateness in common with ordinary sensible experiences, .but which itself is a supersensible event, indeed a full experi­ ence at the center of one’s own inner spiritüal life”. The moral as well as the religious conscience rests upon such a mystic emotional experience, superior to discursive reason­ ing; pre-Christian, and in a higher way also the Christian conscience, has its origin in, such an experience.96 Hence, the fact remans: there is no certitude of reality, which does not finally rest upon external and internal experience, upon a consciousness of the senses and of the inner, higher sense.88 7. We see the criteria of mystic experience emphasized Quaker·, especially by the Quakers, who claim “to reduce religion to its essential traits, to an uttermost simplicity. They be­ lieve supremely in the nearness of God to the human soul, in direct intercourse and immediate communion, in mystical experience, in first-hand discovery of God”.97 Their prin­ ciple is that “religion is something to be done, not a pious * theory, or a creed in a book, or a set of notions to preach about”. “They do not care much for the spectator theory of truth,—that it is something to be observed and raptur­ ously viewed as an object. Nor do they approve that feel­ ing-theory, that truth is something which produces emo­ tional thrills. Truth is not really truth until you go out to do it, until it has ‘motor-effects’ and becomes the tissue and M) Ibid., pp. 93, 94. 94) Die Begründung unserer sittlich-religiosen Überzeugung. Ber­ lin. 1893, pp: 28-30. 85) Ibid., p. 53 sq. ") Ibid., p. 124. 87) Rufus Matthew Jones, Why I am a Quaker, in Twelve Modern Apostles and their Creeds. N. Y. 1926, p. 114. 126 Chapter III fibre of a good life”.88 “The Quakers have always felt the weakness of tradition or antiquity as a basis of authority”?8 “The Quaker endeavors to apply the laboratory method to matters of religion. He asks always for the testimony and verification of experience”. The truths of religion can be tested out best “in the laboratory of man’s own soul and in the experiences of his own life”.100 They are convinced “that the foundations of faith stand sure because they are built upon the eternal structure of the human soul itself, because the most important facts of religion are facts of experience, and finally because everything that has spiritual significance can be tested and verified in the life of man as he lives in relation to God and in relation to his fellow­ men”.101. Bitsch!. 8. The same problem of the relation between faith and knowledge, between science and religion, that Kant and Schleiermacher had faced, engaged the attention oî Albrecht Ritschl (1822-1889). “He was governed by the same motive of reconciling them”, says a modern Protestant writer, “and followed, in general, the same method of reconcilia­ tion. His solution of the problem consisted in a new defini­ tion of religion on the basis of Kant’s and Schleiermacher’s contributions. He combined with them, however, related suggestions from Herbart and Lotze. With Ritschl. the philosophy of religion, which has steadily developed from Kant and the faith philosophers through Schleiermacher . in the direction of a subjective, independent basis for re­ ligion, and of a sharp distinction between religious and scientific knowledge, has come to its final expression in a conception of religion as a *value-theory’ ”.102 Ritschl denied to human reason the power of arriving at a scientific knowledge of God.103 Consequently, for him religion cannot have an intellectual, but only a practicomoral foundation. “Religious knowledge is essentially dis­ tinct from scientific knowledge. It is not acquired by a theoretical insight into truth, but, as the product of re­ ligious faith, is bound up with the practical interests of the soul. Religion is practise, not theory. Knowledge and faith are not only distinct domains ; they are independent of, and separated from, each other. While knowledge rests upon «8) Ibid., p. 119. 88 ) Ibid., p. 119. 100) Ibid., pp. 120, 121. i°i) Ibid., p. 122. 102) Errett Gates, The Development of Modern Christianity, in A Guide to the Study of the Christian Religion, ed. by G. B. Smith, Chi­ cago, Ill., (Second Impression) 1917, pp. 456, 457. 103) cf. Ritschfs Théologie und Metaphysik. Bonn. 1887 (2’ed.), pp. 7-40; Die christUche Lehre von Rechtf ertigung und Versohnung. Bonn. 1888-1889 ( 3'ed.), pp. 16-20. Emotional Religion 127 judgments of existence (Seinsurteile), faith proceeds on independent ‘judgments of value’ (Werturteile,) which affirm nothing concerning the essence or nature of divine things, but refer simply to the usefulness and fruitfulness , of religious ideas. Anticipating to some extent the prin­ ciples of Pragmatism, put forward in a later generation by W. James, Schiller, etc., Ritschl declared that knowledge alone valuable, which in practice brings us forward. Not what the thing is ‘in itself’, but what it is ‘for us’, is de­ cisive”.104 He is particularly opposed to a “mystic-metaphysical theory of knowledge”, and an immediate union of the soul with God and Christ. He champions rather a mediate union of the soul, by means of the historical influences proceeding from the community and of the corresponding functions of the soul. “Without the medium of the word of God, which is Law and Gospel, and without the exact reminder of this personal Revelation in Christ, there is no personal relation­ ship between a Christian and God”. In his opinion the doc­ trine of Lutheran theology, expounded in the seventeenth century, regarding a mystic union of the soul with God is untenable.105 Religion is for Ritschl “an interpretation of man’s ’of’Æe’ relation to God and the world, guided by the thought of the sublime power of God to realize the end of this bless­ edness of man ... In every religion what is sought, with the help of the superhuman power reverenced by man, is a solution of the contradiction in which man finds him­ self, as both a part of the world of nature and a spiritual personality claiming to dominate nature”.106 Accord­ ingly, the ground of religious faith is the practical need of happiness, and the experience of satisfaction which morality and religion offer for its fulfilment. In opposi­ tion to Kant, Ritschl grounds not only religion but also morality upon the feelings of pleasure and pain, through which man experiences either joy because of his 104) J. Pohle, art. “Ritschlianism", in CE. XIII, p. 87. Italics in­ serted. 105) Ritschl, Geschichte des Pietismus. Bonn. 1880-1886, II, pp. 10-12, 29-32, 98-100; Théologie und Metaphysik, pp. 41-54. 106 ) Die christliche Lehre von Rechtfertigung etc., Ill, pp. 185, 189. English transi. “The Christian Doctrine of Justification and Re­ conciliation”. The positive development of the doctrine. By H. R. Mack­ intosh and A. B. Macaulay. Edinburgh. 1902 (2’ed.), pp. 194, 199- | 1, 1 . } 128 t To Positive Christian F'aith Through the Church. Chapter III dominion over the world by God’s help, or pain because of the want of such help; therefore, in this sense upon judgments of value. He writes: “Religious knowledge •moves in independent value judgments, which-relate to man’s attitude to the world, and call forth feelings of pleasure or pain, in which man enjoys the dominion over the world vouchsafed him by God, or feels grievously the lack of God’s help to that end ’ ’.107 He is against making religion a “subordinate appendix to morality”.108 He agrees with Kant in rejecting a natural religion of theo­ retical or metaphysical reason, but he disagrees with him in that he repudiates a natural religion of the practical reason, for, he insists that religion comes about only through the medium of positive Revelation; for there never was a natural religion without positive doctrine and tradition; the Lutheran theologians adhering to Melanchthon and Scholasticism have also erred like Kant in this respect. All religions were and are positive re­ ligions, the Christian Religion in the fullest measure.109 Despite this philosophical-practical method of grounding the Faith in the Kantian sense, Ritschl exerted such a far-reaching influence in theological circles, particularly by reason of this approximation to Positivism.110 Ritschl does not seek to arrive at positive Christian Faith like Kant, through a philosophico-practical faith based on need; neither does he plan to come to Christ, and through Christ to the Church, like Çîchleiermacher, by means of a subjective, experiential faith. His ap­ proach to faith in Christ and His Gospel, and to trust in the forgiveness of sin, to divine sonship and beati­ tude, in the kingdom of God, Who is Love, is rather through the ecclesiastical community. In the Ritschlian conception “justifying faith is possible only in the Christian community. The Church of Christ (by io?) English 108) 109) 110) Die christl. Lehre von Rechtfertigung etc., Ill, pp. 194-196; transi., p. 205. Ibid., Ill, 209. 215 foot-note. Ibid., Ill, pp. 185-193; Théologie und Metaphysik, pp. 65-66. Schmid, ibid., p. 219. Emotional Religion 129 which, however, is to be understood no external institution with legal organization) is, on the one hand, the aggregate of all the justified believers, but, on the other hand, has, as the enduring fruit of the work of Christ, a duration and existence prior to all its members, just as the whole is prior to its parts. Like the children in the family and the citizens in the state, all believers must also be born in an already existing Christian community. In this alone is God preached and in this alone, through the preaching of Christ and His work, is that justifying faith rendered possible, in virtue of which the individual experiences regeneration and attains to adoption as a son of God . . . Since the Christian Faith exists only through personal experience, or subjec­ tive acquaintance with justification and reconciliation, the objects of faith are not presented to the mind from without through a Divine Revelation as an authoritative rule of faith, but become vividly present for the Christian only through subjective experience. The revelation of God is given only to the believer who religiously lays hold of it by experience and recognizes it as such . ** 111 This approach to Faith is perhaps the reason why, in the second and third edition of his work on “Justification and Reconciliation”, Ritschl stresses and puts into the fore­ ground not a philosophical-practical method of proof, but rather a theological-mystic proof in the anti-Kantian sense112 after the manner of Spener. Theology, so Ritschl writes, cannot enter upon either a direct or an indirect proof of the truth of Christianity, in that it seeks to demon­ strate its harmonization with any philosophical or juristic view of life. For Christianity stands really in opposition to these . . . The scientific proof for its truth will have to be sought for along the line of thought already excellently stated by opener. Whoever fulfils the will of God, will know that Christ’s message is true (John vii, 17). Still, the ground of the Christian Faith is only an experience, through the soul’s reaction, of the salvific operations of God’s word coming from without; it is not, however, a secret union with God in the ground of the soul itself, that is, not a un io mystica. Hence, in this stricter sense Ritschl’s doctrine disclaims the appelation of “mystic”.113 ni) J. Pohle, art. “Ritschlianism”, in CE. XIII, p. 87. Italics in­ serted. cf. A. E. Garvie, The Ritschlian Theology. Edinburgh, 1889; which according to R. Mackintosh is the "standard work”. 112) Kant's Werke, ed. Rosenkrantz. X, 310-311. US) Ritschl, Die christliche Lehre von Rechtfertigung etc., (2’ed., 1882-1883; S’ed., 1888-1889, pp. 20-25. 130 Chapter III In other words, just as many philosophers of modern emotional religion generally regard the religious feeling as an immediate experience, or' laying hold, of the Deity, hence, not as a practical feeling of value, but rather as a kind of mystic knowledge, so, too, in Ritschl and many of his pupils we note a similar ambiguity. On the one hand, Ritschl says that the judgments of value, which go to make up the kernel of religious knowledge, have their motive solely in the feeling of value, which the objects arouse in the believer; and, on the other hand, he calls the origin of faith also an inner experience, thus, passing over to the other interpretation of feeling.114 Kaftan. 9. Julius Kaftan essays to define more exactly the rela­ tion between the philosophical-practical and the theologicalexperiential method of grounding the Faith, in that he at­ tributes only to the latter the power of engendering certi­ tude. Already the feelings and the will, so he writes,: and the striving after well-being,’ direct theoretical knowledge and enable man to find satisfaction in morality and religion, and finally in a rational speculation according to practical norms. This, however, has nothing to do with subjective mood and arbitrariness, but “is in its way just as objective as the theoretical function of any science”, even though with its judgments of value it does not possess such a com­ pelling force as science and, purely as such, does .not pass beyond a merely rational postulate, hypotheses, proofs, of probability.115 Rational postulates of a kingdom of God Λ offer only probability; certitude arises only through the Revelation of this kingdom of God in Christianity, and through the preaching of the justifying and reconciling love of God made known to us by that Revelation; “The subjec­ tive need in itself engenders no certitude, and just as little does the latter spring from the acceptance on authority of an objectively existing Revelation. Only where the subjec­ tive need lays hold of Revelation, as objectively given and self-announcing, is such certitude attained”.116 Only thus does rational speculation pass beyond mere rational postu­ lates and hypotheses, mere conjectures and probabilities, and arrive at a full apo log etic proof of the reality of that kingdom of God in Christianity as the grounding of dog­ matics.117 Thus, apologetics and the System of Christian Certitude are not separated from each other, as in Frank’s U4) J. Mausbach, Die Religion und RCK. I, pp. 81-82. ns) Die Wahrheit r der christlichen 393-440. English transi.' "The Truth of Geo. Ferris. Edinburgh. 1894, 2 vols. 116) Ibid., pp. 549-553. h?) Ibid., das moderne Seelenleben, in ' Religion. Basel. 1888, pp. the Christian Religion”, by pp. 490 sq; 547-554; 569-571. IJ! ί 1 Emotional Religion 131 system, but they are regarded as one and the same for the purpose of laying this foundation of Faith.118 10. Richard Lipsius opposed this positivistic concep- L1i'sl,ia tion of Revelation, which Kaftan assumed as regards Ritschl and his school. With Fr. A. Lange he also championed the neo-Kantian theory of knowledge. Knowledge comes only through internal and external experience; over and above this, there are only ideal conceptions of speculative reason, winged by fancy, and the practical experiences of truth that satisfy the feelings. Like morality, religion,, too, owes its origin to the “self-assertiveness of man in the face of the external natural world” ; to that extent moral and religious ideas are like two branches of a common root; Religion has as its presupposition the Revelation of God; both are cor­ relative concepts. To both sides of subjective religion— piety and faith—there correspond objectively, as aspects of Revelation, manifestation in nature and history, and in­ spiration within the spirit.119 But faith in Revelation does not come into being, so Lipsius thinks, merely in an: exter­ nal way, through the spirit oif Christ forever operating in the community, but also in an internal manner, through the authentication of Revelation within ourselves by the testi­ monium Spiritus Sancti, by an immediate touching of our spirit by the Holy Spirit and thé unio mystica with Him’.120 As regards content, Lipsius * theology largely coincides with the “liberal theology” of Ritschl.121 11. In France, Auguste Sabatier (d. 1909), Dean of Sabatier, the Protestant theological faculty at Paris, stirred up much interest and exerted a wide-spread influence, even in many circles of Catholics in France, by his theology, which in many points manifests contact with the theology of Ritschl, Kaftan, and Lipsius. Sabatier’s method of grounding the Faith is partly a philosophical-practical in the neo-Kantian sense, and partly also a theological-mystic method, although -the distinction between the two methods is not always clearly discernible. The opposition between the theoretical and the practical reason, between nature and the spirit, between cosmic and 118) A. v. Schmid, ibid., p. 221. 118) cf. Lipsius, Dogmank. Braunschweig. 1879 (2’ed.) ; Theologische Prinzipienlehre, § 16-17 ; Neue Beitrage zur wissenschaftlichen Grundlegung der Dogmatik, I-V, in Jahrbûcher der prot. Theol. 1885, pp. 177 sq. 12°) cf. Lipsius, Dogmatische Beitrage zur Verteidigung und Erlauterung meines Lehrbuches. Leipzig. 1878, pp. 16-17; RitschVsche Théologie. Leipzig. 1888, pp. 24-25. 121 ) A. v. Schmid, ibid., p. 221. 132 Chapter III self-consciousness, is to be resolved according to him by religion in the heart of man. Essentially this is a religion of the heart or the feelings. It arises from the practical need of protection in the face of the limitations and the threats of the physical world, from the initial contradiction of the inner life of man. “All human development springs from religion and ends with it. Art, morals, science itself, fade and waste away, if this supreme inspiration be want­ ing to them”.122 Confidence in God’s assistance, and the intercourse of the heart with God through prayer, are the vital pulse of religion.123 Natural religion is not a religion, because “it deprives man of prayer; it leaves God and man at a distance from each other”.124* “In all piety there is some positive manifestation of God. The ideas of religion and Revelation are, therefore, correlative and religiously inseparable. Religion is simply the subjective Revelation of God in man, and Revelation is religion objective in God”.126 Revelation is supernatural in cause, natural in its realization and appropriation. There are not two Revela­ tions different in nature and opposed to each other. “Reve­ lation is one, in different forms and various degrees. It is at once supernatural and natural: supernatural by the cause which engenders it in souls, and which, always re­ maining invisible and transcendent, never exhausts or im­ prisons itself in the phenomena it produces ; natural, by its effects, because, realizing itself in history, it always appears therein conditioned by the historical environment and by the common laws which regulate the human mind”.126 Miracles are not the criteria of Divine Revelation.127 “It is nonsense to demand a criterion of evangelical Revela­ tion other than itself, any other evidence, i. e., than its own truth, beauty, and efficiency”.128 “Only one criterion is sufficient and infallible: every Divine Revelation, every religious experience fit to nourish and sustain your soul, must be able to repeat and continue itself as an actual Reve­ lation and an individual experience in your own conscious­ ness”.12’ “Instead of reasoning we have here to live, to experience, and to test”.130 122) Esquisse d’une philosophie de la religion. Paris. 1897. We quote from the English translation Outlines of a Philosophy of Re­ ligion. (N. Y. Geo. H. Doran Co.; 2’ed.), pp. 13-27. 12») Ibid., p. 27. i24) Ibid., p. 30. 125) ibid., p. 34. 12») Ibid., p. 64. W) Ibid., pp. 48 sq. «8) Ibid., p. 62. 12») Ibid., p. 62. 180) Sabatier The Religions of Authority and the Religion of the Spirit. Transi, by Louise S. Houghton, N. Y., 1904, p. 240. Emotional Religion 133 Sabatier teaches that we must distinguish between the Christian Revelation and the Sacred Scriptures, which are its documents ; “the word of God is in the Bible, but all the Bible is not the word of God”. This sharp distinction is an inalienable achievement of modern theology.181 All relig­ ious knowledge of the truths of Divine Revelation is inade­ quate, symbolic. Under all things lies hidden mystery. “Who says symbol says at the same time occultation and Revelation”. This is the symbolism of philosophy and the­ ology,182*and in this respect Sabatier approximates the doc­ trine of Lipsius.133 For Sabatier, therefore, Faith is an act of liberation from inner division and oppression, a bold salto vitale, not only dependence; as regards content, it is a practical feel­ ing, an act of confidence, not a proof.184 12. Wm. Ralph Inge, Dean of St, Paul’s in London, in»·. England, believes that “the Gospel of Christ is the religion of the Spirit in its purest form”. “It is not modern, but older than Catholicism and much older than Protestantism. It goes back to the New Testament, and we may even say to Christ Himself, Whose ‘secret and method’, as Matthew Arnold said, were the necessity of ‘dying to live’, and in­ wardness”.185 It is “distinguished by its friendly attitude towards secular culture, by its insistence on divine im­ manence, by its resolute determination to find the seat of authority, not in tradition, or in the arbitrary commands of God, or in an external and supernatural Revelation, but in the heart and wind of man, illuminated by the Spirit of Christ. This illumination must be earned, or rather pre­ pared for, by a strenuous course of discipline. The religious life begins with faith, which has been defined by Frederick Myers as the resolution to stand or fall by the noblest hypothesis. phis venture of the will and conscience pro­ gressively verifies itself as we progress on the upward path. That which began as an experiment ends as an experi­ ence”*.™ In this religion of the Spirit “the infallibilities are gone, the infallible Church as well as the infallible book. Nor can we trust to the Inner Light as the old Quakers did . . . As for the old proof from Miracle and Prophecy, we now see that, even if the fact could be established, they 181) Outlines etc., pp. 51-53. 182) The Religions of Authority etc., pp. 322, 326. 188) Schmid, ibid., pp. 222, 223. 184) Mausbach, Die Religion etc., I, p. 82. 186) The Future of Christianity, in Twelve Modern Apostles and Their Creeds. N. Y. 1926, pp. 14, 12, 13. 188) Ibid., pp. 12,13. I '134 IK ! , i I > ,I i ’ ! I I i I i ■ i Chapter III would not carry the weight which the old apologetics placed on them. . . We are in fact driven back upon the Testimonium Spiritus Sancti, the witness of the spiritual life to itself. And it is enough”.137 SMerbiom. 13. Finally, in modern times there is a marked ten­ dency to substitute for Schleiermacher’s “feeling of absolute dependence”, a feeling of power, of trust, of moral freedom, of peace. In this interpretation of “feeling” it is not difficult for theologians to approximate more closely to Luther’s doctrine of fiducial faith.138 Thus, Nathan Sôderblom, late Archbishop of Upsala, Sweden, claims in the first place that he is a Lutheran because he owes to his section of the Church “an overwhelming sense of the greatness of God’s free grace as granting forgiveness and peace to the troubled human heart and saving men from perdition, not through their own perishable endeavors and observances and works, but through faith in Jesus Christ.”139 SUMMARY. 1. Let us now summarize.the various viewpoints elab­ orated in the preceding pages. The advocates of modern emotional religion, like the voluntarists, separate faith from science and seek to construct the certitude of Faith upon non-rational^prounds^ They appeal to the subjec­ tive criterion of Christian experience, which may be described in general as “the state or condition produced in the mental, moral and spiritual nature of man, when he conforms to the conditions which Christianity de­ clares to be necessary to union and fellowship with God. To experience is to learn by ‘practical trial or proof.’; ‘to try or prove by use, by suffering, or enjoyment’ ”.140 But the precise manner in which this Christian experi­ ence takes place is variously interpreted. For instance, it is said to consist in ‘ ‘ the feeling of the need of redemp­ tion, and the feeling of redemption through Christ’’ (Schleiermâcher); “the spiritual experience of regener137) Ibid., pp. 15, 18. 138) Mausbach, Die Religion und das moderne^ Seelenleben, in RCK, I, p. 82. 139) Why I am a Lutheran, in Twelve Modern Apostles and Their Creeds, pp. 78, 79. HQ) E. Y. Mullins, Why is Christianity True? Philadelphia, Pa. 1905, p. 266; cf. Stearns The Evidence of Christian Experience, which according to some is the standard work along this line. » . Emotional Religion 135 atioh together with conversion” (Frank); “the experi­ ence of regeneration as a mere forgiveness of sin” (Domer); “the inner witness vouchsafed to the penitent and inquiring sinner by the Holy Ghost, through the teaching of the Scriptures, assuring him of truth, pardon and salvation through Jesus Christ” (Keyser) “a spiritual process in-which the whole religious life of man is active, and in which the self-authentication of the Bible is felt” (Mullins); “a feeling of value, which faith in God’s saving grace in Christ brings to the soul’'(Ritschl, Garvie); “an experience of our subjective need of justi­ fication and reconciliation, and the subjective laying hold of salvific Revelation by Faith” (Kaftan); “an experi­ ence by which we feel that Revelation nourishes and sus­ tains the soul”. (Sabatier); “an experience of our own spiritual life witnessing to itself” (Inge). Or this ex­ perience is interpreted not so much as a practical feeling of value, as rather “an experience of being immediately touched and stirred by the Divine” (Kostlin); and a “unio mystica with the Divine” (Liysius); “a direct intercourse and immediate union, in mystical experience, in a first-hand discovery” (Quakers); in other words, as a kind of mystical knowledge. 2. Some seek to come to Christ and through Christ to the Church on the basis of this sentimental faith ; others, however, wish to arrive at faith in Christ through the Church, and the historical elements of Christianity ; others finally, through the laboratory of man's own soul, and the experiences of his own life (Quakers), entirely apart from commentaries or the authority of priests. 3. As regards the verification of Christian experience there is a variety of interpretation ; for instance, appeal is made “to the self-authentication of the Sacred Scrip­ tures as subjectively felt by the believer”, or to “the witness of the spiritual life itself”, or to the “experi­ ence of countless other people”, or to “the witness of the Holy "Spirit”, or to “the workableness of Christian ni) Leander S. Keyser, A System of Christian Evidence. Bur­ lington, Iowa. 1924 (3’ed.), p. 130. 136 experience in practical life” etc., in other words, generally to further experiences. t i ί Chapter III ' However, it must be noted that the appeal to Chris­ tian experience is not regarded as the exclusive criterion of modern Protestantism. Many have recourse also to the Person of Jesus Christ, to His supernatural character, His moral grandeur, His Miracles and Prophecies, especially His Resurrection, and to the evidence from the history of Christianity. Generally speaking, however, modern Protestants either wholly discard the external tokens, particularly Miracles, or insist that “ Miracles are not the chief evidence of Christianity and the proof of Revelation”;1*2 the inner testimony of the Holy Spirit “impinging directly on the believer’s consciousness, is more convincing than outward Miracles would be ; it is, indeed, the final proof for the individual who receives it”.148 Thus, external criteria are either entirely ignored, or at least relegated to a secondary place as evidences of Christian certitude. The primacy of value is accorded to “inner Christian experience” as the test of credibility. I t ! $0 ‘MjRITICISM ί 1. In every system of religious thought there are kernels of truth intermingled with patent errors. So, too, subject under consideration. The Catholic apolo­ gist freely admits that Faith, as a moral and super­ natural act, includes the elevating and gracious impres­ sions, which the advocates of modern emotional religion stress so emphatically. But he dissents from the erroneous evaluation placed by modern Protestantism upon these subjective experiences. These latter are not sub­ stitutes for the objective grounds of Faith. They pre­ pare the way for the act of Faith by opening the mind and the heart to attend to the objective grounds of belief, subjective Expetut® for objwtivi * Ground of Faith. ; ' · Mullins, ibid., p. 182. 143 ) Keyser, ibid., p. 132. Criticism 137 as Catholic theologians have often indicated.144145 Then too, at times these subjective impressions may be so strong, that they may function as reflexive motives of certitude. However, they are not the real ground and support of faith,as will appear from the following considerations. 2. We note among the advocates of a religion of the heart and feelings an intermingling of two lines of thought;for clarity’s sakewe shall treat them separately. • a) Some regard the religious feeling as an expres­ sion of the souVs need, an acknowledgment of creatural misery, emptiness, dependence, yearning for higher light and assistance. In its whole tone and tendency it reminds one of Kant’s postulates of practical reason, as well as of the standards which Pragmatism applies to religious truth. But it avoids the conceptual element, the abstract side of Kant’s postulates; a sinaple^act.pf^the^spul, Jnj describable _and mvsterious_in^_charac.ter, a feeling, a sigh, a surrender of the heart, takes the place of all the reflections of reason and of all the consideraiions I I ί I ίΜΒ of the will; in fact, it suffices to make the receptive soul regard ffial need as actually satisfied, and to believe in the In­ finite, in a harmony of the cosmic forces, in a blessed consummation and a good God.—However, precisely be­ cause of this obscure and purely subjective character, the feelings just described are even less capable than Kant’s postulates of communicating with certitude the highest and most luminous thought content, namely, the existence of God. No one will deny, of course, that the vision of human misery, the feeling of painful abandonment and the fervent desire for happiness, prepare the way for Faith, and accompany the initial manifestations of re­ ligious certitude. But they do not generate certitude it­ self. Indeed the struggle of the inquirer and doubter is rather an evident sign that real religion is riot yet presΊ!! 144) cf. St. Thomas Aquinas, Quodlib. q. 2. a. 6, where he speaks of an “inner vocation” of God as a help to faith ; cf. also Origen, Contra Celsum, I, 46; Suarez, De Fide disp. 4, s. 6, n. 4. 145) J. Mausbach, Grundzüge der katholischen Apologetik. Münster i. W. 1921 (3*-4’ed.), p. 23. Fate· ΏμοτΙμ of Religion. 138 Chapter III ent within the soûl; it comes actually only when truth, the certitude of the Divine, enters into the mind in some way that is capable of communicating reality. The strongest need of the soul does not, of itself, bring a comforter and helper; the most consuming hunger does > not supply nourishment. How vain, then, to imagine that in the religious sphere the heart “can create its own God’’ in accordance with its deepest wishes and yearn­ ings ! And when the feelings take on a religious charac­ ter (e. g., the feeling of dependence on God and the wish to be near Him), obviously the real concept of God is already present in the soul; therefore, religion is al­ ready theoretically grounded. But the very general feel­ ings, which these philosophers regard as the source of the knowledge of God, the yearning for a unified pur' pose and consummation of being, for a moral, blissful perfection of the Ego, are quite incapable of functioning as proofs of religious facts ; they are also too empty and indefinite to be able to overcome, in times of difficult struggle, the sensual impulses of life and to supply the comfort, which the soul needs in those trying times.146 b) Other advocates of emotional religion interpret the religious sentiments rather as feelings of freedom and joy, of power and certitude, of “espousal’-’.147 As Wm. James puts it: “The time of tension in our soul is over, that of happy relaxation, of calm deep breathing, of an eternal present, with no discordant future to be anxious about, has arrived. Fear is not held in abeyance as it is by mere morality, it is positively expunged and washed away”.148—Such moods of the soul are indeed a 11 N λ. i 7VTIU ·»· * 148) J, Mausbach, Die Religion und das moderne Seelenleben, in RCK. I, pp. 82, 83. 147) Wm. James, The Varieties of Religious Experience, pp. 47, *48: “Like love, like wrath, like hope, ambition, jealousy, like every other instinctive eagerness and impulse, it (religion) adds to life an enchantment which is not rationally or logically deducible from any-? thing _ . . else . . . . Religious feeling is thus an absolute .addition to the If λ Subject’s range of life. It gives him a new sphere of power . . religion is to mean anything definite for us, it seems to me that we ought to take it as meaning this added dimension of emotion, this enthusiastie temper of espousal, in religions where-morality strictly so .called can at best but bow its head and acquiesce”. x 148) ibid., p. 47. Criticism 139 frequent and precious accompanying phenomenon of religious certitude ; but they do not constitute its essence. They play about our thinking and willing like “sacred music”, but so long as the text of the hymn, the thoughts y and hopes, announce nothing of the -true, living God, this music is not “sacred”; this “enthusiastic temper of espousal” might just as truly be termed secular as re­ ligious. These sentiments of happy power and peace presuppose the possession of the genuine faith,· the inner fulness of divine powers; they are- tokens and fruits a life in God rather than its grounds and essence. Perhaps the depth and energy of such feelings can-ζΛΤΎ A At not be exhausted on rational and logical grounds; perhaps their fervor and cordiality oftentimes far outstrip _ - - —our powers of description ; still, that does not mean that they hang in the air “without an object”, or that their underlying thought may be false as well, as true. The blissful and peace-bringing element of religion is grounded upon the conviction, that we are dealing with no mere figment of the imagination, but with the highest realities, which, in content and value, far .surpass the narrow circle of our experience. Only such an earnest and decisive faith, not a timid and broken faith, is ablé to pour the balm of consolation into man’s heart. But whence can faith obtain this certitude, if the feelings, which are really the effects of faith, are also supposed to constitute its essential groundwork and support Î149 Obviously, therefore, unless one wishes arbitrarily to pass off purely secular feelings for religious feelings, one must unquestionably concede to religion a certain,, characteristic thought content.160 Thus, a faulty theory of religion lies at the basis of modern emotional religion. 3. Let us now consider this same concept of religion in its relation to the Christian Faith. Dmiculties and __ Contradictions. -The older Theology of the orthodox Lutheran and Re­ formed confessions grounded the fides divina in God’s savJ. Mausbach, ibid., I, p. 84. Ibid., p. 85. 11 » 140 ing Revelation, and in the divine inspiration of the Sacred Scriptures, as the documents of Revelation, upon an inner experience of the heart or feelings ; but it left unsolved the problem as to whether and how that experience might serve as the ground of Christian certitude. On the other hand, modem Theology of the positive believing type, such as is reflected especially in Frank’s “System of Christian Certi­ tude”, has come to realize that the inner experience consists of certain subjective movements or impressions, which have been awakened by the external preaching of the word of faith. Consequently, it insists that the fides divina relative to the objects of faith must assume those experimental facts as its starting point, if it is to arrive at certitude. It begins, therefore, with creatural, experiential facts. I 1 . • I, 11 i » I ■ ■I y • 1 i i I ' I Chapter III a) The proximate experiential fact stressed by many advocates of the theory of “emotional religion” is the soul’s need of salvation. A desiderium innatum, an innate desire ofsalvation, is said to have resided already in the hearts of our first parents. But we ask: Does fallen, spoiled human nature still possess such a desire? Or is the contradiction of fallen nature to all the higher or so-called spiritual things so strong, that we are com­ pelled to ascribe the desire for these blessings exclusive­ ly to the gracious operation of the Holy Spirit, Who makes man’s heart receptive of the external preaching of salvific Revelation, and bears witness to it indhe soul? Orthodox Protestant Theology either did not raise this question at all, or answered it in various ways according to the diverse conceptions of sinful human nature. b) Others emphasize rather the emotional impres­ sions of freedom and bliss, of peace and assurance, which satisfy the soul's need of salvation, as the bridge leading to the fides divina. Again we ask: How does the Holy Spirit manifest Himself to the individual, as the Witness of the truth of God’s saving word, by means of these subjective impressions? Is it perhaps in virtue of an immediate vision of the Spirit in the sense of Theosophy, or even of Ontologism? This type of theology would be the first to disclaim any such allegation. The only way in which the Holy Spirit can reveal Himself to the indi­ vidual, as the Witness of Revelation, according to these Criticism 141 theologians is by virtue of the principle of causality. Solely by reason of this rational principle is it possible cither to deny that these impressions are natural, or to affirm that they are supernatural and divine, and thus to arrive at salvific Faith through those experiences.151 Therefore, in the end this type of theology must appeal to other than purely emotional grounds of belief. c) Moreover, there are other difficulties to be solved by this orthodox type of modern Protestant Theology. Tn the first place, there is the question as to whether and how a Divine faith can arise from such facts of creatural experience. Then, too, this Divine faith, as understood by these Protestants, implies that God graciously de­ clares every one just and righteous, who trustingly ac­ cepts the message of Revelation, even though such a one is not really just and righteous, even though such a one remains in his inner self the same sinner as before.™ But how can God’s word be trusted, if He is not faithful to His word; if through grace He pronounces a person just and righteous, but does not really by His grace make him just and righteous? Finally, this Divine Faith is said to arise solely on the basis of an experience of the heart or feelings; but the facts or impressions of such an experience, even though they be divine and super­ natural in origin, cannot constitute an objective ground of the certitude of Divine faith.153 4.* Experiential facts of moral reinforcement and intellectual peace, the workableness of Christian experience, the moral power of religious faith, can be verified only after a long and faithful testing. How, then, can they be reckoned among the motives, which influence a person in his first decision to embrace the faith!154 5. The mystic experience of modern Protestantism may also take the form of feelings of value, as appears in the Ritschlian school of theology. We have already 161 ) 152) 16a) 1M) A. v. Schmid, ibid., pp. 239, 240. cf. J. Mohler, Symbolism. English transi, by Robertson, p.110. A. v. Schmid, ibid., pp. 240, 241. Mausbach, Grundzüge sic., p. 23. st

raeG.n«r on. PRAGMATISM Pragmatism may designate a) a tendency in philosophy, an attitude of mind towards philosophy, which insists on usefulness, or practical consequences, as a test of truth ; b) a theory of the nature of ideas and truth, a theory of knowledge ; c) a theory about reality, a metaphysics.1 Here we are directly concerned with Pragmatism only in its relation to the natural knowability of Divine Revelation. 178) Gutberlet, ibid., II, p. 104; cf. J. Kleutgen, Théologie der Vorzeit, 2’ed., pp. 391 sq. i) Wm. James, in Journal of Philosophy, Psychology etc., V, p. 85; cf. Wm. Turner, art. "Pragmatism”, in CE. XII, p. 33 sq; Leslie J. Walker, S. J., Theories of Knowledge. N. Y. & London, 1911 (2' ed.), for a scholarly study of Pragmatism in its various forms on the basis of original sources. ’ ‘ : The Criteria of Pragmatism and Modernism 157 The attitude of the Pragmatist is “the attitude of look­ ing away from first things, principles, categories, supposed necessities ; and of looking towards last things, fruits, con­ sequence, facts”.2* Knowledge is said to be “true”, only in so far as it helps mankind to advance in a practical way. Truth is usefulness; it resolves itself into “error” just as soon as it has lost its usefulness, or workableness, or just as soon as it has proved its hurtfulness for practical life. Thus, “irut/t” is something relative and mutable. In the evolution of life, and still more in the development of human experience and human modes of thought, Pragma­ tists insist that the supreme idea, which governs the whole, is not that of the “ideal” or of the “true”, but rather of the “good”. Theory is subordinate to practise, the “true” is subordinate to the “good”. The “true” is not the source of the “good”. Action is primary; knowledge is always derivative, secondary, subservient, useful.8 “Truth is a form of the good”. Utility is the essence of the truth-rela­ tion. Truth is not transcendent, but changeable, “ambula­ tory”, as Wm. James puts it. In other words, no truth is made and set aside, or outside of experience ; experience is a stream out of which we can never step ; no item of experi­ ence can ever be verified definitely and irrevocably ; it is verified provisionally now, but may be verified again to­ morrow, when I acquire a new experience. All truths are empirical ; they are “man-made” ; hence Humanism is only another name for Pragmatism. The mutability and rela­ tivity of truth manifest themselves spontaneously in the advancement, or hindrance of practical interests. Thought­ systems or ideas, which today have outgrown their useful­ ness, formerly contained within themselves their own justi­ fication and “relative truth”; now they are “antiquated” and, therefore, false. The truth which today we have labor­ iously acquired will be repudiated in a later stage of in­ quiry, if it has lost its vital power. Thus, “truth” is a fluent concept, entirely submerged in the stream of time and carried along by its current. The application of Pragmatism to Religion and Revela­ tion is perfectly obvious; the one and only element which can come up for consideration in this respect, is “the judg­ ment of value”. The truth of a religion is measured nega­ tively, by the lack of value which theoretical truths possess in respect of the interests of religion; positively, by the 2) Wm. James, Pragmatism. N. Y. 1908, p. 55. ·) Walker, ibid., p. 545 sq. Application of Pragmatism to Religion and Revelation 158 . ·-» - . Chapter. IV ? value which a religion enjoys in regard to its practical use­ fulness for life and culture.4 I i I •I 1 I * I t I I ΐ 1 I ' 1 1 t j * ’’ o?Godim^.f The apostle off the pragmatic method of grounding P°ueeiMa“nd Religion is pre-eminently William James of Harvard, whom a numerous following acclaims with enthusiasm. Through the repudiation of causality and finality by Hume, Kant and Darwin, so James argues, every meta­ physic and, therefore, also the scientific proof of God have been done away with once and for alii “The bare . fact that all idealists since Kant have felt entitled either to scout or to neglect them (i. e., the argument for God’s existence) shows that they are not solid enough to serve as religion’s all sufficient foundation . . . Causation is indeed too obscure a principle to bear the weight of the whole structure of theology. As .for the argument from design, see how,Darwinian ideas have revolutionized it”. These arguments “prove nothing rigoursly. They only corroborate our pre-existent partialities ”.B Even though God’s existence were proven, religious life could derive no useful motive from the “scholastic attributes” of God. Of what use are the so-called metaphysical attributes, e. g., God’s aseity or His necessariness, His immateriality; His simplicity, etc.? “I cannot conceive of its being of the smallest consequence to us réligiously that, any one of them should be true”.6 James admits that the· moral attributes do indeed “positively determine fear-and hope and expectation, and are the‘foundations for the saintly life”. Still, “it stands with" them as ill as with the arguments for His (i. e., God’s) existence. Not only do post-Kantian idealists reject them root and -branch, but it is a plain historic fact that they never have • converted any one who has found in the moral com­ plexion of the world, as he experienced 'it, reasons for 4) J. Pohle, Natur und Vbematur, in RCK, I, p. 476. ®) The Varieties of Religious Experience. A Study of Human Nature, Being the Gifford Lectures, on Natural Religion delivered at Edinburgh in 1901-1902. N. Y. & London. 1925 (35’ed.), pp. 437-439. 6) Ibid., p. 446. 4 ! The Criteria of Pragmatism and Modernism j 159 doubting that agoodGod can have framed it*’.7 They are practically useless. James, therefore/ concludes that the value of re- J’hilosofMci1 ligious opinions “can only be ascertained by spiritual judgments directly passed upon them; judgments based on our own immediate feeling primarily ; and secondarily oh what we can ascertain of their experiential relations to our moral needs and to the rest of what we hold as true. Immediate luminousness, in short, philosophical reasonableness, and moral helpfulness are the only avail­ able criteria”. “In other words, not its origin, but the way in which it works on the whole”, is the*final test. “Our practise is the only sure evidence, even to ourselves, that we are genuinely Christians”.8 Repudiating the scholastic- and embracing the empirical method, James decides that “on the whole one type of religion is approved by its fruits, and another type condemned”.9 In the words of Professor Leuba10 “God is not known, he is not understood; he is used—sometimes as meat-, purveyor, sometimes as moral support, sometimes as a friend, sometimes as an object of love. If he proves Himself useful, the religious consciousness asks for no more than that. Does God really exist? How does He exist? What is He ? are so many irrelevant questions. Not God, but life, more life, a larger, richer, more satisfying life, is, in the last analysis, the end of religion. The love of life, at any and every level of development, is the re­ ligious impulse”. James unreservedly acknowledges the value of personal holiness for the social welfare: “The great saints are immediate successes; the smaller ones are at least heralds and harbingers, and they may be leavens-also, of a better mundane order”.11 To the ob­ jection of modern psychologists of religion (Starbuck etc.), who point out that the founders of religion, and ’) Ibid., pp. 447, 448. 8) Ibid., pp. 18-20. ») Ibid., p. 327. 10) The Contents of Religious Consciousness, in- the Monist, xi, p. 586, (July, 1901), cited by James, ibid., pp. 506, 507. H) James, The Varieties of Religious Experience, p. 377. ' i i « I ( 1 1 ( 1 ' | 1 | I jI i | I ! 160 Chapter IV religious geniuses give evidence of a pathological char­ acter, James answers that this does not prejudice the practical value of their doctrine and example. For it is necessary to make a sharp distinction between the origin and value of a religion, and the person and thing. Saints are to be judged according to their fruits, not according to their psychopathic disposition. “By their fruits ye shall know them, not by their roots”. On the basis of this distinction, Pragmatism is supposed to free our piety from “the bugaboo of morbid origin” of re­ ligion,12*towards which radical psychology of religion is definitely tending. CRITICISM We are concerned here only with the criticism of the pragmatic proof in respect of the criteria of Religion and Revelation. For a more detailed appreciation of the value of pragmatic truth, and of the pragmatic criteria of truth, the student is referred to special treatises.1* 1. In general we note an intermingling of truth and error. We freely admit that truth and life, idea and practise, can never be sharply and clearly separated from each other. However, it seems to us that Pragma­ tism has confused their respective roles; it has turned things upside down. It has transmuted effect into cause and vice versa. A religion, or a revelation, is not true because it is useful ; rather it is useful precisely because it is true. Usefulness is a consequence, not the principle of religious truth. Truth cannot be mere utility, for utility is the consequence of truth. Far from being only a “form of the good”, the true precedes the good as its prius; for the desirability of things, in which transcen­ dental goodness consists, presupposes knowability or truth. In like manner the idea of God is of value for the human race, only if there is a corresponding objec­ tive reality, namely, the existence of God. Or is religion 12) Ibid., pp. 13-25; cf. J. Pohle, Natur und Übematur, in RCK. I, pp. 476, 477. 13 ) cf. Leslie Walker, S· J·, ibid., pp. 550-620. The Criteria of Pragmatism and Modernism 161 to nourish itself on phantoms and imaginary entities'? 2. The proposition of “the tree and its fruits” is a genuine Christian principle, and in its logical setting is nothing else except the scholastic argumentum ex conse­ quentiis, inasmuch as not infrequently the truth, or falsity, of a principle can- be rightly judged from its practical consequences. But “the criterion of the fruits” is, of itself alone, insufficient; for at times, per accidens, a true conclusion can follow from a false antecedent. Thus, even though Islamism has produced a high degree of secular culture, as in Spain and elsewhere, this “fruit” alone is not sufficient to warrant the conclusion as to-its “truth”. On the other hand, as a negative cri­ terion the appeal to the fruits of a religion is valid ac­ cording to the logical axiom: Ex falso consequente sequitur falsum antecedens. If a principle as such leads to consequences, which are either’contrary to reason or immoral, eo ipso, the tree stands' self-condemned by its fruits.14 3. Whoever applies the norm of value alone to a re­ ligion, places himself at once in a very precarious position, nay more, involves himself in contradictions. What is the norm according to which we ought to evaluate a religion? Is it the ideal of Christianity? If the pragmatist appeals to this standard of value, he surrenders the very essence of Pragmatism, for he acknowledges an absolute truth, which transcends all empiricism and psychology. Or is this norm,‘perhaps, the changing judgments and moods of the changing spirit of the age? If so, the pragmatist would also have to grant the liceity of polyandry, polygamy, prostitu­ tion, suicide, duelling, abortion, etc., at least in so far as a community or age regards these immoral practices as “useful” for culture and, hence, as moral and true. In his polemic against a radical psychology of religion, Wm. James has recourse to the infelicitous distinction between the origin and the value of a religion. But in the matter of a Divine Revelation it is erroneous to separate absolutely the person from'the cause. For, if Christ as a Person was a paranoic, and St. Paul an epileptic, we must reject as nonsense the cause which they championed. Revelations proceeding from an “unhealthy brain” cannot possibly be 14) J. Pohle, ibid., I, pp. 477, 478; cf. above, pp. 64, 66-67. Unwarranted Conclusione. Contradictions. ï 1 162 Chapter IV i I I ! of divine origin; in fact, we repudiate them instinctively. We gratefully accept the happy solution of a mathematical problem, or the technical invention of an airplane, even though they are the fruits of a deranged mind, because at times we have at our disposal the means for investigating the value, or lack of value, of these achievements. But we exercise no such forbearance as regards the revelation of things divine, for in this respect, when there is question of the credibility of an alleged revelation, we demand also the proper authentication of the Person.15 II. " ! * » ! i I I ; ! MODERNISM rf ' Modernism suffers apologetically from the same fun­ damental weakness as religious Pragmatism with which it is spiritually allied. Like the Pragmatist the Modern­ ist denies that truth is absolute, eternal and unchangeable; for him truth is always relative and fluent; thus, from the very outset it is impossible to speak of “only one true” Religion, Revelation, Church. Our religious life, so the Modernist contends, is the spontaneous product and expression of the feeling, or sense, which emerges from the depths of our subconsciousness in which the Divine is immanent. This attitude effectively closes the door against the proof of truth on the basis of Miracles and Prophecies. At most, one might speak of an internal criterion ; but this test is, and remains, thoroughly subjective, even when Modernists speak of an “objective” method of proof. This subjective proof from immanence may be stated thus: Even though all religions, which give evidence of life, are “true” because of that life, still Catholicism is the most perfect religion, because it corresponds closest with the immanent needs of the human heart. Such is the viewpoint of moderate Modernism. “As for the others, who might be called Integralists”, so Pius the Tenth says, “they would .show to the non-believer, as hidden in his being, the very germ which Christ Himself had in His consciousness, and which He transmitted to -------------_ 15) J. Pohle, ibid., I, pp. 478, 479; cf. G. Michelet, Dieu et l’A gnosticisme contemporain, Paris. 1909, p. 86 sq. Criticism 163 mankind ’ ’.le Since, therefore, the immediate 44 feeling of the Divine” is at the same time its own proof of Divine Revelation in man’s consciousness, in the final analysis there is no further need of any other criterion; inner experience is its own criterion.11 This radicalism, which destroys all objective religion, far outstrips the moderate subjectivism which has domi­ nated Protestant orthodoxy since Luther’s time. It betrays a close affinity with that tendency in Protestant theology, which champions a “sentimental faith” (Jacobi, Schleier­ macher), a “religious instinct” (Twesten), the “private testimony of the Holy Spirit” (Pietism), of which we have spoken in detail in the preceding chapter. But its true birth­ place is Liberal Protestantism, such as has been incorpor­ ated in Ritschlianism. French Modernism finds its echo in the writings of A. Sabatier, the mouth-piece of German Illuminxsm.16 18 17 CRITICISM 1. In the preceding chapter we have shown that, as Christians, we cannot get along with a religion of the feelings only. For us, 44religious experience” is not the primary fact, which is followed by the intellectual inter­ pretation of those experiences; but rather, vice versa, objective Revelation must precede, in order to be trans­ lated into subjective experience. Only by arbitrarily assuming that every Christian has the right to feel that he is an inspired organ of Revelation, and to act accord­ ingly, is it possible to regard religious “experience” as the original and primary fact, upon which then follows the preaching of that message to the believer. On this latter hypothesis we should also have to take into the bargain the absurdity, that all these so-called divinely inspired prophets and apostles may rightly pawn off as divine wisdom all kinds of opinions and con­ victions, no matter how contradictory they may be, as 16) 17) 18) lation", Encyclical "Pascendi dominici gregis”, in DB. n. 2103. J. Pohle, ibid., I, pp. 470, 480. J. Pohle, ibid., I, 480; cf. our volume "The Theory of Reve­ I, 1, pp. 55-61. Pt­ 164 Chapter IV the history of Pietism abundantly testifies. Whoever relies solely upon the testimony of the Spirit unto Him­ self, builds upon sand; he also becomes guilty of the logical fallacy of assuming, as the basis of his proof, the very thing that needs proof, namely, that it is the Holy Spirit that speaks, and not his own private spirit.19 crjteHoni^ 2. The appeal made by Modernists to the moral n lvlduaHetic· power, which Christian experience- creates within the human heart, has only individualistic value; it .lacks the mighty recruiting power of that propaganda, -which slumbers within the essence of Christianity.20 'It is unnatural for man to appropriate a Religion based on Revelation and Facts, solely by means of an inner per­ sonal experience.21 rneoneistenaee. 3. Finally, whoever appeals to the religious and moral transformations, which primitive Christianity has effected in the countries bordering on the Mediterranean Sea, as a proof of its divine origin, has really abandoned the internal criteria, and taken refuge in a “historical . Miracle”, which, in a previous chapter, we have classed among the external criteria. It is beyond question, therefore, that a strict proof for the divinity of Revelation cannot be had without the added assistance of the external criteria, particularly Miracles and Prophecies.22 CHAPTER V. t THE CRITERIA OF THE “NEW APOLOGETICS” Generaijcharac- eria During the latter half of the past century, a' method of apologetic demonstration came into vogue, especially in France, which became known as the “New Apologet­ ics”. It sought to ground the proof of the divine origin 19) J. Pohle, ibid., I, p. 480. 20) J. Pohle, ibid., I, p. 480; cf. above, pp. 148, 149. 21) J. Mausbach, Grundziige der katholischen Apologetik. Müns­ ter i. W., 1921 (3’-4* ed.), p. 23. 22) J. Pohle, ibid., I, p. 481. The Criteria of the “New Apologetics” 165 of the Christian Religion upon the native aspirations of the soul, hence upon a mystic or, as some of its chief advocates prefer to express it, upon the psychological basis of the exigencies of the feelings and the will, and r t upon the corresponding fitness of Christianity, and4 Christianity alone, to -satisfy them.1 It has a negative and a positive side. Its negative side consists in the rejection, or at least in the depreciation, either in principle or for tactical reasons, of metaphysics, as the instrument for proving God’s existence-and for laying the groundwork of-Faith; hence, in the separation of Science and Faith. Its positive side appears, on the one hand, in the Apologetics of Immanence, or Need,m&er the leadership of Blondel; and, on the other hand, in the PsychologicoMoral Apologetics, or Social Apologetics, or the Apolo­ getics of Value, or the Method of Accommodation, as it is variously called, with Ollé-Laprùne, Fonsegrive and Brunetière as its most distinguished exponents.2 The negative attitude of the “New Apologetics” towards Attph££>Xard’ metaphysics is evinced by the fact, that many Frenchmen 'OMp y‘ rallied under the banner of Agnosticism, as understood either by Kant, or by Comte and Spencer, or by Hegel and Renan. Faith and Science were completely divorced from each other or, at least traditional apologetics, in so far as it rests upon Aristotelian-scholastic metaphysics, was de­ clared to be unsuited to our times, since it was supposed to have lost its influence over the “modern mind”. The Protestant attitude is reflected particularly in the writings of Auguste Sabatier.8, Misguided, in part, by Pascal and de Lamennais, con­ fused by the Positivism, which Littré proclaimed in the words: “Quelque recherche qu’on ait fait, jamais un mira­ cle ne s’est produit là où il pouvait être observé et constaté”, and finally blinded by neo-Kantianism, these Catholics shared more or less the viewpoint of Aulard, who in his 1) Al. v. Schmid, Apologetik als speculative Grundlegung der Théologie. Freiburg i. B. 1900, p. 200. 2) Anton Gisler, Der Modemismus. Einsiedeln. 1913 (4’ed.), pp. 251, 252. 8) Esquisse d’une philosophie de la religion. Paris. (8’ed.), p. 353 sq. English transi. “Outlines of a Philosophy of Religion* Based on Psychology and History". (Geo. H. Doran Co.). N. Y. 166 I ' ! ; I 't I , i !ς ’ I Chapter V. controversy with Buisson declared, that we must lead the old God of metaphysics to the frontier, and dismiss Him with thanks for the passing services which He had ren­ dered.4 . jSSSrt. Vs brtefly recount the historical factors which led up to this attitude towards metaphysics. There was, in the first place, Descartes, whose philosophy was strongly sub­ jectivistic, and who sought to discredit the traditional proofs for the existence of God and the immortality of the soul. Secondly, Pascal’s reasoning offered a wide berth to Mysticism. Male branehe and the Traditionalists misunder­ stood the innate powers of human reason. The Deists had struck mighty blows against the Fact of the Christian Rev­ elation. Finally, we must not pass over Rousseau, the father of Romanticism, the enthusiast of the beautiful in Nature, the panegyrist of the unsullied goodness of Nature; neither may we forget to mention Chateaubriand, in whose Apology of Christianity, Romanticism unfolds its glittering pinions. But above all others, the Romanticists were the most eloquent advocates of passion, of enthusiasm, of the impulses of the heart; they raised Mysticism high above the cold assent of reason. Even Kant himself felt the in­ fluence of Rousseau. Now, when the spirit of Voltaire, of the Encyclopedists and Positivists in France, sought to drown the spiritual in the floods of Materialism, and the school of Cousin offered neither a defense nor a haven of refuge, the philosophers, especially Renouvier, bachelier, Boutroux and others, in­ voked the spirit of Kant to preserve for the youth of France at least the idea of duty, and hence also the idea of God, of free will, and of immortality. Then too, certain Protestants (Buisson, Steeg, Pecaut), who had emigrated from Switzerland and become leaders in the French system of education, labored in a similar spirit. Indeed, in the opinion of some Frenchmen the fact, that these ideas were preserved in the French schools, is largely due to Criticism.6 Others, however, refuse to pay such a high tribute of gratitude to Kantianism. Thus, Maurice Barrés, in his romance “Les Déracinés”,6 wields a sharp sword against the Kantian theory of knowledge, against his categorical imperative, against his exotic philosophy, which permits <) Thamiry, Les deux aspects de Vimmanence. Paris. 1908, p. 259; cf, Fonsegrive, in La Quinzaine, Jan. 1, 1897, p. 108; later in Le Catholicisme et la vie de l’esprit. 1906 (2’ed.), pp. 1-4. B) For instance, Leclère, Le mouvement catholique kantien en France. Kantstudien VII (1902), p. 348. «) Paris. 1897. Apologetics of Immanence or Need 167 several pupils of the Lycée of Nancy to lapse step by 'Step into unbelief, and one of them even to end as a robber and a murderer: first déraciné and then décapité.7 On the other hand, the Catholic pulpit and Catholic apologetics did not perhaps realize sufficiently their duty of defending the Faith with the weapons of genuine phil­ osophy. Without robbing Lacordaire and Gratry of any of their glory, it may be truthfully said that their method of defense aimed in a one-sided fashion at showing the har­ mony between the spiritual and social needs of men and of Faith. In consequence, other thinkers were led to “laicize” Lacordaire’s sermons, that is, to create an apolo­ getics, which was constructed upon the basis of feeling, morality and sociology, rather than upon metaphysics. The temptation to do this was all the greater, since, despite the Church's condemnation of Lamennais, Bautain and Bonnetty, Kant’s postulate of the practical reason shone like a star of hope and refuge amidst the positivistic darkness. Moreover, in the heads of many there buzzed the very am­ biguous catch-word, that Faith contains “une part d’irra­ tionnel”, and must be wholly divorced from science. Finally, the tendency of our own age, which has turned away from speculation and aims predominantly at energetic action, also had a share in clamoring for a philosophy, which pro­ ceeds from action as its most certain and dearest principle. Thus,, men hoped to be able to give to apologetics a new principle, which, by virtue of its7 power of appeal and attractiveness, would far surpass the intellectual apolo­ getics of the past.8* ' * J. APOLOGETICS OF IMMANENCE OR NEED. The father of this “New Philosophy” is Bergson. Maurice Blondel,8 Abbé Denis, Leroy, Laberthonnière,10 elaborated and reconstructed it, and sought to place it in the service of apologetics. Its chief characteristics are the following. 7) Gisler, ibid., pp. 253-256. 8) Ibid., pp. 256, 257. ») Lettre sur les exigences de la pensée contemporaine en matière d’apologétique.— Annales de philosophie chrétienne, Jan. — July, 1896.—L'Action. 1893. iû) Laberthonnière often attacked the old method of the theo­ logians and scholastic philosophy in the Annales de philosophie chrétienne. The Sacred Congregation of the Index condemned the Annales that appeared between 1905 and 1913. 168 Moderate Agnosticism , 1 I Chapter V. . A. 1. The advocates of this philosophy look upon intellectualism as plainly erroneous; they champion a moderate agnosticism. Speculative reason alone, so they insist, cannot arrive at metaphysical· truth ; to be able to do so, the understanding must be grounded upon, and supported by, moral ideas and feelings, by aesthetic sentiments, and by impulses of the will. In other words, speculative reason can defend its onotological validity only according to the practical exigen­ cies of human action. Aside from the exigencies of action, our speculative knowledge remains notional and subjective; it merely posits the problem of action and directs its solu­ tion; we arrive at objective reality by means of action.11 Only that is true, which I embrace and experience with the totality of the soul’s powers, not merely with my intellect, but with my whole soul;-truth is the work of the whole spirit.12 Accordingly, the proofs for God’s existence, when considered only speculatively, are merely notional and do not prove the divine reality. The only correct dogmatism, is moral dogmatism, which makes action, not evident knowledge, the corner stone of philosophy, inasmuch as action imposes itself irresistibly as the condition of, our n) Blondel, L’Action, Paris. 1893, p. 463, writes: “Pour la sci­ ence, entre ce qui paraît être à jamais et ce qui est, quelle différence saurait-on découvrir? et comment distinguer la réalité même d’avec invincible et permanente illusion, ou, pour ainsi parler, d’avec une apparence éternelle? Pour la pratique, il en est autrement: en faisant COMME SI c’est, seule elle possède ce qui est, si c’est vraiment”; Ibid., pp. 426-427: “Montrer que nous sommes forcément amenés à affirmer (quelle que soit d’ailleurs la valeur de cette assertion) la réalité des objects de la connaissance et des fins de l’action ... ce n’est point, malgré le renouvellement de la perspective, sortir du déterminisme des phénomènes, c’est manifester comment, par cela seul que nous pensons et que nous agissons, il nous est nécessaire de faire comme si cet ordre universel était réel et ces obligations fondées”. Ibid., p. 297: “La’Métaphysique a sa substance dans la volonté agissante. Elle n’a de vérité.que sous cet aspect expérimental et dynamique : elle est moins une science de ce qui est que de ce qui' fait être et devenir: l’idéal d’aujourd’hui peut être le réel de demain”. Ibid., p. 437 : La connaissance qui avant l’option était simplement sub­ jective et propulsive, devient, après, privative et constitutive de l’être ... La seconde de ces connaissances, celle qui succède à la détermina­ tion librement prise en face de cette réalité nécessairement conçue, n’est plus seulement une disposition subjective; au lieu de poser le problème pratique, elle en traduit la solution dans notre pensée; au lieu de nous mettre en présence de ce qui est à faire, elle recueille, dans ce qui est fait, ce qui est. C’est donc vraiment une connaissance objective, même alors qu’elle est réduite à constater le déficit de l'action”. 12) A. Leclère, Kantstudien, Vif (Ï902), p. 30? sq._ , i i Apologetics of Immanence or Need 169 self-assertion and happiness. Action of this kind, or the longing for and the need of it, is the most certain ground­ work for further intellectual operations ; it is also the deep­ est and the primal ground, earlier even than thought, which is itself also action.13 Hence, the old definition of truth, as adaequatio rei et intellectus, must-be rejected14 in favor of another definition, namely, veritas est adaequatio realis mentis et vitae. That is to say, we possess truth, when our mind knows and affirms the exigencies of our life and action. The first operation of the spirit, therefore, is said to Attitude towarde be a kind of surrender (by faith) to God and the Church. External·c** 1* ·· An immediate consequence of this viewpoint is the new and questionable teaching, that the knowledge of Mira­ cles does not lead to Faith; on the contrary, we accept Miracles because we believe; a Miracle is really Faith’s dearest child. For, there are no natural rational proofs for Miracles; they are excluded for the very reason, that the constant 13) L'Action, p. XXI: “Abordant la science de l’action, il n’y a donc rien que je puisse tenir pour accordé, rien ni des faits, ni des principes, ni des devoirs; c’est :à me retirer tout appui précaire qut je viens de travailler. Qu’on ne prétende point, comme Descartes, par un artifice qui sent l’école tout sérieux qu’il est, extraire du doute et de l’illusion la réalité même de l’être; car je ne sens point de con­ sistance dans cette réalité du rêve, elle est vide et reste hors de moi. Qu’on ne me parle point, avec Pascal, de, jouer croix ou‘ pile sur le néant de l’éternité; car parier ce serait déjà ratifier l’alternative. Qu’on ne me fasse pas, après Kant, surgir je ne sais de quelle nuit Je ne sais quel Impératif catégorique; car je le traiterais en suspect et en intrus. Il faut, au contraire, accueillir toutes les néga­ tions qui s’entre-détruisent, comme s’il était possible de les admettre ensemble; il faut entrer dans tous les préjugés, comme s’ils étaient légitimes; dans toutes les erreurs, comme si elles étaient sincères”, etc.. Ibid,, pp. VII, VIII: “A consulter l’évidence immédiate, l’action dans ma vie est un fait, le plus général et le plus constant de tous . . . Toute règle de vie qui serait uniquement fondée sur une théorie philosophique et des principes abstraits serait téméraire: je ne puis différer d’agir jusqu’à ce que l’évidence ait paru, et toute évidence qui brille à l’esprit est partielle. Une pure connaissance ne suffit jamais à nous mouvoir parce qu’elle ne nous saisit pas tout entiers: en toute acte, il y a un acte de foi”. Ibid., p. XIII: “Il s’agit du tout de l’homme; ce n’est donc pas dans la pensée seule qu’on doit le chercher. C'est dans l'action qu’il va falloir transporter le centre de la philoso­ phie, parce que là se trouve le centre de la vie”. 14) Blondel, Point de départ de la recherche philosophique, in Annales de Philosophie chrétienne, 1906, art. 1, p. 235: “A l’abstraite et chimérique adaequatio rei et intellectus se substitue . . . l’adaequatio reâlis mentis et vitae”. 170 Chapter V. regularity of nature's operations is not something grounded in the world of reality itself; rather this regularity is fictitiously ascribed to it and thrown over it» like an arti­ ficial net, by our understanding. The world of external reality is wholly indeterministic, everything (hence, laws too) is changeable and fluent. Thoroughly convinced of the changeableness of all natural laws, modern science does not venture, save only provisionally, to formulate a single law as irrefragable.18 In other words, apart from the exigencies of human action, speculative reason cannot know with certainty ontological reality, nor any separate extra­ mental fact. The separation of phenomena, like the fixity of nature’s laws, is due solely to our subjective conception, not to reality itself which is ever changing. Hence, a Miracle is not a derogation from the laws of nature as they are in themselves, but as they appear to us, dérogations “aux ap­ parences anthropomorphiques”, as Blondel writes: or déro­ gations “à un ordre illusoire” according to P. Laberthonnière.18 Accordingly, the advocates of the “New Philosophy” refuse to acknowledge the philosophical knowability of the proving force of a Miracle. That is to say, the ontological value of a Miracle, as a token of the special divine inter­ vention for the purpose of confirming and proving the Fact of Revelation, which is admitted by common sense, cannot be defended philosophically and scientifically. For them, a Miracle possesses only_svwhoZic value, that is, it manifests to us the presence of God in the world and in our life, there­ by directing our minds to examine the religion, which it symbolically confirms. Nay more, this symbolic value of a Miracle can be perceived only by minds, which are already conscious of the exigencies of moral human action, and rightly disposed to admit God’s activity in ordinary facts. Hence, according to Blondel,16 17 if a Miracle be examined metaphysically, no more will be discovered in it than in ordinary facts; even the most ordinary fact embodies the 16 ) Gisler, ibid,, pp. 258, 259. ie) cf. Bulletin de la Société française de Philosophie, June 1911, p. 144 . . . March 1912, p. 143; also P. DeTonquédec, Immanence, pp. 200-227. 17) L'Action, p. 396: “L’idée de lois fixes dans la nature n’est q’une idole; chaque phénomène est un cas singulier et une solution unique. A aller au fond des choses, il n’y a rien de plus sans doute dans le miracle que dans la moindre des fait ordinaires: mais aussi il n’y a rien de moins dans le plus ordinaire des faits que dans le miracle: et voilà le sens de ces brusqueries exceptionnelles qui pro­ voquent la réflexion à des conclusions plus générales. Ce qu’elles révèlent c’est que le divin n’est pas seulement dans ce qui semble dépasser la puissance accoutumée de l’homme et de la nature, mais Apologetics of Immanence or Need 171 same content as a Miracle, for, in all facts the presence of God's activity is apparent to a mind rightly disposed; only a Miracle compels our attention, and symbolically in­ cites us to examine into religion. Thus, the proving force of Miracles is made subordinate to the exigencies of our action, that is, to the method of immanence. The same is true as regards “moral” Miracles, for in­ stance, the marvelous life of the Church.17· 2. Bergson and Blondel also agree· as regards the ρμιο·οΡηχ ot principle of Immanence (from the Latin, in manore, i. e., “man*ne·· the quality of any action which begins and ends within the agent) and its transcendental consequences. Their philosophy starts with the Ego; they refuse to admit anything as a fact, especially in a religious respect, un­ less the grounds of that fact are found within the Ego. Nothing can enter into man, so they insist, which does not proceed from him and manifest itself in some way as a postulate, or a need, of his soul. Every truth, every duty, every command, must be in a sense autonomous and autochthonous; it may not be presented to me sim­ ply and solely from without as a historical fact, a tradi­ tional doctrine, or duty. Hence, the apologist ought to show that of ourselves alone we are, in point of fact, not self-sufficient ; that our thought and action need cer­ tain desiderata and requisita; grace, Revelation, an in­ fallible teaching authority, etc. In order to live and to act in accordance with reason and conscience, we seek for powers higher than our own, we need a supplement partout là même où nous estimons volontiers que l'homme et la nature se suffisent. Les miracles ne sont donc miraculeux qu'au regard de ceux qui sont déjà prêts à reconnaître l'action divine dans les évènements et les actes les plus habituels. Ces coups brusques n'agissent qu'autant qu’on en saisit, non pas les merveilleux sensibles, qu'est-ce que cela, mais le sens symbolique". 17·) Ibid., p. 395: “Qu’ils soient ou non surnaturels en leur prin­ cipe, ce n’est point dans les signes sensibles eux-mêmes, qu’il faut voir l'origine de notre idée de révélation. C’est par le développement de l'activité pratique et grâce à l’effort de la volonté pour s’egaler à son propre élan, qu’est né, on a vu comment, le besoin d'une corre­ spondance extérieure et d'un complément nécessaire à notre action intime". Ibid., p. 397: “Ce n’est donc pas de la révélation même (dans l’hypothèse où elle n'est pas), ni des phénomènes naturels (dans l’hy­ pothèse où elle n’est pas) que peut venir à l’homme l'idée de pré­ ceptes ou de dogmes révélés. C'est d'une initiative interne que jaillit cette notion". 172 Chapter V. from the supernatural order. The apologist ought to make it plain that our inmost soul calls out : The super­ natural is necessary for us to enable us to live as we ought.17b B. Armed with’the philosophy of Immanence, Blondel next proceeds to construct the Apologetics of Immanence. He discards the traditional, doctrinal, objective and rational apologetics18, which, he says, aimed at emphasiz­ ing only objective Faith, and wholly neglected its subjec­ tive side, the Act of Faith, the preparation for Faith.1* In Blondel’s opinion the apologetic method of Fonsegrive, Brunetière and others, is also inefficacious. They believed that the chief task of apologetics was the subjective prep­ aration of the believer, but it was to be effected by psycho­ logical means, namely, by disclosing the beauty, the moral and social usefulness, the universal harmony between Faith and the aspirations of the human spirit. However, Blondel is convinced that to impress the modern mentality, which has been brought up in the school of Criticism, we must employ arguments of a totally different kind. It has often been said that metaphysics is gone, never to return. Blondel offers to show how this metaphysics can return after all under a new and totally different form. Without such a metaphysics one cannot even touch the problem, to say nothing of solving it.20 Therefore, the Apologetics of Immanence claims to be strictly philosophical. It takes as its starting point “Action”; from this point of vantage it seeks to develop 17b) Gisler, ibid., p. 259 ; cf. E. Thimary, art. "Immanence, in CE. VII, p. 682 sq; also Aug. and Alb. Valensin, art. "Immanence (Doctrine et Methode d’)”, in DAFC, fasc. VIII, colls. 569 sq.· with appended bibliography. 18) Blondel, Lettre sur les exigences de la pensée contemporaine en matière d’apologétique et sur la méthode de la philosophie dans l’étude du problème religieux. Annales de philosophie chrétienne, Jan.-July, 1896, p. 83: “S’opiniâtrer à restaurer ce qui dans l’ancienne école est mort, au moyen d’un rationalisme mort, c’est d’avance re­ tomber sous les coups de la double critique qui a tué la pseudo­ philosophie chrétienne par la métaphysique de la transcendance, et qui a tué la pseudo-philosophie rationaliste par la doctrine de l'immanence, elle-même dépassée”. 18) Lettre, p. 22., 20) Blondel, Annales de philosophie chrétienne, Nov. 1895, p. 189- Apologetics ofJmmanence or Need 173 all truth.21 What does Blondel understand by “Action”? He means the concrete act of vital thought, which reflects for us our own-selves and all things else.22 Now, Action postulates the supernatural: “Thé progress of our will compels us to admit our insufficiency, 'leads us to the de­ sire of some help (au besoin d’ un surcroît), enables us, not, indeed, to create or to define it, but to recognize and to accept it”.23 * If the will has not found full satisfaction in individual and social activity, it seeks it beyond the world of phe­ nomena, in the Infinite, in order to pay worship to it, but in a superstitious manner, by materializing,it as a fetish, or by anthropomorphizing it, drawing near to it by petitions and sacrifices, or by deifying ethical ideals after the manner of Kant, or by deifying metaphysical phantoms, construc­ tions, the ideals of science and of art, and thus is a believer •—a negative believer—despite the rejection of all dogmas ; or the will espouses a new mysticism, which assumes an un­ bounded critical attitude, and pays homage to a progressive action for action’s sake, without an object, without faith, without rites, without prièsts.24 It is impossible to mistake the impotency and insufficiency of the whole order of nature; Accordingly, an inventory of our immanent resources “brings to light, on the one hand, our irrepressible aspira­ tions towards the' infinitely True, Good, and Beautiful, and, on the other hand, the insufficiency of our means to attain these ends. This comparison shows that our nature, left to itself, is not in a state of equilibrium”.25 But whither are we to go? Where can we find salvation? We wish to be self-sufficient, and we cannot be. If we are to find the One Thing Necessary (l’unique nécessaire) ; if our 21) Blondel, L'Action, p. 465: “A la vérité du primat de l’action’, 'au commencement était l’Action’, répond la grande affirmation de l’égale primauté de la vérité: ‘Principio erat Verbum’. Ce règne de la vérité est tout entier hors de nous, elle ne sera, jamais désarmée de son sceptre de fer; mais aussi ce règne de la vérité est tout entier en nous, puisque nous en produisons en nous-mêmes toutes les despo­ tiques exigences . . . Du moindre de nos actes, du moindre des faits, il suffit de tirer ce qui s’y trouve, pour rencontrer l’inévitable présence, non pas seulement d’une abstraite cause première, mais du- seul auteur et du vrai consommateur de toute réalité concrète. Jusqu’au dernier. détail du dernier des phénomènes imperceptibles, l’action médiatrice fait la vérité et l’être de tout ce qui est’ 22) Lettre, p. 57. 23) Lettre, p. 38. 24) L'Action, pp. 306-318. 25) Thamiry, art. "Immanence", iri CE VII, p. 686. J i 174 Chapter V. nature is to achieve its destiny, “it needs a help which is essentially beyond it—a transcendent help * ’26; we must ascend from the sphere of the immanent to the sphere of the transcendent. This Vunique nécessaire cannot be proved by demonstration and deduction. Metaphysical conceptions and definitions ought not, indeed, to be rejected; but they are, of themselves, sterile phantoms of reason. The concept of a First Cause, or of an Ethical Ideal, or the ideas of a meta­ physical perfection, of an actus purus, are vain, false and idolatrous, when looked at in themselves, as abstract thoughts; but they are true, vitally efficacious, when they are taken as practical certitudes, which satisfy the will: "C’est donc dans la pratique même que la certitude de Funique nécessaire a son fondement”.27 In like manner supernatural Revelation, with its dogmas and precepts, can acquire certainty for us only in this way. It is certain for us, only if we offer to it a receptivity (dis­ position d’obéissance) free from all selfish strivings; if we accept that Revelation as a gift coming from God, which makes possible for us a higher life in Faith and action, and which atones for, arid redeems, us from the defects and fail­ ings, which attach to our nature. However, in order to be believed, as it ought to be believed, revealed doctrine must itself offer the grounds of Faith and prove its certainty. In this respect, the only proof that can be of service is an effica­ cious experimental proof (une expérimentation effective). Faith does not enter into the heart by means of thought; rather it is practical action, which draws down from above a divine light for the spirit. God is operative in this action ; hence, the thought, which follows upon action, is richer as regards the Infinite than the thought which precedes it.28 suuury. To sum up : According to Blondel present day philos­ ophers are thoroughly wedded to the principle of im­ manence; they regard human reason as autonomous and autochthonous, and refuse to accept anything from with­ out, that is not required for the perfect and connatural 2«) Ibid., p. 686. 27) L'Action, pp. 319-320. 28) Ibid., pp. 397-403, summarized in Schmid, ibid., pp. 206-207. i Apologetics of Immanence or Need 175 evolution of our faculties.20 *29 Hence, when the apologist proposes the Christian Religion as supernatural, that is, as something, imposed from without, which must be accepted under the pain of eternal damnation, he meets at once with the bitterest opposition. To cope with this modern mentality, he must start with the principle of immanence. He ought to show that? the supernatural, although not due to human nature, is, nevertheless, in some way demanded from within, as a help for the per­ fect evolution of our action; hence, we must embrace it. This method consists “in eqùating within our own con­ sciousness, what we seem to think, to wish and to do, with what we really do, wish, and think, in such a way that in the fictitious negations, or the ends artificially desired, those profound affirmations and irresistible needs, which they imply, shall still be found”. This in­ ternal analysis, this psychologic examination of con­ science, brings the human soul to recognize itself as relative to a transcendent Being, thereby setting before us the problem of God. It arouses in man a more vivid consciousness of his weakness and his need of help, thereby impelling him to acts of humility, which inspire prayer and attract grace.90 Thus, Blondel advocates a relative, not an absolute, immanence as understood by Modernists. The latter assert that the Catholic Religion proceeds from our vital immanence, in accordance with the evolution of the natural religious sense ; whereas the former only affirms that the Catholic Religion, although supernatural and revealed by God, is postulated by our 20 ) Blondel, Lettre sur les exigences de la Pensée contemporaine en matière d’Apologétique, in Annales de Philosophie chrétienne, Jan.-July, 1896, p. 600: “La pensée moderne avec une susceptibilité jalouse considère la notion d’immanence comme la condition même de la philosophie; c’est à dire que, si parmi les idées régnantes, il y a un résultat auquel elle s’attache comme à un progrès certain, c’est l’idée très juste en son fond que rien ne peut entrer en l’homme qui ne sorte de lui et ne corresponde en quelque façon à un besoin d’ex­ pansion, et que ni comme fait historique, ni comme enseignement traditionnel, ni comme obligation surajoutée du dehors, il n’v a pour lui vérité qui compte et précepte admissible sans être, de quelque manière, autonome et autochtone”. 80 ) Thamiry, ibid., p. 686. 176 .’ « * Chapter V. .. ...... . nature from within; it does indeed'transcend the> powers of our nature, but not the exigencies of our nature. With­ in us, there a re-aspirations for something higher, for the Infinite and the Divine, which we desire as our ultimate end, from within, by the necessity of our nature. But we cannot(attain to this Infinite Being without His help; hence, our nature intrinsically demands a supernatural help from God, that is, Divine Revelation. It also de^· mands a Mediator and Saviour, in order that through His assistance we may be able to approach God. Thus, “a method of immanence developed in its integrity be­ comes exclusive of a doctrine of immanence. * ’ Blondel next endeavors to show by history, that these Divine helps, which our nature demands, are; found· solely in Christianity and in the Catholic Church. Thereupon the divine origin of Catholicism, which is manifested sym­ bolically by Miracles and the marvelous life of the Church, becomes practically certain through our experi­ ence of the Christian Religion under grace.8182Conse­ quently, by the credibility of the mysteries of Faith the advocates of relative immanence understand their aptitude for belief, inasmuch as they appear conformable 'to the aspirations and exigencies of our nature.12 ** CRITICISM False Principles Closely akin to Kantianism. 1. The philosopher of Konigsberg might object here and there to an important point in the “Nouvelle Philos­ ophie” of Bergson, Blondel, and their pupils; but, on the whole, he would discern much of his own spirit re­ flected therein. He would find there the siibjectivistic conception ,of the world and of certitude—both in part thè product of the mind itself, and dependent upon emo­ tional and volitional factors ; he would recognize there especially the concept of immanence. Just as Kant 81 ) cf. L’Action, p. 402. 82 ) P. Fr. Reg. Gar rigou-Lagrange, Ο. P., Theologia fundamen­ talis secundum S. Thomae doctrinam. Romae et Parisiis. 1918, vol. I, p. 125 sq., vol. II, p. 3 sq., (3’ed., 1925), pp. 44 sq., 317-sq. Criticism 177 makes the-ideas of God, of free will, of immortality, pro­ ceed from the idea of duty, so, too, these philosophers look upon all religious dogmas as flowing from the total­ ity of the soul’s needs. Finally, Kant, the energetic op­ ponent of the so-called “statutory” in Religion, could point to the idea of religious evolution in the “New Philosophy”, as well as to the mystic, emotional element in Faith. Hence, he might rejoice that his “Kritik der reinen Vernunft”, his “Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der blossen Vernunft”, and his “Streit der Fakultàten”, had not been written in vain, at least as far as these Frenchmen are concerned. He might even show that the French Immanentists had outstripped him, inasmuch as they have made theoretical reason dependent upon prac­ tical, reason to a far greater degree than he himself had done, since they ascribe to the emotional, volitional and moral element, to Action, the primary role in the whole process of knowledge.83 a) The Apologetics of Immanence, or Need, rests, in the first place, upon the erroneous doctrine of semi­ agnosticism. These philosopher^ champion the agnosticism of specu- Semi-amoeticism. lative reason, as is evident from their definition of truth. For them, truth is not the,“adaeg«aiio seu conformitas rei et intellectus” ; they conceive truth in a merely subjective manner as “adaequatio seu conformitas mentis et vitae”. That is ’to say, only that judgment is true, which is in con­ formity with the exigencies of our life. Hence, extramental reality can be known only according to the exigencies of .human action ; only practical certitude is obtainable. But according to St. Thomas, only the truth of the practical in­ tellect, or the truth of prudence, depends “on the conformity with a right appetite”.And the rectitude of the appetite depends on the first principles of reason, which are true accordingly as they are in conformity with the thing itself.33 35 34 Hence, it is difficult to see how these philosophers can escape the condemnation which the Church placed upon the kindred 33) p. 263. 34) 85) p. 297, A. Leclère, Kantetudien VII (1892), p. 360'sq; Gisler, ibid.; ST. I, II, q. 57, a. 5, ad 3. Garrigou-Lagrange, Ο. P., ibid., II, *p. 3, foot-note; (3’ed.), foot-note. 178 Chapter V. viewpoint of the Modernists : “Veritas non est immutabilis plus quam ipse homo, quippe quae cum ipso, in ipso et per ipsum evolvitur”.86 An immediate consequence of this agnosticism is the denial of the philosophical knowability of Miracles, and also of the existence of God. Likewise, if the concepts in which dogmatic formulae are expressed, lack ontological and transcendental validity, the dogmas also lose their absolute truth and immutability. Thus, again these philosophers seem to approximate to the teaching of the twenty-sixth condemned proposition of the Modernists: “Dogmata fidei retinenda sunt tantummodo juxta sensum practicum, id est tamquam norma praeceptiva agendi, non vero tamquam norma credendi”.87 Therefore, the semi-agnosticism of these philosophers leads to strict agnosticism.38 semï-immânen. Rejoinder of the New Philosophy. The second foundation of the “New Philosophy” is the principle of semi-immanentism, which exaggerates our natural desire for the supernatural, and thus leads to the error of Baianism.88 89 For, if the Catholic Religion is demanded by our nature, it is due to us, and thus is not supernatural. For, the super­ natural is not merely above the powers, but also above the exigencies of nature. What our nature demands is only natural beatitude, which consists in an abstractive knowl­ edge of God, and in a natural love proportionate to that knowledge. Compare this viewpoint with the condemned proposition of Baius: “Humanae naturae sublimatio et exaltatio in consortium divinae naturae debita fuit integ­ ritati primae condicionis, et proinde naturalis dicenda est, et non supernaturalis”.46 The advocates of the “New Philosophy”, for example, P. Laberthonnière41, reply that Blondel can and ought to be 88) DB. n. 2058. 37) DB. n. 2026. 38) Garrigou-Lagrange, Ο. P., i6id., I, p. 129, (3’ed.), p. 48. 89) Ibid., I, pp. 129, 130; (3’ed.), pp. 48, 49. 40) DB. n. 1021. Thus, also Pius X teaches in his Encyclical “Pascendi dominici gregis” : ,rWe have grave reason to complain that there are Catholics who, while rejecting immanence as a doctrine, employ it as a method of apologetics, and who do this so impudently that they seem to admit, not merely a capacity and a suitability for the supernatural as such, as has at all times been emphasized within due limits by Catholic apologists, but that there is in human nature a true and rigorous need for the supernatural order”. (DB. n. 2103). 41) Cf. Annale» de Philosophie chrétienne, March-April, 1897; IDEM, Essais de philosophie religieuse, p. 168 sq. /. Criticism 179 interpreted more. benignly, and that his doctrine, far from deserving the strictures mentioned above, really merits our commendation. For, Blondel, so they explain, is not speak­ ing of human nature in the abstract; he has in mind man, not as he might have been created according to the exigeni cies of nature ; rather he is speaking of human nature in the concrete, as it exists here and now; he is discoursing on : man, destined as he is to the supernatural order. Now, man ! does not find himself in a purely natural state or condition ; ! he is really under the influence of actual grace, which impels him to turn to God, the Author of the supernatural order, i even though he does not actually possess habitual grace and supernatural Faith. Even in the state of fallen nature, the human soul experiences within itself a certain vague con­ sciousness, almost wholly obliterated indeed, of its original elevation to the supernatural order and of its Divine dig­ nity, as St. Augustine teaches.4243Moreover, in the present order every Divine dispensation is fraught with God’s grace; hence, it is not temerity to assert that in man certain pious desires and aspirations well up, under the impulse of grace to be sure, which argue an exigency of the supernat­ ural order. Therefore, so these philosophers maintain, we may hold that even before he has a perfect knowledge of I Revelation, man may experience a certain need of the (supernatural order. However, this experience is not due to human, nature left to itself, but inasmuch as it is subject to the influence of Divine grace, which is continually mov­ ing man to Faith.42 h It is not necessary that this aspiration towards Chrisi tianity be perceived in our consciousness, since it is, strictly P speaking, supernatural in its end or purpose ; it suffices that i we be conscious of our incapacity to fulfil the highest ten; dencies of our soul, and that we recognize that these aspiraÎ tions may find their satisfaction in Christianity. We are able to experience our own restlessness of soul, even as St. Augustine did when he wrote: “Irrequietum est cor nos­ trum, donec requiescat in Te”.44 Hence, even though this ' postulate of our nature is not immediately evident, still, anyone who knows how to interpret the immediate and ■ 42) De spiritu et littera, c. 28: "non usque adeo imago Dei ter­ renorum affectuum labe detrita est, ut nulla in ea velut lineamenta extrema remanserint; unde merito dici possit etiam in ipsa impietate vitae suae aliqua legis divinae sapere”. 43) Garrigou-Lagrange, O. P., ibid., I, p. 130; (3’ed.), p. 49; cf. Aemil. Dorch, S. J., Institutiones theologiae fundamentalis. Oeniponte, 1916, I, p. 487. «) Garrigou-Lagrange, O. P., ibid., I, p. 130; (3’ed.), p. 49. I 180 Chapter V. spontaneous tendency of the soul, which, as Tertullian says, is “naturally Christian”, will recognize that postulate under the things which are systematically offered to the soul, and impinge upon the consciousness. We cannot, indeed, know the supernatural as such; but there is doubtless much more in reality than in our power of apprehension; hence, from what we know of reality or of action, we deduce some knowledge of that reality as existing outside ourselves, and as postulated by our immanent appetite, even though it does not exist within our apprehension.45 Thus, according to this interpretation of Blondel’s doc­ trine, grace or the operation of the Holy Spirit moves a cer­ tain exigency within our souls, and by virtue of that move­ ment leads us to Revealed Religion, in fact, to the Christian Religion. For the aspirations, which we experience within, and which are excited by the exigency already latent in our souls, are far more sublime than our immanent powers, which of themselves alone are incapable of satis­ fying these tendencies. Looking about, we discover in a certain concrete religion, that is, in Christianity, the way that makes it possible for ûs to satisfy these aspirations. Hence, we are led to embrace that religion as the right way, and thus the motions and illuminations of Divine grace are for us indications and proofs of supernatural truth.46 3 J ! , I , I I 1 I This Rejoinder This rejoinder of the “New Philosophy” does not really unwiSd!” solve the question at issue; it merely defers it. The prob­ lem in regard to the original and primal destiny of the human race to a supernatural end, still clamors for solution. Is this destiny to a supernatural end altogether gra­ tuitous, or is it postulated from within, as these apologists would prove by the principle of immanence?—For, this principle of immanence is either securely rooted in the original ordering or destiny of the human race to a. super­ natural end, or it is not. If it is not, then the “New Apolo­ getics” does not prove its contention, and the objections of Naturalism remain unsolved. If, on the contrary, it is safely lodged in that divine decree by which God destines mankind to a supernatural end, how is it possible to avoid the error of Baius?—There is no escape from this dilemma, save perhaps by a worse error, namely, by the denial of the ontological value of our reason : thus, the exigency of the i i _______ 45) J. V. Bainvel, De vera religione et apologetica. Paris. 1914, pp. 139, 140. 46) Dorsch, S. J., ibid., I, p. 489. Criticism 181 supernatural order would be merely subjectively, not ob­ jectively, necessary.47 r? c) The Apologetics of Immanence, or Need, does not Fidebm. prove the credibility or the divine origin of Christianity, rather it approximates to Fideism. It does, indeed, to a certain extent show that Christian­ ity is a beautiful and attractive religion, and deserving of religious experience ; nay more, that it is morally necessary to enable the modern man to live in accordance with the dignity of human nature. But-this does not prove that the Catholic Religion, with all its dogmas and precepts, must be believed most firmly and irrevocably by Divine Faith, and that there never will be a more perfect religion than the Christian. Agnostic prejudices and the almost exclusive use of internal subjective motives render such a proof ineffectual.48 This method presents a false notion of credibility, for, it identifies Divine Faith, more or less, with religious ex­ perience, which is common to all religions.49 Divine Faith is grounded on the authority of God revealing, and not on religious experience. According to Blondel, the divine origin of Catholicism becomes certain only in a practical way, that is, through the experience of the Christian Re­ ligion, under the assistance of grace. The Catholic Church, on the-contrary, teaches that our rational certitude as re­ gards the Fact of Revelation ought to be much stronger, in order that we may be able to believe most firmly on the authority of God revealing.50 Moreover, a man who does not yet believe, but is con­ scious of the need of faith, is counselled by these new apolo­ gists to act as though he already believed, in order that he may arrive at certitude» as regards Revelation, by means of this action or experience of Catholicism. But how is it pos­ sible to have this experience of Catholicism without receiv­ ing the Sacraments, and how can one receive the Sacra­ ments who does not as yet believe? This attitude of mind closely approximates to the conception of the Modernists condemned by Pius X: “The aim he (the Modernist) sets 47) Garrigou-Lagrange, Ο. P., ibid., I, p. 130; (3’ed.), p. 49. For a deeper critical examination of this part of Blondel’s doctrine the student might consult P. De Tonquédec, Immanence. ’ Paris, 1913, p. 155 sq; also Alb. Valensin, art. “Immanence (Methode d’), in DAFC, fasc. VIII, col. 600 sq. *8) Garrigou-Lagrange, Ο. P., ibid., II, p. 4; (3’ed.), p. 298. . «) Ibid., II, p. 4; (3’ed.), p. 298. »o> Ibid., I, p. 130; (3’ed.), pp. 49, 50. 182 Chapter V. before himself is to make one, who is still without faith, attain that experience of the Catholic religion, which, ac­ cording to the system, is the sole basis of faith”.61 And “if you ask”, so the Encyclical adds, “on what foundation this assertion of the believer rests, he answers : In the personal experience of the individual. On this head, the Modernists differ from the Rationalists, only to fall into the views of the Protestants and pseudo-Mystics”.62 2. In the light of this critical appreciation of the method of relative immanence, the chief limitations and excellencies of the method may be summarized under the following heads. ·*Μ. of a) In the first place, the scope of this method is limited by the very same exigencies which it formulates, that is, by the exigencies of the “philosophers”, the élite, at least under the rigorous form which the scientific application of the theory implies. Hence, Blondel’s “I/Action” is not a popular apologetics.66 b) The psychologic analysis of man’s present misery and needs on the one hand, and of his legitimate aspira­ tions on the other, manifests the fact, that man is not selfsufficient and that he needs some divine help, in order to arrive at his natural end, namely, the fulfillment of all the precepts of the natural law. But this does not prove that this help must necessarily be supernatural. For, strictly speaking, God might also offer to man sufficient natural assistance to enable him to reach his final end, as we have shown in the chapter on the Necessity of Revela­ tion.64 Hence, if we experience certain vague aspirations for this superadditum, we may not conclude with certainty that it is supernatural in the strict theological connotation of that term. In the present order of the human race, a supernatural help is, indeed, necessary, but only because, as Revelation informs us, mankind has been destined to a supernatural end. This fact, however, can be known with certainty only through history, not by purely philosophical reasoning.66 Therefore, this method of itself alone is impotent to prove the fact of the supernatural. As Thamiry says, it51 * 55 54 53 52 51) DB. n. 2101. 52) DB. n. 2081. 53) Alb. Valensin, ibid., col. 609. 54) Baierl, The Theory of Revelation, I, sec. 1, p. 123 sq. 55) Ad. Tanquerey, Synopsis theologiae dogmaticae. Romae, Tornaci, Parians. 1922. (19'ed.), I, pp. 55, 56. j Criticism J 183 is doubtful whether this method, by its immanent analysis of human action, caii\bring the believer to hear and heed “the appeal of preventive or sanctifying grace”, which would then express itself in psychologic facts discernible by observation and philosophical analysis (Cardinal Dechamps) ; whether it would enable us to experience God, or at least “to find in our action the supernatural element which is said to enter into His Constitution” (P. Laberthonnière) ; whether, finally, it would justify us in affirm­ ing with certitude, that the object of oùr “irrepressible aspirations” is a “supernatural Unnamed” (Blondel), an object which is “beyond and above the natural order” (Ligeard). All such attempts, “when they lead to anything, seem to do so only at the price of confounding the notion of the transcendent with that of the preternatural, or even of the supernatural—or, again, at the price of confounding the divine co-operation and divine grace. In a word, if the psychologic analysis of the tendencies of human nature ends in ‘showing, without recourse to what Revelation gives us, that man desires infinitely more than the natural order can give him’ (Ligeard), it does not follow that we can say with any certainty that this ‘desired increase’ is a supernatural Unnamed. As a matter of fact, (1) the nat­ ural order far exceeds in vastness the object of my analysis; (2) between my nature and the supernatural there is the preternatural; (3) the aids to which my nature aspires, and which God gives me, are not necessarily of the supernatural order. Besides, even if a supernatural action does in fact manifest itself under these religious aspir­ ations, immanent analysis, apprehending only psychological phenomena, cannot detect it”.6® • The method of relative immanence manifests certain excellencies of a legitimate scope. a) It can help man to arrive at Faith. For, normally it is necessary to have the desire to believe (pius credulitatis affectus) as a preliminary step to faith. St. Thomas says : “Cum alicui proponuntur aeterna bona, primo vult ea, secundo vult eis inhaerere per amorem, et tertio vult sperare ea, et quarto vult credere ea ut credens possit jam sperare et amare et habere”.66 67 Since the method of rela­ tive immanence stimulates the desire, not, indeed, of the supernatural as such, but of some help, it disposes, at least 66> Art. "Immanence” in CE. VII, pp. 686, 687. B7) III Sent. dist. 23, q. 2, a. 5 ad 4; cf. St. Augustine, De quan­ titate animae, c. xix, n. 24; De vera religione, c. x. n. 20; De utilitate credendi, c. xvi, η. 84; De ordine, 1. Π, c. xix, η. 61. Excellencies of the Method. 184 Cardinal Dechampe. Chapter V. negatively, a person of good will to embrace whatever offers to satisfy all his exigencies and aspirations. b) It also offers to philosophical thought the. justifica­ tion for man’s adherence by faith to the supernatural. For, it shows that the supernatural, the gift of God to man, is neither tyranny nor something foreign to reason. Hence' it cannot be said that the problem of the supernatural is inconceivable and inadmissible.68 c) Finally, it is an excellent means to prepare the. way for the historical demonstration of Divine Revelation. For, it enables the modern mind, which proclaims the autonomy of reason, to recognize man’s insufficiency and his need'of some superadded assistance, thereby disposing it to con­ sider the external criteria of Catholicism. Therefore, we concede to this method a certain priority of time, but not of value, that is to say, a priority as regards preparing the inquirer, not in itself and from the objective viewpoint.69 The Redemptorist, and afterwards Archbishop of Malines, Belgium, Cardinal Dechamps, has worked out an apologetic demonstration, which embraces the method of relative immanence and the traditional, historical demon­ stration. The manifold arguments, so ..he maintains, in­ ternal and external, ought to be combined into a homo­ geneous and formal unity, thus forming a complete apolo­ getics (apologétique intégrale). He.states the program in these words: “Ecoute et,regarde, dit-il: Il n’y a que deux faits à vérifier, l’un en vous, l’autre hors de vous; ils se recherchent pour s’embrasser, de tous les deux, Je témoin c’est vous-même”.58 *60 Thus, he grounds the apologetic dem­ onstration upon a twofold fact, the one interior, the other exterior. The former is the starting-point, and consists in the con­ sciousness of our needs, especially in relation to religion and morality. “Who is satisfied with his natural condition? Who does not yearn for à more perfect condition? Who does not perceive in his soul a true echo of those words of St: Paul : ‘Every creature groaneth, and travailéth in pain until now’ . . . Therefore, it is true that nature longs for the supernatural, which ought to heal and perfect it, and that Deism, which denies the positive, supernatural and living order of the relation existing between God and man, is a 58 ) Alb. Valensin, ibid., col. 608. 69 ) Garrigou-Lagrange, Ο. P., ibid., I, p. 131; (3’ed.), p. 298. 60) De la Demonstration de la Foi ou Entretiens sur la demon­ stration catholique de la révélation chrétienne. Premier Entretien, p. 1 (H. Dessain, Malines). Criticism 185 doctrine contrary to nature. The supernatural is not con­ trary to nature, but rather the healing, exaltation, perfec­ tion of nature”. We feel the need of some authority, in which we can have full confidence as regards the things necessary for our final end. In consequence, we are pre­ pared to offer an attentive and docile ear to this authority, provided, of course, that it can show that it is worthy of credence. The external fact is the Church, which lays claim to infallible authority in religious matters, and which -by vir­ tue of the great number of her members, her qualities and the. splendid benefits, which she unceasingly confers in the religious and moral sphere, gains the friendship of souls and appears truly worthy of our credence and allegiance. The apologist realizes, of course, that he must search the records of the past for the credentials of the Church. There­ fore, he opens up the Gospels and studies them according to the historical ^method, and establishes the transcendence of Christianity, and the right of the Church to' her title of “catholic”. The force of this demonstration is in the sources. But its practical efficacy, its aptitude to take hold of men, will not appear independently of actual conditions. Hence, the external fact must be joined with the internal fact.61 These two different methods of demonstration do not place before the apologist paths theoretically equivalent, and separately capable of leading to a decisive conclusion; rather both of them are indispensable, but in different ways, for a full and complete demonstration; And their synthesis is in the living man. For the act by which man adhères to.Faith, is not the simple resultant of an historical inquiry in accordance with positive methods. This act is preceded by the gift of God, namely, grace. The beginning of; this' process is within the soul. It ends by facing the external fact. Hence, the “apologétique integrate” is both internal and external.62* Some authors, it is true, are unsympathetic towards this method of Cardinal Dechamps and, for various rea­ sons, accuse it of subjectivism and traditionalism. How­ ever, it is practically the method advanced by the Vatican Council.68 For instance, P. A. Matignon, S. J., .objects that the proof resting on the innate needs of the human heart, is not a real demonstration and does not beget full certi61) cf. Alb. 62) 63) Dechamps, Oevres, (H. Dessain), Malines, t. I, III, IV, XVI; Valensin, ibid., colls. 610, 611; Tanquerey, ibid., I, pp. 44, 45. Alb. Valensin, ibid., col. 611. DB. n. 1785-1794; cf. J. V. Bainvel, S. J., ibid., p. 136. 186 Chapter V. tude.M To this the Cardinal replied, that the psychological need and its disclosure are, to be sure, no argument for the necessity of supernatural Revelation, but only for its credibility, and that the apologetic proof that proceeds from this argument does not render superfluous the demonstra­ tion drawn from external facts, but rather presupposes it, and from this viewpoint is really a demonstrative proof on intrinsic grounds.®5 II. General Charac­ terisation. PSYCHOLOGICO-MORAL APOLOGETICS. Akin to Blondel’s method of Immanence, and yet dif­ fering from it, is the method espoused by Ollé-Laprune, Fonsegrive, Denis, Brunetière and others. Their aim is to deduce a proof for the truth of the Christian Religion from the harmony of Christianity with the inmost aspir­ ations of the soul, with the laws of reason and morality, with the postulates of life. Nature and the Christian Religion are in perfect accord. This form of apologetic demonstration may be termed the Psychologico-Moral Apologetics, or the Apologetics of Value, or Social Apologetics. Ollé-Laprune, Denis and Fonsegrive reject Kantian­ ism; they do not question the ability of theoretical rea­ son to prove the existence of God.68 But speculative proofs, so they insist, no longer exert much influence over the modern mentality; moral and psychological arguments, on the other hand, appeal to minds educated in Kantianism and modern philosophy. If we are to gain access to the modern mind, it is necessary to take man as we find him, and to speak the language which he understands.67 Brunetière advocates a similar method. Let us examine these aspects of the “New Apologetics” more in detail.64 64) Le Question du Surnaturel. Paris. 1861, pp. 10-12. 66) Dechamps, Pie IX et les erreurs contemporains. 1864, pp. 291305; cf. Schmid, ibid., p. 201. 66) Ollé-Laprune, De la certitude morale. Paris. 1880, p. 105. For Fonsegrive ci. Quinzaine, March 16, 1907: Novissima verba. 67) Fonsegrive, Le catholicisme et la vie de Vesprit. Paris. 1906, pp. 9, 58, 70. Ollé-Laprune, Le prix de la vie. Pari*. 1909, (3’«d.), p, 105 sq., Les sources de la paix intellectuelle. Pari*. <5’ed.)t P- 78. Psychologico-Moral Apologetics 187 Ollé-Laprune û Leon Ollé-Laprune (1839-1898) was instrumental in Κρ^°οΡ11*πι1 establishing a new school of apologetics in France. His doctrine, which finds expression in various works,6*68 is written with an enthusiastic conviction and a deep and splendid eloquence. He distinguishes, in the first place, between religion and philosophy, for, religion is not merely an operation of the intellect, but also a practical operation. In agreement with Hurter’s Compendium, he differentiates between man’s natural end, natural happi­ ness, and the means that correspond to that end, and man’s supernatural end, supernatural beatitude, which consists in the beatific vision, and the proportionate means to that end; hence, between natural and super­ natural religion, that is, the Christian Religion, which is grounded on positive authority and transcends the powers of human nature.69 The basic thought of his important work on “Moral cJfStSi·. Certitude” deals with the question: Is there really such a thing as metaphysical, natural-religious and apolo­ getic certitude! He answers in the affirmative, but he contends that this certitude is only moral. In the Preface to this work, he acknowledges his indebtedness most of all to the influence of Gr a try’s publication concerning the knowledge of God, and to a philosophical inquiry con­ cerning moral certitude written by C. Caro. Moral truths, in the stricter sense, are such as constitute the subject matter of morality and moral science. In the broader sense, moral truths are also such metaphysical and natural religious truths, as are closely associated with moral truths in the stricter sense. They are espe­ cially the following four: the moral law, freedom, God and immortality. They are partly inner experiential facts, partly rational postulates; they are, moreover, objec6S) Besides the works already cited above in notes 66 and 67, cf. La philosophie et le temps present. 1890; La Vitalité chrétienne, 1901; Raison et Rationalisme, €9) La prix de la vie. Paris. 1897, pp. 341-365. k 188 Chapter V, tively certain and universally valid truths, which we are in duty bound to acknowledge. But in view of the fact, that in many respects they do not possess evidence, which excludes ^every unreasonable and sophisticated doubt, they are only truths of natural faith; still, they are actual or demonstrable rational truths which are objectively certain. Understood in this sense, they: are truths of natural rational faith, and, hence, they must be carefully differentiated from the truths of positive, supernatural Faith, which have for their formal ground of certitude, or motive, the authority of God revealing, and for their end, or purpose, supernatural beatitude, and'transcend the sphere of human reason. Thereby; so Ollé-Laprune believes, every kind of false mysticism and scepticism is eradicated.70 Thus, two extreme tendencies are eliminated : on the one hand, the tendency of certain writers, who exaggerate moral faith, for instance, Pascal, Maine de Biran, Kant, Fichte in his writing on the destiny of man, Jacobi, Hamilton and Mansel; and, on the other hand, thetendency of such writers as Cour^ not, Spencer, John Stuart Mill, who. undervalue moral faith, credit it with mere probability, or even regard it as an illusion. Both tendencies lead to false mysticism and scepticism.71 According to Kant, a belief in rational creatures outside of ourselves, and historical faith, ought to appeal to sciences but a belief in transcendental things, on the contrary, ought not to have recourse to science. Ollé-Laprune, however, maintains that, for both classes of objects, rational knowledge and rational faith are really possible, since their objects are partly evident to us, and partly also inevident or obscure; moreover, moral faith as. regards supersensible things is an objec­ tively certain faith that1 binds in conscience, and not merely a subjectively certain faith “of need or. neces­ sity”.72 Therefore, the question as to whether faith 70) De la Certitude Morale, Paris. 1898 (3’ed.), pp. 10-12. 98-125. 168-169. 71) Ibid,, pp. 126-312. 72) Ibid,, pp. 113. 146-163. Psychol ogico-Mor ai Apologetics 189 (croyance) is the ground of intellectual.knowledge must, in Ollé-Laprune’s opinion, receive both- a negative and an affirmative answer with qualifications. It must be an­ swered negatively, inasmuch as faith cannot be the ground of all intellectual knowledge, if that faith be con­ ceived as a mere instinctive or sentimental faith, or in the sense of Fidei sm, which ends in scepticism, and re­ stricts all knowledge to the phenomena only. The ques­ tion must be answered affirmatively, inasmuch as intel­ lectual ' certitude concerning many things, especially supersensible .things, is, from the viewpoint of their object, only partly evident, and partly inevident, being dependent upon trust or confidence, and is, therefore, also a mixed certitude, or only moral certitude.73 According to Ollé-Laprune metaphysics is, indeed, a “Si?hcertitS? science ; but it is not a science grounded upon pure evi­ dence, and dependent upon free will only from the view­ point of its exercise; rather it is a science that rests upon * “moral certitude”, and depends upon free will also from the viewpoint of its assent, so that not every unreason­ able doubt becomes impossible, but only reasonable doubt. In this latter respect, it is rooted in pure faith ; but this faith is not a tradionalistic or fideistic faith, neither is it a positive divine faith; rather itds affiuman moral faith, based on the authority and testimony of rea­ son, and, therefore, in this wider sense it, is a faith of authority and testimony.74 As metaphysical science is not to be grounded fideis- Aroiogeucs. tically upon a mere sentimental arid volitional basis, but at the same time upon an objective rational foundation; so, too, apologetic science. Such is the basic theme of Ollee-Laprune’s volume on “The Sources of Intellectual Peace”. Man and human society yearn for peace. The so-called exact science cannot show how this peace may be acquired. Only a science that aims higher is able to accomplish this, inasmuch as it proceeds from certain 78) De la Certitude morale, pp. 205-227. 74) La Philosophie et le temps présent. pp. 257-290. Paris. 1894 (2’ed.), 190 Chapter V. generally acknowledged conceptions, needs and aspira­ tions, and seeks for the means to bring about their fulfill­ ment and satisfaction, and finally to insure the full en­ joyment of intellectual peace. Indifference to truth can­ not produce this peace; least of all, can it be the ground­ work for a fruitful union of souls, whose end is to do away with misery. Only the knowledge of truth, not mere feeling and good will, liberates, and is able to be the basis of a firm association and a common action for the realization of this end. To be sure, a person can rest content with a minimum of truth in the beginning, but not permanently.75 But where is the whole truth to be1 found? OlléLaprune replies: Only in Christianity and the Catholic Church. The exact sciences, despite their marvelous progress, have not the words of eternal life, just as little as philosophy, or the science of history, or art. Chris­ tianity alone possesses the words of eternal life, and the Church with her dogmas ; il faut que l’Eglise refasse une chrétienté,· il faut qu’elle recommence sans se répéter. By Christianizing thought in this way, there will come into being a new philosophy, which will absorb the precious achievements of the exact sciences and through them enrich and rejuvenate metaphysics, without sacri­ ficing anything of its possessions. To this end, it will make use of the philosophy of St. Thomas, but not sim­ ply by a process of reproduction. Ollé-Laprune thinks that such a philosophy has already been inaugurated by Gratry and Caro, although it is still far from perfec­ tion, and perhaps never will be fully realized. To arrive at such a philosophy, we must seek after the things that unite rather than separate the minds of men.75 CRITICISM AmbiruoutTer1. a) Ollé-Laprune distinguishes between rational ”on«i Fkith." knowledge resting on pure evidence, which make every doubt, even an unreasonable and sophistical doubt, im-' 75) Les sources de la paix intellectuelle. pp. 3-31. 76) Ibid; pp. 39-47. 107-120. Paris. 1893 (2’ed.), Psychologico-Moral Apologetics 191 possible, and rational faith based on moral evidence, which excludes every reasonable doubt, but, in view of the partial obscurity of its object, does not preclude every unreasonable doubt; he conceives the latter, how­ ever, as an objectively grounded, rational faith. In so far he has not abandoned traditional metaphysics—gen­ eral and special—; for an objectively grounded, rational faith is really nothing else except rational knowledge of a morally compelling kind, as contradistinguished from a purely evident, rational knowledge that possesses absolutely compelling force. Still, because of the am­ biguity of the term “rational faith”, and the danger of misinterpretation inherent in that expression, it seems preferable to avoid it and, furthermore, to use the words “faith of authority and faith of testimony” only in rela­ tion to positive historical faith.77 b) Ollé-Laprune also departs from the traditional c^nfcal.” terminology adopted by Catholic theologians in regard to “moral certitude”. He defines this as a firm adhesion of the mind to historical and metaphysical truths bear­ ing on the moral life, which is given under the influence of moral dispositions, and with the concurrence of the the will, even though per se an objective proof might suffice.7879But this definition is really the cause of an equivocation; for, it is derived, not from that which is per se the motive of this certitude, but rather from dis­ positions, which per se do not concur in the formation o£ such a certitude. On the basis of this definition, we should have to admit that the existence of God, as proven by valid metaphysical arguments, would be only morally certain and, that a philosopher, who was very clear visioned but perverse, could not, without the proper moral dispositions, arrive at a certain knowledge of God’s existence,—surely an erroneous conception. Such a definition, however, might, indeed, be useful as an ar­ gumentum ad hominem in controversy with agnostics.78 77) Schmid, ibid., p. 204. W) De la Certitude Morale, pp, 413-414. 79) Garrigou-Lagrange, O. P., ibid., I, p. 530, foot-note. L 192 Chapter V. 2. There is another point in Ollé-Laprune’s system which goes deeper than mere terminology. He is of the opinion, that traditional metaphysics ought to be further developed; in union with Gratry,80 he conceived rational faith as a natural belief in God after the manner of. $ moderate Ontologism. Reason (raison), so he teaches, starts from the phenomena of the exterior and interior world of experience, and harks back to their efficient causes and substances, to their essences and essential laws, which reason expresses in concepts, ideas, and judg­ ments. Reason is able to exercise this activity, only in so far as it has received the impetus thereto from God, and perceives this divine activity by means of a divine sense latent within itself, ’without, however, having .an immediate, although imperfect, intuition of the same, such as Malebranche assumed according to Ontologism in its strict form.81 Thus, God is the internal Teacher, Who speaks within our souls, the sun of every intelligence, the light, that enlightens us. Every thought, in some way or other, includes God (“toute pensée implique Dieu en quelque sorte”)· The divine sense, which is proper to us, is an instinctive, natural faith, which by reflection * can be transformed into concepts, into the idea of God, as the necessary and all perfect primal Being. God is ever present to our reason (“Dieu est sans cesse présent à la raison”) ; but the idea of God is not an innate idea resting upon an immediate intuition; rather it is a product of our reason, and of the activity of God that awakens it. We merely strive to obtain a clearer vision thereof; if it were merely an illusion, the human spirit would be caught in the meshes of an incurable error.82 80) -cf. Schmid, Erkenntnislehre, Freiburg i. B., 1890; II, 348354; IDEM, art. “OntoLogismus”, in Buchberger Kirchliches Handlexikon, Freiburg i. B. 1912, II, col. 1216. 81) cf. Geo. M. Sauvage, art. “Ontologism”, in CE. XI, p. ,257 sq. 82) Ollé-Laprune, La Philosophie de Malebranche, Paris. 1870, II, pp. 291-344, where among other things he writes: “Nous-ne voy­ ons pas la substance de Dieu par intuition, mais nous sentons Dieu" (p. 326). “Naturellement avant toute réflexion nous croyons au néces­ saire et au parfait réellement subsistent et nous y croyons parce qu'il est en nous agissant sur nous et se révélant à nous par son action que Psych ologico-Mor al Apologetics $ 193 Thus, for Ollé-Laprune the Divine Primal Being is, not merely the active ground of our rational knowledge, but also an objective ground of its certitude, which really imparts to our knowledge of the causality operating in the world its full centrifugal force. He rejects an im­ mediate vision of God as something due to us by nature, since it is supernatural in character; but from this it follows, that the human spirit would not be involved in an incurable error, if such an intuition were denied it.83 It is not Ollé-Laprune's intention to break with the prin- Ν** ζ£^ * ci pies of traditional apologetics, nor would he wish others Traditional to question them. He merely wishes to add to it a new, Ap°lo*etiee· youthful vigour, by unfolding the germ which it em­ bodies. He only desires to see it assume a development in a way, that accords more fully with the demands of the present age, by showing that the immanent needs of the human intellect, heart; and will, attain their full satisfac­ tion only in so far, as the transcendent truths of the super­ sensible and supernatural order, which never grow old, but which have largely disappeared from the mind and heart of the modern world, again permeate, dominate, and deify the life of the individual, and of society. His aim is to offer to those who have gone astray in metaphysics, and in the apology of Christianity feared upon it, a helping hand, so that on the basis of the psychological facts, which they admit in common with us, they may again become aware of the saving truths and benedictions of Christianity, or at least that they may lay hold of them in a more intimate and vital manner, and finally concede to the intellectual powers of human reason the full confidence, which they deserve.84 3. Doubtless the good intentions and efforts of this -ι-v, ·, t i i · Γ · n -, .. , - Philosopher-Apologist are praiseworthy and well suited to remove prejudices, thereby preparing modern unbe­ lievers for the acceptance of Divine Revelation. But this method, which relegates tlie externat criteria to a sec­ ondary position, does not present an adequate proof of nous atteste le sens divin” (p. 330). “Nous aspirons à la claire vue c’est un fait incontestable ... si elle n’etait qu’une chimère, l’esprit humain serait par nature dans un irrémédiable erreur” (pp. 339,341). 83) Schmid, ibid., pp. 204, 205. 84 ) Ibid., pp. 205, 206; cf. Jacques Zeiller, Leon Ollé-Laprune, Paris (Gabalda), 1932. inadequate to Trove Divine 194 Chapter V, the credibility of Catholic Christianity. By showing that Christianity is in perfect accord with the aspira­ tions of our nature, and that the remedy for our miseries is to be found only in Christianity and the Catholic Church, the practical obligation of embracing the teach­ ings of the Catholic Church becomes manifest. However, in order to demonstrate the credibility of Catholic Chris­ tianity, it is not enough to show that there is a moral necessity of embracing it for the right ordering of our whole moral life; it is, above all else, necessary to demon­ strate the divine origin of the doctrine of Christ and of the Church. For, the mysteries of faith must be believed because of the authority of God Who reveals them, and not simply on account of their necessity for right con­ duct. Thus, this method involves an erroneous concept of credibility65 The same criticism applies also to the apologetic method of Fonsegrive, Denis, and Brunetière, which we shall now consider briefly. Fonsegrive. A Georges Fonsegrive (Yves le Querdec), in his volume entitled “Le Catholicisme et la vie de Vesprit”,** opposes Blondel’s rejection of traditional apologetics, but he con­ curs with him in the claim, that there is an urgent need of a modern apologetics, which will take cognizance of men as they are. With the Oratorian Laberthonnière, and the Jesuit Bachelet, he tries to defend Blondel against the accu­ sations of Idealism, Scepticism, neo-Kantianism, etc., which his scholastic adversaries have raised against him; for, Fonsegrive believes that the needs of human nature, which lie at the basis of Blondel’s apologetics, do not necessarily lead to these consequences.85 *87 On the basis of an Apologetics of Need, strict rational knowledge is, of course, not obtain­ able, but only a knowledge that is mixed with a natural faith (croyance) as regards the truth of the Christian Re­ ligion; but Fonsegrive does not think that this viewpoint involves Scepticism as its consequence. Human knowledge 85) Garrigou-Lagrange, Ο. P., ibid., I, p. 125. 8«) Paris. 1899. 87) Ibid., pp. 58-67. Peychologico-Moral Apologetics ;195 and human science, for the most part, include something obscure and mysterious, which can, indeed, become the ob0 ject of doubt, but which, nevertheless, can be assented to by virtue of an act of the will. Hence, they also include faith as a partial elemeht : “il y a une part de croyance dans la science même”. If modern apologetics demands a natural faith in this sense, and is opposed to a strict demonstration, it does not understand these terms in the same sense as its scholastic adversaries; consequently, it acknowledges the definitions of the Vatican Council no less -than its scholastic opponents and, so far as the principles are con­ cerned, it is not necessarily constrained to reject science in the Aristotelian-scholastic sense.88 Furthermore, when modern apologetics shows that true life can be achieved only in Catholic Christianity, it simply aims at establishing the appropriateness, not, in a rationalistic sense, the strict necessity of positive Christianity and of Catholicism. To that extent, therefore, traditional apologetics must remain unimpaired: “la démonstration logique ne perd pour cela aucune de ses qualités; elle demeure excellente et vraie”.89 Fonsegrive argues thus : For the right ordering of our life, it is necessary to reflect upon our inmost nature and its legitimate aspirations. Now, our consciousness bears witness to the fact that we perceive within ourselves many desires, which by our own powers alone we are unable to satisfy. We long to know and to understand whatever is true, but we know only a very few things, and these also quite imperfectly; we wish to embrace whatever is good, but we cannot by our own resources alone obtain the good ; we aspire to a complete life, above the merely human, to a God-like life, but, after many and arduous efforts, we are compelled to admit that such a life is inaccessible to us. We note that the Christian Religion claims to be able to satisfy our aspirations. For, it teaches that man is destined to a higher, a God-like life ; that the Word became flesh, in order that man might become God ; that He instituted the means by which we might become the adopted sons of God, and, by sharing in the Divine nature, tend to life eternal. Thus, the Christian Religion, far from extinguishing the intellectual and spiritual life of man, really exalts it and lifts it to higher spheres. Therefore, if we wish to arrive at a complete and perfect life, we ought to embrace Chris­ tianity. On the other hand, this religion manifests some very certain signs, namely, Miracles, not merely in the «) Ibid., pp. 67-83. 8») Ibid., p. 29; cf. Schmid, ibid., pp. 207-208. I 196 Chapter V. physical, but also in the intellectual and moral order, which reveal its divinity. On the hypothesis of a supernatural life, these'Miracles do not seem to be impossible to human reason ; on the contrary, they appear to be in perfect accord with right reason. Thus, the method of Fonsegrive places the emphasis upon the internal, subjective criteria, al­ though, at the same time, it admits and employs the ex­ ternal-signs of Divine Revelation; but it invokes the latter, only after the aprioristic prejudices against them have been removed.90 Denis. The editor of the Annales de Philosophie chrétienne, Ch. Denis, published a similar work under the title “Esquisse d’une Apologie Philosophique du Christianisme”, which is a reprint of articles contributed by him to that Review in 1 897-1898. The basic thought of these articles, apart from various inaccuracies and historical errors which they con­ tain, may be summarized as follows. The intellectualistic demonstration of the Apology of Christianity ought to'be supplemented by the psychological method, which rests upon the needs of' the heart, the will, and the activities of * will, as well as upon the intellect. The' traditional the apologetic method ought to be perfected by rrieans of a’ new method, which possesses evidential value not merely for the faithful, but' also for unbelievers. It is true, the ex­ ternal motives of credibility suffice for the majority of minds, but not for all; many require motives of internal credibility. The supernatural, in consonance with its defi­ nition, must be above us and exalt us, cannot proceed from ourselves, is not due to us, but is the free gift of God. But true philosophy ought to beget the conviction, that the impotency and insufficiency of our nature is able to find its support and perfection by' means of the supernatural, so that the latter, while not, indeed, a juridical postulate, is, nevertheless, a possible postulate, a presumption, a hypoth­ esis. True philosophy is also capable of accrediting the transcendent truths of Christianity with an immanent cred­ ibility, inasmuch as these truths offer to the inner needs, aspirations, postulates of our nature, a satisfaction un­ dreamt of, which fills the soul with new power and life. This satisfaction serves as a criterion directly indicative eo) cf. Ives le Querdec, Le Fils de Vesprit, Paris, 1905; Tanquerey, ibid., I, pp. 50, 51. Psychologico-Moral Apologetics * , ? j ! < i \ I I [ ; ■ • e 197 of their Divine origin, and makes possible an experiential p proof of their credibility.01 The old traditional apologetic method of the truth of Christianity is, according to Denis, dogmatic, since in its argumentation it rests upon biblico-ecclesiastical testiip monies; in the Summa Theologica of St. Thomas of Aquin it assumed a scientific, in the decrees De Fide of the Vatican Council a solemn ecclesiastical formulation. The new method, on the other hand, is by its nature philosophical, and, therefore, it has evidential value not merely for the faithful, but also for unbelievers. Accordingly, it is more in accord with the demands of the present age. It had already been utilized in the first four centuries—especially by Justin and Augustine—later, particularly by St. Bonaventure, by the author of the Imitation of Christ, and by St. Francis of Sales. But for the past three centuries, it has been well nigh forgotten, and did not receive due recognition in the current text-books. Only in .recent times was it restored to its proper place in religious psychology, thanks to the efforts of Maine de Biran, V. Dechamps, Car­ dinal Newman, de Broglie, Ollé-Laprune, Blondel, and others. It is a method of immanence, in that it derives the proof for the truth of positive Christianity, and of the Catholic Church, from the inner needs of men and mankind, in opposition to the Rationalism that was represented in France, especially by A. Sabatier and his school; hence, it does not merit the anathemas which the representatives of the older apologetic method frequently heaped upon it.91 92 C. Mano advocated a similar viewpoint in his essay entitled "Le Problème Apologétique”?» Brunetière. With the death of Ferdinand Brunetière, Catholic France, lost one of her noblest sons, a bold fighter, and the best religious lecturer, aside from Lacordaire, that she has ever possessed,—“un admirable et un vénérable et un imposant directeur d’esprit, un maître d’âmes”—as Gaguet wrote in the “Gallois” (Dec. 10, 1906). Brunetière travelled through­ out France, Italy, Holland, and Switzerland, to defend the 91 ) Esquisse d'une Apologie phü. du Christianisme. Paris. 1898, pp. 182-245. 261-296; “la crédibilité du Christianisme n'est donc pas seulement une crédibilité de logique et de raison raisonnante, elle est une crédibilité d’espérience. et de fait” (p. 286). *2) Schmid, ibid., pp. 208, 209. . . M) Paris. 1899. ... . . 198 Chapter V. Faith by his exalted, powerful and original eloquence, against the assaults of Liberalism. This pilgrim had jour­ neyed from afar, from the frontiers of atheism, before he finally made his profession of Faith, and his hand lovingly clasped the crucifix, which he had sought for so long.®4 NeoKBnttanbm. In the light of this heroic enthusiasm, this marvelous apologetic ability, it is all the more to be regretted that Brunetière was caught in the meshes of neo-Kantianisw, as is evident from his joy over Balfour’s book/'TAe Founda­ tions of Belief”, which openly espouses Agnosticism, as well as from the long Preface, which he wrote for that volume.96 Science, and by it Brunetière means also philos­ ophy, guarantees for us neither the existence of an external world, nor the existence of anything external whatsoever, which corresponds to our sense perceptions, nothing con­ ceptual, which is the counterpart of the sensible.96 We do not owe religion, or religions, to an act of reason, so he writes. A rational religion (“une religion ‘rationelle’”) is no religion.97 Between science and religion, there is no place for philosophy as a system of knowledge.®8 Reason is not the ground of faith; rather faith is the ground of reason.®9 One must believe, in order to know ; the abasia of science is faith.1” The time will come soon, when the feelings and the will will be given their natural place in the groundwork of faith.101 do not believe without grounds, but these grounds ***’ of belief, so Brunetière continues, are not of an intellectual sort. We believe, because we wish to believe, namely, for reasons of the moral order, because we experience the need of some standard, and because neither nature nor man dis­ cover such a standard within themselves.102 The need of believing resides in the nature and the constitution of the spirit; it is a “category", which conditions action, science, and morality. It is grounded in the feelings and the will; partly, too, it depends upon authority and tradition.103 His- moSj H) Gisler, ibid,, pp. 264-278. W) Lea Bases de la Croyance. Paris. 1897. 96) Ibid., p. XIV; IDEM, Sur les chemins de la croyance, Paris, 1905, p. 154. v •T) Les Bases de la Croyance, pp. XX, XXXIV. M) Ibid., p. XXXII. W) Discours de Combat, 1« série, “Le besoin de croire", p. 302. 100) Ibid., p. 322. Lamennais also wrote: “Toute certitude repose sur la foi” (Essay sur I’indifference, II, p. 41). tel) Les Bases de la Croyance, p. XXXVII. La science et la religion. 1895, p. 62. 1M) Discours de Combat, 1er série, p. 339, and passim. i Psychologico-Moral Apologetics if 199 ^°ry proves that reason can decide nothing as regards the immortality of the soul, faith enlightens us in this respect.104 ' Like Kant in his “Critique of Pure Reason”, Balfour and Brunetière question the value of metaphysics ; the existence B A of God, the immortality and the freedom of the human soul, are said to be inaccessible by rational proof; practical rea­ son, faith, must come to the rescue.106 Renouvier taught 1 approximately the same doctrine: Every proposition, to be affirmed as certain, demands an act of the will; science is ; the result of an act of faith, and all science rests accordIingly on faith.10® Realizing that his adherence to neo-Kantianism would be strenuously opposed by the theologians and philosophers of the old school, who looked upon this system as their worst eqemy, Brunetière hastened to remind them in the I words of Montesquieu, that he was only imitating the pracI tise of the ancient Romans, who after having conquered all the nations in turn, always renounced their customary methods, just as soon as they had discovered better ones. ’ So, too, the arms of defence must be altered to suit the new i exigencies of our age.107 But Brunetière forgot that, even ! though the old Romans did frequently change their weap; ons and plan of battle, they never surrendered their experienced arm, that wielded the new weapon. By surren­ dering metaphysics, Brunetière did not only throw away this or that apologetic weapon, but he abandoned the very basic condition, the arm of all apologetics, especially of all I universally valid apologetics, which leads to the portals of the supernatural. What he offers us in his Raisons actuelles de croire, as positive apologetic weapons and values, are, indeed, valuable pearls, but they make us feel all the more vividly the loss of the diamond of metaphysics, which has been discarded.108 '* λ ΰ Brunetière made use of many modern points of view in his apologetic method. There is in the first place the positi­ vistic viewpoint. His volume entitled “Sur les chemins de la croyance” ends with the sentence: “The ultilization of Dûcouré de Combat, nouvelle série, p. 20; cf. Gisler, ibid.., pp. 280 sq. IOS) G. Fonsegrive, Le catholicisme et la vie de l’esprit. Paris. 1906, p. 62. ibid., p. 45. IOT) Sur le» chemin» de la croyance, p. XV. 1M) Gisler, ibid., pp. 281, 282. 200 . I I ■ ■ |i iî I ! I Çhapter V. Postivism will be the first step of the twentieth century on the path to Faith”.109 He expressly claims to have'followed the method of Comte faithfully, in so far as it starts with a fact (à partir du fait), regards a fact only as a fact, and never generalizes, save within the limits of fact.110 He champions this method as the fitting and proper apologetic method against heretics; but, at the same time, he insists that he wishes to extract from Kant and Comte, only what is apologetically good and useful.111 Hence, Brunetière does not claim that Postivism can offer everything that is requisite for apologetics. It is only the “first step” in the process, and his intention is simply to play Postivism against itself, in order to compel it to make certain admissions. What he demanded of Postivism, or of August Comte, is the fact that, apart from religion and in­ dependently of it, morality can neither be developed nor justified nor preserved; secondly, that this religion, what­ ever it be, can neither be “natural”, nor “individual”, but only “social”, and can be grounded only upon the assump­ tion of the supernatural ; thirdly, and that only incidently, that Catholicism in the course of history has satisfied these demands, which science posits and determines. Nothing more and nothing less ! He does not, therefore, claim that this method demonstrates the transcendence or the divinity of Christianity. It is only a step, indeed, the first step, on the path to Faith. Thus, he anticipates the objection which insists that Positivism is utterly worthless apologetically, for the simple reason that no religion of the “Absolute” can ' be proved by means of a philosophy of the “Relative”.112 00 de/of en' Brunetière employs the positivistic method immediately Christianity. an(j primarily, in order to make clear the social excellencies of Christianity and Catholicism. For him, the chief apolo­ getic motive was the harmony between the democratic'and the Christian idea. In his speech at Lille, Nov. 18, 1900, he asserted that for himself the most decisive, grounds for believing were those of a moral and social character. His affection for the common people, for the democratic ideal, finds protection, and also limitation, in the Catholic Church alone ; only there does he discover the basis for the- re­ publican watch-word, in which he still puts his faith: “Liberté, égalité, fraternité”. And not the basis merely, 109) “L’utilization du positivisme sera la première étape du vingtième siècle sur le chemin de la croyance”; cf. also Discoure de Combat, nouvelle série, pp. 172-190. 110) Sur les chemins etc., p. XI. m) Lettres de combat, 1912, p. 234. ·, 112) Gisler, ibid., pp. 283, 284. i Psychologico-Moral Apologetica i "i 201 but also the interpretation of this watch-word can be found iZ only in the Christian idea, nowhere else.113 In the same way he emphasizes how Christianity was first of all a religion of the poor.11* Catholicism is likewise a government, whereas Protestantism is simply the lack of - government (“le protestantisme n’est que l’absence de gouvernement”) ; “to rule is it not very necessary to begin by being a government” ? And because it is a government, Catholicism can absorb its heretics, destroy, or even, as occasion demands, employ them for its own benefit. And becaùse it is a government, Catholicism has also a “doctrine” and a “tradition”, the full force of which he recently experienced, while reading Tolstoy’s latest writing in regard to war and the Christian spirit. How well advised was not'Catholicism, so Brunetière reflected, nay more, how political, in that it persistently refused to surrender the Sacred Scriptures to the interpretations of individual minds!115 Finally, Brunetière shows how superior Catholicism is to Protestantism, since it is not merely a “theology”, or a psychology, but a “sociology”; in the critical hour in which we now find ourselves, this is a great advantage.116 He de­ veloped the same idea in the conference at Geneva, Dec. 17, 1901, when he accused Calvin of having intellectualized, aristocraticized, individualized, religion.117 “The power of Christianity”, so we hear him say in another conference, “is today,,above all else a social power”.118 i, J I 118) Les raisons actuelles de croire, in Discours de Combat, nou­ velle série, pp. 25; 33 sq. 114) Revue des deux Mondes, 1895, Jan., p. 110. 115) Ibid., p. 114. u«) Ibid., p. 115. 117) Discours de Combat, nouvelle série, p. 123 sq. : “L’oeuvre de Calvin”. 118 ) Discours de Combat, ibid., p. 171. llfl) However, Brunetière also admitted that his apologetic method of demonstration was not absolute and decisive. In his raisons actuelles de croire he says: “Ces raisons vous paraîtront-elles, peutêtre, entachées, ou suspectes au moins de fidéismel et craindrez-vous i j i * CRITICISM 1. Brunetière undoubtedly went astray, when he cast aside metaphysics as an apologetic weapon ; he probably also overestimated the import of his “raisons actuelles de croire”, particularly in his earlier years.119 i Poaitive values, j 202 Defecta. Chapter V. Nevertheless, from the viewpoint of apologetics, it is highly significant that this distinguished scholar, and matchless literary critic, affirmed the bankruptcy of a purely natural philosophy of life; that he destroyed by Positivism Renan’s dream of a scientific organization of humanity (“organiser scientifiquement l’humanité”) and finally, that he showed in such a splendid manner that natural science is incapable of doing away with' mystery (supprimer “le mystère”).120 Never were the social power and the social indispens­ ability of the Church lauded in such a manly, diversified, and mighty language as issued from the lips and pen of Brunetière; that was the positive .side of his apologetic activity, his instructive, valuable, and lasting contribu­ tion to the cause of truth. His example, too, is an apology. When he saw that the political and moral order was imperilled by a false faith, he hastened as the “miles Domini” from city to city, awakening Catholic hope by his polemic speeches. To the first volume of these speeches he prefixed, as his motto, Cicero’s words: “Omne officium quod ad conjunc­ tionem hominum et ad societatem tuendam valet, est anteponendum illi officio, quod cognitione et scientia con­ tinetur”. Ten years this oratorical campaign continued. “For ten years”, says Barboux, “he defied ridicule, un­ popularity, injustice, and scorn, thereby revealing in his activity and person the splendor of a mighty eloquence, espoused to the beauty of duty faithfully performed.”121 2. If we submit the “New Apologetics” to the test of criticism, we do so, not precisely because it is new, but rather because it rests upon questionable grounds. peut-être qu’en dernière analyse, elles n’aboutissent qu’à fonder la foi sur l’impuissance de la raison? Je ne pense pas. Ce que l’on pourrait plutôt dire, c’est qu’elles ne sont pas encore assez détermi­ nantes. Il semble qu’elles aient aussi quelque chose de trop ’utilitaire , * et surtout qu’elles ne nous mènent pas au-delà d’un vagua déisme. Ce sont des raisons de croire à sa véracité”. (Discours de Combat, Nou­ velle série, p. 23). Thus, Brunetière himself specifies the points, which give to his apologetics the character of mere relativity. Moreover, only too often he touches the fringes of Fideism. 12®) Revue des deux Mondes, 1895, Jan., p. 99. The citations from Renan are from his “L’avenir de la science’’, p. 37. 121) Discours de réception, Feb. 20, 1908. Psychologico-Moral Apologetics 203 The Church has always not only permitted, but even encouraged, her children to search for, and to walk upon, 0 apologetic paths, which in a sense were new, as is evident from the fact, that not all of her converts have returned into her fold by the same paths. Brunetière says in this regard, that a beautiful book might be written under the a caption, “The Psychology of Conversion”. With Cardinal Newman he points to the eunuch of Candace, queen of the Ethiopians, to the converts of the Areopagus, to the con­ verted philosophers of the second and third centuries, and to the more recent converts, for example, Theodor de la Rive, Lady Herbert of Lea, the Baroness of Kônneriz, I. Hecker, and others.122 And when the apologists Justin, Barnabas, Tertullian, battled'against ancient Judaism; when Augustine entered the lists against the secular power of paganism, Thomas against Mohammedan Philosophy and Religion, and its pantheistically interpretedAristotelianism; when Bellarmin took his stand against the so-called' Reformers ; Newton, Leibniz, Bergier, Haller, and Euler fought against Deism; Chateaubriand; Fraissinous, Lacordaire faced Rationalism and Materialism; when Goerres, Drey, Vosen, Weiss, Bougaud, de Broglie, Schanz, Pesch, Schell, Gutberlet, arose to ward off Criticism, Pantheism, and Darwinism,—apolo­ getics assumed a different battle array, and changed its tactics and its weapons of defence. And rightly, too. For, apologetics can, and must, contain a changing element; that is grounded in its very nature. The defence of the Faith must keep abreast of thè times, and adapt itself to the changing conditions. The means for awakening and strengthening the will to believe, and the joy of believing, cannot always be the same. The attitude of mind and the receptivity of men, the value-judgments in regard to dogmas, the ideals of life, are mutable; like the stars, they ascend and descend on the firmament of one’s philosophy of life; if the apologist is to be effective, he must studiously watch the signs of the times. Hence, the Catholic apologist is wholly within his rights, if he puts such a strong emphasis not upon Miracles only, but also upon the psychological, artistic, social, and moral side of Christianity; for grace, understanding, and will co-operate in the genesis of Faith. He may not look upon a one-sided cultivation of the understanding, a mere demon­ stration, the formation of the judgment of credibility only, as the end towards which he is to direct his efforts, at least; not when there is question of practical apologetics. 122) “Let raison» actuelles de croire”, Discours de Combat, Nou­ velle série, p. 11. 204 , I Chapter V. He must likewise aim at cultivating the will; in order that it might become enthusiastic through the motives of God and eternity, of the duty of believing, and the rea­ sonableness of believing, of the beauty, usefulness and har­ mony of faith, thereby commanding the intellect to assent, to make a real act of faith. Precisely because the will has such an important rôle to play in the act of faith, apologetics may, and must, be not merely didactic, but also stimulating and inspirational. This is true in a special degree, as noted above, if the apologist is to be not only ..a speculator, but also a man of action ; if he is to present not merely in an abstract manner the proofs, which show that one can and must believe, but likewise the motives and in­ spirations, which will move to the acceptance of, and the firm adherence to, faith. Indeed, nothing could be more erroneous than to assume, that the intellect is led to accept dogma in the same way as a mathematical tenet. For, the same didactic method does not hold for mathematics and religion; for, mathematics directs itself only to the intellect, whereas religion appeals also to the will. Hence, in matters of faith, the affective factor is very important, especially in the modern age, when men place such a high estimate upon moods and psychic dispositions, and emphasize so strongly the primacy of the will.123 The method of stressing whatever is' socially: useful., beautiful, harmonious, and consolatory in Faith, is an error from the apologetic viewpoint, only if it is done in a one­ sided. fashion, and at the expense of rational knowledge ; only if the will is to be moved to command -the act of faith, without first having been enlightened by the torch of a cer­ tain judgment of credibility; in short, such an apologetic method becomes wrong, if apologetics is merely voluntar­ istic, while claiming at the same time to be the absolute, adequate, and exclusively valid apologetics. Just as the apologist, especially when he, like the teacher of religion, aims at practical ends, may not pass over the motives of the will, so, also, and to the same extent, he must stress the intellectual grounds of faith; for, faith is not merely free, but also reasonable. The spirit cannot arrive at a reasonable faith, once the wings of metaphysics have been broken; the pinions of Kantian postulates are incapable of soaring so high.124 128) Long before the neo-apologetic school, Catholic apologists stressed and appreciated the motives which are derived from inner, subjective experience. We refer the student especially to P. Kleutgen, Théologie der Vorzeit, 4, p. 203 sq. 124) Gisler, ibid., pp. 288-292.............................. b Psychologico-Moral Apologetics 205 The weak side of the Psychologico-Moral or Social Apol­ ogetics is apparent. If with Brunetière I deduce the truth of Christianity from its social usefulness, I do not satisfy logic; perhaps I even become undignified and officious. For, it has already been said, with perfect truth, that religion is no panacea for all the infirmities and defects of human society. It is no social arcanum for the preservation and amelioration of all possible things. Religion is above all else truth. If Fr. Coppée was led to Catholicism by the path of suffering, Huysmans by the path of art, Paul Bourget by the path of morality, we will not quarrel about individual cases. We only remark that thousands of others have de­ sired a much more reliable Beatrice, to guide them into the kingdom of supernatural Revelation and grace. On'the other hand, we are far from wishing to deny to this apologetic method all value. The words of Pascal: “Le coeur a ses raisons que la raison ne connaît point”, contain much that is true. Therefore, we are willing to admit moral proofs, as proofs of convenience, as auxiliary proofs, as motives, as an appeal to man’s emotional life. Let the apologist show as insistently as possible the beauty of Catholicism, the consonance between social welfare and Catholicism, between suffering and Catholicism. Let him appeal to reverence for the faith of our fathers, who have stood firmly in that faith, battled, and died for it; let him appeal to love of country, to history, to father and mother! All these things are mighty levers for moving the will ; they are not merely proofs but also motives, and that of the most glorious kind. By them the will is made mobile, is warmed, made enthusiastic, not only for the joyous perception, but also for the realization of the content of faith. We thank the new apologists for having so insistently stressed the emo­ tional side of apologetics, the voluntaristic element, the pius credulitatis affectus (the pious wish to believe). Psychic dispositions and moods are a valuable means in the hand of the apologist; for, the emotions always have an influence on the intellect. Hence, it is not enough to bring forward, and to pile up before the spirit in a mechanical manner, the schemata of dogmas; it is also necessary, that they be experienced and loved interiorly, in the midst of the sun-rise of the world of Divine Revelation and grace. But we may not forget, that historical, social, and philoso­ phical facts are often ambiguous, that they may possess evi­ dential value for religion in general, but not for the super­ natural Religion of the Catholic Church.125 126) Gisler, ibid., pp. 292-294. 206 Chapter V. Thus, this apologetic method ‘‘has undoubted merits from that practical standpoint as an aid to, and comple­ ment of, the intellectual defense of objective and his­ torical Christian evidence. Christianity effects a har­ mony between two great facts—the external fact of a positive, historical, Divine Revelation, and the internal fact of the moral and religious aspirations of the human soul. But the consciousness of these aspirations, and the experienced fact of their finding the fullest satisfaction in certain religious beliefs,—those namely, of Chris­ tianity,—must of necessity raise a problem for the indi­ vidual-intellect, the problem of investigating the objec­ tive credentials of doctrinal Christianity. And until the believer or seeker finds these to be rationally adequate, he cannot find intellectual repose, the repose of convic­ tion or certitude, in the meré consciousness, that assent to these doctrines satisfies instincts and yearnings of his , nature”.12* Hence, Brunetière *s mode of grounding moral and re­ ligious beliefs according to -the criterion of what serves the higher interests of humanity (which for him is Chris­ tianity, but for Balfour the vague mass of moral and religious influences felt in our social environment) is entirely unsatisfactory. “It is open to anyone to assail it on such lines as these : Granted that history shows the influence of Christianity to be wholly bénéficient, am I, therefore, bound to accept its moral and religious teach­ ing! It may be good ; it may be the best : but show me that I am morally bound to accept the good, or the best. If I happen to be a utilitarian, or a hedonist, why should I abandon my utilitarian ethical system, or my hedonist programme of self-gratificati on, and espouse Christian­ ity! If these are wrong, and if it is right, you must prove it: you must show your reasons. But this pre­ cisely is seeking a rational basis for moral and religious belief. You appeal to what Christianity has done for the progress of humanity. Progress towards what! What is 12β) P. Coffey, Epistemology, London. 1917, II, p. 352. Concept and Kinds'of Miracles ’207 the end or aim of human life Î You think that’humanity really profits and is really served by accepting the re­ fl ligious teaching and submitting to the moral code of Christianity. But what if I disagree; if with Schopen­ hauer or Nietzsche I hold the Christian conception of □ human society and human nature and human destiny to be no better than an illusion; if, in fine, I hold it folly to sacrifice individual pleasure, present and attainable, to an ideal of some social good that is future and proble­ matical! Who is to decide between us! Reason alone can decide; your reason and my reason. And whether we succeed in coming to an agreement or not, one thing at least is„glear: that the ultimate decision of all such ques­ tions must be reached by reason, or else never reached. Between reasoned certitude and scepticism there may, indeed, be a battle-ground, but there can be no restingplace”.127 Let us, therefore, continue the old "traditional apolo­ getics, but let us join with it the hew, to form what Car­ dinal Dechamps calls the “apologétique integrate”. Chapter VI. CONCEPT AND KINDS OF MIRACLES , Retrospect and In chapters three, four, and five, we have discussed Proepect· the opinions of those who extoll the internal, subjective criteria of Divine Revelation. Our study has led to the conclusion that these criteria, do, indeed, possess a cer­ tain evidential value, but that it,is erroneous to ascribe to them the primacy of value, for demonstrating the cred­ ibility of God’s self-disclnsnre. This primacy belongs rallier to the external, objective signs, the most promi­ nent of which are Miracles and Prophecies, as we have indicated in outline in the first and second chapters of this treatise. We now proceed to present a more de>27) Coffey, ibid., pp. 350, 351.