THEODICY A Class Manual in the Philosophy of Deity By Right Rev. Msgr. PAUL J. GLENN, Ph.D., S.T.D. PRESIDENT OF COLLEGE-SEMINARY OF ST. CHARLES BORROMEO, COLUMBUS, 0. B. HERDER »5 BOOK CO. SOUTH BROADWAY, ST LOUIS, MO. AND 33 QUEEN SQUARE, 1948 LONDON, W. C. PREFACE Î Î J This textbook in Natural Theology,—one of the most notable and the more neglected parts of philoso­ phy,·—is meant to supply to the modern college stu­ dent some readily intelligible account of fundamental truths. It is not meant, and does not presume, to pre­ sent a complete study of deeply involved points of doctrine. Like the other manuals of the present series, this book tries to rear a sturdy framework or scaffolding upon which the young student may take confident stand for the long and difficult task of building up his edifice of philosophical knowledge. It does not seek recognition as the finished building, nor even as a finished portion of the building. But the building cannot be raised at all unless the builder have a proper place and a sure position for the work he has to do. Thus, it may, without boastfulness, be claimed that the service of such a book as this is an indispensable one. Some readers may be disappointed to find in these pages little of the interesting (and sometimes profitable) discussion which is ardently aroused by the mention of such terms as, Thowiism, Molinism, Scientia Media, Premotion, v Supercotnprehension, vi PREFACE Future Contingencies, Futuribilia. It has seemed best to deal briefly and calmly with these matters instead of recognizing in them the call to glorious encounter. If our Rolands and our Olivers seem too frequently to leave the field arm-in-arm after a short exchange of compliments, it is only because we have generally held them to the mere statement of their terms of meeting, so that the youthful student may have a clear notion of what their differences are all about. We stress the point that this book is not for the specialist. The first portion of this manual,—in which we prove the existence of God,—is shaped upon the traditional model of St. Thomas. No better plan has been devised than this, and it would be sheer folly to attempt another in the name of modernity. These arguments will be found modern enough, in the sense of new, by any adversary upon whom the stu­ dent may employ them. For our age has many notable gaps in its culture, and none greater nor more lamentable than the great open space which should be occupied by the recognition of God and His place of supremacy and control. Arnold Lunn writes that, when he expounded these ancient proofs before a group of modern university students, his audience was astounded to learn that such fresh and cogent arguments exist. It is hoped that this manual will render good service to college classes, to studious individuals out PREFACE VII of college, and even to those who have never been in. Certainly, the matter with which it deals is its most eloquent recommendation to the attention of serious minds. If that matter has not been treated with seemly skill and thoroughness, the book has still its value. For gold, though imperfectly refined, is always precious, always a treasure worthy of quest and possession. P. J. G. College of St. Charles Borromeo, Columbus, Ohio. CONTENTS FAGE Preface V Introduction................................................................................... i BOOK FIRST THE EXISTENCE OF GOD CHAPTER I. God’s Existence a Demonstrable Truth 13 1 13 > Art. I. The Question of God’s Existence Art. 2. The Need and Possibility of Dem­ onstrating God’s Existence .... 28 II. Demonstration of the Existence of God 53 Art. I. The Chief Types of Causes. 53 -**Art. 2. The Proof from Efficient Causality 61 «•♦Art. 3. The Proof from Formal and Final Causality......................................................... /I Art. 4. Certain Supplementary Proofs . 85 BOOK SECOND THE NATURE OF GOD I. The Essence of God........................................... 105 Art. I. The Physical Essence of God . . 105 Art. 2. The Metaphysical Essence of God 131 ix CONTENTS CHAPTER II. ΓΛ6Ϊ The Attributes oe God.................................... 143 Art. i. The Divine Attributes in General 144 Art. 2. The Divine Attributes in Special 15! BOOK THIRD THE OPERATIONS OF GOD I Π. The Immanent Operations God , . 181 Art. I. The Operations of God’s Intellect 181 Art. 2. The Operations of God’s Will . . 205 Art. 3. The Personal Nature of God . .231 of The Transient Operations of God. . . 244 Art. I. The Divine Operation of Creation 245 Art. 2. The Divine Operation of Conserva­ tion ..................................................................... 259 Art. 3. The Divine Operation of Concur­ rence .......................................................... 2^5 Art. 4. The Divine Operation of Govern­ ance and Providence................................281 Index......................................................................................... IN T ROD U CT ΓΟ N I. Name 2. Definition 3. Object 4. Importance 5. Division I. NAME The term theodicy (from the Greek theos “God” and dike “right; custom; usage; manner”) was coined by the famous philosopher and mathematician Gottfried Wilhelm Leibnitz (1646-1716) who used it in his Essays on Theodicy to express the justice or the righteous manner of God’s dealings with man­ kind, which he defended against those who felt that the evils of life are an argument for atheism. The term theodicy thus literally means ‘‘God's justice” or “God’s righteous way.” But this original meaning was quickly expanded to include not only the bene­ ficent providence of God, but the whole of God,— nature, attributes, and operations. In a word, theodicy became a synonym for natural theology. Theology had long been distinguished as (a) natural theology which is a part of philosophy, and which is the science of God as knowable by unaided human reason; and (b) supernatural theology or divine theology which is the science of God as manifested by Divine Revela­ tion. The term theodicy came in handily to replace the more cumbrous natural theology (although it is I THEODICY not an accurate name for that science) and to allow the simple name theology to be used for the super­ natural science. Convenience and long usage have established the term theodicy in its present meaning. Theodicy means natural theology. And natural theol­ ogy means the philosophical science which sets forth all that human reason can discover by its unaided efforts about God, His existence, His nature, His attributes, and His operations. The term theology, by the way, comes from the Greek theos “God,” and logos “science,” and literally means the science of God. 2. DEFINITION Theodicy is the philosophical science of God. a) Theodicy is a science. The term science (from Latin scire “to know”) means not only knowledge, but a special kind of knowledge. It means knowledge that is evidenced and therefore certain. And the evi­ dence or proof of any point of knowledge lies in the fact that we recognize its reasons or its causes or both. Therefore science has often been defined as “knowledge through causes or reasons.” Such is the fundamental meaning of the term science without the -article. Now, a science is any defined branch of knowl­ edge which sets forth the truths that belong to its domain in a clear and orderly fashion and with all ’ possible completeness, and which adds to these truths the reasons (or causes) which make the truths know- INTRODUCTION 3 able with certitude to the thinking mind. Theodicy meets the requirements here mentioned; it sets forth the truths that the unaided human mind can discover about God ; it presents these truths in a manner that is clear, orderly, logical, and complete; it offers, at every step of its development, the evidence, the proofs, which the mind requires to make it give its full and unwavering assent to the doctrines proposed. There­ fore, theodicy is justly called a science. b) Theodicy is a philosophical science. A philo­ sophical science is one of the branches of philosophy. Such a science has twO distinctive features. First of all, it is a human science, that is, it is built up by reason unenlightened by Revelation. Thus it is distinguished from the divine science of theology. Among human sciences, a philosophical science is distinguished as one that seeks the very last discoverable causes and reasons for its data; its quest is an ultimate investiga­ tion; it is not content with proximate causes and rea­ sons such as the other human sciences find adequate for their respective purposes. Every science asks and answers the questions “Why?” and “How do we know that?” ; a philosophical science keeps on asking “Why?” and “How?” until it has pushed back the inquiry as far as it is humanly possible to go with it. A philosophical science deals with knowledge that is root-deep, and it digs out the deepest roots. These, then, are the two marks of a philosophical science: it is a human science, and it is an ultimate science. The- 4 THEODICY odicy has these two marks, and is, in consequence, a philosophical science. c) Theodicy is the science of God. The phrase “of God” means, as is evident, “about God.” The preposi­ tion “of” is not possessive, but objective, it docs not indicate the knowledge that belongs to God, but the knowledge which man can gain about God in 1 limself and in all the phases under which He is viewed by the limited human mind. 3. OBJECT The object of a science is its scope, its field of inves­ tigation, its subject-matter. Further, it is the special way in which it does its work in its field, or it is the special purpose which guides it in its work. Thus the object of any science is twofold. The subject-matter, the field of inquiry, is the material object of the science. The special way, or purpose, or end-in-view, which a science has in dealing with its subject-matter or material object is the formal object of that science. Many sciences may have the same material object, for many more or less independent inquiries may be pros­ ecuted in the same general field. But each science has its own distinct and distinctive formal object which it shares completely with no other science. That is why this object is called formal ; it gives formal character to the science; it makes the science just what it is formally or as such. To illustrate all this. Many sciences deal with the Muai INTRODUCTION 5 earth under one aspect or another. Such, for example, are geology, geodisy, geography, geonomy, gcogony, and even geometry. All these sciences study the earth ; they have therefore the same material object. But no two of these sciences study the earth in the same special way or with the same special purpose. Geology studies the earth in its rock formations: geodisy studies the earth in its contours ; geography studies the earth in its natural or artificial partitions; geonomy studies the earth as subject to certain physical laws; geogeny studies the earth to discover its origins ; geometry in its first form was a study of the earth in its mensurable bulk and its mensurable movements. Thus, while all these sciences have the same material object, each of them has its own formal object. If two sciences were to have the one identical formal ob­ ject, they would not really be two sciences at all, but one science. It is manifest that a science is formally constituted in its special character by its formal ob­ ject; it is equally manifest that a science is distin­ guished from all other sciences by its formal object. Theodicy studies God. God is, therefore, the ma­ terial object of this science. But theology (the divine science) also studies God as its material object. The distinction between theodicy and theology lies in their respective formal objects. For theodicy studies God by the unaided light of reason, and theology studies God by the light of reason aided by Revela­ tion. 6 THEODICY The material object of theodicy is God. The formal object of theodicy is God as knozvable by unaided human reason. 4. IMPORTANCE Regarded absolutely, or in itself and independently of its relationships with other sciences, theodicy is far and away the most important of all human sciences. For it deals with the most sublime subject that can engage the mind of man. And when theodicy is viewed in its relations to other sciences, it still maintains its place of preeminence. For every other science rests ultimately upon certain assumptions which theodicy does not assume, but proves ; every other science is based upon notions of primal causality, of an ordered universe (and hence an Orderer), of an arrangement and balance, of a consistency and constancy in nature. Let scientists ignore this fact as they may, it remains a fact beyond dispute. St. Augustine was voicing no pious sentiment but expressing the clearest of rea­ soned conclusions when he said that those who try to philosophize, or to play the scientist, while ignoring or denying God, only succeed in entangling themselves in a net of contradictions. It is manifest, therefore, that theodicy, in view of its supreme object and of its fundamental relations to other sciences, is a most im­ portant study. Not only is theodicy the most important of philo- INTRODUCTION 7 sophical sciences in its object and in its relationships with other sciences; it is important because it meets the highest and strongest tendencies of the human mind;because its certain conclusions are a satisfaction to the noblest emotional yearnings ; because it gives meaning to the bewildering universe of sentient ex­ perience; because it makes intelligible the resistless human bent and bias for moral conduct. Theodicy is the best that the human mind can do for man, for that strange being whose life is a blending of the most curious and even opposite elements; for man, the creature of penetrating reason and unseeing passion ; for man, who moves among the hard and gross things of sense with the deepest spiritual longings in his soul; for man, whose tendency to be wilful and per­ verse is inextricably bound up with an insatiable ap­ petite for what is moral and good. So great is the essential service of theodicy that those who scorn its ministry and ignore God who is its object are com­ pelled by their human constitution to make up a theodicy of their own, a theodicy which suffers only from the fact that it is wholly false. It is of first im­ portance, then, that we bring reason to a calm, clear, penetrating view of facts, and follow its course through all complexities to inevitable conclusions about the First Reality. It is important that we build up the true theodicy of which our mind and our whole being have need. Man is, of course, a philosopher by à. thy-jT · ' i i i' p ■ L j i! I ji i; j i ij h ji |ί 1 j i ' ! I i i . ■ ; . i ' I ! nature. The most uncultured and untrained has some sort of natural theology at the back of his view of all things. But for persons of education such a vague theodicy will not suffice, even if it happens to be a true theodicy as far as it goes. We need the discipline oi philosophical theodicy for our minds, and we need its conclusions for our lives. Not that it is all-sufficing. It is the best that natural powers can do for us, but man needs more than nature; man needs supernature. Nor, for us who have the divine gift of faith, is theodicy meant to supplant faith or to rationalize it into a cold and mathematical formula. Theodicy supplements faith, rendering service by showing how reasonable and even inescapable are the first truths of faith; and it equips us for the task of showing others, who have not the faith, the first inviting reaches of the straight path that leads through reason to certainty and security of life in the one Institution on earth where men can really be at home. 5. IN TROD THEODICY 8 I i fdgh'- * DIVISION Three questions define the plan we are to follow in this present study. They are the following : j. Is there a God? 2. What is God? 3. What does God do? The first question inquires about the existence of God; the second, about His nature; the third, about Elis operations. These three topics,—the existence, the nature, and the operations of God,—will be discussed in three Books with Chapters as follows: „jk First Bor existence oi God The E xt 1. Gt God's Existence a Demonstrable Truth Chap. II. Detnoiislration of the Existence or (n>d Chap. "" ()f Cod The NatuK Chap. 1. lbt r,.< . Chap. Π. I bc God Book T .1. HIRD i i 1KJJ The Operations of God Ch;ιρ. I. The Immanent OP' erations of God Cha p. II. The Transient OP' erations of God _ οί Ate BOOK FIRST THE EXISTENCE OF GOD This Book discusses, first of all, the demonstrability of the Existence of God : it asks whether there is any need for proving a truth which some have called self-evident ; then it inquires whether—granted a proof is required—it is pos­ sible to establish such a proof. To both queries an affirmative answer is given: we need proof for God’s existence, and such proof is actually available. The Book goes on to set forth the traditional proofs for the existence of God, and answers the objections that are brought against their valid­ ity. These points are discussed in two Chapters : Chapter I. God’s Existence a Demonstrable Truth Chapter II. Demonstration of the Existence of God CHAPTER I GOD’S EXISTENCE A DEMONSTRABLE TRUTH This Chapter discusses the need and the possibility of proving that God exists. It answers the question-, : i> there any need of going to the trouble of dimming out rational proofs for the existence of God; is not 1 lis existence a selfevident fact? Or, if it be not self-evident to the mind, is it not a manifest requirement of the liner feelings or emotions; does not a man experience the “value” called God as some­ thing intuitively certain and requiring no process of proof? On the other hand, the Chapter answers the mistaken charge of the Kantian, the agnostic, and the skeptic, that any ra­ tional proof for the existence of God is based upon a causal relation among phenomena (that is, the merely apparent or sensible qualities of things) and has no power to evidence the nature of that supposed Being from which causal ac­ tion proceeds. Thus the Chapter deals with two schools of thought, the one declaring that no proof for God’s existence is needed, the other maintaining that no valid proof is pos­ sible. These mistaken assertions are investigated in two Articles, as follows : Article i. The Question of God’s Existence Article 2. The Need and Possibility of Demonstrating God’s Existence Article i. The Question of God’s Existence a) Meaning of Terms b) Urgency of the Question c) Theories on the Point a) MEANING OF TERMS We take the term existence in its first and obvious 13 \ 14 c* .· tv - Λ-ê 'll K ife THEODICY meaning. When we ask whether a thing exists, we ask whether it is actual, whether it is present among those realities which are not merely possible (or potential, as philosophers say) but which are here. In ontology,—the science of fundamental meta­ physics, which is the very core of philosophy,—we learn that a being is a reality, and that a reality is any­ thing that exists or can be thought of as actually exist­ ing. A reality is therefore an existible thing. And realities are classed as potential and actual realities. A potential reality is one that can exist because (a) the thought of it as existing involves no contradiction ; thus, for example, a glass mountain is a potential reality while a square circle is not, since the latter is self-contradictory and seif-canceling ; and (b) there is already in existence a being, a power, which is able to draw the potential thing out of its state of pos­ sibility and confer actuality upon it ; in short, there is a being which can cause it to exist. An actual reality, on the other hand, is one that is really here. It is here either (a) because it has been produced by its causes, and is no longer a mere possibility but an actualized being ; it is a caused being ; it is an effect; it is a contingent being, that is, a being contingent upon or dependent upon its causes; or (b) because it is so completely perfect and self-sufficing that it involves in itself the perfection called existence, and it therefore must exist and cannot be non-existent; it is an un­ caused being; it is not an effect; it is a necessary GOD’S EXISTENCE A TRUTH 15 being; it is pure actuality since is has about it no po­ tentiality which has been or is to be actualized by the action of causes. Now, when wc come to discuss the existence of God, we speak not of potential or possible existence but of actual existence. Further, we speak not of caused existence but of uncaused existence; not of contingent existence but of necessary existence; not of effected existence but of ptire actuality. So much for the term existence. Now what of the term God? We must give at least a general explanation of the meaning of this latter term before we can begin to discuss the question of God’s existence. For the limited human mind cannot even start to investigate the existence (potential or actual) of a reality until it has somehow conceived, at least in a general way, just what the reality in question is. There have been philosophers, and not the least in ability or the least esteemed or the least influential, who made the per­ fectly inane statement, “Even if you can know that God is, you cannot know what tie is.” How can any­ one know that a thing exists unless he knows what thing ? It is as though a person should say, “There’s something ” and then stop short. And when the ex­ cusably curious auditor of that somewhat incon­ clusive and airy statement asked (as infallibly he would ask), “What?” the answer would be, “I don’t know.” Surely, the explanation of such a remark would necessarily be either aberration or alcohol. It 16 THEODICY is not the statement one would expect, delivered with smug complacency as the conclusion of a profound process of reasoning, by revered men of mind. And if the philosopher hastened to explain by adding, “Oh, I mean there’s something that started all this mess,” or, “There’s something back of this obvious universe, we don’t know what,” then it is bare charity to point out to him that he does know what, or he pretends to know what, for he states that there is an Originator or a Hidden Supporting Force that accounts for the world we live in and look upon. The moment you as­ sign to your “something” an intelligible role in the origin or management of things, you so far define your “something” and make it this special kind of thing. If you know what a thing does, you have at least a partial grasp of what that thing is. Even Mat­ thew Arnold professed some knowledge (granted a very sketchy knowledge) of what God is when he described Him as “The enduring power, not our­ selves, which makes for righteousness.” How the somber Matthew must have rolled that sounding state­ ment from his tongue. How pleased he must have felt, and with what satisfaction he must have stroked his mutton-chop whiskers ; across the lengthening decades one can almost hear him purr. There is no position so intolerable as the agnostic position, the position which declares God to be the Great Unknowable, the Being that exists, we don’t GOD’S EXISTENCE A TRUTH 17 know what. The atheistic position is far more human and reasonable, absurd as it proves to be under in­ vestigation. For the atheist knows what the term God means, and he denies the actuality or the existence of what it means. 1 le denies not signification, but signifi­ cance. But the agnostic makes the word meaningless, and then denies its meaning. The agnostic is a man who hears a phrase in an unfamiliar tongue, and promptly declares it mere gibberish which can have no meaning for anybody. The point we have here so labored is a most important one and it must not be overlooked or forgotten for a moment in all that follows. You cannot know that a thing exists without knowing, in some dim measure, what it is that exists. Nor can you deny existence to a thing without being able, with some degree of exactness, to describe the conceivable thing at -which your denial is directed. What, then, is meant by the term God? Most people of any period in the world’s history would answer the question promptly by saying that God (whether Fie really exists or not) is conceived of as an actual Being who is the supreme Originator and Ruler of the world and all things in it. A fewr people in any age, and a great many people in some ages, would say that the term God is a sort of blanket-name for a number of super-human beings, or even invisible “forces” viewed collectively as “Nature,” which together man­ age the universe ; such people would be polytheists, 18 THEODICY (from the Greek poly “many” and theos “God”) or believers in a plurality of gods. The first group, to whom God is one actuality, would be monotheists (from monos “single” and theos). Yet back of all the gods of the polytheists would be the single idea of deity, of Godhead, of divinity, so that, as Λ1 r. Chester­ ton declares, the idea of one supreme Power and one supreme Being is behind all the gods of all the mythol­ ogies “like the sky behind the clouds.” For Godhead is necessarily conceived as first and as supreme in both Power and Being. And to say that a Being is first and supreme is to say that It is without peer, that It stands alone in its awful place, that It is a single Being, not a plurality of Beings. Even polytheism in its crudest form looks back to monotheism from which it is a lapse and a retrogression. The points we have made give us a fair description of what the term God means to the generality of men. It means a Being (whatever be true of His existence or non-existence) that is thought of as actual, one, first, supreme, the originator and the ruler of the universe. It is of such a Being that we speak when we take up the momentous question of the existence of God. It is of such a Being,—conceived by the manin-the-street as the Almighty Ruler, and by the philos­ opher as the Necessary Being and the Pure Actuality, —that we ask, “Does He exist? Have we need to prove His existence? If we have this need, can the need be met by valid demonstration?” GOD’S EXISTENCE A TRUTH 19 b) URGENCY OF THE QUESTION Anyone who entertains ethereal academic, doubts about the existence of original sin will have them blown to shreds like a fog in a gale if he can be in­ duced to take one really attentive glance at the world about him, particularly at the funny two-legged crea­ tures known as human beings that one sees every­ where. Let him look at men, and listen to what they are saying, and follow their thoughts and fancies, and weigh the meaning of their conduct. He will find that his inevitable theory of mechanical evolution and progress with its gospel of “onward, upward, holding steady to the goal” turns to the silliest sort of detached doctrinizing when it is brought into the light of human facts ; it will never explain the wide diversity and the tumultuous clashes of human aims, ambitions, hopes, employments. If the evolutionist with his ten­ der doubts about the tragedy of Eden were to come upon a flock of chickens or a herd of horses rushing about in wild disorder, he would instantly conclude that something had disturbed them. If he were to see a lake or pond frothed by churning waves, he would understand at once that wind or some eruptive inner force must account for the commotion. Yet the evolutionist walks daily through crowds of his fellow­ men whose aims, ideals, and conduct are more furi­ ously in conflict than warring waves or milling cattle, and he does not notice that something must have dis­ turbed them. He does not notice that they are in any 20 THEODICY state of confusion and commotion. Or if he docs, he calls the commotion difference of opinion, and thinks it a good thing; whereas, of course, it is nothing of the sort. If he found three men staring at a brick and explaining it violently in totally different ways; if he found one man calling it delicious cheese, and a second man declaring it a trick of the capitalists, and the third man praising it as an attractive bunch of violets, he would know that something had gone wrong with the minds of these men. He would not say that they were progressive fellows showing the world the worth of a healthy difference of opinion ; for once, even an evolutionist with doubts about the Fall would understand that the question in the case is not one of opinion at all, but of a fundamental fact which has first to be recognized before opinions about it are valuable or even sane. But the evolutionist finds every day, and every hour if he chooses, men who differ on really important things, such as the meaning of life, in a fashion quite as wild as that of the three madmen with their brick, and he does not notice anything odd in the fact. He finds men with fantastic notions about a brick, and he knows that something is wrong with their minds ; he finds men with equally fantastic notions about life, and he does not acknowledge that something must be wrong with their souls. He finds one man to whom life is a plodding business of getting bread and cheese; he finds another to whom life is a mere war against plots, against the whips and scorns GOD’S EXISTENCE A TRUTH 21 of time, the oppressor’s wrong, the proud man’s con­ tumely ; he finds a third man to whom life is as tîiflmg as a boutonniere. And, with glazed evolutional y eye in fixed imbecility staring, he takes in the situation and calls it Difference of Opinion and Progress; or, with eyes tightly closed, lie calls it Enlightenment ; or, in a frenzy of delight, he flourishes a calendar and calls it the Modern Mind. At all events, the evolution­ ist fails to see that the situation calls for an explana­ tion. And there is an explanation. It is an explanation made to us by word from Heaven, but, had that mes­ sage never come, the explanation might have been .made by any plain man with sight enough to tell a hawk from handsaw and mind enough to know that two and two make four. The explanation lies in the fact that something has upset man, has got him off balance, has twisted his viewpoint and set askew his scale of values. We call that something original sin. It has not made men mad, but it has disorientated men, and it is the one really urgent need of men to get orientated aright. And to be orientated aright men must fairly face and come to grips with the first and fundamental question of the existence of God. For on the right settlement of that question, everything else depends. And yet, to the ordinary average man of the world, and more particularly to the ordinary average philos­ opher and teacher and moulder of the public mind, nothing seems more remote from the needs of life, I 22 THEODICY nothing seems less practically important, than the settlement of the question of the existence of God. Discussion of it is brushed aside as of no consequence when there are pressing matters at hand, like a raise in rents, or a flutter in the stock-market, or rumors of war-clouds over the Orient, or Doctor Dewey’s views on the substantive mind, or the details of a match at tennis or golf. God’s existence is regarded as a thing of academic interest merely, a subject for idle discus­ sion in those few drab hours of life that draw no illumination from politics, business, or sport. And even such discussion is frankly regarded as a sort of time-killer, for it is tacitly assumed from the start that no conclusion can ever be drawn from it. Chester­ ton remarks, “We are more and more to discuss de­ tails in art, politics, literature. A man’s opinion on tramcars matters; his opinion on Botticelli matters; his opinion on all things does not matter. He may turn over and explore a million objects, but he must not find that strange object, the universe ; for if he does he will have a religion, and be lost. Everything mat­ ters—except everything.” Now, if the average man of the world or the aver­ age leader of thought and of talk would pause long enough in his worldly career, and in his talk, to face plain facts, he would not only be amazed, but his knees would knock together in terror, at the smashingly practical character of this question which he had regarded as detached and academic. Upon the exist- GOD’S EXISTENCE A TRUTH 23 ence or non-existence of God depends the whole nature of the business of life, and the business of life in surely practical. If there is a God, and I am His creature, made to serve His purposes; and if I am doing nothing of the sort, and am not even trying to know His purposes, then assuredly i am in a bad way and there is occasion for terror and quaking knees. For, quite apart from threatening punishment, I face the terrifying fact that my whole existence,—-my views, my aims, my thoughts and ideals, my work and my amusement, my attitudes, my dreams, my deal­ ings with my fellows,—comes to a sum-total of futil­ ity and failure, of disaster and defeat. I who have prated of practical things, have been running a race towards a wrong goal. I who have talked of the needs of life, have missed them all. I who have demanded plain facts, have failed to see the plainest fact. I who have gloried to lead others, have led them all astray. Surely, there is no imbecility so monstrous, no in­ sanity so vile and inexcusable, as the bland assump­ tion that the question of God’s existence is of no practical urgency. For fundamentally it is the only urgent question, and the only practical question, that a man needs to face. Once that question is rightly an­ swered, the whole pattern of life and of conduct takes form and lies with meaning before the eyes, and the one path that it is essential to discover opens clear before the feet. 24 c) THEODICY THEORIES ON THE POINT Here we shall merely list some of the doctrines that have been propounded in answer to the question, “Does God exist; and, if so, can 1 le be known ; and, if He can be known, how is this knowledge ob­ tained?” We shall not pause to explain these doctrines in detail, nor shall we here answer those that are false and to be refuted. Explanation and refutation will both come in their places in a later part of our study. But it is necessary for us to have at the outset a knowledge of these names and a notion of what they mean. z. Theism is a general name for any belief in God. It is not to be confused with deism, which has a special meaning, although both terms come from words that mean God, the one Greek (Theos) and the other Latin (Deus). 2. Atheism is the opposite of theism. The letter a prefixed to a Greek derivative is usually equivalent to a non prefixed to an English word. Atheism declares that God does not exist. Of course, there is no such thing as atheism in a pure form ; it is never a simple denial, but is always a replacement. Your atheist finds himself compelled to substitute for God some such sterile notion as force, or energy, or nature, or even that latest pet of the faddists, “value.” 3. Agnosticism,—a term derived from the Greek agnostikos “not knowing; ignorant,”—is the theory that God cannot be known, that men must be content GOD’S EXISTENCE A TRUTH 25 to remain in ignorance about I lis Being and Essence. It is not the denial of God's existence, it is denial of His knowability. Ft is the theory that God is, but no man can know tvha! He is. It is not the Christian doctrine that man cannot know God exhaustively ; it is the anti-Christian doctrine that man cannot know God at all, beyond the wholly illogical recognition of His existence. We have spoken in some detail of the silliness of the agnostic position, and we shall have occasion to speak of it again. 4. Pantheism,-—from the Greek pan “everything; all” and lheos “God,”—identifies, in one way or another, God and the universe. The cruder sort of pantheism makes the bodily world part and parcel of the substance of God; it teaches that God has poured Himself out, like a lake into little inlets about the shore, or like a fire in leaping flames and flying sparks, and thus it makes all things outpourings or emana­ tions of God. This type of pantheism is called emanationism. Another form of pantheism makes the world and all things in it the manifestations of God, not His physical parts. And since a manifestation is not itself a substantial thing (think, for instance, of the mani­ festation of happiness which is a smile, or the mani­ festation of anger which is a frown), this type of pantheism tends to become idealistic, that is, to de­ clare the visible universe only a projection of ideas or fancies, to deny its solid actuality, and to fall back on one invisible divine substance as the only thing that j I η , I 26 THEODICY truly exists. Such an idealistic pantheism is latent in the doctrines of Immanuel Kant (1724-1804), the most influential of philosophers in the modern period i i of history, and it was openly developed from his prinI * ciples by his immediate followers, Fichte, Schelling, ; ! and Hegel. : 5. Monotheism, as we have seen, means the doc! I trine that there is only one God. I 6. Polytheism is the doctrine that there exists a 1 plurality of gods or at least of world-controlling I forces. I 7. Deism,—from Latin Deus “God,”—is the i theory which admits the existence of God, and even His knowability, but which denies His providence and His governance of creatures. Deism holds that God has made the world, but has since ceased to care (for it, and has tossed it aside to fend for itself. ! H j , i ' i I 8. Ontologism,—from Greek on (onto-) “being” and logos “science; knowledge,”—is the doctrine that the order of science or knowledge reflects the order of / reality or being, and that, in consequence, the First Actuality is the first thing known by the mind. There­ fore, says ontologism, the very first act of the mind is a vague but fundamental conception of deity. p. Traditionalism is the doctrine which holds that the human mind is not able to demonstrate God’s existence, but that it gets its knowledge of God by way of faith in a primitive revelation made to the ι*ι· n GOD’S EXISTENCE A TRUTH 27 1 first men by Almighty God Himself, and handed down through all the generations of men by oral tradition. 10. To the foregoing types of theory we may add a few others that arc not specifically concerned with the existence of God or man’s knowledge of God, but which bear more or less directly upon these points. Skepticism is a theory of doubt or denial about man’s ability to know anything for certain, and thus it in­ cludes doubt or denial of his ability to know God. Rationalism is the doctrine that human reason can fully cope with all the truths that exist or are existible, and that anything involving a reach into mystery or an acknowledgment of infinity is,—since reason can­ not cope with it fully,—to be rejected as something untrue, fictional. Pragmatism holds that the workableness of any thought, scheme, action, or its suitableness in its circumstances, determines its character as true or as good; thus pragmatism denies or at least ignores the eternal standard of morality and the eternal source of truth which,—considered objectively and fundamentally,—is God, the Divine Essence. j j Relativism (of which pragmatism is one form or variety) is the general theory that every truth depends for its being upon the aspect in which it is seen or the circumstances to which it is referred ; and thus relativ­ ism involves a denial of the absolute, the non-relative, truth of the existence of God. | j j 1 I I | | | I J || 1 !1 1 THEODICY SUMMARY OF THE ARTICLE In this Article we have defined the terms of the question of God's existence. We have seen that the existence here in question is an actual, uncaused, necessary existence. We have declared what is gen­ erally meant to any mind by the term God, and, in passing, we have shown the inanity of the agnostic statement that man can know that God exists but docs not know what God is. We have stressed the im­ portance of the inquiry into God’s existence as the most pressing and practical of questions. Finally, we have listed many theories which have to deal, more or less directly, with this important question. Article 2. The Need and Possibility of Demonstrating God’s Existence a) Need of the Demonstration b) Possibility of the Demonstration a) NEED of the demonstration A demonstration is not a simple synonym for proof. For a proof may be compelling, or convincing, or merely persuading. But a demonstration is always a compelling proof. It is a proof “to the eyes” as an eloquent Latin expression has it,—not, of course, that it is limited to the universe of things visible to bodily eyes. When the teacher of history informs the school­ boy that Columbus discovered America in 1492, there is, if the lad be skeptical, a wealth of proof avail- GOD’S EXISTENCE A TRUTH 29 able, but there is no demonstrating the truth in question. Of its nature, it is something that depends on statements and documents and the word of man. It is not something lhat, given objective data to examine, the mind sees to be inevitable, as, for ex­ ample, the mind sees that the sum of two and two is inevitable. But the teacher of geometry has no need to call witnesses and to adduce the testimony of re­ liable documents for the purpose of convincing the doubting pupil that the angles of a triangle come to 1800. This is a truth that can be reasoned out so thoroughly and completely that the person who under­ stands every step of the process is compelled to recog­ nize it. And only such a compelling proof is entitled in strict justice to the name demonstration. Now, do we require a demonstration for the truth of God’s existence? We do unless that truth is selfevident. For there are two sorts of truths that do not require demonstration. One is the sort of truth already considered in reference to the history lesson, in which demonstration is not required because it does not apply and indeed is not available. The other sort of truth that does not need demonstration is the truth that is inevitably recognized at first glance (or intuitively, by immediate or direct grasp, as philos­ ophers say). You cannot, for example, demonstrate your own existence and so compel yourself to recog­ nize the fact that you are here. For demonstration is always a process of analyzing the subject to be proved, 30 THEODICY of getting it down to terms of its simple elements, and of seeing how these inevitably fit together. But your own existence is itself a simple and an elemental thing, not subject to further analysis. You have a direct and an intuitive grasp of it; it obtrudes itself upon your acceptance so inescapably that even if you deny it you affirm it. Try to deny your own existence, and to express the denial in intelligible terms. You may say, “I do not exist.” But why then do you say “I”? What you have said amounts to this, “I’m here to say I’m not here.” If you really doubt your own existence (or any self-evident truth) you must lapse into complete and endless silence, and, in the dark despair of your non-existent mind, you must forever admit that even your doubts are non-existent. Thus there are truths so simple and inescapable that the moment we understand the terms in which they are expressed (whether these be mental terms or speech­ terms) we understand the necessary connection of the terms and are forced to acknowledge, and to under­ stand, that what they express is necessarily true. Such truths are called self-evident. Now, manifestly, the existence of God is not a thing to be proved to us by historical documents. Indirectly, of course, all human history is a proof of an existing and provident God. But directly, and considered absolutely or in itself, the existence of God cannot be a mere historical truth like the discovery of America in 1492. Is it, then, a self-evident truth ? If so, it needs no demonstration. GOD’S EXISTENCE A TRUTH 31 If we consult our own experience, each of us will doubtless say at once, “I learned the truth of God’s existence, first from my mother’s teaching, and later by noticing that the world and all things in it re­ quire an accounting Hirst ( ausc.” We may all truly say (omitting consideration of the divine gift of faith) that our natural or human knowledge of God has its origin in human reason dealing with the ob­ jective world about us. Reason approved the accept­ ance of early instruction from those whose constant care and love made us certain that they would not mislead or deceive us in a matter of the utmost im­ portance. Reason later recognized the more direct evidence for God’s existence, presented by the exist­ ence of creatures and an ordered universe. Hence, so experience testifies, the truth of God’s existence is not something obtruded upon senses or mind as selfevident. It is something that has to be learned. It is a truth to be reasoned out, directly or indirectly. There­ fore, we say, the truth of God’s existence is not selfevident, but requires demonstration. Yet there is a subtle consideration to be made be­ fore we declare with finality that the truth of God’s existence is not a self-evident truth. It is this: God exists necessarily, for He is all-perfect, and involves in Himself the perfection called existence. Existence is of Elis very essence and nature. Therefore, to a mind that thoroughly understands the whole meaning of the idea God, the note of existence is evidently con- -V' 32 J -fri-, ρ^^\ΐ ^^-l·’ ^4ί,» 'i THEODICY tained in it; the proposition “God is an Existent Be­ ing” is one in which the subject demands the predicate, for it contains it; and a mind capable of instantly analyzing the subject would know the predicate too; thus the proposition, to such a tnind, would be seitevident. But the human mind is not such a mind. As we shall presently see, we build up our idea of God by the laborious process of mental abstraction, and while the building is wholly justified by fact, and is in no sense the figment or fictional creation of the mind, it is, none the less, a process that involves attention, 'abstraction, analysis, synthesis, reasoning. It is an .. idea that is worked out by the mind from the data of ^experience, and is not intuitively grasped. And even when the idea has been formed, it is not necessarily present to the mind with that degree of distinctness and detail which would make every thought of God a keen realization of Elis necessary existence. A man may have the clear idea of God, and may fully ac­ knowledge God as actual, and may make God, as in­ deed he should, the whole goal of his activity and his life, and yet not advert directly to the fact that God, who exists, has got to exist. The note of God’s neces­ sity may be entirely overlooked even by the mind that has a clear and fully usable idea of God. Therefore we say that while the proposition, “God is an Existent Being” is self-evident in itself, and would be known with absolute certitude, not needing or admitting demonstration, by a mind adequate to understand its GOD’S EXISTENCE A TRUTH 33 subject in the fullest and completes! and most instan­ taneous manner, yet this proposition is not selfevident to the limited human mind, and, for that mind, it is a proposition which, both admits and requires demonstration. In other words, we say that the propo­ sition in question is self-evident in itself, hut not selfevident to the human mind. To use the old Latin formula, the proposition is for sc nota quoad sc but not per se nota quoad nos, “self-evident in itself, but not self-evident to us.” Out of the fact that the truth of God’s existence is self-evident in itself a certain confusion can arise in the mind that is not acutely attentive, and a mistaken conviction may be evoked that God’s existence can actually be proved by the fact that we have the idea of God. St. Anselm (1033-1 109), a philosopher and theologian of wondrous mentality, was not prevented by his great natural gifts from making this mistake. He elaborated the so-called ontological argument for God’s existence, and he was followed in it by Des­ cartes (1596-1650), Leibnitz (1646-1716), and Spinoza (1632—1677), c'ach of whom gave the argu­ ment a special phrasing and shading of his own. St. Anselm, however, may be regarded as the originator of the famous argument, and it has intrigued many since his time. He was fully‘aware of the compelling nature of the usual demonstration of God’s existence, a demonstration which proceeds from the created and contingent universe to the increate and necessary 34 THEODICY First Cause. But he believed that another true argu­ ment could be developed, which would proceed from the concept or idea of God in the human mind to the actual existence of God. 11 is argument may be staled thus: Everyone understands by God the most perfect Being that the human mind can think of ; but, if God does not really exist, then He is not the most perfect Being thinkable, for He lacks the perfection called existence : therefore, God must exist. The argument is not valid. Its conclusion is not justified by its prem­ isses. Let us restate it, drawing the only allowable conclusion, and we shall see the fallacy of the original form : God is the most perfect Being we can think of ; But the most perfect Being we can think of must be thought of as existing ; Therefore, God must be thought of as existing. Manifestly, we can grant this conclusion and still have no valid proof that God, who must be thought of as existing is, in fact, actually existing outside thought. The argument as proposed by St. Anselm involves a “jump” from the order of thinking to the order of actual being, and Logic condemns as fal­ lacious any argument with such a gap or jump in its structure. Still, we must not think that St. Anselm or any of the notable defenders of this intriguing ontological argument were so childish as to suppose that the mere thought of anything is valid proof for its existence. One of St. Anselm’s early critics had this GOD’S EXISTENCE A TREETH 35 silly notion, and he sought to upset the ontological argument by reducing it to an absurdity, Ide proposed the following argument as paralleling the ontological argument, which, of course, it docs not do at all : I have an idea of a most beautiful and perfect island; But it is not the idea of a most beautiful and perfect­ island unless the island actually exists; Therefore, the island of which I have an idea actually exists. St. Anselm treated this argument with the contempt it deserves. For he was speaking of the infinite Being, of that one and only Being which has existence as one of the phases or notes or component elements of its idea in the mind. Of no finite being, such as an island, can necessary existence be predicated, since the perfection of such a being is always limited and relative (despite the fact that one calls it “most beautiful” and “most perfect”), and existence does not enter into its ade­ quate idea or concept. But, as we have seen, the human mind is not capable of an intuitive and adequate con­ cept of God as the necessary Being (but derives its idea of God from the intuitively formed ideas of finite things in the sense-world around us) and so, even in the case of the infinite Being, the ontological argu­ ment, based on human knowledge, is not valid. Our idea of God as the necessary Being, that is, the Being which necessarily exists, is reasoned knowledge, and the idea itself is not evidence of the existence of its object; this evidence is found in the objective reason- 36 THEODICY ing that justified us in forming the idea. lienee it appears that reasoning, the working out of demon­ stration, is still required for the truth of God’s exist­ ence to which the human mind assents ; nor is the ontological argument a valid demonstration. Thomas Reid (1710—1796) and his followers in the so-called “Scottish School of Common Sense” declared that no demonstration of God’s existence is needed because we have a certain equipment of in­ tellectual judgments that are instinctively formed, and these neither require nor admit demonstration ; and among such necessitated judgments is the judgment, “God exists.” Something of the same sort is the doctrine of Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) who taught that practical reason makes us acknowledge the exist­ ence of God as an inevitable fact, although the think­ ing mind (or theorizing reason) cannot work out a true proof for it. Then there is the sentimentalist doctrine of Friedrich Jacobi (1743-1819) which holds that man has a natural longing for God and a natural affection for virtuous living, and by force of this feeling he is inescapably aware of religious and moral truths and needs no rational demonstration to support the certainty with which he holds them. To Reid and Kant we may say that a blind instinct can­ not be one and the same as the intellect or reason which struggles ever for light and for evidence; the instinct theory (or the practical reason theory, which is the same thing ) cuts straight against our whole con- GOD’S EXISTENCE A TRUTH 37 cept of reasoning and of intellectual knowledge. Reid and. Kant merely contradict themselves when they try to explain intellectual or rational conviction on the basis of that which is wholly different from intel­ lect or reason. As for the doctrine of Jacobi, it is sufficient to remark that we can have no longings, yearning’s, or affections without previous knowledge; we must know a thing, at least in some measure, be­ fore we can intellectually realize it as desirable. Back of the sentiment of Jacobi must be knowledge, and manifestly it must be knowledge of mind, of intel­ lect, of reason, for God is in no wise the object of any of the senses. But the object of intellectual knowledge, unless it be self-evident, is capable of rational discus­ sion, or reasoned argument, and of demonstration. And in as far as an important intellectual object admits demonstration it also requires it. The most notable of all the theories which declare that the existence of God needs no demonstration to our minds is the theory called ontologism. The theory itself is very old, but the only famous proponent of it belongs to the modern era of history. He is Nicole Malebranche (1638-1715), a learned, a pious, but a much mistaken man. The theory of ontologism lays down, without offering proof for it, the following principle as fundamental : the order of thought (called the logical order) must parallel the order of existence (called the ontological order). Therefore, since God is the first Being in the order of existence, He must be 38 THEODICY the first also in the order of thought. In other words, God is not only the first Being, but He is the first Be­ ing we know. Our very first idea, formed when we come to use our infant minds, is the idea of God. Ontologism goes on to say that, since God contains in Himself, as identical with His essence, the archetypal ideas or “exemplars” of all things creatable, the more we know God, the more we know His creation. Indeed, says ontologism, our knowledge of creatures is explicable only by the fact that it is acquired in and through our knowledge of God. The theory does not maintain that we are aware of the first-formed idea of God, nor that we advert to this idea early in life as we gather knowledge of creatures through its minis­ tration. Ontologism sets forth its doctrine as a some­ what defiant fact, and not as something that a man can check by his own memory or his ολνη experience ; indeed, as we have seen, experience is all against it. But it is not experience alone that makes ontologism an inadmissible doctrine ; there are other very definite and destructive objections to it. For example, ontolo­ gism would make the finite human mind naturally 'adequate for the grasp of an infinite object. In other words, it would make the human mind naturally finite and naturally infinite at the same time, which is a manifest contradiction in thought and in terms. Only when the finite mind is raised and enlarged, so to speak, and furnished supernaturally with a medium called the Light of Glory, is it enabled to see God as GOD’S EXISTENCE A TRUTH 39 He is, and, even then, its grasp, while intuitive, is not exhaustive, but will be eternally enriched in the con­ templation of the Ever Ancient lever New. But never can the Infinite be the immediate natural and propor­ tionate object of the linite mind. Hence, ontologism is wholly inadmissible as involving a self-evident con­ tradiction. Further, ontologism renders inexplicable the fact that imagination (a sentient and material faculty) constantly co-operates with the human intel­ lect in the forming and using of ideas; imagination goes along, so to speak, with intellect, and keeps pace with it in its own way and in the measure of its limita­ tions, even when intellect is engaged in the most abstruse reasoning. Now, if we behold the essences of things directly in our intuitive idea of God, this known service of imagination is not only useless but it is a thing impossble to explain; it flies straight in the face of the axiomatic truth that nature does nothing in vain. Again, ontologism overlooks the fact that when a man has a direct and intuitive knowledge of God he is instantly constituted thereby in the state of heavenly happiness, which is obviously not the case Avith human beings here on earth. For all these rea­ sons, any one of which would suffice, we reject ontologism as a wholly fallacious doctrine. And with ontologism, we reject its thesis that God’s existence needs no demonstration to the human mind. Reason and experience, then, assure us that our knowledge of God’s existence is not self-evident THEODICY knowledge for our minds. It is a truth that admits demonstration and, in that same measure, requires it. We have need for the demonstration of the truth of God’s existence. We must now inquire whether ibis need can he met. We arc to investigate the possibility of demonstrating the existence of God. b) POSSIBILITY OF THE DEMONSTRATION Against the possibility of demonstrating the exist­ ence of God stand the theories of (a) atheism which denies that there is a God to prove existent; (b) agnosticism which declares God existent (or admits that He may exist) but declares Him unknowable; (c) traditionalism which teaches that the human mind is powerless to formulate a true demonstration in this case, but has its certitude of God’s existence from a primitive revelation made to the first men and handed \ down to us by tradition. Now, we need not here make any direct attack on the atheistic position, for our whole study confutes it, and we shall have the pleasure of pointing out the fact in brief detail on a later page. Here we are to deal with the agnostic and the traditionalist positions. But before we take up the rather simple matter of their refutation, we must mention certain types of demon­ stration listed by logicians, and decide which of these may be used for our present purpose. A demonstration is, first of all, either direct or indirect. A direct demonstration deals with reasons or GOD’S EXISTENCE A TRUTH 41 causes which affect the thing demonstrated. An in­ direct demonstration shows that something is true because its opposite is false, groundless, seif-contra­ dictory, or that it leads, it accepted, to absurdities. Tn other words, a direct demonstration proves a point itself; an indirect demonstration proves the contra­ dictory point unacceptable. When you meet the skep­ tic’s claim that the hitman mind is incapable of achieving true certitude, you may demonstrate the existence of certitude by showing the character of objective evidence and its inevitable effect upon the mind ; then your demonstration is direct. But you may also confute the skeptic by taking his own word that no certainty is achievable, and asking him how he be­ came certain of that. Tn a word, a direct demonstra­ tion establishes a position as right in itself ; an indirect demonstration establishes a position as right by show­ ing that its contradictory is wrong. An indirect demonstration is valid because, as we learned in Logic, two contradictories cannot be simultaneously true nor simultaneously false; one must be true, one false ; for contradictories exhaust the possibilities and cover the whole ground : the proof that one is true is proof positive and complete that the other is false; the proof that one is false is complete proof that the other is true. Our present concern is the possibility of . direct demonstration of the truth of God’s exist­ ence. Now, a direct demonstration deals with causes 42 THEODICY and reasons, and the plan of its formulation is always either “cause to effect’’ or “effect to cause.” The “cause to effect” type of demonstration is called priori demonstration. A priori means “from before­ hand”; it indicates the forehanded view, so to say, which one takes from the consideration of a cause looking towards the effect that must come from that cause. If, for example, you argue thus: “Spherical bodies throw spherical shadows. The earth is a spher­ ical body. Therefore, the earth will throw a spherical shadow,” you are arguing a priori. You do not take the shadow as a known effect to begin with ; you take the cause of the shadow, and from the consideration of the cause you look forward, so to speak (or a priori) to the inevitable effect.—If demonstration (argues from “effect to cause,” it is called a posteriori demonstration. A posteriori means “from after­ wards” ; it indicates the backward view from an effect to its accounting cause. The a priori view knows the effect before it is there by studying the cause and learning what the effect, when it comes, must be. The a posteriori view knows the effect after it is there, and learns from studying it what sort of cause is re­ quired to explain it. If, for instance, you argue thus : “All bodies which throw spherical shadows are them­ selves spherical. The earth throws a spherical shadow. Therefore, the earth itself is spherical,” you are argu­ ing a posteriori. You are taking an effect (i. e., the shadow) and arguing from it to its accounting cause. GOD’S EXISTENCE A TRUTH 43 We need not pati>e here io explain or illustrate further than we have done the type of demonstration called imlirecL h'or. while we shah not hesitate to employ it when it offers its service, our present con­ cern is flic possibili! i>f direct demonstration of the existence of God. We ask: Is direct A monstration in this case possible; and, if so, are both the a priori and the a posteriori types of it available to us; or, if but one type can serve us, which of the two is it : We answer: Direct demonstration of the existence of God is possible, for any naturally knowable truth that is not self-evident is capable of direct or indirect demonstration ; and when the truth to be demon­ strated stands in a causal relation to known effects, then direct demonstration is possible. Now the exist­ ence of God is a naturally knowable truth as the whole history of mankind attests, and God is, by very con­ cept and definition, a Being that stands in causal rela­ tion to known effects, that is, to the visible universe. Therefore, direct demonstration of the existence of God is possible. But it is manifest that the type of direct demonstra­ tion called a priori or cause-to~effect demonstration will not serve us here. For God cannot be approached a priori. We cannot, so to speak, get back of God, for the very concept of God is a concept of the absolutely first Being. We cannot study God in His causes, for He has no causes ; the first and necessary Being is inevitably causeless. Nor can we study the essence of 44 THEODICY God in an a priori fashion, seeking to know from this essence what the attributes or perfections of < md must be, even though, by a special view of our miuds, we make a distinction in the absolutely simple ( i. c., un­ divided and indivisible) God, and regard the I Heine Essence in the light of a cause, and the Divine Per­ fections in the light of effects. For to do this we should have to possess an immediate and intuitive knowledge of the Divine Essence to begin with, and that, as a fact, we do not possess. The progress of our knowledge is all the other way about. We advance from the knowledge of creatures, and of creatural perfections, to the knowledge of the Divine Perfec­ tions, and thus our detailed knowledge of the Divine Essence Itself is built up in the effcct-to-cause or a posteriori fashion, and not a priori. We form our knowledge of God a posteriori, and in four steps : we first recognize God as the First Cause of all things ; secondly, we attribute to God all that we recognize in creatures as perfection; thirdly, we attribute this perfection to God in a manner eminently superior to that in which individual per­ fections are found in creatures ; fourthly, we remove from our idea of divine perfection every limitation or imperfection, attributing to God all possible perfec­ tions in an absolutely infinite or boundless degree and in perfect unity and simplicity, identifying them all in the undivided Divine Essence. Thus our knowledge of God is the result of the convergence of four GOD’S EXISTENCE A TRUTH 45 “ways” : the way of causality; the way of attribution: the way of excellence or transcendence ; the way of removal or denial of limitation. And clear reason justifies the approach to the sure knowledge of God by these four converging· paths. Thus we possess a distinct idea of God, the Infinite Being, although we cannot have a perfectly comprehensive idea of Him in our finite minds. But, for the matter of that, none of our ideas is perfectly comprehensive; none of them exhausts the knowability of its object. Our idea of God is clear, distinct, usable, sufficient. It is a genuine idea, not a figment of the mind, for it is formed by the mind working on solid reality and advancing along the solid paths of abstractive reasoning. The ontological argument of St. Anselm, which we have discussed in detail, is an attempt to prove God’s existence in a somewhat a priori fashion. It is not a purely a priori argument. Rather, it is an argument a simultaneo, that is, an argument which proceeds from the existence of the idea of God in our minds to the simultaneous actual existence of God outside our minds. The argument does not pretend to deal with the cause of God, for the very notion of such a cause is an absurdity ; it would be the notion of “a cause of the causeless” which is a manifest contradiction. But, as we have amply seen, even the <7 simultaneo type of demonstration fails to afford us a valid proof for the existence of God. By exclusion, then, we know that the only type 46 THEODICY of direct demonstration available in this case,—and we have seen that direct demonstration is possible,— is the a posteriori or off cct-to-cause type. By this type of thinking we build up our knowledge of Cod; by this type of proof we establish the actual existence of God. And it is this type of thinking that serves us, fundamentally, in all our reasoning. For, granted that there can be such a thing as an a priori argu­ ment, there is ever back of it a truth that was learned a posteriori. Thus, though you begin your argument about the shadow of the earth in this fashion : “Spher­ ical bodies throw spherical shadows,” and go on to conclude that the earth, being spherical, will throw a spherical shadow, you have learned a posteriori your original facts that the shadows of bodies conform to the shapes of bodies, and that the earth is spherical. To deny value to a posteriori reasoning is to bank­ rupt all human knowledge and to relapse into the evil silence of complete skepticism. But, it is objected, the a posteriori type of demon­ stration is an effect-to-cause demonstration ; it involves the dread thing called causality, and there are philosophers in the world who have no stomach for causality, and turn sick at the very mention of it. Since Immanuel Kant (1724—1804) threw his cloud of prideful doubt across the lightsome land of human intelligence, the doctrine of causality has been sus­ pect in many minds. The positivists, for instance, who are one of the many companies in the motley GOD’S EXISTENCE A TRUTH 47 regiment of agnostics, will have none of it, for they cannot put pure causality into a test-tube or on a scale or cut it in sections on a microtome, and so they deny it. They fall back upon a theory of succession or constant sequence, and say that what we call effect follozvs what we call cause, but we cannot sa)· more about it nor connect the two essentially. This, of course, is explaining something by explaining it away ; it is solving a problem by blotting the problem out, a strange procedure for a scientific mind. Further, it is a denial of fundamental and universal human experi­ ence, and, in consequence, it is the denial of the basis of all knowledge and certitude. Besides, the thing called succession, and the theory which proposes it, are not objects that can be sensed or handled in a laboratory. The positivist neatly contradicts himself when he essays to attack causality. For the rest, his argument that only the data of sense can be positively or scientifically known involves a quite evident ab­ surdity. For what are the data of sense? They are not things the senses know. The senses do not know any­ thing. The man who has the senses knows something by their use. The man who has a mind also knows something by its use. It is the man that knows in either case, not the senses nor the mind. Therefore, to say that only what a man knows by the conscious use of his senses is reliably known, and what he knows (as he knows causality) by his mind is not reliably known, is just as foolish as to say that what a man -? 11 48 -1 ù- ·* ί\ ΐ ίί A U& f -. C THEODICY learns by the sense of touch is reliably known, but what he learns by the sense of sight is not reliableknown. Eut there arc many who sec the absurdity of the extreme positivistic position and these do a neat ma­ neuver and come up smiling on a new tack. They say that causality can indeed be known, but that we cannot carry it “beyond the realm of the phenomenal.'’ In other words, you can know what causes stomach­ ache, and you can know what causes this to cause stomach-ache, but you cannot ultimately know what causes the stomach. You can know cause and effect within the borders of the bodily world, but your rea­ son, which carries you successfully through causality in this world, cannot take wing and bear you aloft into the world of the ultimate and primal causality. Why? It seems that these peculiar people who limit causality to the phenomenal world (that is, the world of sense, of bodily appearances) have themselves explored the outer and invisible realm ; they have been there ; they know all about it ; and they tell ordinary stupid peo­ ple like you and me that we cannot go there. If we are not very stupid, we shall resent this intolerable impertinence. These scientistic people declare that only the realm of sense-reality can be dealt with sci­ entifically; only in this realm can causality be known. Does that doctrine belong to the realm of sense? By what sense does one acquire that knowledge? Again we come back to the fundamental fallacy involved ~ GGD’S EXISTENCE A TROTH 49 in all this nice assignment of fields and areas in which sound knowledge can be garnered. Not that we should not make clean distinctions between the field of sensa­ tion and (liât of intellection; indeed, it is the failure to notice the fence between these fields that is charac­ teristic of all the muddle of even the finest minds since Descartes (1596-1650). And it is the very failure of the positivists and of the positivistic to notice the distinction, that mixes them all up, and enables them to propose with serious faces a wholly intellectual and reasoned conclusion (though their reason be twisted) as the fundamental principle of an entirely sensistic system ! Once more we insist that in the case of hu­ man knowledge, whether it be knowledge of cows or of causality, it is the num who knows, not his senses and not his mind. And there is certainly no scien­ tific or philosophical ground for admitting value to one sort of awareness and denying it to the other. You may indeed follow with critical care any com­ plex line of intellectual procedure; but so you must do in any penetrating use of the senses. And you cannot be critical of either sentient or intellectual pro­ cedure without the use of the very mind whose re­ liability is questioned or denied with the question or denial of man’s knowledge of causality, even of pri­ mal causality. For the rest, any causality belongs to the supra-phenomenal world. There are phenomena which mark effects, and show' the presence and the action of causes, but causality itself is no phenome- tJS* id î-ç ίί-t ΛΛ" i is I* J 5o THEODICY non; and what it produces by way of phenomena is regulari}' only secondary to an underlying and nonphcnomenal effect upon the very essences of things. To sum up : the knowledge which we possess of causality is a direct intuition of the mind working with ■the findings of sense. It is a fundamental certitude that makes us connect cause and effect, and upon it not only all human knowledge but all human practice is built up. Even those who twist their minds into an acceptance of a bizarre theory which denies causality or limits it to the realm of phenomena (where, strictly speaking, it does not even apply, except in a secondary way) are forced in their practice to recognize causal­ ity as true and as validly known. Even if we allow the positivistic and scientistic people to play about with names, and to call causality by the name of succession, or constant sequence, we recognize clearly from their whole procedure, and even from their terminology in unguarded moments, that they mean by these names (neither more nor less than genuine causality. Causal­ ity is simply inescapable in the whole experience of ; man, and it affords to philosopher, theologian, and ( scientist, as to the man in the street, the ground of ‘..argument and of demonstration. Therefore, with clear minds and spirits unburdened with the intoler­ able positivistic error, we take up the proofs for God’s existence, basing them on causality, proceeding in a true and valid a posteriori manner to make clear the most important truth of all. And to the stubborn H jjk GOD’S EXISTENCE A TRUTH 51 positivistic person who refuses to accompany us on this interesting and all-important journey, we say, “While you’re waiting, you might try to account for the succession and constant sequence of things in this world, and for what these tilings scream at you about the non-phcnomcnal world. For even a positivist can’t deny that succession and constant sequence are things that demand a bit of explaining.’’ The agnostic, then, is wrong when he insists that God cannot be known. For a cause can be known, and the effects from which we proceed to the knowledge of the cause, are, in the present case, all about us. Our whole procedure in setting forth the demonstration of God’s existence will be a sufficient refutation of ag­ nosticism, if any further refutation be needed than that already given. The traditionalist also is wrong. His theory of a primitive revelation is so far true ; there doubtless was a primitive revelation. But to say that there had to be such a revelation, by physical necessity, so that man could never have had a knowl­ edge of God without it ; and to say that our knowledge of God is a blind acceptance of the human tradition, is to make wild assertions that do not square with the facts; the fact of the human mind is against it; the fact of the human experience is against it; and noth­ ing really is for it. We have seen in the present study that God’s existence can be proved, and that there is a valid way for developing this proof. To the tradition­ alist then we say, “What! Are you answered?” And S2 THEODICY if he is not answered, we may say, losing reverence momentarily for his solemn stupidity, “We can’t prove God’s existence? Just watch us do it.” SUMMARY OF THE ARTICLE In this Article we have explained the meaning of demonstration, and have discovered that the truth of God’s existence is not self-evident to our minds, and therefore admits and requires demonstration. We have noticed the defects of the demonstration at­ tempted by St. Anselm and others (called the on­ tological argument') and have rejected this as an inept proof, and one that does not dispense us from the ne­ cessity of finding other and valuable evidence for God’s existence. We have seen that the true demon­ stration of God’s existence is not furnished by the instinct theory of Reid and the Scottish School, by Kant and his theory of practical reason, or by Jacobi and his theory of religious and moral sentiment. Viewing all these theories, we find that the need still exists for valid demonstration of God’s existence. Further, we have seen that this need can be met by a proof that is direct and a posteriori, a proof neces­ sarily involving causality. Against the doctrines that deny value to the argument from causality, and against the whole agnostic, and traditionalistic posi­ tion, we have established our right to use this argu ­ ment in building up a true demonstration. CHAPTER It DEMONSTRATION OF THE EXISTENCE OF GOD This Chapter sets forth the traditional a posteriori proofs for the existence of God. All of these proofs are applications of the principle of causality, that is, of the fundamental truth which may be fully expressed as follows : ‘‘Every effect re­ quires, to explain its existence, the existence of an adequate cause or sum of causes, and it ultimately requires the exist­ ence of an uncaused and necessarily existing First Cause which is Subsistent Being Itself.” But, although all the proofs here offered are expressions of causality, all do not exhibit the same type of causality. Therefore, as a kind of preface to our demonstration, we offer a short introductory Article on the chief types of causes. In the succeeding Articles we present the proofs for God’s existence. The Chapter is divided into these Articles : Article i. The Chief Types of Causes Article 2. The Proof from Efficient Causality Article 3. The Proof from Formal and Final Causality Article 4. Certain Supplementary Proofs Article i. The Chief Types of Causes a) Meaning of Cause b) Intrinsic Causes c) Extrinsic Causes a) MEANING OF CAUSE A cause is anything that contributes, in any way and measure whatever, to the -producing of a thing. 53 yr 54 THEODICY The thing produced by causes is called an effect. Be­ tween cause and effect there is a constant relation which, viewed from the standpoint of the cause, is causality, and viewed from the standpoint of the effect is dependency or contingency. That which is the effect of one cause may be the cause of a further effect. In­ deed the world around us is a tissue of causes and effects. We distinguish cause and principle. A principle is that which gives rise to anything, or is its point of origin. Thus a cause is always a principle, for it is the point of origin of the effect and it gives rise to the effect. But some points of origin are merely startingpoints, and not effecting or producing sources. Thus, the dawn is the starting point, or principle, of the day, but dawn is not the cause of day. Thus a man’s con­ victions are the true source of his free conduct, but they are not the cause of his free conduct; this cause is his will; the convictions are principles but not causes. Therefore, every cause is a principle, but not every principle is a cause. We distinguish cause and reason. A reason is that which contributes in any way to the understanding of a thing; it explains, whereas a cause produces. Every­ thing that exists has reasons which explain it and account for it; but not everything that exists has its cause or causes. God has reasons, and we arc to in­ vestigate them in our present study. But God has no causes, for He is the first Being, and not a Being DEMONSTRATION OF EXISTENCE 55 consequent upon causes. Now, every cause is a reason ; that is, when you know the cause of an effect, you have an explanation of the effect. But there are ex­ planations other than causes ; we explain and even demonstrate the existence of God but we do not as­ sign causes to God. Therefore, every cause is a reason but not every reason is a cause. Fire is a reason for heat and is the cause of heat; heat is a reason for fire (that is, it manifests or explains the presence of fire) but heat is not the cause of fire ; it is its effect. We distinguish cause and occasion. An occasion is some extrinsic circumstance or set of circumstances which may induce a cause to act. The sight of a priest or of a rosary in the hands of a little sodalist may lead an anti-clerical to curse and swear ; what he sees is not the cause of the evil language, but its occasion. There is never an essential and intrinsic connection between the occasion and the cause which acts on occasion, but there is frequently a powerful, if ex­ trinsic, influence exercised by occasion. For this rea­ son we have the practical truisms: “Fie that loves danger shall perish in it” ; “He who wills not to avoid occasions of sin, does not will to avoid sin” ; “Tell me the company you keep, and I’ll tell you what you are,” and so on. b) INTRINSIC CAUSES An intrinsic cause is one that is right in the effect, not external to it, but part and parcel with it. 56 THEODICY There are two types of intrinsic cause, material cause and formal cause. - » 1. A material cause is the bodily matter out of which an object is made. Thus the material cause of a statue is wood or plaster or marble. It is manifest that spiritual things have no material cause, for they are not composed of matter. The material out of which a bodily thing is made is a true cause, for with­ out it the effect would not be there. Without wood, plaster, marble, silver, or some other bodily substance, there could be no statue. And the production of the statue truly depended upon some suitable substance existing that could be carved or moulded into a statue. Indeed, this statue which I here look upon would not be this statue if any other matter but that precise mat­ ter which is in it were used in the making. Thus the matter, the material make-up, of any bodily substance has the nature of a true cause. Remember the defini­ tiori of cause : that which contributes, in any manner or measure whatever, to the producing of a thing. Notice that the material of which a bodily object is made is right in that object; it is intrinsic to that ob­ ject; thus a material cause is an intrinsic cause. 2. A formal cause is that which constitutes an effect as the precise kind of thing it is, constitutes it formally or as such. Now, the precise kind of thing which the effect is, may mean the precise kind of sub­ stance or the precise kind of accidental being. Thus, in a silver statue, I distinguish that which makes this DEMONSTRATION OF EXISTENCE 57 bodily substance the precise kind of substance it is, that is, silver, and 1 call this the substantial form or the substantial formal cause of the statue. Further, I distinguish in the statue that which makes this silver object the precise kind of thing it is in its acci­ dental being, that is, in its shape and size and image­ value, and so on; and each point of this kind is an accidental form of the statue, and its accidental formal cause. Notice that the statue would not be this precise thing (substantially) if any other substance than silver were used to make it ; nor would it be precisely this identical thing if any accidental determinant or form were different, if, for instance, it were made of some other quantity of silver, or were smaller or larger or represented some other person than it now does. Thus, every single one of the determinants or forms (the one substantial form and the several acci­ dental forms) makes its contribution to the effect I call this statue. Each of these forms is therefore a true cause. And notice that the forms or formal causes are right in the effect itself : the statue is silver ; the statue is marked and determined by this weight, this size, this location, this shape, and so on. Therefore, a for­ mal cause, whether substantial or accidental, is an in­ trinsic cause. To sum up. Intrinsic causes are thus distinguished : Material Cause. -< Formal Γ substantial t accidental 58 C) THEODICY EXTRINSIC CAUSES An extrinsic cause is outside the effect, not part and parcel with it. There are two chief types of extrinsic cause, effi­ cient cause and final cause. l. An efficient cause is a cause which by its own activity produces an effect. The sculptor who carved the statue is its efficient cause. Now the efficient cause is frequently subserved by instrumental causes, as the sculptor was served by the tools he used, and by the natural instruments of hands, fingers, muscles, sin­ ews. The efficient cause is often also served by an exemplar-cause, that is, the model or pattern after which the work of the efficient cause is fashioned. Thus the sculptor (the efficient cause of the statue) was subserved not only by instruments (that is, in­ strumental causes') but by some model, image, or pat­ tern, which he had physically before him as he worked, or at least pictured in his imagination (that is, an exemplar-cause), and which served as his plan and his guide. Notice that both instruments and exemplar have their influence on the effect and make a distinct contribution to it; without these causes the finished statue would not exist, or it would not exist as the precise thing it is in every detail. Therefore, instru­ ments and exemplar deserve the name of true causes. Notice further that the efficient cause, the instrumen­ tal causes, and the exemplar-cause, are things exter­ nal to, or extrinsic to, the effect ; they are not right in I)Of< )\STRATION OF EXISTENCE 59 the effect itself ; hence the)7 are called extrinsic causes. 2. A final cause is the goal or end towards which the work of the efficient cause is directed in the active producing of the effect. Wherever we find efficient causation, we find some goal, some term, something aimed at, whether consciously or unconsciously. The lifeless forces of nature, such as wind and erosion, tend towards their effect by a natural drive or energy. In living things, in plants and animals, we notice an obvious tendency towards development, maturity, fruitfulness. But only an intelligent or understanding being (that is, only a rational being) is capable of setting a goal, proposing an end to itself, and working to attain it. And every rational creature does so set its goal in every free act, but always sets it (of necessity) in the direction of good to be attained; for towards the Supreme Good every creature is directed by the inmost requirements of its being. The ultimate goal, absolutely speaking, sought by man in every free act, *'is the supreme or highest good, and supreme happi­ ness in the attainment of that good. But any proxi­ mate or remote goal which is not absolutely ultimate (and which is conceived of as a means to carry one in the direction of the ultimate goal) is freely chosen by man (that is, by the only bodily rational creature) in his deliberate activity. So we say, to illustrate our defi­ nition of final cause, that the sculptor must have had some reason for making the statue, something that drew him to the work of making it, something that THEODICY DEMONSTRATION OF EXISTENCE made its making appear a good thing and led him to choose it freely. Perhaps it was money, perhaps love of art, perhaps a mere pleasant way to spend the time ; but some purpose there must have been, else the statue never would have been produced. 'This purpose is the final cause of the statue. For man, a final cause is also a motive; it moves the human efficient cause to the free work of producing the effect. But for God, the final cause is not a motive, since God is in no wise influenced or moved, but chooses with supreme and wholly unswayed free choice. God has, in all His tran­ sient operations, a purpose, but no motive ; for man, purpose is usually a pretty accurate synonym for mo­ tive. The final cause is manifestly extrinsic to the effect; it is something outside the effect itself, and something at which the effect is, so to speak, aimed and directed. To sum up. Extrinsic causes are distinguished thus : and as extrinsic to the effect {efficient and final cause). Tn the subsequent study we shall find that God is the supreme Efficient and the last Final Cause of all creation. 6o Efficient Cause. - instrumental subserved by ~ [ exemplar Final SUMMARY OF THE ARTICLE This brief Article has taught us the meaning of cause. We have defined cause, and have noticed how it is distinguished from principle, reason, and occa­ sion. We have classified the chief types of causes as intrinsic to the effect {material and formal cause) 61 Article 2. The Proof from Efficient Causality a) Proof from Motion Efficient Causes a) b) Proof from the Order of c) Proof from Contingency PROOF FROM MOTION By motion or movement is meant any transit, any change, from one state of being to another. Motion is most readily illustrated by local movement, that is, by the movement of bodily things in space. Such movement is all about us all the time ; it goes on within us; it obtrudes itself upon our notice constantly. We find such motion or movement in the sunrise and sun­ set, in the rustling leaves, in the darting fly, in the beating of our hearts, in the twitching of our fingers, in the steps we take, in the creeping clouds, in the heaving ocean. But this movement of bodily things in space is not the only movement or motion in the world. There is motion in the transit from ignorance to knowledge, in the making up of our minds, in the change from the state of sin to the state of grace. Any transit, any going-over, from one state of being (substantial or accidental) to another is motion. Now, the principle of motion, that is, the self- THEODICY DEMONSTRATION OF EXISTENCE evident truth which is the first source of sound reason­ ing about motion, is this: Whatever is moved is moved by something other than itself, or, in the famil­ iar Latin formula which we should know, Quidquid movetur ab alio movetur. For motion requires a mover as well as a thing moved. And a little attention will make clear the fact that mover and thing moved can­ not possibly be one and the same thing. As far as bodily or local movement is concerned the point is ex­ pressed in the physical law of inertia which tells us that bodies at rest tend to remain at rest ; they never originate movement in themselves and of themselves; the thought is as self-contradictory as that of a man lifting himself by his own boot-straps. To moving bodies, motion has been communicated; it has been bestowed and given; it has come from some external source. And what is true of local motion in bodies is true of change of quality or quantity and of any mo­ tion at all. Living bodies are said to move themselves, and life is sometimes defined as the power of self-movement. But living bodies do not move themselves into ex­ istence ; nor do they dower themselves with the power called life. Life-movements depend upon the existence of an inner substantial principle (which did not move itself into existence) called the life-principle or soul or psyche or entelechy; and in the execution of life­ movements in bodies, part moves part. A living body has been (marvellously and mysteriously) assembled or “moved together’’ ; it did not assemble its own parts in the first place for it was not there to do so even if it could. And so its subsequent movements are not self-movements in the full sense; these depend upon the balance of parts, the assembly, the organism or vital unity, which is not self-originating. It still re­ mains true that whatever is moved is moved by some­ thing other than itself. To put the matter in the more stately philosophical terminology ; Anything movable is in the state of po­ tentiality with respect to the movement which it may undergo. When the movement takes place, the po­ tentiality is actualized. Now, it is a principle of meta­ physics that nothing is actualized except under the activity of something which is already actual ; no potentality is self-actualizing. St. Thomas Aquinas puts the point thus : “Motion takes place inasmuch as things are changed from the potential to the actual, and this demands some actual agent to move them from the potential state.” Now, it cannot be that any­ thing is both potential and actual under the same as­ pect or in precisely the same way; therefore the mover and the thing moved cannot be identical. What­ ever is moved is moved by something other than itself. That, then, is the first point to remember. Motion is not self-originating, and wherever motion exists, there exists a mover which is something other than the thing moved. The second point is this : you cannot go on forever with a senes of movers and things 62 63 - 64 THEODICY moved. If Z is moved by Y, and Y is moved by X, and X is moved by W, and W is moved by V, ibis sort of thing may go on through a long chain or scries, but it does not go on endlessly. Somewhere you must conic to an absolute A which is not moved by anything else, which, in fact, is not moved at all. For it is one of the chief of self-evident principles that a “process unto actual infinity” is impossible. The agnostic may object that we go too far in demanding a first mover itself unmoved. He may say, “It’s all very well to follow the chain of mover-and-moved, but where it slips out of the realm of bodily reality it slips entirely out of sight.” Yes, but we can know, and that with full certitude, that it does not slip out of existence when it slips out of sight. The chain that hangs a few visible links before our eyes, one duly supporting the next below it according to honored custom, may be lost in cloudy heights, but this fact does not make us less aware that the invisible portion of it is there, and that somewhere in the higher reaches there is a link' hooked over a solid peg, and the peg supports the whole suspended chain, visible and invisible. To ac­ knowledge the links we see and then to deny that there is anything knowable about the links we do not see, and especially the first link, is actually to take away the only reason there is for believing what our eyes be­ hold. If, out there “beyond,” there is no knowable first link solidly moored on something that supports the whole chain, then the thing we see is something h __ ._ __ ______-λ----- - «π» ■ DEMONSTRATION OF EXISTENCE 65 at once more and less than a miracle; it is something monstrous, and all our talk and reasoning about it become gibberish. To refuse to sec an argument, or a chain, to the end, though it be a bitter end or a bitterly disliked end, is not to acknowledge, with humility, the powerlessness of the human mind to investigate invisible reality ; it is to assert the powerlessness of the human mind to recognize visible reality. It is manifest that this argument from motion is a phase or aspect of the requirements of efficient cau­ sality. For the mover is the efficient cause of the movement. Hence, with St. Thomas who puts this argument first, we list it, with the two that follow, under the general heading of Proof from Efficient Causality. We may sum up our argument thus : If there is motion in the world, there exists a mover, and ultimately a First Mover Itself Unmoved. Now, manifestly, there is motion in the world. Therefore, there exists a mover, and ultimately a First Mover Itself Unmoved. This First Mover we call God. Therefore God exists. b) PROOF FROM THE ORDER OF EFFICIENT CAUSES An efficient cause is, as we have learned, a cause that by its own action produces an effect. Now, this effect may, in turn, be the efficient cause of another effect, and this of another, and so on. Tn a machine, one part moves another, and this another, the whole movement of all the parts depending upon the steam eSsHæF 3S J THEODICY DEMONSTRATION OF EXISTENCE or electricity or water or other force which moves the first of these parts. We sometimes see a large fac­ tory full of moving machines and travelling belts, and all movement is communicated from one master engine or one enormous fly-wheel; efficient causality is communicated from point to point and from part to part, each movement being first an effect of an effi­ cient cause, and then an efficient cause of a further effect. In nature about us we may observe exam­ ples of the same “subordination or order of efficient causes.” Thus the sun acts as an efficient cause in shedding its light and warmth upon the plant; the plant, availing itself of the sun’s contribution, grows and flourishes and puts forth fruit. Again, the golfer, surely one of nature’s noblest sights, moves his arms ; the arms move the club ; the club (perhaps) moves the ball; and here is a neat chain of connected efficient causes. It is needless to multiply examples, for there are such chains of efficient causation (or such “an order of efficient causes”) to be observed on all sides. Now, just as motion cannot -arise-of itself ; just as a thing moved cannot be its own mover, so a thing efficiently caused cannot be its own cause. As. St. Thomas says, “It cannot be that anything is its own efficient cause; if it were, it would exist before itself, which is impossible.” Therefore, where we find a thing efficiently produced or effected, we must look for its cause in something other than itself. To quote St. Thomas once more, “In every con­ nected series of efficient causes, the first is the cause of the intermediate (one or many), and the interme­ diate is the cause of the last. Remove the cause and the effect is gone; remove the first cause and there remains neither intermediate nor last.” Therefore, he concludes, one cannot say a chain of efficient cau­ sality reaches back unto infinity, for to say that is to deny actuality to the first cause, and so to deny it to all the rest of the chain. One must come to the first cause in any series or chain of efficient causes, and one must come to the First Cause to account for all the chains, and this First Cause must be itself uncaused. For it is first, no cause is prior to it, nothing produces it; it is causeless, unproduced. Reason demands that such a Being must exist to account for the efficient causation we behold all about us in the world, and for the universe itself which is demonstrably an ef­ fect, that is, the product of efficient causality. We call this Uncaused First Cause, God. Therefore, God ex­ ists. We may sum up the argument in this way : 66 67 If there exists a true order or connection of efficient causes, there must exist a First Cause, Itself Un­ caused. Now, there does exist, as is manifest all about us, a true order or connection of efficient causes. Therefore, there must exist a First Cause, Itself Un­ caused. This we call God. Therefore, God exists. 68 C.) THEODICY PROOF FROM CONTINGENCY Contingence or contingency means dependency ; it is the converse of causality· If causality is “heads,” contingency is “tails.” A thing caused is said to be contingent upon, or dependent upon, the action <>i the efficient cause (or causes) that produced it. A thing uncaused (and such a Being is only one, namely, God ) is said to be necessary; it is not dependent upon causes ; it is not contingent ; for it is causeless and unpro­ duced and exists of necessity, that is, it cannot be non­ existent. Thus there is a. fundamental classification of reality into necessary and contingent reality. All creatural reality, all worldly, reality, is finite and hence contingent. Now, a contingent thing may exist, but, if it does exist, it exists by grace of the causes that gave it existence. In itself it involves no necessity for ex­ istence ; it didn’t have to exist, and it does not contain in itself the explanation of its existence. In itself, it is possible, and that is the most that can be said for it. That finite or contingent things exist is proof posi­ tive that they can exist, but it is equally proof positive that they might not have existed. Well, if everything is of this character; if everything is contingent; if everything is something that might not exist, there must have been a time when absolutely nothing ex­ isted. And, by that token, it must still be true that absolutely nothing exists. For in the blank of absolute nothingness there is no actuality that could draw pos­ DEMONSTRATION OF EXISTENCE 69 sible things into existence; absolute nothingness is simply nothing, and nothing it must remain. ] fence, the very existence of contingent things (and all crea­ tures are contingent) is indisputable proof that there exists a Being that is not contingent, but necessary. And, as necessary, it must be prior to all the contin­ gent things that ultimately depend upon it for their existence; it must be first. Therefore, there exists a First and a Necessary Being, and this we call God. Therefore, God exists. When we say that a thing is contingent or depend­ ent we label it as a thing subject to change, to mo­ tion, to efficient causality. It has been changed from its state of possibility or potentiality to actuality; it has been moved from non-being into being; it has been efficiently caused. Ponder these words of the great G. K. C., applying them to the three arguments we have thus far considered : “Mr. Wells must surely realize the first and simplest of the paradoxes that sit by the springs of truth. He must surely see that the fact of two things being different implies that they are similar. The hare and the tortoise may differ in the quality of swiftness, but they must agree in the quality of motion. The swiftest hare cannot be swifter than an isosceles triangle or the idea of pinkness. When we say the hare moves faster, we say the tor­ toise moves. And when we say of a thing that it moves, we say, without need of other words, that there are things that do not move. And even in the THEODICY DEMONSTRATION OF EXISTENCE act of saying that things change, we say that there is something unchangeable.” We may put our argument from contingency in this brief form : ficient Cause Itself Uncaused, a First and Necessary Being. This Being we call God. 7° If contingent things exist, they demand as their ulti­ mate explanation (that is, as their sufficient rca.-on for existing) the existence of a Being which is neces­ sary and non-contingent, a First Being which does not depend on causes. Now, it is undeniable that contingent things exist. Therefore, there exists a Being which is necessary and non-contingent, a First Being which does not de­ pend on causes. This Being we call God. Therefore, God exists. SUMMARY OF THE ARTICLE In this Article we have presented the first three arguments for the existence of God in the order in which they are set forth by St. Thomas Aquinas. It is manifest that these three arguments, or proofs, as we are fully justified in calling them, are all applications of the principle of efficient causality. This principle may be succinctly stated in these words : No effect is efficiently produced without an adequate producing or efficient cause. We have considered efficient causality as it is manifested in motion, in the subordination or order of causes, and in contingency. Any one of these proofs is conclusive. Their cumulative force is abso­ lutely compelling to sound reason. Reason therefore demands the existence of a Prime Mover, a First Ef- 71 Article 3. The Proof from Formal and Final Causality a) Proof from Grades of Perfection b) Proof from Government of the World c) Proof from Alan’s Ultimate Goal Things bear the impress of their efficient cause in two notable ways. They manifest its power and skill and, in a sense, its character, in their formal struc­ ture, their being considered formally or as such. And they manifest its purpose in the way they work. In the first of the three arguments here to be presented we view creatures in the light of what may, at least analogously, be called their formal cause. .Many au­ thors prefer to see in this argument a further applica­ tion of efficient causality (and indeed this is not to be denied) with a tinge of exemplar-causality. In the second and third arguments we view creatures in the light of the end or goal for which they are made and to which they tend ; in a word we see them in the light of their final causality. a) proof from grades of perfection By the perfection of a thing we mean its thorough making. The word perfection comes from the Latin per and factum which, freely rendered, means “made V ’'ιϊ’ζ^^- ί^ί*’ - γ fri5* ^ί-* ‘ 1 72 £ THEODICY through and through.’’ A thing is perfect or lo'S per­ fection when it is all that it ought to he, when no item or element that should be present in it is lacking. Of course, there is a pedantic quibble about the pro­ priety of speaking of grades or degrees of perfection ; it is sometimes asserted that a thing is perfect or it is not perfect, and that nothing more may be said of it. In other words, it is said that perfect is an absolute term, not admitting comparison; it is a positive with­ out comparative or superlative. Now, this is true enough when one considers a single thing, or a single essence in the abstract. A reality either measures up to the full stature of what it should be, or it falls short. But when we contrast things essentially different, it is manifest that one fulness may be less than another fulness ; as the stone, for instance, is less in the order of fulness of being and activity than the plant, and in that sense is less perfect than the plant. The same is true of contrasted qualities like wisdom and goodness and virtue and beauty. Outside all the individuals and the classes of which such qualities may be predicated there is some absolute standard, which the mind per­ force conceives, and with which it compares the indi­ viduals and classes and rates them as lesser and greater in perfection as they share less fully or more fully the impress of the absolute standard. Thus the argu­ ment about the terms perfect and perfection appears to be one for grammarians and purists rather than for philosophers; for, whatever the requirements of ιΜ DEMONSTRATION OF EXISTENCE 73 diction and pure style, the thought or idea that is ex­ pressed by the phrase degrees of perfection is quite clear and quite valuable. Perhaps, however, it would be wiser (and certainly it would silence the grumbling of the pedants and pundits) if we were to have the words perfect and perfection and use some such words as good and goodness; there can surely be no quibble about the meaning of good, and better. And indeed St. Thomas Aquinas uses tins very set of terms (with others) in his presentation of the argument under discussion. “We find in things,” he says, “degrees of more and less, and they are called more or less good, more or less true, more or less noble, and so on. But more or less is predicated of things inasmuch as the)- bear reference to a most.'" In other words, there must be a supreme standard, which is not itself subject to measurement by comparison with a further standard (for it is supreme}. Things are more or less (good, noble, true, etc. ) by a kind of measurement ; a measure is applied to them in a manner analogous to that in which a yardstick is applied to a piece of cloth and which is found to he more or less than a yard. But the first source and standard of measurement cannot conceivably be measurable itself. The things that have more or less may'be said to share or participate in a limited measure what the ultimate standard possesses simply and unshared in a measureless and absolute way. Things, therefore, which have degrees of good 74 THEODICY and better; more noble, less noble, etc., require the existence of that which is measurelessly most, best, truest; noblest, as the ultimate source and standard of their shared goodness, truth, nobility. We may set the argument in this form : If there are real degrees of more and less in things about us in this world, there must exist a most, a maximum, a greatest, not only in a relative sense as the greatest in a certain order, but in an absolute sense as boundlessly greatest. Now, as is manifest, there are real degrees of more and less in things about us in this world. Therefore, there exists a most, a maximum, a greatest, not only in a relative sense, but in an absolute sense. This Greatest we call God. Therefore, God exists. b) PROOF FROM GOVERNMENT OF THE WORLD This proof is sometimes called the teleological ar­ gument, the term deriving from the Greek telos which means “end,” that is, in the present use, “goal, aim, purpose.” Sometimes the proof is called the argu­ ment from design, since things in the world are mani­ festly made and designed, planned and built, to do a certain thing, that is, to achieve a certain end. Now, when we speak of the teleological tendency of things, or of their design in structure and function, we are necessarily speaking of how things are governed in their being and their operations, and of how they are guided to their end or goal. For this reason we keep the older name for this argument and call it the proof from the government of the world. The proof DEMONSTRATION OF EXISTENCE 7$ is an appeal to final causality; it calls attention to the fact that things are made for an end; it points to their final cause. The world as a whole, and all things in the world taken in groups or classes, and all members of all classes, manifest the most amazing arrangement and design, harmony and balance. Be they lifeless or liv­ ing, great or small, bodily creatures are structurally and functionally fitted for certain definite activities, and these they tend, by a resistless bent of nature, to exercise and fulfill. They are subjected to definite laws of being and activity, laws which they could not have imposed upon themselves. Their manifest arrangement,, balance, harmony of partsÿ direction of effort^ mark them as suited for an end (that is, for the doing of a definite thing), as made for an end, designed· for an end ; and their activities or opera­ tions show them steadily tending to the end for which they are fitted and designed, and so show them as governed to their end. Consider the structure and the operations of the simplest plant. Notice that it is made of various parts, yet its life is one force which holds the different parts in a compact anti active unity ; it feeds them all, draw­ ing sustenance from alien substances and turning this into the very substance of the plant itself; it directs and unifies, it builds up and maintains the interrela­ tion and interdependence and the sympathy of all the parts. Surely here is order, balance, government. 7ns, boundaries, drawbacks, hindrances; which is abmlutely free from dependencies and influences: which is boundless and infinite. And by a perl eel mn of God, we mean one of the special phases in which llie indivisible Divine Essence is viewed by the human mind. In the next Chapter we shall discuss certain per­ fections oi God, which, for lack of a better term, we call His properties or attributes. But here we must consider what may be called the fundamental perfections of God, and in these we discern His physical essence. We may limit these fundamental perfections to four. These indicate that God is one in Himself and one in His kind, that is, that God is one and that God is the only God; that God is with­ out parts or divisions or divisibility ; that God is limitlessly or boundlessly perfect ; that God is a ’^spirit. In a word, The.„fundamental perfections of ' God. ..are .uyaity.,. simplicityt^itlfinity, spirituality. We must speak briefly of each of these perfections : I. The Unity of God. By the unity of God we indicate the one single Essence of God. By faith we know that God, who„ is. Qne-ixiJEssence,...is. ...Three. in. Person, but this fact does not touch our present inquiry in any way. The mystery of the Blessed ^Trinity cannot be handled by philosophy; human reason unaided by revelation cannot prove or dis- the essence of god 113 prove it; all that can be certainly known by reason is that the mystery docs not come into contradiction and conflict with rationally known truths, there­ fore, the question of the d rinity is strictly theo­ logical, and has no place in (lie discussions of theodicy. But faith and reason are at one in their unqualified assertion that God is one Essence, one Nature, one Substance. 'This is what we mean by the unity of God. And the term unity also involves in itself (in the present instance) the perfection called unicity or uniqueness, that is, the perfection whereby the one God is the only God. It is a basic truth of metaphysics that every being is one; inas­ much as a thing is a thing, it is that one thing. But limited things can have others of their kind. No being can be a plurality of itself; but it can admit an equality of other things with itself. Thus Socrates is one man; there cannot be a plurality of Socrates, even if a million men are called by the same name. This one man is this one man; he has unity. But he has not unicity, for there are many other men, many other beings of the same essential kind as himself. With the I'irst and Necessary Being this is not so. Not only is this Being one in itself with perfect unity, but it is the only thing of its kind. It has unity and unicity. It is not only one; it is also unique. These points we are now to prove. There have been people in the world's history (and there are still some today) who thought that s 8 114 ς ( I / / \ THEODICY many gods exist; these people arc polytheists, and their doctrine is polytheism. Polytheism is some­ times a belief in, and worship of, a host of invisible beings, good or bad; this variety of polytheism is demonohttry or demon worship, using the term de­ mon in its Greek sense as a kind of angel or a kind of devil; thus the term demonolatry docs not neces­ sarily mean devil-worship. Sometimes polytheism finds expression in the worship of ancestors (this is religious animism, also anthropolatry). Sometimes it is the worship of animals (this is sodlatry) ; some­ times, the worship of the sun, moon, and stars (Sabeism) ; sometimes, the worship of natural or artificial objects in the bodily world (fetichism). A special form of polytheism limits the deities to two, a supreme Good Being and an equally or al­ most ecjually supreme Evil Being ; this doctrine (called religious dualism') was professed by the an­ cient Manichaeans and, somewhat later, by the Gnostics, Against all these, stands our doctrine that God is one and the only God. Against polytheism we assert the truth of monotheism. That God is one and the only God is, first of all, manifest in the unity and order of the world around us; in the harmony of the universe. We find such unity and harmony in the smallest creature as well as in the whole complexity of the cosmos. Now, where there is a great and most complex design, and where this design exhibits, in the large and in its THE ESSENCE OF GOD most minute details, an amazing harmony, balance, unity, it is manifest that the design is not the product of a plurality of beings but of one. Even in the little works of art and of practical utility (of art and of artisansbip) that are designed and exe­ cuted by men, we find one controlling plan; one ar­ chitect designs a building, and though many may confer about the plans, the finished product is a uni­ fied decision which comes from, or is adopted by, one controlling or master mind. The most clever artist cannot finish a picture left incomplete, in such a manner as to deceive experts about the points or parts where the one artist left off and the other be­ gan. A lover of Dickens would instantly detect thé fact that a completed Edwin Drood was not all the work of his beloved novelist, even if he had never read the part that Dickens wrote, before taking' up the completed story. Now, the unity of the world, in its smallest and largest aspects, is such a unity as no human work of art or craftsmanship could ever re­ motely approach. It is surely manifest to the fair mind that the universe has a single Author. This is not a compelling argument; but it is a fully legiti­ mate argument, and an extremely strong one. Even John Stuart Mill admits its force and value. He is quoted by Father Boedder, S.J. (in Natural The­ ology of the famed Stonyhurst Series; pp. 69-70), and from the quotation we select a sentence or two : “When once the double conviction has found entry 116 mil h!|n ' I I THEODICY into the mind—that every event depends on ante­ cedents ; and at the same time that to bring it about many antecedents must concur, perhaps all the ante­ cedents in Nature, insomuch that a slight difference in any one of them might have prevented the phe­ nomenon, or materially altered its character—the conviction follows that no one event, certainly no one kind of events, can be absolutely pre-ordained or governed by any Being but one who holds in his hand the reins of all Nature and not of some depart­ ment only. . . . The reason, then, why monotheism may be accepted as the representative of theism in the abstract, is not so much because it is the theism of all the more improved portions of the human race, as because it is the only theism which can claim for itself any footing on scientific ground” (Mill, Three Essays on Religion, pp. 132ft'.). We have proved, by compelling argument, that God is the First and the Necessary Being. Now, there cannot conceivably be a plurality of such Beings. How can a plurality of beings all be first? And, if they could, how could they be distinguished one from another, not in our minds but among themselves? For a being which exists of necessity is Self-existent Being. If two or more such Beings could exist, how could they be distinct Beings, that is, really a plurality and not one single Essence ? Could they be distinguished by self-existence itself? No; for in this they are at one. Could they be dis- THE ESSENCE OF GOD 117 tinguished by something necessarily connected with self-éxistence? No; for what is necessarily connected with self-existence belongs to all self-existent things and is not conceivably a mark of distinction among them. Could they be distinguished by some charac­ teristic which does not necessarily belong to self­ existence? No; for such a characteristic would be an accidental thing (or an accident, as philosophers say), and there cannot be anything accidental in a being which is not subject to causes ; and no selfexistent being is conceivably subject to causes; it cannot be affected by accidents at all. We are driven to conclude that the apparent plurality of selfexistent Beings is only apparent ; that in reality there can be but one Self-existent Being. This must be the First and the Necessary Being, or God. There­ fore, God is one. Therefore, God is unique. St. Thomas Aquinas puts the argument in this way, “If Socrates were this man by the same thing " that makes him a man, there could not be a plurality of men any more than there can be a plurality of Socrates. But God is His nature. That whereby God is God, is that whereby God is this God. And hence it is impossible that there should be more than one God.” The unity of God is quite simply and directly proved by the fact that He is infinite and by the fact that He is absolutely simple. We do not offer these proofs here for we have not yet established n8 THEODICY the infinity and simplicity of God. But we shall presently set forth these truths, and then we shall hark back to the present consideration, noticing how the unity of God is inescapably proved in the perfec­ tions mentioned. \ fl·, '. The Simplicity of God. By the term simple we mean indivisible. A simple thing has no parts, and hence it cannot be divided into parts. Contrasted with a simple thing is a composite or compound thing; such a thing has parts, and can be distin­ guished, and often physically divided, into its parts. Some creatures are physically simple ; such, for in­ stance, is the human soul; such also is any substan­ tial form of any substance. But creatures all admit a metaphysical composition, inasmuch as they are essences which have received existence, they are sub­ sistent things in certain respective orders of nature, and so we say they are compounded of essence and existence and of subsistence and nature. Moreover, all creatures are compounds of potentiality and ac­ tuality, for they are actualizations of what could be, and they are subject to (substantial or accidental) change, and thus they are (actually) what they are, and they are (potentially) what they can become. Further, there is in creatures a logical composition inasmuch as they can be classified by the mind in groups, classes, kinds, marked by generic and specific differences ; in this sense the essence man is seen by THE ESSENCE OF GOD ? the mind to be "composed” or "compounded” of the genus animal and the specific difference rational. Now, when we say that God is simple we mean that there is in God no composition, no compounding, no putting together of elements or parts ; and we assert that from God all composition is excluded, physical, metaphysical, logical. Although, as we shall see, the mind does make distinctions in God, and we speak of different and distinct attributes and perfections of God; and, although the mind has some ground and justification for such distinction, the mind, nevertheless, does not consider God in any sense as a composite of all these perfections, but always re­ minds itself of the fact that in God all perfections are identified in the absolutely simple unity of the one and indivisible Divine Essence. God is the First and the Necessary Being. Now, such a Being cannot conceivably be compounded or composed. The First Being cannot be a composite being, for any compounding requires a cause that is prior to the being compounded, that is, a cause which brings the elements into union. And the Neces­ sary Being cannot be a composite being, for a com­ posite being is contingent upon the union of its parts or elements ; and contingency is the flat contradictory of necessity. So much for a general proof. We may profitably say a brief word to show that the various types of composition are necessarily excluded from God. 120 THEODICY In God there is no physical composition. For physical composition means the putting together of literal parts, that is to say, of parts of which some at least are bodily parts, and the whole composite resulting is a body. But God is not bodily. For a body is always a thing that is subject to movement by something not itself, whereas, as we have dis­ tinctly proved, God is the First Mover Himself Un­ moved. ,χζ&) In God there is no metaphysical composition. God is the First and Necessary Being, and is there­ fore self-existent, that is, He exists by His essence ; existence and essence in such a Being must be ab­ solutely identified. Further, God is Pure Actuality, for the First Being owes nothing to causes and can­ not be affected by causes, that is, cannot become or be actualized ; in a word, such a Being has no poten­ tiality in Itself, but is purely Actuality. Hence, God is not a compound of essence and existence, of ac­ tuality and potentiality. In a word God is not meta­ physically compounded. In God there is no logical composition. For we have seen that God is one God and the only God, and this by a requirement of His Being and Essence. He is not, therefore, classified by the mind as a certain kind or a certain genus of reality, marked off by special difference from other realities of the same general kind. For the Divine Essence is the only thing of its kind; it is absolutely unique, and so is THE ESSENCE OF GOD 121 not subject to a literal classification by the mind. In God, therefore, there is no logical composition. God is thus seen by reason as a Being that is necessarily simple with complete and absolute (i. e., unqualified, unconditional) simplicity. But how does it happen, then, that we speak of God’s perfections as distinct realities? We speak of God’s unity, Ilis simplicity, Elis infinity, Ilis spirituality. Presently we shall speak of His power, Ilis immensity, His ubiquity, His knowledge, His will. In a word, we "ma^ëP’distinctions in God, and we ask how we may do so if God is wholly one and simple in Himself. The answer lies in the fact that the limited human mind cannot deal with the unlimited Divine Essence except by taking aspects and views suited to its own limited nature. The mind can obtain knowledge of God, granted that this knowledge is never adequate ; and it must do this in its own way according to the old axiom, quidquid accipitur ad modum accipientis accipitur, “Whatever is taken in, is accepted accord­ ing to the capacities of the receiver.” Well, then, are the distinctions we make in God purely rational or purely logical distinctions? That is, are they distinc­ tions which have no foundation outside the mind, but are invented, so to speak, by the mind itself to enable it to deal in some fashion with the object considered? No; the distinctions we make in God are indeed rational or logical; they are not real dis­ tinctions, that is, they are not distinctions on the II Illi HIT ii I 122 li 1 THEODICY part of the divine Reality considered; we have just seen that there are no real distinctions in God (ex­ cept, of course, that one real distinction of Rersoas, with which theodicy has no concern). But the mind has some basis in reality for its distinctions in God. For, granted that all the perfections of God are one with His undivided Essence in the most perfect identity, the human mind which apprehends these perfections and this Essence has its direct and proper experience with limited things which, in point of power, knowledge, will, and so on, present really distinct aspects to its view. In a creature, power is really distinct from knowledge, mercy is really dis­ tinct from justice; unity is really distinct from will. And, while the perfections of creatures are referred to God, partly in a figurative or analogical way, and partly in a formal but transcendent way, it is these perfections of creatures that give the mind its basis for making distinctions in God. Therefore, the mind has not a literal and perfect foundation for such distinctions, nor is it without foundation altogether ; it is said to have an imperfect foundation in reality for the distinctions it draws in the one indivisible God. From .the; simplicity of God[ it follows, that. God is per fectly’completein .HimselL. ,H e is not conceivably the part of something else. For God, the First Cause of all things cannot be iden- THE ESSENCE OF GOD J23 lifted with the effects which He produces; the effi­ cient cause is always essentially distinct from its effect, and God is the Efficient Cause of all positive reality. Further, if God were to enter into composi­ tion with any creature as its part, He would have to do this as its matter or its form. But God is not matter, for matter is potential and God is Pure Actuality/ Nor can God be the form of anything, for such a form is shared or participated unto the in-formed and completed reality of which it is a part, and as such, that is, as a part, it is subsequent to what it is in its own distinct essence. But God is not subsequent to anything ; He is absolutely and perfectly the First Being. Further, the form of any­ thing, coming into union with matter to constitute the thing, actualizes its own potentiality; but God is in no sense potential, but is Pure Actuality. Hence God cannot be part of anything else. He cannot be the “soul of the world” as the Stoics thought; He cannot be spread out or manifested “in parts” as the pantheists think ; He cannot be identified with the creatural world as a whole (for the world is not simple) nor as its part. The simplicity of God is a cogent proof of His unity.. For that which is simple is manifestly one in itself. And if the simple being is also the First and the Necessary. Being, it follows that it cannot be. a plurality, but is one and tinique. !24 THEODICY j. The Infinity of God. The term infinity, with its adjective infinite, comes from the Latin in, a nega­ tive particle, and finis “end,” “boundary,” “limit.” Thus the literal meaning of infinity is “boundlcssnessT”’ fruhlimitcdncss.” When we say that Cod is infinite, we mean that there is, and can be, no limit or boundary to His being or His perfections. And, since God is simple, His infinite perfections are not parts or elements of Elis Divine Essence, or qualities which that Essence enjoys, but they are identified, in measureless degree, with the Divine Essence Itself. The First and Necessary Being must be infinite. For limitation always involves a cause of limitation, and there is no cause that can exercise causal limit­ ing action upon that which is absolutely first and therefore prior to every cause of every kind. One might be tempted to say, “A limitation means a lack, and a lack does not require a truly efficient cause, but is a deficiency.” But such a limitation as we here consider is not a mere lack, but a positive imposition of boundaries. And such a limitation certainly does require a true efficient cause. ConsidêFYhF poifif from this angle : When any­ thing is given, it is given in a certain measure, for that which is capable of transference by gift is not infinite or, at least, cannot be infinitely imparted. If a man gives his boy ten dollars he gives so much; but he also, quite as definitely, gives no more. What is given is necessarily finite. But the truth goes THE ESSENCE OF GOD 125 farther than this. What is not given,—and we mean, of course, actuality winch is not given,—is necessarily infinite. For perfection (i. e., actuality ) which is unr_eceivgd, ungiven, has about it nothing that could limit it. An unmixed perfection contains in itself no requirement for limitation, and indeed no possibility of being, limited except under the action of limiting external causes. Now, the perfection of God is un­ given and unreceived; it is perfection in the highest, purest, unmixed sense; it is perfection not subject to causal action since it is identified in the simple and first Actuality with the Divine Essence of that Actuality. Nothing conceivable, then, could limit it; it"ïffffêt, of necessity, be infinite. There is ever a tendency on the part of proud and impatient minds to dismiss as impossible what is found to be unimaginable. The imagination cannot adequately picture infinity, and hence there is a temptation in certain minds to say that infinity is either impossible or unknowable. But, it may justly be retorted, the mind can understand infinity, can know what it means, even though the imagination is powerless to picture it adequately. The imagination cannot picture the object of any idea adequately, even the object of the most finite or least universal of ideas. But this does not hinder the mind from knowing that object. The imagination is ever a great help to the mind, offering its images in illustration and analogy w’hen they are not available as more 1 126 THEODICY direct expressions of the meaning of the mind’s ideas and thoughts ; and indeed the mind arises to its concepts from the images of the imagination which reflect the findings of the other senses. The imagina­ tion is tireless in its presentation of images; it fur­ nishes endless illustrations. And, as a man, studying the copious printed pictures which accompany a sci­ entific treatise, may learn from them something of the nature and trend of the treatise itself, though he be unable to understand its terms, so may the mind (even more surely and powerfully) come to the knowledge of the realities which imagination most imperfectly suggests. For the rest, if imagination cannot adequately picture infinity, neither can it ade­ quately picture an actuality which is first and yet not infinite. The mind inevitably reaches out and infers infinity; it affirms infinity; and this is true of the mind of the doubter and the atheist as surely as it is true of the mind that stands. Jq Tact-and to . faith. To the one, infinity is doubtful, but the region of the dubious stretches away endlessly unto the very infinity that is doubted; to the second, infinity is denied, but an infinite nothingness remains. Those that complain of the limitations of the imagination, and base their doubts or denials of infinity upon that limitation, are most unreasonably trying to make the imagination something other than it is; they are trying to make it in all respects the equal of the mind or intellect itself, whereas it is, by its nature, THE ESSENCE- OF GOD 127 on a lower plane, and is meant as a means by which a man mounts upward to the region of intellectual knowledge. No man complains that his eyes cannot take in all the world at one glance, nor docs he de­ clare world-travel impossible because he does not clearly see at the outset all possible paths that his eager feet may follow. In his own way, man cer­ tainly can know, and indeed must know, what in­ finity means; man can know, and inevitably does know, that the absolutely first actuality must be in­ finite. Human knowledge of infinity, like human knowledge of anything, is necessarily finite and not fully comprehensive; but it may be true knowledge as far as it goes. Therefore, it is a foolish and futile objection to infinity that finds it inadmissible on the grounds of limitations in a necessarily limited hu­ man faculty. The infinity of the First and Necessary Being is a compelling proof of the unity of that Being. Per­ haps the most forceful way of setting out that proof is that called the demonstratio per absurdum which is the indirect but inescapable evidence of the truth by reason of the impossible character of its contra­ dictory. Let us suppose then that there can be a plurality of infinite beings, at least two. We shall call these A and B. Both are infinite. How, then, will you distinguish one from the other? The minute you draw a line of distinction or of demarcation1 be­ tween them, you put a limit on both, and neither is 128 THEODICY infinite. Here you have the absurdity (which you cannot escape if infinity is pluralized) of two beings which are infinite and not infinite at one and the same time! Look at the same thing in a slightly dilferent way : The infinity called A has its own perfec­ tions in measureless degree, identified with its es­ sence. It is infinite, remember, and therefore no conceivable perfection is absent from it. Now, the infinity called B also has its own perfections in meas­ ureless degree, identified with its essence. B is in­ finite, and no conceivable perfection is absent from it. But if A’s perfection is its very own, it is absent from B, and B is not infinite. So too, B’s perfection belongs to B (not to A) and therefore A is not infinite. Again we come to the absurd and impossible conclusion that A and B are both infinite and not infinite. Manifestly, this cannot be. We can only conclude that a plurality of infinities is impossible. The infinite Being is necessarily one and only; It has unity and unicity. Further, the infinity of God is absolute proof of the simplicity of God. For no separate and distinct perfection can be infinite in its own sphere, since a plurality of infinite perfections is a plurality of in­ finities, which we have just shown to be impossible. God’s perfections are therefore identified; they are one. But God cannot be one in Being with one in­ finite perfection distinct. from. His Being, for here again would be a plurality of infinities. Therefore, ίί THE ESSENCE OF GOD 1.29 God, in Being (essence, existence, nature, substance) and in perfections must be absolutely one and in­ divisible, and all perfections must be one identical thing with the Divine Essence Itself. In a word, God must be absolutely simple. Thus we see how the fundamental perfections of God (called distinct perfections to suit our mode of understanding and of study, and distinct, in conse­ quence, by a rational or logical distinction, granted such distinction has a basis in reality) are proof one of the other. Here again, we see suggested the truth that any serious consideration of the human mind leads to and indicates God, if carried far enough. Take up what subject you will in the wide circle of human experience and you take up a point on a definite radius that inevitably leads direct to the In­ finite Centre of all. 4. The Spirituality of God. That God is a Spirit is already proved in the foregoing arguments. For God is simple, and no bodily actuality is simple. God is one and unique, and no bodily being is necessarily so. God is infinite, and a bodily being is, by defini­ tion, mensurable (at least internally, as philosophers put it) and is so limited. Therefore, God is not bodily. But, you may say, granted that 1 le is not bodily, it need not follow that He is a Spirit. There are creatures (like any minor substantial form; say, for example, a plant-soul) that are simple but not Ï30 THEODICY spiritual. True, but such simple creatures are not χ also unique and infinite ; they are ever dependent for ^existence and operation upon other and, indeed. bodily things. But God is Pure Actuality, completely pelf-sufficing, completely self-existent, entirely necesysary. Such a Being has no dependencies, but must / exist in a supersubstantial way in Its own right. / And a being that exists in its own right is either a ( body or a spirit. But, as we have seen, God is not Xa body. God, therefore, is a Spirit. c) THE PHYSICAL ESSENCE OF GOD The physical essence of any actuality is, as we have seen, the sum-total of the perfections that con­ stitute it. Now, the sum-total of the perfections that, so to speak, constitute God in His own proper Being independently of the view of the mind, are the per­ fections we have just considered: unity, uniqueness, simplicity, infinity, spirituality. These perfections, in boundless and essential identity, constitute the physi­ cal essence of God| We may put them all briefly in the little formula we once learned fTomTour cate­ chism, and declare that, declare that the actual understanding of God is His xqetaphysical essence, ί 4. Other Thomists declare that God’s metaphysi­ cal essence is discerned in the fact that lie exists necessarily of Himself. The phrase “of Himself” is, in Latin, a se, and the doctrine here mentioned is expressed in the coined term aseity, which might be literally, if awkwardly, translated into “of Himselfness.” In a word, the fact that God exists of Himself, without cause, necessarily, independently, self-sufficiently, is the fact that the mind lays Hold of in getting a root-grasp of what the term "God means. 5. Most Thomists (and these insist that their doctrine is that of St. Thomas himself) declare that the metaphysical essence of God consists in the fact that He is Subsistent Being Itself. A being is sub­ sistent when it is complete and substantial and ex­ isting and autonomous. All finite substances which subsist do so in virtue of their constituting and sup­ porting causes. But God has no such causes. He sub- 136 THEODICY sists Himself, causelessly, necessarily ; and since He does not have subsistence, but His subsistence (like every perfection predicable of Him) is one with His essence, He is Subsistent Being Itself, Ipsum Esse Subsistens. In this, it is claimed, consists the root­ point of realizing what God really is. Omitting the Nominalist theory (for it is inad­ missible on epistemological grounds) we may sum up the other doctrines thus : God’s metaphysical es­ sence is found in one of these four perfections : radi­ cal infinity, radical or actual comprehension of all knowables, aseity, self-subsistence. b) THE TRUE METAPHYSICAL ESSENCE OF GOD I. It seems that radical infinity is ineptly proposed as the metaphysical essence of God. For to our minds infinity first suggests the way in which God exists rather than God Himself. Of course, we realize upon reflection that God’s infinity is abso­ lutely identified with Himself. But the present quest is for that note in the idea of God which, first and foremost, puts the Divine Essence before the view of our understanding in so far as this may be done at all. And, we repeat, to say that a thing is infinite seems to be saying something about a thing already there, already grasped. Such a note or predication of the mind is made in the second place after the grasp of the essence is made in the first place. For we conceive of a thing as existing (or, more accurately THE ESSENCE OF GOD 137 in the present case, as subsisting, that is, existing as a complete, autonomous, substance) before we con­ ceive it as existing in infinity; we conceive it to be before we conceive it to be infinite. For tin’s reason we do not favor the view of those who declare that God’s metaphysical essence is discerned in 11 is radi­ cal infinity. 2. For the same reason we find unacceptable the doctrine that God’s metaphysical essence is found in His infinite understanding or boundless comprehen­ sion of all knowables. If this means the actual com­ prehension of all things by Almighty God, it suggests an operation of the Divine Essence ; and, of course, an operation presupposes an operator; the idea of an operation is not the first or fundamental note, but the secondary note, in our knowledge of an existing and operating being. And if the doctrine means the radical comprehension or understanding of God (that is, the understanding considered, not as an operation exercised, but in itself, so to speak, as a capacity') then it suggests a power or a faculty, which, to our way of understanding, presupposes the existence of one that has the power or faculty. Again, the idea of God as the all-comprehending (whether as actually or radically comprehending) is not the first and fundamental note in our knowledge of God, but is secondary to, and consequent upon, our knowledge of God as subsisting. 138 THEODICY 3. Is God’s metaphysical essence discerned in the fact that He is Ens a se, that is, a Being who is of Himself ? In other words, is God’s metaphysical es­ sence found in His aseity? Well, to give an un­ qualified “Yes” as the answer, might be misleading. For the implication of the phrase “of Himself’ is “not of another.” That is, to declare that God exists or subsists of Himself stresses the truth that He is not dependent upon any cause, but is self-sufficient and self-explanatory because He is Necessary Being. But the implication that God is not ens ab alio (that is, a being dependent on its causes) is not pertinent to the first and basic grasp of the Divine Essence by our minds. That God is is grasped first, and then comes the realization that He is independently of causes. To put the point in another way: if you say the fact that God exists of Himself is the first and basic fact our minds grasp in knowing God, it may be asked, “Why does the mind so grasp Him?” In other words, a question is possible which delves be­ low, or back of, what you propose as the first and deepest note in the knowledge we have of God. The answer to the question seems to disclose bed-rock. For the answer is, “We know God is Ens a se, we know He exists of Himself, because He is Self­ subsistent Being Itself. 4- We therefore favor as the most adequate expression of the true metaphysical essence of God, BMawmiw THE ESSENCE OF GOD J .39· the doctrine which reposes this essence in the fact that God is Self-subsistent Being Itself. If it be said by the defenders of the aseity-doctrine, ‘'Well, that's what our doctrine means ; we assert radical aseity,” we can only reply with much happiness thcit then we are in perfect agreement with them. The fact of God’s self-subsistence, therefore, or, if you prefer, the fact of God’s radical aseity. is the First and the fundamental note in our mind’s grasp of the Divine Essence. It is the metaphysical essence of God. And God Himself gave to Moses His true and most penetratingly expressive name when He said, “I am Who am . . . thus shalt thou say to the children of Israel: He Who is hath sent me to you” {Exodus Hi, 14). By way of positive argument for the doctrine here proposed as true, we may consider the follow­ ing points : The metaphysical essence of anything is that real­ ity in the thing which, first and foremost, makes it understandable to the mind, and explains to the mind the properties that must be attributed to it. Now, the fact that God is Subsistent Being Itself {Ipsum Esse Subsistens) is that reality in God which makes God understandable and explains the properties or perfections that must be attributed to God. For the actuality of God, the fact that God is Himself there, is our answer to the most penetrat- !4o THEODICY ing questions about Him, such as why He is the First Cause, why He is the Necessary Being, why He is infinitely perfect, why He is simple or uncompounded, why hie is necessarily one. And the implications of that boundless and independent actu­ ality of God are brought out by the questions, and thus that actuality explains the Divine Perfections. But this actuality of God is neither more nor less than His subsistence and His self-subsistence. Therefore, the metaphysical essence of God consists in His self-subsistence, that is, in the fact that He is Self-subsistent Being Itself. God is Pure Actuality. The phrase Pure Actual­ ity or Actus Purus is recognized among philos­ ophers as the true metaphysical definition of God. Now, a true metaphysical definition expresses the true metaphysical essence of the thing defined. But Pitre Actuality means Self-subsistence. A thing is actual when it exists; it is purely actual when it has no potentialities or dependencies about it, but is self-existent ; and its self-existence must be more than the existence of some accidental thing, it must be the existence of that which is a substance in the completest and most perfect sense ; in other words, this self-existence must be self-subsistence. Hence, God’s metaphysical essence consists in the fact that He is Self-subsistent Being Itself. The concept of Pure Actuality is the concept of Self-subsistent Actuality, and the latter phrase is more clear to the THE ESSENCE OF GOD 141 mind than the former. Hence, once more we assert, that the true metaphysical essence of God is found in His Self-subsistence. That which first distinguishes God from all other things is the fact that I lis existence is not an im­ parted existence; it is not something given and re­ ceived, as it always is with things other than God. Now, the mind may not advert, and does not ad­ vert, first and foremost to the distinguishing fea­ tures of a reality, but first sees the reality and then notes its background or distinctions more carefully. But the metaphysical essence of a thing must serve the mind in both these functions: it must present the reality in its root being, and it must serve to explain the distinction of that reality from other things. Merely to distinguish it would not be enough; that is why we reject the theory of actual aseity as the metaphysical essence of God. But we accept, as synonymous with our own doctrine, the theory of radical aseity. For this grasp of God in radical aseity or in the fact that He is Self-subsistent Being Itself is at once the direct and primal grasp of the Di vine Essence by the human mind, and the fundamental, root of . the distinction of. God from "all other things. Again we declare that the true metaphysical essence of God consists in the fact that He is Ipsum 'Esse Subsisfèlif·. That God’s Self-subsistence is the root of all the other Divine Perfections is manifest. St, Thomas 142 THEODICY Aquinas says, “Being taken simply as including every existible perfection, is preeminent above all the individual perfections, such as life, which belong to and follow from it.” And our doctrine ascribes to Cod “Being taken simply as including every- cxistiblc perfection,” for that is what is meant by Subsistent Being Itself. SUMMARY OF THE ARTICLE In this Article we have reviewed our definition (or description) of metaphysical essence. We have set forth very brieffy the five most notable doctrines about the metaphysical essence of God. We have in­ vestigated these doctrines thoroughly, and have found that the most acceptable of them is the more common Thomistic doctrine that the metaphysical essence of God is found in the fact that He is Sub­ sistent Being Itself. CHAPTER II THE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD This Chapter studies the perfections of God which we know must be present in Him, and of Him, by reason of His metaphysical essence. These are the perfections that belong to God by natural necessity. Now, what belongs to a reality by natural necessity is an attribute or a property of that reality. And so we speak here of the proper per­ fections or the attributes of God. Still, the term attribute is used here in an analogous, and not in a literal, sense. For the literal meaning of attribute is a perfection that belongs to an essence, but is not one with that essence ; it is not a substantial thing, but an accidental one in its being, how­ ever necessary be its connection with the essence or the substance to which it is ascribed. In God, however, the perfections called attributes are really one wdth the Divine Essence Itself and wholly inseparable from it ; they are the identical supersubstance that God Himself is ; they are in no wise accidents in God (there can be nothing accidental in Pure Actuality) ; they are God Himself. Keeping this in mind,—and realizing that, while we have good grounds in creatures for making a distinction in God between Himself and His perfections, and among the several perfections themselves, the distinction is, after all, a mental or logical one, and not a real distinction,—we discuss the Divine At­ tributes in two Articles, as follows : Article i. The Divine Attributes in General Article 2. The Divine Attributes in Special M3 144 THEODICY Article i. The Divine Attributes in­ General a) Meaning of Divine Attributes b) Classification of Divine Attributes a) MEANING OF DIVINE ATTRIBUTES By the Divine Attributes we mean those perfec­ tions that, in our limited understanding, must be predicated of God as though they were distinct qualities which, by natural necessity, follow from and characterize the Divine Essence Itself. An attribute is something that must be attributed to a nature because that nature demands it. For ex­ ample, the attribute of infallibility follows from the nature of the Church. For the Church is a divine institution, a work of God Himself, and, in its founding He declared that it was to speak in His name and to lead men to God. Now, such being its nature, how can it conceivably lead men astray? In other words, how can it be denied that this divinely founded and dowered institution is infallible ? The fact of infallibility follows from and attends upon the nature of the Church. Precisely because the Church is the essential thing that it is, it must be infallible. Therefore, by a necessity of its nature (i. e., by natural necessity) the Church must be infallible. And so we say that infallibility is an at­ tribute of the Church. Take another example. We say that the actual exercise of reason (that is, the assa THE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD 145 function of thinking things out. of drawing con­ clusions, of recognizing that two and two make four) is an attribute of man. For, when man's na­ ture is ftilly constituted, and when no element of it is lacking, and when its operations are uuthwarted by immaturity, unconsciousness, disease, man will, —because he is of the nature that he is,—inevitably use his reasoning power. Such a use follows by nat­ ural necessity upon the fully constituted and opera­ tive essence (i. e., the nature} of man. The act of reasoning, or the ability to exercise that act, is there­ fore an attribute of man. The examples show us plainly that in creatures an attribute is something that follows from, and attends upon, the rounded and operative essence of a reality, but is, in itself, an accidental thing, not to be identified with the es­ sence to which it belongs. The Church, for example, is not its infallibility; the Church has infallibility. Nor is man his power to reason ; man has the power to reason. That man be rational (i. e., radically equipped to come to the use of reason) is of his es­ sence, and man is defined as a rational animal ; but man is not necessarily a reasoning animal ; he may not come to the use of that for which he is radi­ cally or fundamentally equipped. The actual use of reason is something that a man has, not something that a man is. But it is something that he has by natural necessity, that is, it is something that neces­ sarily follows, attends upon, and characterizes man’s 146 ί THEODICY nature, when this nature is fully developed and un­ thwarted in any way. Thus we see that an attribute, in proper sense, is something that is really distinct from the essence, nature, substance, to which it is ascribed. And here we notice again that attributes cannot be predicated of God in strict sense, but only in an analogical sense, for all that God has He A, since He is Pure and Simple Actuality. There is in God no real distinction except the real distinc­ tion of the Three Persons of which we have no right to speak in philosophy beyond the mention ol the fact that philosophy finds in such distinction no contradiction of its own facts and principles. Now, an attribute is not only something that belongs to, and attends upon, a rounded and fully con­ stituted essence. It is also something that characicrizesjhat essence?" If maries the'essence as this essence and no other. It is proper Jo this essence, and to this essence alone. Therefore, an attribute is often called a property. The term propertyy derives from the Latin proprius which means “one’s own.” Hence, the attribute of infallibility belongs to the Church alone among all institutions found on the earth; it marks it ; it points it out ; it is its sign and seal and “trade mark” and stamp of identification. So too the ability to use reason is a true property of man. There are other rational beings than man, for every spirit is rational, be it angel or devil, and God is THE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD 147 rationality itself. But the term rational means pos­ sessed of (or, in case of God, identified with) un­ derstanding and will. It docs not necessarily mean the power, and the limitation, involved in the process of thinking things out. God knows all things per­ fectly and eternally in His own essence; angels (and devils, who are fallen angels) know all they can know in an instantaneous grasp of mind, and have no need for the laborious mental process of working out an understandable truth by successive steps. No. man alone among rational beings has the need and the ability to use reason so, and this use is therefore an index of man, a characteristic and mark of iden­ tification ; it belongs to man and to no other ; it is a property of man. Attribute and property are syn­ onymous terms, jet there is this shade of distinc­ tion between them : the term attribute suggests what must be attributed to a reality by natural necessity ; the term property indicates the ground for this necessity of attribution inasmuch as that which must be attributed to a reality belongs to this reality as its very own and is ascribable, in the exact and strict sense of the attribution, to this one reality and to no other. From all this we learn that the proper­ ties (or attributes') of an essence are revealing things; they are the source of our accurate knowl­ edge of essences. For “Handsome is as handsome does”; “Actions speak”; “as a thing is so it acts,— i48 THEODICY that is, so it shows itself in its operative properties”; “Agere sequitur esse—function follows essence”; “By their fruits you shall know them.” To sum up. An attribute or a property is a per­ fection which necessarily belongs to an essence when that essence is fully constituted and unhampered; it is a mark and an indicator of that essence. In finite things, attributes or properties are, in themselves, non-substantial ; they are of the order of accidents or accidentals; they mark and qualify substances. But in the one Pure and Simple Actuality attributes are phases of an undivided Infinite Essence, phases which the limited human mind must take to appre­ hend the Divine Essence at all, and phases which in­ dicate no real distinction in God, but only a rational or logical distinction grounded upon the nature of the finite mind and upon its experience with creatural reality; a distinction, in short, which is logical with a foundation (an imperfect one) in reality. We have already studied some of the Divine At­ tributes. In our investigation of the Divine Essence we had to approach the subject by way of certain fundamental perfections, and all perfections, in pur­ est sense, are attributes of God, and properties of God too, since they are ascribable to Him infinitely and of His Essence and are not so ascribable to any other reality than God. So we learned about God’s unity and unicity, His simplicity, His infinity, His THE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD ■b ;v' 149 spirituality. These are attributes of God. These are properties of God. These are Divine Perfections. To our minds, these (though identified among them­ selves, and identified with all the other perfections we are yet to consider, and identified with the one Divine Essence itself) arc basic or fundamental per­ fections; in a figurative sense, they are constitutive of the Divine Essence. In our present study we are to consider certain other perfections which follow from the constitution of the one, simple, infinite Spirit. . . . ........... ............. .. ^’^b) CLASSIFICATION OF DIVINE ATTRIBUTES The Divine Attributes are classified as absolute and relative; the absolute attributes are further classified as positive and negative. I. Absolute Divine Attributes are those which we consider in studying God in Himself, without bring­ ing into our consideration any reference to creatures that depend on God. The term absolute is from the Latin absolutus which means “loosed from,” “freed from,” “unconditioned.” So when we consider God as “loosed from” all relations which creatures have to Him, and study Elim in Himself alone, we are investigating the absolute perfections of God, that is, the absolute attributes. Such attributes are, for example, the infinity of God, His immutability or 150 THEODICY changelessness, His knowledge or wisdom. Absolute Divine Attributes are positive or negative. (a) Positive Divine Attributes are those which a ffirm a perfection as belonging by necessity to God, and identified with His Being and Essence. Such, for example, are the divine life, the divine will, the divine understanding. (&) Negative Divine Attributes are those which deny imperfections in God. Such, for example, are the divine infinity which denies limitation, the di­ vine simplicity which denies composition, the divine immutability which denies in God the slightest change or shadow of alteration. 2. Relative Divine Attributes are those which in­ volve the relation of creatures to God. Thus the perfection called providence,—that is, the perfection whereby God looks out for His creatures, and not­ ably His rational creatures on earth, seeing that all things work together for good,—is an attribute of God. Manifestly, this attribute implies creatures; it brings creatures “into the picture’’ ; it is a relative attribute. It is to be noticed that relative attributes in God are those that bring creatures into relation with Him; it is inaccurate to say that these at­ tributes bring God into relation to creatures. There is no real relation in God to creatures, but complete and perfect independence; but there is a real and essential relation to God on the part of creatures. THE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD SUMMARY 151 OF THE ARTICLE ' This brief Article has given us an accurate under­ standing of what is meant by the terms attribute and property in their strict and literal meaning as applicable to creatures, and in their analogical mean= ing as predicable of the Pure Actuality and Infinite ■ Simple Essence of God. We have shown that at­ tributes and properties are revealing things, and that ,Jtheir study leads to a knowledge of essences. There­ fore, in our present study about God, we approach /ito Him by way of Idis perfections or attributes. We have classified the Divine Attributes as absolute .and relative, and have seen that the absolute at, ..tributes are either positive or negative. Article 2. The Divine Attributes in Special a) Goodness b) Immensity c) Immutability d) Eternity a) goodness It is a truth manifested in ontology that every being is good. For good means desirable or appetizable, and every being, inasmuch as it is a being, can be the object of appetite or desire. Hence the mea­ sure of being is the measure of goodness, and, view­ ing the terms in their most abstract meaning, good and being are strict synonyms. It follows at once that the Infinite Being is the Infinite Good. i ÎIWIWMi 152 THEODICY In our proof for the existence of God, taken from the grades or degrees of perfection observable in the world, we developed the truth that the ex­ istence of good and bettor (that is, of a lesser or greater fulness of being) points inevitably to the existence of that which is absolutely best. For there is need of an absolute standard before there can be any degrees resulting from a closer or more remote approach to that standard. And we concluded our argument by establishing the existence of the su­ premely perfect and absolutely boundless Good, the Summum Bomim called God. God, therefore, is in­ finitely good; and, since His attributes are one with His essence, God is Infinite Goodness. When we speak of creatures, we make a distinc­ tion between goodness and perfection. Every being, as such, is good; but every being is not perfect. A being may lack some element, some essential or in­ tegral item, and in so far it is imperfect; but even an imperfect being is good as far as it goes, that is, as far as it has being. So the case stands with finite things. To prove a finite thing good is not to prove it perfect. Contrariwise, however, to prove a thing perfect is to prove it good. Hence, to prove God All Perfect is to prove Him the Infinite Good. But, indeed, the terms good and perfect are synonymous when used with reference to the Infinite Being, and whether we take up the point of goodness to estab­ lish the Divine Perfection, or take up the point of THE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD i53 h \ perfection to prove the Divine Goodness, we arc following a fully justified mode of procedure. Here we choose to establish the Divine Goodness by showing that God is the All Perfect. God is Pure Actuality. This point we have men­ tioned repeatedly and have demonstrated more than once. Recall here, that the first actuality can have nothing whatever about it that has been received; for no receiver is first; the giver is prior to the re­ ceiver. All, therefore, that the first being has belongs to its own essence and is not ascribable to any causes. In other words, the first being stands selfsufficient and self-explaining and self-justifying to reason. It is a necessary being. Now, a necessary being is not conceivably subject to development or change, for such processes alwrays result from the action of causes upon the being affected by develop­ ment or change; and the first being, the necessary being, is in no wise subject to causes. Hence there is in the first being no potentiality, no possibilities to be realized, no capacities to be filled up or filled out, no limitations to be extended. But that which is not potential is actual. In our concept of the first being there can be no note except the actual. Such a being is purely and entirely and unmixedly actual. And, since such a being is also, and necessarily, simple, its actuality is identified with its essence. Therefore, God, the First and the Necessary, and the Simple Being, is Pure Actuality. Now, the word ■! 1 ' ‘ j j J 1 l·, ί > ! - i ’ ! : j j fi > J. 15+ THEODICY potentiality is synonymous with imperfection. A thing is said to have potentiality inasmuch as it has about it some capacity not yet filled out, some pos­ sibility not yet actualized; in a word, it lack's some­ thing, and is in so far imperfect. But Cod has about Him absolutely no potentiality; therefore, lie has no lack; therefore, He has no imperfection what­ ever; He is the Pure Actuality and by that token 1 le is Pure Perfection. God therefore is purely or boundlessly perfect; He is All Perfect. And this is saying that Pie is Infinite Goodness. In casual speech the term good often suggests kindness, consideration, devotion, thoughtfulness for others. Thus we say that a devoted mother is a “good mother,” or that a kind person is “very good to everybody.” Now, when we speak of the absolute goodness of God, all that is fine and perfect about this common colloquial meaning of good is included in our use of the term, but this is not the special point of the present consideration. This rather be­ longs to the study which we shall make later in its proper place, the study of the perfection of the Di­ vine Will and, in special, of that Will as expressed in Divine Providence. Here we take a more abstract view of the matter, considering goodness rather as an absolute perfection than a relative perfection in God, that is, as a perfection which reveals God in His own Being rather than one which reveals Him in His dealings with creatures. âSSH aSgàss iaaagi THE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD 155 Let us take just one more compelling argument to show that God is the All Perfect or the All Good in Himself. God is the first cause of all things. Now, what­ ever of perfection is found in any effect must be found in the cause that produced that effect, either in the same way (if the cause be univocal, that is, if the cause be of the same nature as the effect, as it is, for example, in the case of living creatures re­ garded as the causes of their offspring) or in a su­ perior way (if the cause be analogical, as it is, for example, in the case of the sculptor causing the ‘ statue to exist as an image). Hence, all the perfec­ tions of creatures must be found in the cause of all creatures, that is, in God. And, since God is not the univocal but the analogical cause of creatures, these perfections must be found in Him in a way superior to that in which they are found in creatures. St. Thomas Aquinas puts the point thus, “It is evident that an effect preëxists in the power of the cause that can produce it; and such preexistence is not of a lower but of a more perfect order as a mode of existence. Since, then, God is the first cause of all things, it follows that in Him the perfections of all things (existible) are present in an eminent way.” Now, “the perfections of all things existible” is a phrase that might be formulated as “all possible per­ fections.” But if all possible perfections are present in the First Cause, and in an eminently superior THEODICY 156 manner, then the First Cause is simply /XII Perfect. Therefore, God is the All Perfect. Therefore, God is the All Good. In a word, God is Infinite Goodness. b) . Bi 1e IMMENSITY — The term immensity is from Latin, and literally means mcasurelessness. Λ thing is immense when it cannot be measured, confined, estimated, quantified. As a Divine Attribute immensity may be defined as “A perfection whereby the Divine Substance is en­ abled to be present in all things and in all places with­ out being limited or measured by them.” Immensity is not the attribute whereby God is in all things and everywhere. This is His ubiquity or actual omni­ presence. Immensity is rather God's radical omni­ presence. It is viewed by our minds as God’s pozver to be everywhere, whereas ubiquity is the fact of .plod’s being everywhere. We notice here the marked inadequacy of human speech to deal with the Infinite. We speak of the attribute of immensity as that by which God is “en­ abled” to be present everywhere, and we are forced by reason to make a mental apology for the term even as we use it. We know, of course, what is meant, yet words do not adequately serve to ex­ press what is meant. That is why we say that God is ineffable or “inexpressible in speech.” Our lan­ guage only approaches accuracy when dealing with the Infinite Being; it is what priggish people like to ΓψΗΕ ATTRIBUTES OF GOD ‘ 157 call “asymptotic,” meaning that it comes near what is meant but never quite reaches perfect expression. Well, we do what we can, and keep reminding our­ selves of the limitations of speech, and indeed of thought, and ever and anon we say to ourselves, “Do not forget that all that God has He is; the Di­ vine Attributes are one with the Divine Essence.” If a person asks, “Where is God?” we have our answer ready, for we know our little catechism, and we say, “God is everywhere.” If the inquirer says, “Is God in this room?” we answer, “Yes.” If he says, “Is God in me?” or “Is God in that tree?” we answer, “Yes.” But God is not in things in such wise that the things limit, or measure or confine Him, And this suggests that we review our knowledge of how a thing may be in a place. A thing is said to be in a place circumscriptivcly when its own dimensions are co-dimensional with those of a surrounding body. A baseball flying through the air is, at any given moment, completely surrounded by a perfectly fitting pocket of atmos­ phere, the inner concave surface of which meets at all points the outer convex surface of the ball, and determines its proper external place in the air. This is circumscriptive presence, location, or ubication. The term comes from the Latin circumscriptum “written around,” for the containing body (in our example, the air) is drawn around the located body somewhat as a line is drawn or written around a Ip THEODICY coin laid flat on a piece of paper. Circumscriptive presence or location depends upon the external mea­ sures or dimensions of a body perfectly meeting the enveloping surface of a containing body. W’c say external dimensions, for a body has also ils internal extension, and this may best be viewed as the body­ mass contained within its own dimensions as within a film or skin. Wherever the body is, as long as it remains the same body with the same quantity, its internal extension is the same, and its “location” in this internal sense is immovable. Thus the in­ ternal extension and location of the baseball is ever the same, though its outer or external location is changing at each successive moment of its flight. Now, God is not in things circïimscriptively. Such a presence is manifestly a bodily presence, a presence by outer material dimensions, and God is, as we have seen, the Infinite Spirit. Besides, circumscrip­ tive presence is a limiting and determining thing, and God is not limited nor determined by Elis crea­ tures. For any determination is an actualization of potentiality and God is Pure Actuality. Now, a thing may be placed or located or present informatively. This mode of presence is verified when the located reality is a determining factor, a determinant, a form. Thus the substantial form of any body is in the body. Thus the human soul (which is the substantial form of the living human body) is in a man. Thus beauty of feature is in the THE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD 159 beautiful face. Thus the hardness of marble is in the marble. These forms (substantial or accidental) are said to be in the bodies which they determine, establish, or characterize, but it is manifest that they arc not present according to measurements and dimensions. A man’s soul, or his strength, or his appearance, is not in the man in the sense in which the ball is in the air, or a boat is in the water, or a root is in the ground. This is not circumscriptive presence, but informative presence, and the reality so present is said to in-form the thing that it de­ termines, marks, qualifies, limits, characterizes. Our casual use of the terms “inform” and “information” illustrate the root-meaning of the words ; for our knowledge of things in-forms the mind; it gives “shape,” so to speak, to our understanding; it is present in (or “located in”) our minds, not circumscriptively, which is absurd to say in the present case, but informatively. In a word, a thing is pres­ ent or is located informatively when it is a determi­ nant or form (substantial or accidental) affecting that in which it is said to be present or located. Manifestly, God is not in the world informatively. He is not the substantial form of the universe. The old Greek Stoics thought Fie was, and called God the soul of the world. Nor is God the accidental form or determinant of the world,—the shape of the world or its temperature or its appearance or any other item of its accidental determinate being. i: ζ6ο THEODICY For God is the supersubstance, the All Perfect and Self-subsistent Being; He is not the accident (i. e., accidental form) of anything. Thirdly, a thing may be placed or located or pres­ ent in another thing operatively, and it is so present when it exercises activity there. This may happen in such wise that the operating or active power (the thing located) is limited to one single substance, and then it is present operatively and definitively ; thus the soul is present in a man; thus the life-principle is present in a tree. Or the operating or active thing may be present to a plurality of things, spreading its power among them, and then it is present opera­ tively and extensively ; thus the sun is said to be present in all the places on earth that enjoy its light and its warming rays. Or a power may be present unlimitedly to all things, and then it is present opera­ tively and incircumscriptively. In this last named manner, God is present in the world and in every creature; He is present operatively, for all things depend upon Him as their producing and sustaining cause (their cause in being as well as their cause in becoming') and they discharge their connatural func­ tions only in virtue of their God-given equipment and by reason of God’s preserving and concurring action. God is present in all things operatively but incircnmscnptivcly, for He is in no wise measured, limited, or contained, by the universe or any item of it, while He sustains it in being and operation. '1. .η·..·.:·*.·, rf-f-gTr- THE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD 161 Thus God’s immensity means H is radical opera­ tive and incircttmscriplvvc presence everywhere and in all things. His actual operative and incircumscripive presence everywhere and in all things is I lis om­ nipresence or ubiquity. The proof of God’s immensity is drawn from IJ is infinity and from His boundless power. J. God possesses in an eminent degree, as an actu­ ality which is truly identified with His own Divine Essence, every pure perfection. Now, immensity is a pure perfection. For the definition of a pure perfec­ tion is that it involves in itself no limitation or lack or imperfection, and immensity is just such a per­ fection, consisting as it does, in the absence of all limitation. Therefore, God possesses this perfection in an eminent degree, as an actuality which is truly identified with His own Divine Essence. 2. God must be present wherever Fie exercises His power. But God exercises His power every­ where, giving to all things their being, and con­ serving them in existence. Hence God is present everywhere and in all things. For wherever God’s power is, there also is the Divine Essence, since the power of God is identified with His essence. Nor is the power of God in any way limited,—-for God is infinite,—and therefore God is not bounded or mea­ sured by actually existing realities in the world. 162 THEODICY Hence, it cannot be said that God is merely coexten­ sive with the universe. God is not only omnipresent in the sense that He is in every actual place and in every actual reality; l ie has true immcnsity whieh knows no limit or measure by reason of the creatural realities to which and in which God is present. ί There is, of course, a deep mystery in the omni­ presence of God. Our imagination is wholly incap­ able of picturing it, and for this reason it presents some difficulty to our grasp. But the fact of God's omnipresence is inevitable; reason not only allows it, but demands it. The limitations of imagination cannot dim the clarity of that outstanding truth. Nor can the imperfections of mind or the character of our human experience allege anything that avails in the least to weaken the certitude with which the truth is known. We know the truth, and we know why it is truth; to explain in last detail how the truth finds actual expression is beyond our best ef­ forts. Nor is this to be wondered at, since the finite mind cannot fully and adequately comprehend the Infinite. The point to remember is that the mind can and does apprehend the Infinite, that is, knows It with certitude as a fact, and knows about It much that lies within the capacity of the human grasp. Just as the eye cannot take in the whole earth at a glance, but sees that it is there, and takes in much that lies within the immediate range of vision ; just I THE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD 163 as the cup cannot take up the entire ocean, but is dipped into a sea that is unquestionably there, and takes up what its little capacity allows, so docs the mind view Infinity, so docs it take up of Infinity, always sure of Infinity Itself as an actual and an in­ evitable Fact. And the immensity and omnipresence of God are phases of Infinity that the mind acknowl­ edges, and indeed is forced to acknowledge, as fac­ tual; but to picture the immensity of God in imagina­ tion, or even to have a complete and adequate comprehension of it in intellect, is manifestly not to be expected of a creature of strictly and narrowly limited capacities. A thought has sometimes found expression in the form of an objection to God’s immensity, an objection which appeals to the Infinite Dignity as its grounds, and, like most specious objections which have a pious cast, it is very shallow. It amounts to this. There are things in the universe that the human mind and taste find unclean, foul, nasty. Can God be present in these things? If He is present everywhere He is certainly in everything, even in things that are repulsive to the sense of sight and of smell. But is there not some indignity in the thought of God’s presence in such things? Not in the least. St. Augustine remarks that the sunlight is not soiled because it sheds its glory upon fetid refuse. Nor is the Infinite soiled or tainted by His presence in 164 THEODICY such things. Remember God is not contained, con­ fined, restricted, limited, measured, by circumscriptive presence in any reality. For the rest, remember that all being, inasmuch as it is positive being or reality, is good, that is, transcendently or metaphysically good, regardless of what effect it may have upon human palates and noses. Because of our own limita­ tions, nay, because of our own original defilement, we have certain trials of sense and of taste to bear in this world ; but we must not ascribe our limita­ tions to the Almighty, nor think that what affects bodily things in their circumscriptive location can affect in like manner that Infinite who is present to them and in them incircumscriptively. Since God is present in all things and everywhere in an incircumscriptive manner, we must banish from our understanding of His immensity and om­ nipresence all notions of extended parts. God is not partly here and partly there. He is not to be con­ ceived in a bodily manner as a being of immense size. God has neither parts nor size. Such things are the mixed perfections of bodies, and God is Pure Perfection entirely unmixed. Wherever God is, He is wholly present; by Elis essence, by His power. St. Thomas says, “God is in all things by power inas­ much as all things are subject to His will and con­ trol ; He is present in all things by a true presence, inasmuch as all things are open and naked to His i THE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD 165 knowledge; He is present in all things by essence, inasmuch as He is the cause of their being.” c) IMMUTABILITY The literal meaning of the Latin derivative immutalibity is changclessncss. It is a negative term, for it denies something; it denies change or move­ ment or alteration in God. But the. term indicates a positive perfection, for its denial is directed against imperfection or potentiality and hence amounts to an affirmation of perfection or actuality. Here we see illustrated the manner of our progress towards a detailed knowledge of God. We learned long since that our procedure in acquiring such knowledge goes by three steps (after recogniz­ ing Primal Causality, as a preliminary step) called affirmation, denial, and excellence, or, to vary the ex­ pression, attribution, élimination, and transcendence. We affirm of God, or attribute to Him, all perfection ; we deny of God, or eliminate from our concept of Deity, all imperfection ; we predicate pure perfection of God in a manner more excellent, more tran­ scendent, than that which we employ in predicating perfection of creatures. In the present instance, when we declare God immutable, we discern the need of attributing to God a complete identity of Being and Activity; the need of eliminating from our con­ cept of God all change or movement ; the need of pre­ dicating changelessness of God in a truly transcendent | | | .. j '( j J i ’ ! i66 THEODICY way so that it does not convey the idea of mere fixity, which is a limitation, but suggests perfect freedom and boundless eternal action. Therefore, when we say that God is iininiilable, that is, when we assert Divine Immutability as iden­ tified with the Divine Essence Itself, we mean that God is in no wise subject to change; that Ik is in­ deed the Being “with Whom there is no change or shadow of alteration” ; that God is not thereby set in a frozen fixedness but is changelessly free and eternally active. Now, when a creature is called changeless, the predication indicates a mixed perfection, that is, a perfection mingled with imperfection. For, while there is perfection in endurance or duration, there is limitation and imperfection in a merely unvaried duration or fixity in being and activity. Of course, no creature is changeless in any absolute sense; but in a limited and relative sense some creatures are called so. Thus, the human soul is a changeless spirit­ ual substance. Thus, the unvaried opinion of a stub­ born man is a changeless accident. Thus, the more lasting bodily materials are metaphorically change­ less in the sense that change in them occurs very gradually, and that they last a long time. But, whether we speak of substances or accidents, crea­ tures are never changeless in the full and perfect sense of that term. And, when we come to consider THE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD 167 the Divine Changelessncss, we arc ali too likely to bring to our study the notion of the limitations that associate necessarily with what is called changeless­ ness among creatures. By reason of our whole hu­ man experience, our first mental reaction to the thought of changelessncss in God is very likely to be a mistaken one ; we are apt to think of His changelessness as a thing that freezes and fixes God, as a thing that limits Him. Yet we know, upon a moment's reflection, that this cannot be, since God is infinite and subject to no limitation at all. But first we shall look at the compelling proofs for Di­ vine Immutability ; then we shall notice certain mis­ taken thoughts about it which we must avoid for ourselves and correct in others. We shall see that God must be immutable because of His actuality, His simplicity, Elis infinity. r l I. Where there is change or movement (and movement is synonymous with change} there is manifestly the actualization of a potentiality. The thing changed is, to begin with, changeable. It has a capacity for change; and when the change occurs, this capacity is filled out, realized, actualized. Now, God is Pure Actuality. There is no conceivable capac­ ity in God; nothing in God can be regarded as not yet filled out. lienee, there is in God no possibility of change. God is immutable. 168 THEODICY 2. Where there is change, there is always some­ thing that undergoes the change; something which remains the same while the change takes place in it and transforms it in substance or in accidentals. But this means that a changeable reality is a compound of elements, namely, of the underlying thing that supports the change and of the shifting thing that is lost or gained in the change. In a word, a change­ able thing is not simple, but composite. But God is absolutely simple, as we have amply proved in an­ other place. Therefore God is not changeable. God is immutable. 5. Every change means both a loss and a gain. It means the loss of one state or condition and the gain or acquisition of a new state or condition. But there can be neither loss nor gain in God. For God is infinite; and an infinite Being has all perfection in boundless degree, and there is no perfection still to be gained ; and an infinite Being cannot lose any­ thing or it would cease instantly to be infinite, since the loss would mark a lack and a limitation. There­ fore, there can be no change in God. God is im­ mutable. When we say that God is immutable, we mean that Fie is entirely so. Ele is immutable in substance, For He is the Infinite Spirit and a spirit is not substantially changeable but is incorruptible ; be- THE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD 169 sides, God is the Necessary Being, and cannot con­ ceivably fade, diminish, fall away, corrupt. God is immutable in nature, that is, specifically, in under­ standing and in will. For God’s understanding em­ braces all truth changelessly and eternally; and God’s will is changeless, since a change of will is always consequent upon a change of substance or of knowl­ edge, and we have just seen that neither substance nor understanding is changeable in God. Now, it is here that a difficulty may arise in our imperfect minds. We are apt to think that if God’s will does not and cannot change, we are all the helpless victims of an iron destiny and free-will is an illusion. Or, even if we brush aside this basic difficulty, we are likely to think that our prayers of petition to God are valueless, since nothing can lead to a change in the Divine Will. Of course, these difficulties are mere seeming. They occur to us be­ cause, unconsciously, we attribute to God our own human limitations, and misunderstand Elis eternal immutability, making of it a mere fixity. We must remember that God is eternal and infinite. All things knowable are present to God’s knowledge, in fullest detail, from eternity. Hence, every circumstance that conies to our knowledge and bears upon our freechoice is fully known to God from eternity, and from eternity He decrees to concur with our free­ will and, indeed, from eternity He moves it to its free choice. Therefore free-will is not thwarted 170 THEODICY nor macle illusory by God’s changelcssncss. Further, God from eternity knows every possible petition that can ever be offered to Him, and, for those that are actually made, He has, from eternity, prepared the answer. Hence our petitions can and do have their effect. And the petitions must be made, since the answer to them is prepared from eternity as con­ tingent upon our making them. When God grants our requests there is no change in God. From eter­ nity He decrees the answer that comes to us in time. Thus our prayers make all the difference in the world. But they make no change in God. We must avoid the mistake of attributing to God a manner of dealing with us that resembles our dealing with others. For we must take things one after another; we must live and act in a succession of moments, hours, days, years. It is not so with God. All things, past, present, and to come, are perfectly present to God from eternity. Hence, an event that looks to us like an exceptional thing,—such as the answer to a special prayer, or the intervention of God in a miraculous happening,—is just as much a matter of eternal and changeless decree as that which ap­ pears to us as the fixed course of nature continu­ ously sustained. The raising of Lazarus was as much a matter of eternal Will as the universal law that all men must die. The healing of St. Peter’s mother-in-law was just as much a matter of eternal Will as the constant “law” of nature which requires THE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD i7l the cooperation of much time in the curing of a fever, and produces no instantaneous cures. It is interesting to notice that the persons who find difficulty in the thought of God’s immutability are usually the same persons who talk pityingly of the Christian’s “anthropomorphic concept’’ of God. The overwhelming term anthropomorphic is a sim­ ple combination of twO Greek words, anthropos “man,” and morphe “form,” and means, when ap­ plied to our knowledge or concept of God, that we think of Him as a kind of superman. That there is danger of such a concept (or of such an imagina­ tion-image) of God occurring to the mind, is mani­ fest. All mythology is proof of it, and there may be some in our own enlightened age who think of God as a gigantic human figure with flowing beard and piercing eye. Perhaps we might dare to say that one of the reasons,—or, at all events, one of the effects,—of the Incarnation, was to give weak man the true God in human form, so that henceforth the concept of God as man shall be a true concept. But the point we wish specially to make is this : the per­ sons who take a superior attitude and offer criticism of the “anthropomorphic concept” of God, are them­ selves hopelessly and falsely anthropomorphic in their own conception of Deity. For they limit God as they would limit a creature; His immutability is a puzzle to them; Elis eternity baffles them; His infinity and immensity suggest only largeness to them. J 72 THEODICY And in all this, they manifest an idea of God that is only an enlarged idea of a creature. They are doing the one thing that they particularly profess to amid and to censure in others : they are evidencing anthro­ pomorphic limitations in their notion of God. cl) ETERNITY The term eternity means not only endlessness but it means also an absence of beginning and an ab­ sence of successive duration. Only that Being which has had no beginning and will have no end, and whose existence is not a matter of successive days and years but is all present at once, meets the re­ quirements of the term eternal in the strictest sense. And it is in this sense that the terms eternity and eternal are applied to God. Ponder this definition of eternity, made by Boe­ thius about fifteen hundred years ago: “Eternity is the possession, at once, complete and perfect, of boundless life.” Notice the force of every word in the definition. It is the complete possession of endless life, and of beginningless life, that is, “of boundless life.” There is nothing lacking in this possession ; there is not some of the life yet to come, not any of it that has slipped away. And it is the perfect possession of boundless life; it is not held vaguely, as a man might hold great riches without knowing their exact extent or how every penny is stored or invested ; no, it is a perfect possession, a fully real- THE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD 173 ized possession, with nothing vague about it, with nothing running off into the region of misty de­ tails. Further, this complete and perfect possession of boundless life is simultaneously complete and per­ fect; it is not a matter of a clearly remembered past and a clearly envisioned future; it is the perfect possession of boundless life which is all there al once; and that “once” is a changeless eternal now. Consider, too, why Boethius speaks of eternity as the possession of boundless life. He does so because existence or duration has no perfect form but that called life, and the perfect form of existence or dura­ tion must be attributed to the infinite Being. There are three conceivable sorts of duration, and these we call time, aeviternity, and eternity. Time is a measure,—at least, it is ever conceived as such, and in this phase of its concept it is a logical entity,— of existence in bodily things ; it measures and marks existence and operations, happenings and events, in a bodily universe. Time has been pretty well de­ scribed as, “the measure of movements (or events) considered with reference to before and after.” Of the nature of time, and of what modern philosophers are trying to do with it, a full account is given in both Ontology and Cosmology, but we have no need to say more of it here. The second type of duration, aeviternity, is the measure of duration in things that are substantially unchangeable, once they are created, but which are changeable in operation. This term, 174 THEODICY aeviternity (and the adjective acviternal}, is applied to beings that have had a beginning but will never have an end. Human souls, and angels, arc aeviterna! beings. And, as we have seen, eternity and eternal are terms that find just application only to that Be­ ing which is wholly changeless,- which admits no variation in substance or nature or operation; which has neither beginning, end, nor succession in ex­ istence. Now, it is manifest that eternity, like all the Di­ vine Attributes, is not a thing that our imagination can depict. Imagination tries to depict it; it does its best; but it falls far short of success; indeed, it falls short of making even a proper beginning of what would have to be an infinite image. But our mind can know what is meant by eternity, and our reason can, and must, recognize the compelling need for attributing it to God. And thus, though we be finite in all our powers, we can and do realize the eternity of God as a fact, although we acknowledge its appreciation as utterly beyond us. When fancy tries to picture eternity, or even aeviternity, it merely presents an image of tremendously lengthened time. Of course, such imaginative efforts are often of great practical value. A man may dwell upon the pic­ ture of staggering reaches of time, and find in it a strong motive for working to gain an endless heaven and to avoid an endless hell. But the picture is ever THE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD 175 an image of greatly protracted time, and never of endlessness. We have all heard the story of the negro preacher with his graphic description of eternity, the story which describes a little bird taking a drop of water from the Atlantic Ocean, and carrying it, not through the air, but hop by hop across our con­ tinent, to deposit it in the Pacific; then going back, hop by hop, for another drop. The conclusion of the story is that when the little bird has completely emptied the Atlantic into the Pacific by this unbe­ lievably slow process, then eternity shall just have made a start. Or we may have heard and pondered the other graphic description of eternity, or rather, of aeviternity, which is sometimes proposed in some such form as this : “Suppose the earth were a ball of the hardest steel. Now suppose that once in every hundred thousands years a tiny insect were to crawl a few feet on the surface of this enormous steel ball. When the ball is entirely worn away by the crawling insect, then eternity will have just begun.” These descriptions are amusing; and they are not without a certain element of terror for the mind ; and they may serve, as we have said, a very necessary practical purpose. But even such staggering descriptions as these cannot enable imagination to picture eternity or aeviternity. AH they can do is to overwhelm one with enormous reaches of imaginary time. They stress the point of successive duration and of change. ij6 THEODICY Yet all succession is excluded from the concept of eternity; and substantial change is excluded from the concept of aeviternity. Ί hat God is necessarily eternal, or (hat eternity is but one phase of the indivisible Divine Essence, is easily proved. It may be proved by appealing to God’s infinity, to His simplicity, to His immutabil­ ity, to His necessity. We choose to present two short proofs, taken from the fact that God is Neces­ sary Being and from the fact that He is immutable. I. God is Necessary Being. He is Pure Actuality. He is wholly independent of causes. Now, such a Being cannot conceivably have a beginning (else It would be caused; It would be actualized; It would be contingent). Nor can such a Being have an end­ ing (else It would suffer the action of a cause which would bring It to an end ; It would be contingent upon such cause ; It would be in potentiality towards the action of such cause). Nor can such a Being have any succession of times or moments in dura­ tion (else It would be continuously actualized and would not be Pure Actuality to begin with; It would be contingent upon the coming of moments not yet lived ; It would be affected by the causal action of such moments). Hence, the Necessary Be­ ing, the Pure Actuality, the Causeless Being, cannot THE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD 177 be subject to beginning, ending, or succession in existence. Therefore, God is eternal. 2. We have proved that God is immutable. But what is immutable is. necessarily eternal. A being that comes into existence is not immutable, for it comes. A being that has an ending is not immutable, for it goes. A being that suffers succession in its existence is not immutable, for it progresses from moment to moment. Therefore God does not come into existence; Fie does not pass out of existence; He does not undergo the passing of successive pe­ riods, stages, or moments. Therefore, God is eternal. SUMMARY OF THE ARTICLE In this Article we have considered certain Divine Attributes, namely, God’s Goodness or Perfection, His Immensity, His Immutability, His Eternity. In a former Chapter we established the fundamental Divine Attributes of Unity, Simplicity, Infinity, Spirituality. We have based our proof of God’s goodness on the fact that He is Pure Actuality. We have proved the immensity of God, and His ubiquity or omnipresence, from His infinity, and from the fact that He is the necessary ] first Cause which gives and supports the existence of all things. We have found that God is present everywhere and in all 178 THEODICY things operatively and incircumscriptivcly. We have proved the immutability of God from J lis actual­ ity, simplicity, and infinity. We have shown the true meaning of eternity, and have seen that God must be eternal since He is the Necessary Being and is immutable. BOOK THIRD THE OPERATIONS OF GOD '; ? ' Î This Book discusses the operations of God in so far as unaided human reason may apprehend them. It makes no study of the divine activity which theologians call the eternal generation of the Son of God and the eternal pro­ cession of the Holy Ghost : this is a matter of Revelation, not of philosophy. This Book studies the activity of God’s intellect and will, wherein God is the Creator, Conserver, and Governor of creatures and the Concurring Principle in their activities. In a word, this Book studies the internal or immanent operations of the Divine Intellect and the Divine Will, and the transient effects (or, less accurately, the transient operations of God) whereby all creatures stand in an essential and real relation to their Creator, Conserver, Governor, and Concurring Principle. The Book has two Chapters : Chapter I. The Immanent Operations of God Chapter II. The Transient Operations of God NEW,; gàj ΑΤΓ i J CHAPTER I i I /THE IMMANENT OPERATIONS OF GOD This Chapter studies the operations of understanding and willing which are identified with the Divine Essence, and which, so to speak, constitute that Essence as a Personal Nature. An immanent operation is one that remains, in it­ self and in its main effect, within the principle that gives rise to it. It is a vital operation, a life-operation. Now, the life of God is not an organic life ; there can be no question of vegetal or sentient operations in God ; but there can and must be the perfect, the infinite, operations of intellect and will. These operations are not accidents in God, as under­ standing and willing are in man. For in God there are no accidents; all that God has He is; all perfections are identi­ fied in God with the simple Divine Essence. The Chapter is divided into three Articles, as follows: Article I. The Operations of God’s Intellect Article 2. The Operations of God’s Will Article 3. The Personal Nature of God Article i. The Operations of God’s Intellect a) The Divine Knowledge Divine Knowledge b) Classification of the c) The Divine Ideas a) THE DIVINE KNOWLEDGE We have seen that God is the All Perfect. Every pure perfection is found in God in infinite degree. 181 A. CW WA:.T ;T 182 THEODICY Now, knowledge is a pure perfection. Therefore, we see how right and reasonable is the statement of our little catechism, “God knows all things.” God’s knowledge not only extends to all things, but it exhausts the knowability of things. Such knowledge is called comprehensive knowledge. Truly comprehensive knowledge is beyond the capacity of any creature; all creatural knowledge is apprehen­ sive merely. For to comprehend a thing is to know it thoroughly in itself and in all its actual and pos­ sible relations with other things. To comprehend a thing is not merely to know what the thing is, and how it stands with reference to other things; it is also to know all that the thing could be and how it could stand with reference to all other things actual and possible. Manifestly, such complete knowledge is not within the grasp of a finite understanding. Yet such knowledge must be predicated of the Infinite Understanding. Truly comprehensive, and hence infinite, knowl­ edge is called perfect science. It is our purpose to prove that this perfect science exists in God and is one with the Divine Essence Itself. The proof is direct and compelling. The infinitely perfect Being must possess, in a transcendent or eminent way, all pure perfections. ( Now, knowledge is a pure perfection, for it involves j in itself (omitting consideration of the manner in i which some creatures must laboriously acquire it) IMMANENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 183 no imperfection. Hence knowledge must exist in the infinitely perfect Being in a transcendent or eminent way. But knowledge cannot exist in the infinitely perfect Being in a transcendent way except it be comprehensive knowledge, that is, perfect science. Therefore, perfect science exists in the infinitely per- . feet Being, that is, in God. But, since God is abso- ' lutely simple, His knowledge is not something added \ to His essence, or compounded with His essence; it is something identified with Elis essence. Hence, God not only has perfect science; He is perfect sci­ ence; He is infinite understanding. In Criteriology we learn that non-materiality is the root of knowledge and of knowing. A thing that is wholly material, such as a stone, has no amplitude of function, no power of taking in the “forms” of other things as such (that is, as of other things), but is limited to its own form ; and any accidental form which it receives it makes its own. But a knowing-creature (animal or man) can receive or take in other things cognitionally ; it can know them ; it can take in their forms without making them its own; it can possess the forms of other things (that is, can know other things) as other things. In a word, a knowing-creature is less limited than a non­ knowing creature because it has less of the limita­ tion imposed by sheer materiality or bodiliness. And the less of materiality about a knowing-creature, the wider and deeper its range of knowledge, and the i 84 THEODICY more pure, universal, and abstract are the items or elements of its knowledge. Thus the intellectual knowledge of man is of wide and deep range, is universal and abstract, while the sentient knowledge of man or beast is limited to concrete and singular things. In a word, the more a thing is removed from materiality and the limitations that come with materiality, the more perfect is its operation of knowing and the more embracing and complete is its knowledge. Now, God is the Infinite Spirit. In God there is no materiality whatever. Therefore, in God there is nothing to limit and qualify know ledge. It follows that God’s knowledge must be the most perfect possible. In God there is perfect science. God is perfect science; God is infinite understanding. Now, it may be asked, “What is the object of God’s knowledge?” The simple answer is, “All things knowable.” But there is need to make a dis­ tinction here, and to discern what is the primary, and what the secondary, object of the Divine In­ tellect. The primary object of a knowing-power (or sim­ ply the primary object of knowledge in any knower) is that which is attained by the knower directly, immediately, and in itself. The secondary object of a knowing-power is that which it can know through or by reason of the primary object. The primary object of the Divine Intellect is the Divine Essence Itself. For, in any knowing-being, j 1 , I ; ί i i IMMANENT OPERATIONS OE GOD 185 there is a proportion, an equality, between the thing it is framed to know and its power to know it. But between the Infinite Understanding and what it can know there can be a proportion or equality only if the object known be itself infinite. And the only infinite object is the Infinite Being, that is, the Di­ vine Essence Itself. There tore, God knows Him­ self, first and foremost (that is, as primaiy object). Nor is there any force in the objection that if God knows Himself perfectly He is, so to speak, defined and limited by that knowledge, and, since God is in no wise limited, this involves a contradiction and cannot be; therefore, says the objection, God does not perfectly know Himself. The objection is short­ sighted. For if there is anything that God’s knowl­ edge does not include, it is imperfect knowledge, and is therefore a lack and a limit in the perfect and limitless God. In a word, the objection seeks to avoid a difficulty which is merely apparent by diving full force into a difficulty which is real and unan­ swerable. Of course, if God's knowledge were a thing which God merely has; if it were an acquisi­ tion of God; if it were something superadded to the Divine Essence, it would be a limiting thing, and for God to know Himself would be for God to know the boundaries of the Boundless and to recognize limits in the Limitless. But, as we have seen, God’s knowledge is one with Himself. It is not something acquired by God as creatural knowledge is acquired 186 THEODICY by a knowing-creature. What we call God’s knowl­ edge is only one phase of God’s infinite essence. And to say that God knows Himself perfectly, and that the Divine Essence is the primary object of the Di­ vine Understanding, is merely to say that God is Himself. Hence the objection is manifestly founded upon a seeming difficulty merely, and not upon a real one. In knowing Flimself perfectly (that is, compre­ hensively) God knows the full extent of all His powers. He therefore knows all things creatable, all things sustainable, all things with which Ide can concur in being and in action. In a word, in and through His knowledge of Himself, God knows all other things. Now, what is known in and through the primary object of knowledge is the secondary object of knowledge. Therefore, all things other than God, all creatures and all their actual and pos­ sible relations, constitute the secondary object of God’s knowledge or of the Divine Intellect. St. Thomas Aquinas puts the matter thus, “It is clear that God knows Himself perfectly, else He would not be perfect in being, for His very being is to know. Now, if anything is known perfectly, its pozver is known. And if a power is perfectly known, there are known also the realities to which the power extends and in which it produces its effects. There­ fore, since the Divine Power extends to all things as their First Efficient Cause, it follows that God I IMMANENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 187 in knowing Himself knows all things other than Himself.” God’s knowledge of all things other than Him­ self, that is, His knowledge of all creatural reality, is not a mere general knowledge, but is perfect in all details, ft is truly comprehensive knowledge, since it is knowledge in and of the Infinite Being. Therefore, God knows every single thing that now exists, has existed, will exist, or could exist. All things, actual and possible, necessary and free, sub­ stantial and accidental, are perfectly comprehended by the Divine Intellect. God knows Himself perfectly, and He knows all other things in Himself. In this the Divine Knowl­ edge is different from creatural knowledge, say human knowledge. For a man knows things in them­ selves by reason of a species or cognitional image which the realities known impress upon his knowing­ powers or faculties. A man receives his knowledge; it is something over and above his essence and not part and parcel with his essence itself. A man gathers his knowledge, beginning with the sense-grasp of bodily things which he finds about him in this world. From this he rises to intellectual concepts, and to the knowledge of things bodily and non-bodily in their essences. Thus we say that a man knows reali­ ties in themselves and not in himself. But God’s knowledge is not acquired, not gathered, not built up, not reasoned out or abstracted. God’s knowledge 188 THEODICY does not result in God from the impression upon the Divine Mind of the images or species of crea­ tures. God’s knowledge is necessarily one with the Divine Essence, and is therefore changeless and eternal. God’s knowledge of creatures does not de­ pend upon the creatures being here to impress them­ selves upon His notice; God needs no experience of creatures to form in Himself the ideas by which they are known; His knowledge of creatures is full and perfect from eternity and was thus full and per­ fect before any creature existed. Nor is God’s knowl­ edge improved or in any wise altered by the fact that certain creatures come into existence at a mo­ ment and in a manner eternally decreed by the Di­ vine Will. From eternity God knows all possible creatures, in all their possible relations, in Himself, and not in themselves. In the single and simple and eternal grasp of Elis unchanging essence, God per­ fectly and eternally knows all creatural realities. N Λ A special question which has been the subject of a prolonged and still unsettled controversy must here be presented. It may be expressed in these terms, “In what manner does God know future free events (called ‘future contingencies’), that is, things that arc actually going to happen, but are not in them­ selves things that need to happen since they depend upon the free choice of rational creatures?’’ A fu­ ture contingency or future free event depends upon, IMMANENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 189 or is contingent upon, the- operation of causes that are not truly prediciablc, since these causes arc not necessitated but free. That John, who is three, will marry Jane, newly born, twenty years hence on a certain day and at a certain hour, may be a fact, but, at this moment, it is a future contingency. That James will quarrel with his employer next year and throw up his job, may come to pass in actual fact, but right now it is a future contingency or future free event. God knows that these future contingen­ cies will come to pass; there is no doubt or question on that point. But the controversy focusses upon the manner or the mode of God’s knowledge of fu­ ture contingencies. Iloiu does God know these future free events? The following opinions are offered in answer to this question : I. The Doctrine of Molina. Molina, a famous Spanish Jesuit of the sixteenth century, notable both as a theologian and a philosopher, held that God knows future free events in his “supcrcomprehension of causes,” independently of any decree of the Divine Will. This opinion seems inadequate. For to know a contingent or free event in its causes, is to have only a more or less perfect conjectural knowl­ edge of the event ; it is to be in position to make a more or Jess perfectly accurate guess about the event. But God’s knowledge is in all ways most perfect and most certain, with no guesswork about it. j go THEODICY 2. The Doctrine of Banes. Banez, famous Dom­ inican contemporary and countryman of Molina, held that God knows future free events in the eter­ nal decrees of I fis will. This doctrine, baldly stated, seems misleading·. Bor the divine decrees arc not blindly issued laws, nor arc they decrees which de­ stroy the real freedom of free causes. Yet, in itself, the blunt doctrine of Banez seems to suggest both of these impossibilities. 5. The Doctrine of Cajetan. Cajetan, sixteenth century Italian theologian and philosopher, holds the opinion commonly accepted as the Thomistic doc­ trine (that is, as the true interpretation of the doc­ trine of St. Thomas Aquinas). lie teaches that God knows all future events, including future free events, in His own essence, as present, and in the light of His eternal determining decrees. This doctrine ap­ pears to be the most acceptable of all. We pause upon its several points for a brief word of explana­ tion and proof. «) God knows future contingencies as present. For the process of time has no limiting effect upon the Infinite Mind; to God there is no future and no past; all things are present to His knowledge. And, granted that future free events are future to finite minds, and hence are but a matter of conjecture or uncertain knowledge, they are present to the Infinite Mind and are thus the object of certain knowledge. IMMANENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 191 Again, the future free events that are actually going; to happen, have, when they happen, the necessity of fact. In themselves, considered abstractly, they do not need to happen; they depend upun free choice; but when the choice is once made and the events actu­ ally come to pass, then they have to he what they are. Now, the Infinite Mind actually beholds these events, as present, and hence as having the necessity of fact, which does not in the least affect their es­ sentially free character, but which renders them ob­ jects of certain knowledge in the Infinite Mind. &) God knows future contingencies in His own essence. For the Divine Essence, viewed as the Di­ vine Knowledge, embraces completely all possibili­ ties, and so embraces all future realities. Thus the Divine Essence Itself is sufficient reason to account for God’s knowledge of future free events. c) God knows future contingencies in the light .of His eternal determining decrees. For all things ■' have their being in the will and power of God to bestow it, and in the will and power of God to con­ cur in creatural activities and operations. Hence, while the free wills of rational creatures are truly free, and they truly choose their proximate objects, such freedom and such choice is dependent upon God’s eternal decrees to create the free wills, to sus­ tain them in freedom, and to move them and to concur in their free choice. Ontology teaches us that the root­ principle of sheer possibility is the Divine Intellect; 192 THEODICY tilings possible have their possibility, in last analysis, because they are known as possible in the Divine Mind. And their extrinsic possibility (that is, their possibility as things c.xistible, not merely as things thinkable) depends upon the Divine \\ ill, and hence on the eternal decrees of God. Now, future free events arc more than merely possible, since they are, as a fact, going to take place. But if the Divine Will and its decrees are requisite for extrinsic possibilité··, it is still more evident that the Divine Will and its de­ crees are required for future actuality; for if even the lesser mode of being requires the Divine Will, certainly the greater or more perfect mode of being requires It. /' b) CLASSIFICATION OF THE DIVINE KNOWLEDGE / 's \ i We may distinguish in God (by a distinction of reason based on reality) knowledge that is : I. Spec­ illative or Practical; 2. Necessary or Free; 5. Approving or Non-approving; 4. Knowledge of Simple Intelligence or Knowledge of Vision. The last clas­ sification is, far and away, the most important we have here to consider. But we shall say a word of the other types too. I. Speculative knowledge means knowledge that contemplates truth but has no direct concern with action. When a man studies ancient history for the sake of information, he does not propose to do any- ΐΙιΐιίΠΤΙΜΓ^Γ^^^^λ.:^··^·^-·^:^ - .. ' A-J-T . IMMANENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 193 tiling with the knowledge acquired. fl is aim is specu­ lative. He wants knowledge for the enlightenment and enrichment of mind it gives him ; he wants truth to know it, to contemplate it. Such, in general, is spec­ ulative knowledge. The term spcci/laiivc conics from the Latin verb speculari “to look at.” But when a man studies carpentry, or engineering, he intends to use his knowledge in doing things. His aim is prac­ tical. He wants to know that he may do something in consequence. Such is practical knowledge. The word practical has its roots in the Greek prattcin “to make, to do.” Now, God’s knowledge of Himself is manifestly speculative knowledge. His knowledge of things other than Himself is at once speculative and practical. Of things sheerly possible, not con­ sidered as to be made or not made but seen merely in themselves as what could be made, God has specu­ lative knowledge, and, inasmuch as possibility in­ volves something practical (namely, what could actually be made or done) His knowledge is also practical. Of things that are not but are going to be, it is manifest that the Divine Knowledge is both speculative and practical ; speculative inasmuch as it knows them as things, practical inasmuch as it knows them as things to be made. Of existing things, God’s knowledge is speculative inasmuch as these things are knowable objects and, indeed, are per­ fectly known in the Divine Essence ; and practical inasmuch as God knows how to sustain these things 194 THEODICY in being and operation. God's knowledge of evil is mainly speculative, yet it is also practical inasmuch as it is knowledge of what God permits, impedes, or draws into place in Ilis providence. 2. God’s knowledge of Himself is necessary knowledge, that is, He knows Himself perfectly and cannot be ignorant of Himself; as He is Necessary Being, and as His knowledge is one with His Es­ sence, so He is Necessary Knowledge. God’s knowl­ edge of things that depend for being upon His perfectly free and infinite Will is called free knowl­ edge. God cannot be ignorant of these things, but they are not one with Himself as Necessary Knowl­ edge, even though they be known in His eternal Essence. 5. God’s knowledge of creatures in their positive being, that is, in their essential and transcendental goodness, is knowledge which involves approval. So the Creator, looking upon and knowing the works of His hands, “saw that they were very good.” God’s knowledge of things in their positive being or goodness is not something aloof and detached ; it is not knowledge merely, but it is causal knowledge, since God, whose essence and knowledge are really identified, is the cause of these things ; hence, neces­ sarily, He approves them. God’s knowledge of evils, of deficiencies, is non-approving, since God is only L^..· LMMANENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 195 the accidental cause of physical evil, and is in no sense the cause of sin or moral evil. 4. The most important distinction of the Divine Knowledge is that which classifies it as () The Knowledge of Vision. (u) The Knowledge of Simple Intelligence is that Divine Knowledge which has as its object (that is, as the thing known) all things possible but not things that arc ever to be. All that could be, but have not been, are not, nor wall be,—these things are the object of the Divine Knowledge of Simple Intelligence. (ά) The Knowledge of Vision is that Divine Knowledge which has as its object all that has been, is, or will be actual. Things that have existed in the past, or exist now, or will exist in time to come,— these are the object of the Knowledge of Vision; these things lie within the direct view, so to speak, of God, which beholds them as present, no matter what be their position in the time-limited view of finite minds. Now, Molina and many other philosophers have taught that a third classification is to be made in the Divine Knowledge, and that ibis holds a middle place between the two types just mentioned, and is to be called, in consequence, scientia media, or “Mid­ dle Knowledge.” The Latin term, scientia media, - . * j _. .... ... igô THEODICY is universally used when this classification of Divine Knowledge is in question; one never hears or reads the English translation of it. The Molmist doctrine amounts to this: God knows thim/s merely possible by His Knowledge of Simple Intelligence ; lie knows all actual things, including those truly future, by His Knowledge of Vision. .Bui there is a special class of things not included among the objects of these two types of knowledge. There arc the things which a man would do if certain conditions were to be fulfilled, but which, as a fact, he will not do be­ cause those conditions will not be fulfilled. These things are called “conditionally future events” or, in the commonly used Latin term, futuribilia. The futuribilia (things that are not truly future, since they will never come to pass, but things condition­ ally future because under certain conditions, that will not be realized, they would come to pass by the free choice of man) are the objects of the scientia media. We do not find acceptable the doctrine of Molina, nor are we prepared to recognize the scientia media as a necessary classification of the Divine Knowl­ edge. We do not agree that the futuribilia consti­ tute a special class of knowables, distinct from the respective objects of the Knowledge of Simple In­ telligence and the Knowledge of Vision. And where we find no truly and definitely distinct object of IMMANENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 197 knowledge, we must not assert the existence of a definitely distinct type oi knowing. Certainly, we admit, and emphatically assert, that God knows all things knowable, including the futuri­ bilia. Our Lord gave expression to His knowledge of such conditionally future events when I le said (Luke x, /5) : “Woe to thee, Corozain, woe to thee. Bethsaida. For if in Tyre and Sidon had been wrought the might)- works that have been wrought in you, they would have done penance long ago, sitting in sackcloth and ashes.” God knows the futuribilia. But we assert that this knowledge is Knowledge of Simple Intelligence. We find no need for declaring the existence of a scientia media. We do not find acceptable the Molinist argument that the futuribilia are an object distinct from the respective objects of the other two types of Divine Knowledge, and that futuribilia are something more than things sheerly possible (which fall under Simple Intelli­ gence) and something less than things to be actual in future (which fall under Vision). God's knowledge of things to come is Knowledge of Vision, for the time element does not affect the Infinite Mind, and things to come are seen as pres­ ent. God’s knowledge of things that would come under certain conditions is cither knowledge of what will be when conditions are fulfilled (and this is Knowledge of Vision) ; or it is knowledge of i98 THEODICY what would be, but actually will not be. since the conditions arc not to be fulfilled, and this amounts to knowledge of things possible, and comes under the Knowledge of Simple Intelligence. Father Boedder, S.J., in his Natural 7 hcology (p.2 (called so analogically) means a plurality in what G essentially non-plural or simple. No plurality is induced in God by His perfect comprehension of all things in the one indivisible and infinitely simple species which is His own essence. SUMMARY OF THE ARTICLE In this Article we have learned, by strict reason­ ing, that in God there is the most perfect knowledge, perfect science, infinite understanding, and that this knowledge is really one with the Divine Essence It­ self. We have seen that God’s own essence is the primary object of the Divine Mind, and that the realities other than God (that is, all creatural possi­ bilities) constitute the secondary object of God’s knowledge. We have learned that God, in knowing Himself, knows all other things perfectly and eter­ nally, and thus He knows creatures in Himself, and not in themselves. We have studied the question of God’s knozvledge of future contingencies or future free events, and have found the doctrines of Molina and Banez less acceptable than that of Cajetan, who, following St. Thomas Aquinas, holds that God knows all future events, including future IMMANENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 205 contingencies, in His own essence, as présent, and consequent upon His eternal determining decrees. We have classified the Divine Knowledge as specu­ lative and practical, as necessary and free, as ap­ proving and non-approz'ing, as Knowledge of Simple Intelligencc and Knowledge of Kision. We have re­ jected die scientia media theory as unnecessary to explain God’s knowledge of futuribilia, that is, of events that depend upon human choice, and which will not take place actually, hut would take place were certain conditions to be fulfilled. We have seen that there is no real conflict between God’s fore­ knowledge and man’s free-will. We have studied the Divine Ideas or exemplars or archetypes of all creat­ able things, which exist in the mind of God; we have found that these ideas are not formed severally by any knowing-proccss or knowing-effort of the Divine Intellect, but exist perfectly in and of the Divine Essence from eternity. We have learned that God’s essence is the single and simple and infinite species in which He eternally knows all things. Article 2. The Operations of God’s Will a) The Divine Will b) Classification of Will-acts in God c) Object of the Divine Will d) The Divine Will and Evil a) THE DIVINE WILL The will is the tendency to follow intellectual knowledge by appropriate action. It is the intellectual 2θ6 THEODICY appetency. Tt is the power or faculty to choose a course of action which is intellectually manifested as good to follow. All these descriptions of will are. of course, literally applicable to the facalhy of will­ ing in a ratio nul créai arc, that is, in a creature en­ dowed with understanding and the ability to act with conscious purpose in consequence of its find­ ings. When we speak of God, we must remove from our concept of will all that makes it a limited and imperfect thing, all that makes it a faculty or ac­ cidental power, all that makes it something really distinct from understanding and from the essence of the being which understands. For in God there is no real distinction save that of the distinction of Persons in the Trinity, a distinction which we have no right to discuss in a purely human or rational science. God’s will must exist, for will is a perfec­ tion and God is identified with the infinity of all perfections subsisting in simple and eternal unity. But God’s will is not, as our wills are, a power which God has; no, God’s will is a perfection which God is; it is one with the essence of God. Therefore, just as it is correct to say that God is infinite mind or infinite understanding or infinite knowledge, so it is correct to say that God is infinite will. Still, we are limited by the inadequacies of creatural understand­ ing and of human speech, and, if we are to discuss the Divine Will at all, we must perforce discuss It in terms that express It as something akin to the IMMANENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 207 creatural faculty of will that we know and experi­ ence within our limited selves. Our language is neces­ sarily analogical in this discussion, as it is in the discussion of all the Divine Perfections. Now, can God be truly and factually regarded as Will? Is God infinite will? In more understandable, but less accurate speech, is there a will in Godr I. In God there is, formally or as such, and in an eminent or transcendent way, all that our knowledge of creatures discloses to us as pure and unsrjymixed perfection. Now, will in itself (and not in its halting and limited creatural exercise) is unquestion­ ably a pure and unmixed perfection. For there is nothing of imperfection in the tendency to follow knowledge with appropriate action ; on the contrary, knowledge without tendency or ability to act upon it would be itself imperfect, since knowledge finds its fulfillment and rounded meaning in being carried out ; and hence this capacity or faculty for carrying out knowledge is itself a perfection. In creatures, the will is subject to influences that hamper and thwart it; it is capable of an abuse that turns it against the very purpose of its existence; it is pos­ sible to employ it in a fashion that is morally evil and to make it the directive force behind movements that are both physically and morally bad. We say that every human will is weak; we say that many a human will is a bad will (not in itself indeed but ΣΖΞΣΣΖΖΗΖΖΖΣΣ 208 deficiencies, and defections is an evil in the willingpower itself. Tn will, considered purely in itself, there is nothing that the mind can discover but pure perfection. Therefore, this perfection is a pure and unmixed perfection, and it must be attributed for­ mally to the Infinite Being. Hence we must attribute will to God. God is Infinite Will. 2. Wherever there is understanding there must be will. For wherever there is knowledge there is tendency to follow knowledge. This truth is evident, almost self-evident, and it receives full confirmation in the check-up of our own experience. For knowl­ edge is seldom purely and entirely speculative ; very frequently,—and in some measure always,—it points on to something-to-be-done. Knowledge is a light that frequently reveals a path that may be followed; it discovers not only facts, but ways and means ; it illumines no meaningless universe with a merely entertaining light, but shows ends to be attained. And this truth which is predicable, in due measure, of all knowledge, even sentient knowledge, is mani­ festly most truly and inevitably predicable of in­ tellectual knowledge. Rightly do we declare that where there is understanding there is a drive and tendency to use understanding practically, to act on it, to carry out its plans for good, to achieve the TO-.1- ai·,. IMMANENT OPERATIONS OF GOD THEODICY in its use) ; and these declarations point to defi­ ciencies, limits, evils. But none of these limitations, ,i .λ H-.-C. 209 objects it shows to be desirable or necessary. In a word, rightly do we say that where there is an un­ derstanding there is a will. Now, as we have seen, God is Infinite l/nderstanding; therefore (since God is simple and all perfections are identified with His essence) God is also Infinite Will. b) CLASSIFICATION OF WILL-ACTS IN GOD We distinguish in God will-acts that are ante­ cedent and those that are consequent, and so we speak of God’s antecedent will and His consequent will. God’s antecedent will is the Divine Will inasmuch as it wills good and rejects evil simply, without tak­ ing into account (hence antecedently to) any condi­ tions or circumstances that might make what is simply or generally good a non-good or evil in cer­ tain cases. Thus, by His antecedent will, God wills all men to be saved. For salvation is the highest good of man, and God wills it simply or antecedently for all, without consideration of the circumstances which, in individual cases, might make it unjust. God’s consequent will is the Divine Will inasmuch as it wills what is good and rejects evil, not abso­ lutely, simply, unconditionally, and in a general way, but in the special circumstances and conditions of each complex situation. Taking into account (and hence consequent upon but not dependently on) these 210 THEODICY special circumstances and conditions, God's conse­ quent will decrees the punishment, and not the salva­ tion, of the unrepentant sinner, even though, by His antecedent will, God wills the salvation of all men. Of course, the consequent will decrees what is good, and this in a more special way than the antecedent w ill. It is good, in general, that all men be saved, and the salvation of all is willed or wished by the antecedent will of God. It is good, in each special case, that full justice should be done, and it is evil for justice to be traversed or offended; the consequent will of God wills that the unrepentant sinner should have justice. In the case of the unrepentant sinner, punishment is good, as being required by justice. c) OBJECT OF THE DIVINE WILL The object of any faculty is what that faculty ob­ tains or achieves in its normal function, and that which it is connaturally fitted to attain and towards the attainment of which it tends. Now, while the Divine Will is not a faculty, but is identified with the Divine Essence, we speak of It in human terms as though It were a faculty. The object of any faculty is twofold, namely, primary and secondary. The primary object, as we have seen in discussing the Divine Intellect, is that which the faculty tends to attain by its direct and immediate and first-and-foremost action; it is that which the faculty tends per se primo (of itself and IMMANENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 21 r primarily) to attain. The secondary object is that which the faculty tends to attain in, through, or by reason of its primary object. Thus, for instance, the faculty of sight in man tends to attain, that is, to perceive, colored surface. This is the primary object of sight. But because sight perceives colored surface, it perceives also where such surface termi­ nates, and thus perceives the shape or figure of visi­ ble objects. This is a secondary object of sight. We have already learned that the primary object of the Divine Mind or Intellect is the Divine Essence It­ self. And we have also seen that, in comprehending the Divine Essence, the mind of God comprehends all the Divine Powers and all that these can accom­ plish, and hence comprehends all creatures. In and through and by reason of the perfectly compre­ hended Divine Essence (primary object), the mind of God comprehends all creatable things (secondary object). Now, as it is with the Divine Mind, so is it also with the Divine Will. The primary object of ) the Divine Will is the Divine Essence Itself, and the J secondary object is all that is in line with the pri­ mary, and may be viewed as related to it as means to end. But, before discussing and proving this point, we must say a word about the nature of will-acts in general. The intellect tends to embrace and understand all truth. The will tends to attain and possess and en­ joy all good. Now, the tendency towards good is at 212 THEODICY the same time a tendency away from evil. And this tendency may, in all cases, be truly regarded as love. The acts proper to the will itself are often listed as these six: wish ; intention; consent to the requisite means of carrying out intention: choice of suitable means; use of such means, enjoyment of the good attained. Every one of these six will-acts is an aspect or expression of love. To have a wish is to entertain a simple love of the thing wished for; to intend a thing is to like or love it enough to have the purpose of attaining it ; to consent to the means required to achieve an end is to like or love that end enough to undertake or undergo what is necessary to attain it; to choose means is to like the end enough to take pains in the election of ways to come by it; to use the means chosen is a further expression of this love ; and to enjoy the beloved object when attained, is to rest in'it complacently or lovingly. And where there is love there is hatred, where there is choice there is rejection; just as a step towards the north is inevitably a step away from the south. Hence, to wish an end or object is to reject what is opposed to that object and its at­ tainment ; to intend an end is to turn away from its opposite ; and so with all the will-acts. Thus rejec­ tion or hatred is, so to speak, the under-side of love; it is part and parcel with love itself. Therefore, we repeat, all will-acts may be considered in terms of love. And when we come to the study of the object IMMANENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 213 of the Divine Will, primary and secondary, we seek to learn what the Divine Will loves. We have two points to establish. First, God loves Himself necessarily, as the primary object of the Divine will. Secondly, God loves things other than Himself freely, as the secondary object of the Divine Will. I. God loves Himself necessarily as the primary object of the Divine Will. This truth has two dis­ tinct parts; God loves Himself as the primary ob­ ject of the Divine Will ; and this love is not free but necessary. («) The primary object of any will is that which is the ultimate and full answer to the will-tendency. Now, the Divine Will is an infinite tendency or appetite for good, and Its ultimate and full answer must be Infinite Good Itself, that is to say, the ultimate and full answer to the tendency called the will of God must be the Divine Essence Itself. For only the Divine Essence is an Infinite Good. Again, as we have already seen, will is con­ sequent upon intellect. Will is a tendency to follow understanding, and to lay hold of and possess (that is, to love) what the understanding knows as good and desirable (that is, as lovable). Now, the Divine Intellect or Understanding knows the Divine Essence as supremely perfect and lovable, and hence the Divine Will tends primarily towards the Divine Essence as Its end. God, therefore, loves Himself; the Divine 214 THEODICY Essence is the primary object of the Divine Will. (&) The tendency of any faculty towards its primary object is a necessary tendency; it is what llic faculty is for; it is that which defines the faculty and gives it meaning. But, as we have seen, the primary object of the Divine Will is the Divine Essence. I lence, the Divine Will tends towards (that is, loves) the Divine Essence necessarily. This does not involve any limitation in God ; it does not mean that God is necessitated by anything extrinsic to Himself. Tn creatures, it is true, the perfect object of a faculty necessitates that faculty and, by the same token, limits the faculty and indicates its finite character. This is because the determining or necessitating factor in the case is extrinsic to the creatural faculty itself. But in God, the necessary object is Himself; it is not something extrinsic to the Divine Essence which forces, directs, or limits It ; it is the Divine Essence Itself. Therefore, to say that God neces­ sarily loves the Divine Essence is merely to say that God is God ; it is not to say that God is necessitated by anything that bears upon Him, so to speak, from without, for this (as is manifest, since God is the First Being and the only Necessary Being) is wholly impossible. Gocl freely loves things other than Himself, as the secondary object of the Divine Will. Three special points are to be distinguished in the declara- IMMANENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 215 tion. (a)God loves or wills things other than Him­ self. The fact that creatures exist is ample proof that God wills them to exist; otherwise their exist­ ence is inexplicable. And, even abstracting from the actual existence of creatures, we may prove that God loves or wills things other than Himself, for God is Infinite Goodness and goodness is, of its nature, a thing that tends to communicate itself and to spread itself abroad (bonum est diffusivum sui). Now, the only way in which Infinite Goodness can communicate Itself is by the sharing out, so to speak, of Itself in finite beings. “All creatures,” says St. Thomas Aquinas, “are but the participations of the Divine Goodness.” This does not mean that God ■must create, or that His goodness forces Elim to bring creatures into being; we shall see in a moment that God’s love or will towards creatures is perfectly free and not necessitated. It means only that the tendency of the perfect love, that is, the Divine A'Vill, is to give of its goodness ; it means that God wills or loves things other than Himself, yet in Elimself, and not as though creatures could be (which they cannot) independent of Elimself or endowed with any excellence of their very own. (b) _God wills things other than Himself as the secondary object of the Divine Will. For God, in His perfect compre­ hension of the Divine Essence, which is the primary object of the Divine Will, perfectly comprehends all that is within His power to create, and .wills the... 2l6 THEODICY precise items of this infinite knowledge which shall have actual existence as creatures. Now, the knowl­ edge of creatables in the Divine Essence is the secondary object of the Divine Aliud, and, since will follows understanding, in mode as in fact, the actual choice of what creatables arc to be creatures is the secondary object of the Divine Will. Tn a word, God wills or loves the creatures Tie is to create as the secondary object of the Divine Will. Take up the point in another way: All creatures are means to manifest the perfections of God. But means arc never the primary object of the will; they are secondary to the end towards which they are directed by the will. Hence, creatures (that is, things other than God) are loved or willed as the secondary ob­ ject of the Divine Will, (c) God loves things other than Himself in a manner that is not necessary but free. For the will, even of a creature (man or angel) is not necessitated to any means without which its end can be achieved. But God is Himself the end of the Divine Will, and this end is perfectly possessed, perfectly achieved, without creatures. AVhilc crea­ tures serve to manifest the Divine Perfections, noth­ ing is added to God Himself by such manifestation; it does not supply any lack in God ; it is something extrinsic to IIim without which He is infinitely per­ fect. The manifestation of the Divine Perfections effected by the creation, conservation, and govern­ ance of creatures, is no more an addition to God IMMANENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 217 Himself than a picture of a man is an addition to the man himself. Jt is an external manifestation. The end or primary object of the Divine Will (which is God Himself, or, in other words, the Divine Es­ sence) is perfectly and eternally and necessarily at­ tained, without reference to creatures, and would be so attained if no creature ever existed. Hence, if creatures are loved or willed (as we have seen that they are) this must happen in a way that is not requisite, not needed, not necessary, to fill up or fill out any perfection in God Himself. But that which is not requisite, nor needed, nor necessary, is free. Therefore, God wills (or loves) things other than Himself freely. It is wholly wrong, therefore, to assert, as some learned but mistaken men have done in times past, that God is forced by His goodness to create. God freely chooses to create. And His choice is an expression of the Divine Will (or the .Divine Love) freely attaining a secondary object. It is plain that God is not forced by any of His perfections to any activity affecting things other than Elimself, for every one of His perfections is infinitely identified with every othei' and with the Divine Essence Itself, and the Divine Essence, which is the only Necessary Being, is wholly self-sufficing and requires nothing beyond Itself for Its infinite being and existence. The point is manifest, but it may be effectively proved to the most stubborn or stupid of minds by a brief reductio ad absurdum, that is, by an argu- 218 THEODICY ment which shows the impossible and silly and self­ contradicting consequences of the assertion that God is forced to create. For, were God compelled by His goodness, or by any other of I lis perfections, to create, He would be forced to create all crcatable things, since Infinite Perfection is not to be satisfied by any limited expression. Further, all creatable things would necessarily be created from eternity, for the inner force (or perfection) compelling God to create would exist as long as God is God. Hence, all creatable things would of necessity exist from eternity; none would come into existence in time; none would suffer change or dissolution. Here we have a twofold absurdity, namely, the eternal exist­ ence of an infinity of finite things, and the eternal necessity of what is itself a contingent world. The conclusion is inevitable : God’s will is not forced with reference to its secondary object, but chooses this object freely. A seeming difficulty may here be considered. God is absolutely simple, uncompounded, uncomposed. But we have just seen that the one identical and simple Divine Will embraces Its primary end by a necessary action, and Its secondary end by a free action. Is there not a conflict here ? How can one simple activity of one simple Infinite Will be at once necessary and free? And, with reference to creatures, how can the one Divine Will, which is simple and IMMANENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 219 changeless, choose freely to create certain finite beings; does not Its changelessness involve the neces­ sity of creating just those things which are created or to be created, and so destroy the Divine freechoice? The difficulty here arises from the imperfec­ tion of our human concepts, and from our too-great readiness to attribute (unconsciously) human limi­ tations to the unlimited God. To solve the diffi­ culty, remember that God’s necessary will (or love) towards Himself is merely a phase or expression of the truth that God is God. And freedom (which marks God’s choice of the secondary object of the Divine Will) does not formally consist in a plu­ rality of various acts, or in an ability to “change one’s mind”; indeed such plurality and such change­ ableness or hesitation indicate limitation and im­ perfection. Freedom consists fundamentally in an independence from outside influences. Now, God is wholly independent of creatures, and therefore His relation towards them is wholly and perfectly free. But how shall we compose the apparent difficulty which arises from the fact of God’s changelessness when seen in conjunction with God’s free choice of creatures ? Is not a choice a kind of change ? And creatures are essentially changeable things, contin­ gent and non-necessary ; it would seem that they must be the fruit of a will that has come to a deci­ sion about them, and so has changed. We must re­ call that the will of God is identified with the essence Mil THEODICY of God, and that this essence is eternal. What God wills may be itself contingent and changeable with­ out inducing change and mutability in the Divine Wil! Itself. God, from elernit}', knows all things by perfect comprehension; from eternity His will ex­ ercises Its eternal and changeless, yet free and in­ dependent, choice of creatures. By one simple act God knows all things; by one simple eternal act God wills all that He wills ; by one simple act, nay, by the One Simple Divine Essence, God stands in changeless relation towards Himself necessarily, while He freely brings all things other than Himself into their relations towards Him. d) THE DIVINE WILL AND EVIL Evil or badness is the absence of good. It is not a positive thing but a negative thing. It is not the presence of something that has its own formal con­ stitution as a thing or being; it is the absence of something that ought to be present. Evil is a defec­ tion, a falling away, a failing, a lack, an absence. It is impossible to conceive of evil or to define it except in terms of absent good. Every being is good inasmuch as it is being at all. This is one of the basic truths of fundamental meta­ physics or ontology, and is fully explained in that science. This goodness of being as being is called transcendental or metaphysical goodness, and such goodness is identified with actual being. Being and IMMANENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 221 goodness are synonymous terms when understood in their abstract and metaphysical sense. Hence there is no being which as such is evil. In other words, there is no such thing as metaphysical evil. Eut there is such a thing as physical evil, and there is such a thing as moral evil. When a thing has all that its nature demands for normal being and function, it is physically perfect and physically good; any lack of natural item or element or ingredient renders the thing physically evil or bad. Thus when we say that bread is good bread, we mean that it has physical goodness; that it is properly made and baked; that no item or ingredient or element that it should have is lacking to it. And when we say that bread is bad bread, or that it is “no good,” we mean that some item, ingredient, or element, is lacking. Here we see that physical evil is a lack and an ab­ sence of something that should be present. So sick­ ness is a physical evil, for it is the lack of normal function in an organic nature. So death is a physical evil, for it is the absence of life in what was once an organism supporting life. Other physical evils are wounds, hunger, plagues, harsh climate, inasmuch as these things afflict men or animals, and hence induce a lack, an absence of natural and normal condition and function. But we must make careful distinctions. Poison is a physically bad or evil thing when used as food or medicine; in itself, as poison, it may be physically good : it is good poison, but not good food 222 THEODICY for man. As with physical evil, so with moral evil or sin; it is an absence and a lack. It is the absence and lack of the agreement and conformity that should be present between free human conduct (thought, word, deed, desire, omission) and the rule or norm of what that conduct ought to be. It is the lack of conformity between free human activity on the one hand, and the Eternal Law (which is proxi­ mately applied by consicence, that is, by human rea­ son) on the other. Now, it is manifest that physical evils, and moral evils or sins, exist in the world. The question that here arises is : how far are such evils ascribable to the Divine Will? Is God in any sense the cause of any evil? Before answering this question, we recall the fact that, since evil is always a deficiency and a lack, it requires not so much an effecting cause as a deficiency of cause, a cause that fails to function. With this consideration in mind, we give a direct answer to our question. I. God is in no sense the cause of moral evil or sin. The statement means that God does not will sin either per se (that is, in itself) or per accidens (that is, as accidentally and contingently involved in something that He does will). If God could will moral evil per se or in itself, we should be con­ fronted with the absurdity of Infinite Good contra­ dicting Itself, and showing an intrinsic tendency, so IMMANENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 223 to speak, towards all that conflicts with It. God would be a contradiction in Himself, and hence would be, not only imperfect, but impossible. We should have the Perfect Being as imperfect; the Necessary Being as impossible. Reason cannot ac­ cept such absurdities and contradictions, but is forced to acknowledge that God cannot will per se the existence of moral evil or sin. The sinner, there­ fore, is the sole author of sin ; to him alone it is ascribable ; his will is its cause. This does not mean that the sinner is a self-sufficient being, and the creator of his acts ; it means that the sinner is wholly responsible for his failures, his lack of due action, the absence of good which should mark his moral conduct. Remember the truth that sin, like every evil, is a lack and a failure, and in itself requires as cause a defecting, a failing, rather than an efficient or effecting agent. Neither does God will moral evil per accidens. To will evil per accidens is to will it as involved in some­ thing willed in itself, directly or per se; it is to will it on account of a good greater than that to which the evil in question stands opposed. Thus, to borrow an illus­ tration from the physical order, a man walls the pain and inconvenience and expense of a surgical opera­ tion (evils which stand opposed to comfort of body and peace of mind) on account of a good that is greater than comfort or freedom from money­ worries, namely, life itself and solidly established rabiito.... te' THEODICY IMMANENT OPERATIONS OF GOD norma! health. Now, God cannot will moral evil on account of a greater good than that ίο which the evil in question stands opposed. For the evil in question (that is, moral evil or sin) stands opposed, directly and inevitably, to God Himself; for moral evil is evil of human conduct inasmuch as this is out of line with the Eternal Law and is thus opposed to the Divine Essence. And there can be no greater good in no sense the cause of his crime. Your gift involves the possibility op an abuse which is entirely outside 224 than God who is the Infinite Good. Therefore, God cannot will moral evil per accidens. Now, evil that cannot be divinely willed per se or per accidens cannot be divinely willed at all. For there are no other ways of willing moral evil but these two. Therefore, we are forced to the conclusion that God does not will moral evil at all. God is in no sense the cause of moral evil or sin. God is the author of human nature, which is under­ standing and free. Now, human freedom consists es­ sentially in the capacity of a man to choose this or that lawful thing, to act or to refrain from acting when either course is in line with reason ; it does not consist in man’s capacity to obey or disobey, to do good or do evil. To disobey, to do evil, is always an abuse and not a true use of freedom. God, the Creator is the author of human freedom and of its true use, but not of its abuse or sin. If you give a poor man clothing to cover and warm him, you are the true cause of his comfort and warmth ; but if the man uses the clothing to make a rope with which to hang himself, you are 225 your will and intention, and even opposed to your will. So the gift of freedom involves the possibility of abuse, that is, of sin, though sin is entirely opposed to the will of God who bestows the gift. God gives freedom, and lie does not take it away again from normally functioning man, even when the gift is used for a purpose directly opposite to that for which it was given. To give anything to an unperfected being for proper use is to face the possibility of an improper use, and this fact is particularly evident in the case of the gift of freedom. But to give a thing for use, is not to cause or to will its abuse ; on the contrary, it is to will and to make possible its proper use. There­ fore, though God has given man the freedom which man abuses when he sins or commits moral evil, God does not will, even per accidens, this abuse of what was given, and willed, to be properly used. 2. God does not will physical evil per se, but only per accidens. Physical evil is not merely a limitation ; it is a limitation or falling short of a due perfection, that is, of something that should be present. The natural limitations of any finite thing, each in its own order, are not physical evils ; normal limits are not imperfections in the creature which they mark and determine, but, rightly seen, they are perfections. If mere finiteness were a physical evil, the universe and 226 THEODICY all things in it would necessarily suffer this evil, and there would he no such thing as physical perfection; further, the Creator would be the cause /><·/- st of the universal physical evil, even as He is the cause of the existence and nature of creatures. What we mean by physical evil is a lack of normal and finite perfection that should be present in a creature. Sight is a perfec­ tion in man, even though its range be strictly limited ; and lack of sight is an imperfection in man, that is, it is the absence of a natural perfection that ought to be present, and hence it is a physical evil. God the Creator wills the existence of creatures as the secondary object of the Divine Wilk And God wills that creatures should have their being according to the eternal ideas, archetypes, or exemplars in the Di­ vine Mind; these ideas are objectively perfect, each in its kind. Now, we cannot envision an artist or architect turning out broken and incomplete work for its own sake. Nor can reason accept the suggestion that the Divine Architect should will broken and in­ complete creatures for the mere sake of brokenness and incompletion. Hence we declare that God does not will physical evil per se} that is, in or of itself, and for its own sake. Nevertheless physical evils do exist in the world, and they cannot be wholly ascribed to rebellious and defecting human wills as moral evil must be ascribed. Physical evils must, in some manner, be ascribed to God. But we have seen that they cannot be ascribed am- IMMANENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 227 to Him per se. It remains that physical evils are ascrib­ able to God per accidens. To say that God wills physical evils per accidens is to say that God docs not will such evils in themselves and for themselves but inasmuch as they are involved in the accomplishment of a greater good than that to which the evils stand opposed. In other words, God wills this greater good, and the physical evils that accompany its accomplishment are permitted and endured. Now, the great, the controlling, and the allimportant good in the world, in view of which physi­ cal evils must be endured (and thus are divinely willed per accidens') is the right order of the universe, that is, the proper arrangement of fact and function that keeps all things harmoniously tending towards their Last End. The world and all that is in it are to mani­ fest the external glory of the Creator, and man, who holds the highest place among worldly beings, is to know and serve God, by intellect and will, to practise virtue, and so to attain God and happiness for eter­ nity. This is the Last End of visible creation—the manifestation of God’s glory and the service and at­ tainment of God by human beings. This is the great good in view of which or by reason of which order must be conserved even when it involves the enduring of physical evils. Of course, most physical evils would not exist had man not upset the universe by his origi­ nal sin. But since he has done so, physical evils have come upon the world, not by way of punishment 228 Ίι THEODIO merely, but as out of a rearrangement and an ac­ commodation without which man would .surely fail the purpose of his being. For it is a truth capable of clear proof, if not of strict demonstration, that, were (he world still the original paradise, no man would save his soul. A homely and very imperfect analogy may help us understand the place of physical evils in the mainte­ nance of order in the universe. If a family is to have the happiness and the comfort of seemly home-life, right order must be preserved in the home. And this order must be a moral order, touching the relations of the members of the family in point of obedience, mutual respect, affection, deference, consideration, and sacrifice; and it must be a material order touching all the physical details of homemaking and housekeep­ ing. There can be no peace and joy in the home that is torn with dissensions, marred by disobedience and want of respect, spoiled by selfishness. Nor can there be happiness in the home that is carelessly managed, unclean, needlessly disordered. If the family is to have peace and happiness, there are sacrifices to be endured; if it is to have decent comfort, there are inconveniences to be undergone. Peace is purchased by much self-sacrifice; rest is purchased by labor; cleanliness is bought at the price of continual care and effort. Now, if the right order of the home is bound up with the hardships of self-sacrifice, self-denial, wage-earning, washing, sweeping, cooking, endless IMMANENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 229 putting to rights, so the right order in the universe is bound up with the enduring of physical evils. And, as the homemaker wills per se the peace and happiness of family life, and thus wills per accidens all the in­ conveniences, sacrifices, and discomforts that are in­ volved in maintaining that life, so the Divine Ruler of the world wills per se the eternal peace and happi­ ness of men, and thus wills per accidens all the hard­ ships (called physical evils) which are involved in the ordering of the world in view of that great end. The order of the universe, like that of the home, is both a moral and a material order. Towards the maintenance, and the continual restoration, of this order, physical evils are divinely willed per accidens. The destruction of vegetal life is a physical evil for the plants involved, but it is necessary for the main­ taining of the material order: without it animal life could not endure, nor could man be properly housed and clothed. So also the destruction of animal life for the support of human life is a physical evil for the animals concerned ; yet it is necessary to preserve the order of a world which is for man before all other creatures. And the suffering that man must endure in his body during life, and the hardship of death which must come to all, are stern reminders of moral duty ; they keep a man aware of the fact that his last­ ing good is not here, and that he has a great task to perform and small time in which to accomplish its proper performance. Further, these physical evils are 230 THEODICY means of penance by which a man may remedy the faults of the past, and they are apt exercises by which he may strengthen himself for meeting the trials of the future. Even the suffering of animals, their pains, their diseases, and their death, are, to a thoughtful man, strong incentives to eternal human weal ; they show man what havoc the original sin has wrought upon earth; they impress upon man a better under­ standing of the awful evil of sin; they stir man to penance and reparation. SUMMARY OF THE ARTICLE In this Article we have studied the meaning of the Divine Will, and we have learned that God is truly Infinite Will just as He is Infinite Intellect. We have discussed the antecedent wilt and the consequent will of God. We have learned that the primary object of the Divine Will is the essence of God, or God Him­ self, so that God necessarily loves Himself by infinite and eternal Love which is identified with His own Being. We have seen that the secondary object of the Divine Will are creatures, that is, things other than God, which He wills freely. We have considered the existence of evil (moral and physical) in the world, and have found that God’s will has no part whatever in moral evil, so that He wills it neither per se nor per accidens; and that Lie wills physical evils only per accidens, that is, inasmuch as these are involved in the good which He wills per se. IMMANENT OPERATIONS OF GOD Article 3. The Personal Nature of 231 God a) Meaning of Person b) The Personality of God c) Mistaken Notions on the Point a) meaning of person Philosophers define person as “a complete indi­ vidual and autonomous substance of the rational or­ der.” It will be well for us to examine this definition carefully, weighing the meaning of every phrase. I. A person is a substance. The world of creatures is classified as substances and accidents. A substance is a being that is fitted to exist itself, and not merely as the mark, modification, or qualification of some­ thing else. An accident is a reality that is fitted to exist, not in itself or by itself, but as the mark, modi­ fication, or qualification of something else. A man is a substance; the man’s weight, his height, his name, his abilities, are accidents. An apple is a substance ; its size, color, flavor, hardness or softness, roughness or smoothness, are accidents. Now, it is manifest that the substantial mode of existence (that is, existence of a thing as a substance) is more perfect than the accidental mode. When, therefore, we apply to God the terminology which belongs, in strictest sense, to creatures only, it is inevitable that we should attribute to the Infinite Being the more perfect, and not the less perfect, mode of existence. We say that God is a substance. For, while God is not merely fitted to 232 THEODICY exist Himself, but is the Necessary Being which exists Itself and of Itself (hence, causelessly), we use the term substance as the best we have, and the nearest in meaning, to express the Divine mode of existence. God is a substance; nay, lie is a super-substance ; He is the substance far excellence. And God is purest substance, for there is about Him nothing accidental. All that God has, God is; God is not qualified, marked, or modified by anything attached to or added to His essence. When, therefore, we call God a personal God, we mean, first of all, that God is substantial; He is a substance ; He is no mere abstraction, no vaguely con­ ceived Energy or Power or hovering Atmosphere which men assume in any effort to interpret the uni­ verse. We have already proved that God is the Infinite Spirit. And a spirit is a substance. God is Infinite Spiritual Substance. 2. A person is a complete substance. Among crea­ tures, a complete substance requires no co-substance with which to join in producing a rounded substantial existence. A man, for example, is a complete sub­ stance. But a man’s body, considered alone, is not a complete substance. A man’s body cannot exist as a human body unless the soul in-form it and make it a human body; it is a substance, but not a complete one, since it requires the existence and co-operation of an­ other substance (the soul) to give it completeness and its being and operation as human. Now, a person IMMANENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 233 is not a substantial element of something else ; it is a complete substance. It is manifest that God, the Di­ vine Substance, is a complete substance, for God is simple, and there cannot conceivably be any co-substance added to Him to round out His essence. God is a complete substance. When we say that God has a personal nature, or that God is a personal God, we mean, first of all, that God is a complete and perfect substance. 5. A person is an individual substance. An indi­ vidual is a being that is not distinguished as a plu­ rality; it is just that one thing; and it is distinguished or marked off from everything else. “An individual,” says St. Thomas Aquinas, “is that which is undivided in itself, and is divided off from everything not itself.” Of course, the first suggestion in the idea of individu­ ality is that of a plurality or group of things which are of the same essential kind (as, for example, a group of human beings), each member of which is individuated or marked off from each other member. When we use the term individual with reference to God, we do not accept this first suggestion of the idea of individuality. We do not mean that God is one God among several Gods all of whom have the same kind of nature or essence. For God is one, and the only God, as we have elsewhere proved. We mean, when we call God an individual substance, that He is not plural but one in His essence and nature. We ! 234 ll ■ y/ ; THEODICY cannot employ unaided reason in the discussion of the Trinity of Persons in the One Divine Essence and Nature. But we may say that reason can discover no disproof, no difficulty, in the concept of the Trinity. For a rational essence or nature subsists inasmuch as it lias personality ; and there is nothing in the concept of nature and essence, or in the concept of personality, to manifest a contradiction and an impossibility in the thought of one essence, one nature, subsisting in a plurality of persons. This subject, however, is not for our present discussion. We are concerned here with the individuality of God, which means the indi­ viduality, the oneness, completeness, undividedness, of His Divine Essence. Individuality of essence is requisite for personality, whether that personality be singular or plural. 4. A person is an autonomous substance. The word autonomous mean “operating by its own law.” The ancient Latin phrase for this term is sui juris “operat­ ing by its own right.” Not every substance is autono­ mous. A man’s hand, for example, is a substance; but its operations are not its own; its operations are operations of the man who has the hand. Another way of putting the matter is this: a man’s hand is a sub­ stance; it has substantiality; but it is not subsistent, it lacks subsistence of its own. That which constitutes a substance as sui juris or autonomous is the crowning oerfection of an individual complete substance, and IMMANENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 235 the name of this perfection is subsistence. Every com­ plete individual substance has subsistence or is auton­ omous. God is, as we have seen, a perfect, complete, individual substance; He is, therefore, a subsistent substance, an autonomous substance. 5. A person is a sub stance of the rational order. A being is said to be “of the rational order” when it is endowed with understanding and will. Now, we have seen that God is Infinite Understanding and Infinite Will. He is therefore, perfectly and infinitely, “of the rational order.” The crowning perfection which sets up a substance as autonomous in its own order is its subsistence, and that special subsistence which con­ stitutes a substance as a being of the rational order is called personality. Any complete individual autono­ mous substance of the rational order has personality or is a person. God, therefore, has personality or is a person. That His personality is not single but trinal, is not of present concern. The only point here to be established is that God is truly personal. b) THE PERSONALITY OF GOD When we speak of God as “a personal God” we mean that God is a true person. Faith informs us that God subsists in three Persons. But that point does not touch our present discussion at all. For we mean, when we call God “a personal God,” that He is truly a substantial Being, complete and perfect and autono- 236 THEODICY mous, and that He knows all things and rules all by His will. Those who deny the personality of God, or profess to believe in “a God but not in a personal God," have some dim notion of a world-force or world-energy directing things blindly, or unfolding itself uncon­ sciously in what we call the development of the world and the progress of events. It is strange that men should be content with such a doctrine, for it conflicts with plain reason and it defeats all the finest tend­ encies of human nature. Yet it is a sad fact that many men, who are very keen on matters of business or sport or pleasure or sin, are very dull on the one matter of overwhelming importance which the human mind has to face, in some manner, and the human will, directly or indirectly, to embrace or reject. Some­ times one hears from unexpected sources a remark which presents in concentrated form all the proud smugness, all the deep stupidity, all the imbecility of which the twisted mind of fallen man is capable. It is the remark that “an intelligent person cannot admit the need or the existence of a personal God.” Precisely the opposite, exactly the contradictory of this state­ ment is true. An intelligent person,—that is, a truly thoughtful and reasonable person, not one who has been labeled intelligent by a college or university, for such labels are cheap and often meaningless,-—is in­ evitably aware of the existence of God; and the measure of intelligence in such a person is the measure IMMANENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 237 with which he recognizes the fact that God is ail-wise and all-provident; in a word, that God is infinitely personal. All the world’s best minds have recognized the personal character of God, almost without excep­ tion. And if the man of importance in college or club, in business or profession, is found to be a scoffer, he may be marked down as a man of no lasting conse­ quence; the whole of human history will back that judgment. Make the rounds of the modern secular (and sectarian!") universities, and look for the faculty-members who profess atheism, agnoticism, or disbelief in a personal God. You will find them, nine times out of ten, in the ranks of the callow instructors, and not among the seasoned professors and heads of departments. For the rest, the gloss of what we have come to call “education” is not a proof of wisdom or of intelligence. Mr. Dooley did not say a contradictory thing, but rather a thing to provoke thought, when he declared, “Hogan is the best read and most ignorant man I know.” It is a demonstrable truth that man cannot come to the full and practised use of his faculties without recognizing the existence of God. If a normal and mature man could be ignorant of God’s existence, his ignorance would certainly be his own fault ; it would be culpable ignorance ; it would be what philosophers call vincible ignorance, that is, ignorance that can be dispelled by ordinary effort and attention. And as a matter of fact (which we have elsewhere considered), : j -■ I j [ j j | j a | g | | | I 238 THEODICY a man who fails to know, or who ignores, the true God, inevitably sets up false gods. But the truly intelligent man cannot be satisfied with false gods. Nor can such a man dwell long upon the facts pre­ sented to his consideration by the world around him, without coming to some understanding of the person­ ality of the true God, the one and infinite First Being. Personality is a pure perfection. But, as we have repeatedly noticed, all pure perfection, in transcendent degree, must be attributed formally to the First and the Necessary Being. Therefore, personality must be attributed to God. God is a personal God. c) mistaken notions on the point The reason which leads many men to reject the terminology of “a personal God” lies in their own mistaken concept of person. To them, a person is a hitman person. The term person suggests not only a substance of the rational order, but a being with body as well as mind (not to utter the terrible word soul'). To them a person is a being with eyes and ears and hands and feet. And, of course, a person need be no such thing. An angel is a person, but it has no body. A human soul is personal, and indeed a person, al­ though not the whole of the human person, and a soul has no bodily members. It is a sad mistake on the part of the “intelligent” men who find it hard to accept “a personal God” that they misconceive person to begin IMMANENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 239 with, and then attribute their own misconception to others and find fault λ\ ith these for accepting it. In brief , these “intelligent” men set up a wholly '(anthro­ pomorphic jidea of God, which is false on the face of it, and then declare that this idea is what other men mean by a personal God. It is a mistake to conceive of a personal God as a kind of benign human giant who has great forces under his control, a penetrating mind, a keen eye, a watchful concern for the affairs of men. It is a mis­ take to think that religion consists in a kind of friendly feeling for this gigantic and powerful being. It is a mistake to conceive of morality as the effort to please this mighty giant and to avoid what offends him. These notions are all false because they all limit God and reduce Elim to the horrid status of a mere superman. The idea of personality in God really in­ volves no such belittling absurdities. Of course, we use human and analogical terms in speaking of the true God, but no truly intelligent man is misled by the limitations of human speech. We do say that God hears our prayers, that Elis eye is ever upon us, that He is concerned for our welfare, that He leads us by His mighty hand. But we recognize, in all these ex­ pressions, the material and figurative expression of what is strictly inexpressible in the essentially limited terms of language, and even of thought. God is in­ comprehensible and ineffable ; He is not to be ade- μημμμββ 240 THEODICY quately known or adequately expressed by human (that is, by finite or limited) means. But what cannot be exhaustively understood and expressed can be understood and expressed in some measure; and it is futile to find fault with human minds and human tongues for their connatural limitations; it is un­ reasonable, too, to belittle human thought because language does not adequately express it. Indeed, we use many expressions, even with reference to worldly and material things, which are, upon strict analysis, faulty and even untrue ; yet these expressions do not mean that the things which they inadequately express are untrue. We speak of a sunrise or of a sunset, and, of course, there is no such thing. But we do not ac­ cuse the man who tells us that he saw a fine sunrise, of a lack of intelligence. We know what he means; we understand that the handy term “sunrise” ex­ presses what would otherwise have to be expressed in a roundabout and lengthy description of the move­ ment of the earth on its axis and its relation to a relatively stationary sun. So when we hear a man speaking of God as hearing our prayers, or seeing our actions, we know what he means ; we do not ac­ cuse him of lack of intelligence; we do not (unless we are of the stupid intelligentsia) imagine that his concept of God is that of a giant with immense ears and with eyes that pierce the clouds above our heads. We know that the man is merely expressing in human and understandable terms the fact that God knows IMMANENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 241 all things and infinitely provides from eternity for all human needs. In a word, we know that the man is speaking of the Infinite Personal Being in the limited terms of a human and· finite personal being, but we are not deceived into thinking that these limited terms mean a similarly limited concept of God in the mind of the speaker. The mistake we have been considering comes, in last analysis, to this : the objectors to “a personal God” always understand by the phrase a being that can be pictured in the imagination. Now, the imagination is a sentient faculty, and its images are all limited and material. God, on the other hand, is non-limited and non-material. It is manifest that there can be no imagination-image, no fancy-picture of God. Nor in­ deed can there be a picture in imagination of any spiritual, that is, non-material, being. Still, imagina­ tion is always trying to serve mind ; it does its best, however little that best may be; and the result of its efforts lies before us in symbolism and art. Of course, this effort of imagination may be very beautiful and very serviceable, but one must never forget that its character is symbolic and not literal. There is no harm, and there may be much good, in picturing an angel as a princely figure, clothed in flowing robes, beautiful of feature, equipped with manifestly inade­ quate wings which seem rooted in the shoulder-blades. There is no harm even in tlie added details of such a picture, details with which we are all familiar, such as 242 THEODICY the obese violin, the foreshortened bow, the ecstatic turn of the angelic eye, the fetching curl of the angelic hair. But it would be a stupid blunder to suppose that this pictured figure is a portrait of an angel, that this material image is a literal likeness of a being that is not material at all. We can take emotional inspiration from a pictured angel ; we can allow the high emotion to influence will and conduct; but we are never for a moment deceived about the image itself. We know that it is a material symbol of a spiritual substance. So too we may find muth that is helpful in the art which seeks to express the Infinite Being in sensible terms. We may be reminded of the Divine Knowledge and of the Holy Trinity by the picture of a great human eye, enclosed in a triangle which suggests the Trinity. But we are not thereby deceived into thinking that God is an eye or that the Trinity is a plane figure of three straight lines and three angles. If we have imagination to serve us in the evolving of symbolism, we have mind which makes us understand symbolism as symbolism and not as literal fact. The educated Catholic has no apologies to make to the objector who finds the idea of “a personal God” unacceptable. The Catholic need not side-step, need not offer the least compromise. What he needs to do for the objector in question is to exercise one of those splendid social virtues called the spiritual works of mercy; he needs “to instruct the ignorant.” A,.k htLa&jft Aaà.- -^.£ y<.. μ :::, 4' ^ΣΤΤ1:··;.λΐ IMMAXTNT OPERATIONS OF GOD 243 SUMMARY OF THE ARTICLE In this Article we have learned, by careful analysis of the definition, the true meaning of person, and we have seen that God is a person, that He is a personal God, and not some vague world-force or some un­ conscious energy evolving itself in what we call the visible universe. We have not dared to overstep the boundaries of philosophical science and to discuss the threefold personality of God in the Blessed Trin­ ity. We have merely mentioned in passing that human reason is inadequate to deal with this surpassing mys­ tery, either to prove it or to disprove it, either to find it manifested to reason or to find it in conflict with reason. But our point of discussion has been found unaffected by the Trinity of Persons in God, since God is a personal God regardless of the singularity or the plurality of persons in which the one undivided Divine Essence subsists. It is the Divine Essence, the Divine Nature, that we find a personal Nature. It is of the Divine Nature that reason is forced to predicate personality and to declare that God is a true person. We have discussed the common errors about the personality of God which lead unthinking men to dis­ like and even to reject the idea of God as a person. CHAPTER Π THE TRANSIENT OPERATIONS OF GOD This Chapter discusses what are inaccurately called God’s transient operations, that is, the operations which make a transit or go across from God to things other than God; in a word, the operations that proceed from God to the uni­ verse to produce, preserve, control and govern it, and to concur with it in its connatural and dependent activities. Now, while there is a real relation to God on the part of creatures, there is no real relation to creatures on the part of God; God would be God in eternal and infinite com­ pleteness were there no creatures; nothing is added to God by the existence or function of creatures; nothing can be taken from God by the being or activity of creatures, nor by the non-existence of creatures. But creatures depend for their whole being and operation upon God. Creatures are effected and affected essentially by God ; God is not affected at all by creatures. This is the reason for our statement that there is no real relation to creatures on the part of God, while there is an essential and real relation to God on the part of creatures. Further, what we call God’s transient operations involve no transiency, no change or mutability, in God Himself. Among finite things, transient activity proceeds from an agent (or actor or doer) and primarily affects something other than the agent ; yet there is always some change or passing movement in the agent itself as the transient activity is accomplished. But when God is the agent, this is not so. There is no change, no transiency in God, as His eternal and changeless decrees find their ac- TRANSIENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 245 tualization in temporal anti changeable creatures. Thus the term transient operations is not to be taken in literal, but in analogical, meaning when it is applied to God, The socalled transient operations of God may be lifted as four: creation, conservation, concurrence, governance (101th providence). These operations we discuss in four Articles, as follows. Article I. Article 2. Article 3. Article 4. The The The The Divine Operation of Creation Divine Operation of Conservation Divine Operation of Concurrence Divine Operation of Governance and Providence Article i. The Divine Operation of Creation a) The Power of God b) Meaning of Creation c) The Fact of Creation a) the power of god Before discussing the exercise of God’s power in the transient divine operations it may be well to say a word on this power itself. We have already seen that God is infinite in all perfection, and power, that is, the ability to make and to do and to accomplish, is in itself a pure perfection. Therefore God must have power. Further, since God is infinitely simple, all that God has, He is. God’s power is, therefore, really identified with the Divine Essence Itself; God is Infinite Power. We express this truth about God when we say that He is omnipotent or almighty. Our catechism expresses the same truth when it declares that “God can do all things, and nothing is hard or impossible to Elim.” 246 THEODICY There are several points to be noticed about the power of God. First, it is not a power that is exer­ cised by effort. Effort suggests imperfection; it means the expenditure of power to overcome ob­ stacles; but there can be no obstacles (or limits) in the way of illimitable power. God’s power is exer­ cised by the Divine Intellect and Will. God is the perfect agens per intellectum et voluntatem (“Agent or actor by intellect and will”). With God, to will is to accomplish. Secondly, God’s infinite power is humanly ex­ pressed as an ability to do all things. And “things” is a word that means what it says; it does not mean contradictions, that is, denials of things. That God cannot make a square circle, or that God cannot make a “two-year-old colt in a minute,” is not a limitation of the unlimited Divine Power. For a square circle means a circle that is not a circle; in a word, it means nothing; it means not a thing but the cancellation and the denial of a thing. So a two-yearold colt that is only a minute old, is a two-year-old that is not a two-year-old, a manifest contradiction. Now, contradictions are intrinsic impossibilities; they are inconceivable as things because they are the opposite of things. This point we have already dis­ cussed and evidenced in the First Book of this manual. Thirdly, God’s power, looked at simply in itself is God’s absolute power. And God’s power, re- TRANSIENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 247 garded as it stands aligned with the other Divine Perfections,—such as Goodness, Wisdom, Justice,— is God’s ordina ted power. Of course, this distinction is one required by our limited minds; for in God Himself all these Perfections are identified with each other and with the Divine Essence Itself. We say that all things are possible to God’s absolute power, but certain things are not possible to God’s ordinated power. .For example, it is within the ab­ solute power of God to take an unrepentant sinner into the glory of Heaven. But, since such an act on God’s part would conflict with the freedom of the human will on the one hand, and with Divine Jus­ tice on the other, we say that it is not within God’s ordinated power so to save a sinner against his will. When, therefore, we say that God is almighty or omnipotent, we mean that God, by the effortless ex­ ercise of the Divine Will (eternally illuminated by the Divine Intellect) can bring into being anything that is not a conflict in itself (and hence a non­ entity, a nothing) or in conflict with the Divine Per­ fections. b) meaning of creation Creation is a term often used in English in a two­ fold meaning. It is used to indicate the act or opera­ tion of creating, and it is used to indicate the fruit or product of this act. Thus we speak of the creation of the world as the operation whereby God produces 248 THEODICY the world. And we may, in emotional moments, sing “All up and down the whole creation:” using the word creation to indicate the world itself which is the fruit or product of the operation <>f creating. Tn our present study we use the terni creation in its active or dynamic sense; we use it to indicate the divine activity or operation whereby God produces things out of nothing. There is a third use of the term creation which we must notice and wholly re­ ject for philosophical purposes; it is that use in which the term is taken as a synonym for product; arrangement; thing made of elements or materials. Thus the milliner may speak of a hat as a “Parisian creation”; thus the poet may speak of his newest sonnet as the creature of his fancy, that is, as a thing created by his mind and imagination. Our study of the definition of creation will show us that this ex­ tended meaning of the term creation is wholly alien to our understanding of it in philosophy. Creation is the active producing of a thing in its entirety out of nothing. It is the producing of a thing, whole and entire, without using any materials of any sort. Philosophers say that the creation of a thing is the total production of the thing ex nihil sui et subjecti, that is, without any element or seedling of the thing being there to begin with (ex nihil sui), and without any materials or subject-matter (ex nihil subjecti} out of which the thing is to be formed. When we say that the Creator makes things out w-jï-’a.faïJis TRANSIENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 249 of nothing, we do not mean that “nothing” is itself a kind of material which is divinely shaped into realities. We mean that, whereas there is nothing to begin with, now, by an act of the Divine Under­ standing and Will, there is something real, lienee, our idea of creation involves no conflict with the axiom ex nihilo nihil fit (“Out of nothing, nothing is made”) since the axiom means that the produc­ tion of things out of elements or materials requires that the elements or materials be there at the outset. But creation is not the production of things out of elements or materials, and hence the absence of these things is in no wise a difficulty to one who can create. Some philosophers, like Victor Cousin (17921867) and Aloysius Ferri (1826-1895), have de­ fined creation in a way that suggests that God draws all creatures out of Himself. This sort of definition is pantheistic in implication, and seems to make the world of creatures part and parcel with the Divine Essence. We cannot accept such a definition of cre­ ation, for it would involve us in hopeless contradic­ tions, making the changeless God one with the changeable world, and the Infinite and Necessary Being one with the contingent universe. Of course, if the phrase “out of Himself” is interpreted to mean “by means of His own unaided power and ir­ resistible will,” it may stand unchallenged; but it is manifest that the phrase is not necessarily to be so interpreted ; it is an indefinite phrase, capable of con- 2.5θ THEODICY dieting interpretations, and hence it is unsuitable for scientific expression. When we say that God creates, we mean that God, by the power of Ilis will, causes things to come into actuality without using any '‘materials'’ of any sort. We mean that God makes substances without re­ quiring any source-substance out of which to make them. All bodily substances have their first origin in creation ; thereafter,—since bodies are substantially changeable,—they normally produce other bodies by the process of substantial transformation called gener­ ation and corruption. All spiritual substances are di­ rectly created, nor can these generate further spiritual substances or undergo any corruption, for spiritual substances are not subject to substantial transforma­ tion. It may be asked whether this thing called creation is possible ; whether there is not in the idea of creation an involved conflict or contradiction ; whether there is not something in creation that is in conflict with God’s ordinated power; whether, finally, there is not something on the part of finite things that resists the notion of sheer production by way of creation. We must consider this question in its three points. Wj. Creation involves in itself, that is, in its very Concept or idea, no contradiction or conflict. It is not an unthinkable thing like a square circle. Indeed, the concept or idea of creation is so far from being self- TRANSIENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 251 contradictory that it imposes itself as necessary upon the mind that seeks to account for the existence of contingent realities. For such things do not have to exist; their existence is explicable only on the grounds that they have been given existence, that they have been brought into existence. And, in last analy­ sis, their being brought into existence must mean their being brought out of nothingness, that is, in their being created; for there can be no endless process of one such thing coming from another, and this from another, and so on forever. There must have been a first production of contingent things ; there must have been a beginning, and a truly first beginning, of things that have in themselves no necessity or absolute re­ quirement for existence. But a truly first production of contingent things is inconceivable except as crea­ tion. Therefore, on the score of the very idea or concept of creation, we find no conflict, no selfcontradiction, no impossibility. On this score, crea­ tion means something entirely possible. 2. Creation involves no contradiction or conflict among the perfections of God; it does not suggest something that is out of harmony with the ordinated Divine Power. For it does not involve the notion of a filling-up or filling-out of the Infinite Being by the existence of finite beings. If creation were conceived of as a thing required by God, or as an activity im­ posed upon God by extrinsic force or even by His 252 THEODICY own goodness, it would conflict with the Divine Per­ fections and so would be impossible to Cod's ordinated power. But we have already seen that Cod is not affected by creatures ; that there is no real relation on (Sod’s part towards them, even though there is an essential and real relation on the part of creatures towards Him; God is wholly and infinitely complete and perfect in Himself without creatures. I?or the rest, God’s power would be incomplete, and not in­ finite, were creation impossible to Him. The idea of creation as truly possible is included in the very idea of the Divine Power. Nor is the idea of creation in any conceivable disagreement with the Divine Wis­ dom, the Divine Justice, the Divine Goodness, or any other of the perfections of God; on the contrary, it appears, both at first sight and upon penetrating study, to be in complete harmony with all the Divine Per­ fections and a worthy external expression and mani­ festation of them. Therefore, on the score of God’s ordinated power, we find no conflict or contradiction in the idea of creation. On this score, creation means something wholly possible. 5. Creation manifestly involves no conflict on the part of things created, that is, on the part of creatures. For such things are existible; they can exist, as is evident in the fact that they do exist ; they can receive existence, and indeed must receive existence if they are to have it at all. But creation is neither more nor j1 TRANSIENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 253 less than the very Erst giving (and receiving) of ex­ istence: it is the giving of existence by the Creator, the receiving of existence by the creature. So far from being out of harmony with the notion of con­ tingent things, creation is necessary to explain the first existence of such things. The meaning of the term creation is, therefore, a consistent and an intelligible meaning. Creation as the fundamental production of contingent substances is conceivable as something entirely possible. We have, later on, to discuss it as something inescapably actual, as an incontrovertible fact. But first we must round out our study of the meaning of creation by inquiring whether it means an activity proper to God alone, or one communicable by God to creatures so that crea­ tures in their turn may create. We must assert at once that creation is so entirely proper to God alone that creatures cannot serve, even instrumentally, as creating agents. Only God can create; creatures cannot be creators either as principal agents or as instrumental agents. We pause upon the three points of this statement. I. Only God can create. A being capable of creat­ ing, that is, of bringing substances into actual exist­ ence without using any pre-existing materials, is a being wholly independent of such materials; such a being has no dependency on substances outside itself. THEODICY This is manifestly true. For where there is nothing of finite substance to begin with, nothing by way of start or element or seedling, and nothing by way of materials out of which to construct a substance (mini sui et subjecti) there is no conceivable way of effect­ ing the production except by sheer intellectual power, that is, by sheer will. And a will that can produce sub­ stances by its own simple exercise is manifestly an independent will, an effortless will, an unhampered or unlimited will. Now, the concept of such a will is the concept of an infinite will. And only God is in­ finite; only God is Infinite Will. Therefore, only God can create. 2. Creatures cannot create as principal agents. This truth is manifest from the foregoing argument, for no creature is possessed of infinite will, and infinite will is required in the principal agent or principal cause of the creative act. 5. Creatures cannot create as instrumental agents. The statement means that no creature can serve God in creating, as a tool or instrument or bodily member can serve man, for example, in his activities. In the act of writing, for instance, man uses the conjoined natural instruments of arm, hand, and fingers, and the artificial instrument of pen or pencil. The man is the principal agent or cause of the writing, but to effect the writing he uses the instrumental causes or TRANSIENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 255 agencies of bodily members and writing-tool. Now we assert that God cannot use creatures as His instru­ ments in creating, nor does this mean a lack of perfec­ tion in God; on the contrary, it indicates the Divine Sufficiency which requires no instruments for its activities. For the requiring of instruments is a mixed or non-pure perfection, involving imperfec­ tion. That a man can write with movements of hand and application of pen or pencil, is a perfection; that a man must employ these instruments to produce the writing, is a limiting thing and an imperfection. But in God there is no shadow of imperfection. Certainly, then, God could never require the service of instru­ ments in creating. But neither is it limiting the power of God to say that He cannot use instruments in the creative activity. For an instrument must have some connatural fitness for the service in which it is em­ ployed, and no creature has the fitness, the infinite fulness, requisite to serve as the physical channel of creative power ; hence, the impossibility of using creatures as instrumental agents in creating is the in­ adequacy of creatures and not the inadequacy of God. To convey infinite power physically by means of an instrument (were that even conceivable) would re­ quire infinity in the instrument as well as in the princi­ pal agent or cause. But the thought of an infinite instrument (that is, an infinite creature) is a selfcontradictory thought ; it indicates something sheerly and intrinsically impossible, as a square circle is im- 256 THEODICY possible. Hence, since finite instruments arc inade­ quate, and since infinite instruments arc unthinkable, we say that no instrumental cause or agency can be used in creating. Further, the use of an instrument is always the employment of it upon some subject, upon something preexisting which récriées the in­ strumental action. But creation is an activity which deals with no subject, no preexisting item, element, or material, for it is the production of a thing in its entirety out of nothing. Therefore, no instrument could render any conceivable service to the creating God. By creation, then, we mean that activity,—which is so proper to God alone that creatures cannot serve even instrumentally in its exercise,—whereby the Di­ vine Power produces realities in their entirety, using nothing preexisting as the font or source of the pro­ duction. c) THE FACT OF CREATION The world of finite realities challenges our atten­ tion and demands a sufficient accounting. We must face and answer the question of the first origin of contingent things. And our answer must be one of three : for I. either the world,-—that is, the universe of finite, changing things about us, and ourselves as part of that universe,—has had no beginning, or 2. the world is only a part or phase of God’s own being and substance, or 3. the world has its origin in the TRANSIENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 257 creative action of God. All theories on first origins in the universe are reducible to these three and to these only. Now, we find the first two of these theories wholly unacceptable as in open conflict with experi­ ence and with reason, and thus we arc compelled to accept the third theory, the theory of creation, as the true and factual doctrine. The world had its first origin in creation; the world was created ; the world is a world of creatures. Let us glance at some reasons which compel this conclusion. I. The world cannot be, as the materialists say, an eternal and unproduced universe. For what is eternal and unproduced must have in itself the sufficient reason for its existence, the ratio sufficiens existentiac suae, which is required to account for every actuality. But an actuality that has in itself the sufficient reason for its existence is pure actuality; it is necessary being, and, by that fact, it is infinite, absolutely simple or uncomposed, and changeless. Now, it is manifest that the world is not necessary, but contingent ; not purely actual, but also potential, not infinite, but limited; not simple, but a manifold or compound ; not changeless, but full of motion or change. Therefore, the world is not eternal and unproduced. But if it is not eternal and unproduced, it has had a beginning, an origin. We cannot, therefore, accept the theory which de­ clares that rhe world has had no origin, no producing cause. 25« THEODICY 2. The world cannot be, as the pantheists say, an outpouring of God, or a phase of God's being and substance, hirst of all, such an outpouring or phase would be a kind of evolution or development of the Divine Substance, and this would involve potentiality in God who is Pure Actuality ; it would involve change in the Immutable Being; it would involve develop­ ment or improvement in the All Perfect. These are manifest contradictions and are wholly impossible. Further, to identify God in any manner with the world is to impose upon God the properties and in­ separable characteristics of the world. It is to make God finite, compounded, contingent, whereas, as we have already proved, God is infinite, simple, neces­ sary. Reason forces us to reject the pantheistic theory of the first origin of the world. 5. If the world is neither unproduced, nor somehow identified with the Divine Substance, it is a world that has had its origin as something other than God. Now, there is no conceivable first origin of things other than God except an origin by way of creation. There­ fore, the world has had its first origin in creation ; the world was created ; creation is an actual fact. SUMMARY OF THE ARTICLE In this Article we have discussed the Divine Power, and have seen that God is necessarily almighty or TRANSIENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 259 omnipotent, and can do all things which involve no intrinsic contradiction (and hence are nothings or not-things). We have distinguished the power of God as absolute and ordinated, according as it is con­ sidered in itself or in conjunction with the goodness, justice, wisdom, and other perfections of God. We have defined creation as the active producing of a thing in its entirety out of nothing. We have justified this definition and have rejected faulty ones, such as those proposed by Cousin and Ferri. We have seen that creation is something wholly possible, since it is thinkable in itself, it does not conflict with the Divine Perfections, and it involves no conflict on the part of things to be produced by it. Further, we have found that creation is inevitably a direct, exercise of infinite power, and is therefore an activity so proper to God alone that creatures cannot serve, even instrumentally, in its exercise. We have seen that creation is not only possible but that the first origin of things other than God must lie in God’s creative action, and that, in consequence ; creation is a fact. Article 2. of The Divine Operation Conservation a) Meaning of Conservation b) The Fact of Divine Conservation a) MEANING OF CONSERVATION Conservation means preservation. As an activity 26ο ΤΗ EO DIC Y or operation, conservation is the preserving of an effect in existence. There are causes in fieri and causes in esse. A. cause in fieri (or “in becoming’’) is required to firing an effect into existence: a cause in esse (or “in being’’) is required to maintain an effect in existence. A cause in fieri is a producing cause; a cause in esse is a con­ serving cause. Conservation is the exercise of a cause in esse. When an effect depends essentially for both pro­ duction and permanence (for fieri and esse) upon a cause, that one identical cause must continue in ac­ tivity or exercise as long as the effect exists. Thus fire is required both to make iron hot and to keep it hot; the sun is required to produce daylight and to maintain daylight. For there is an essential depend­ ency, for both production and permanence, of heat upon fire and of daylight upon the sun. But when the dependency of effect upon cause is essential only in point of production and not of permanence, the effect may be supported in being by another cause than that which gave it being. In other words, the cause in fieri need not, in this case, continue on as the cause in esse. Thus, the sculptor is the cause in fieri of the statue which he carves, but he is not its cause in esse; the accidental form or being which the sculptor confers upon marble by shaping it in a certain way finds a sufficient supporting or conserving cause in the en­ during stuff of which the statue is made; its cause TRANSIENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 261 in esse is the marble itself, and the statue may con­ tinue in c.xistcnce for centuries after the sculptor is in his grave. Eut, ultimately, as ah things work back to first creation as their cause in fieri, so they workback to that same single creating cause as their radical cause in esse ; the creating cause must continue on as a conserving cause, else creatures must fall to noth­ ingness. Here we sec what is meant by the statement that conservation is a continuation of creation. For creation does not bestow being upon something that is already there to receive and hold it; it produces being in entirety out of nothingness; the creature is, in consequence, dependent for both production and permanence upon its creating cause, and this one identical cause must continue in activity or exercise as long as the creature exists. Conservation is the activity of a cause in esse. It means the preserving of an effect in being and exist­ ence. Conservation is direct or indirect. Direct conserva­ tion is the positive preserving of an effect by an ac­ tivity which supplies actual being to the effect or contributes what actively supports the effect in its being. Thus, fire directly conserves the heat in hot water; thus the sun directly conserves the daylight; thus the eating of food directly conserves life and strength. Indirect conservation is the negative pre­ serving of an effect by the exercise of a cause which protects the effect, shields it, wards off or prevents ββ s 262 (fpiEODICv what would harm and destroy it. The placing of a manuscript in an air-tight case is an act of indirect conservation. The enclosing of a delicate vase in a cabinet where it is safe from the sweep of careless hands is also an act of indirect conservation. The nurse-maid who watches an infant so that it does not fall into the fire, or climb to perilous places, or eat what would harm it, is indirectly conserving the wel­ fare of the child. Direct conservation may be called promotive conservation; indirect conservation is, rather preventive. ΐ It is our contention that Divine Conservation is a fact in the world, and that this is not merely indirect, but direct conservation. b) THE FACT OF DIVINE CONSERVATION I. Creatures are contingent realities. They have not in themselves any requirement for existence. They are not self-accounting, self-explanatory, selfsufficient. That they exist is a patent fact; that they do not have to exist is equally evident, for they come into being, they change, they are limited, and things subject to beginning, change, and limitation, are sub­ ject to the action of causes; such things are effects; they are dependent or contingent or non-necessary things. Now, manifestly, contingent things do not lose their contingency when they are created. They require positive production of their entire being in the first moment of their existence, and they require 4^^-ftOS-^^ÎÎS^S™ TRANSIENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 263 a continuance of the producing power at every suc­ cessive moment of their existence. No other or lesser power than their first-producing power (that is, their creating power) will account for their continued existence, since their entire being rests wholly and undividedly in that power. Therefore, contingent beings require for their existence the continuation of the creating power which is the power of God alone. And the continuation of this power is Divine Con­ servation. Hence, the contingent beings in the world around us, and the world itself, require and have the support of the activity called Divine Conservation. Divine Conservation is, therefore, a fact. 2. An effect which depends for production and permanence upon a certain cause requires the direct conserving activity of that cause. For such an effect has an essential and entire dependency upon its cause ; it requires the cause to hold it in being. No mere pro­ tection from destructive forces will insure its exist­ ence, for it cannot, in itself, maintain existence. Hence, indirect conservation is not sufficient to account for such an effect in continued existence; direct conservation is required. Now, all crea­ tures are, as we have seen, contingent upon their First Cause by an essential and entire dependency; creatures depend for production and permanence upon causes which are ultimately focussed and founded upon the First Cause, and which have their 2 64 THEODICY own existence and aciivitv by virtue of the operation of the hirst Cause. Only the hirst 1 lias in itself the snfhciency of sc)f-existence without dependency upon any other agency or force or factor. Ί here fore the First (.’anse, by Its positive exercise ol causal activity, is required to account for the sustained exist­ ence of creatural reality, in other words, the exercise of direct Divine Conservation is required to explain the existence of the world and all things in it. Direct Divine Conservation is, therefore, a fact. 5. A creature depends for existence upon its Creator. It exists by reason of the positive will of the Creator to bring it into existence. It does not exist by reason of the Creator’s mere willingness to leave it alone and not to destroy it. And a creature continues in existence by the sustained positive will of the Creator, not by His merely negative or indirect will. Now, the positive will of the Creator, which is thus manifested in the production and continuation of creatural existences, is neither more nor less than direct Divine Conservation. Therefore, direct Divine Conservation is a fact. SUMMARY OF THE ARTICLE In this very brief but important Article we have learned the meaning of conservation in general, and of Divine Conservation in special. We have seen that conservation is the exercise of a cause in esse, and TRANSIENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 265 that it may be direct or indirect, that is, promotive or preventive. according as it is a positive or a nega­ tive contribution to the continued existence of an effect. We have proved that Divine ( 'onservation is a fact in the world, and that it is direct conservation. We have drawn our proof from the contingency of creatures, from their entire and essential dependency upon the First Cause and upon the positive choice of the Divine Will. Article 3. The Divine of Operation Concurrence a) Meaning of Concurrence b) The Fact of Divine Concurrence c) The Mode or Manner of Divine Concurrence a) MEANING OF CONCURRENCE All actuality rests fundamentally upon God. Crea­ tures cannot bring themselves into existence, nor can they conserve themselves in existence once the Divine Power has brought them there. In other words, crea­ tures need God the Creator, and God the Conserver. This fact we have already seen to be inevitable. But we must go further and express a third need of crea­ tures. Creatures are created and conserved not only as essences but as natures; not only as things of a certain type or kind, but as things with certain con­ natural powers and functions ; not only as things existible, but as things operable ; not only as things 266 THEODICY static, but as things dynamic. In a word, creatures have activities and operations, and these (in the radi­ cal equipment or power whence they flow, and in their actual exercise) require the aciion and cooperation of God to explain their existence. Here then is the third need of creatures : the cooperation or concur­ rence of God in their powers of action and in the exercise of these powers. Creatures therefore require God the Creator, God the Conserver, and God the Cooperator or Concurrer. Now, the word concurrence is, in its literal force, a weak word in the present use. For to concur means “to run alongside,” “to go along with,” and it sug­ gests the working together of partial causes which conspire to produce an effect. But it is a demonstrable truth that in creatural actions, the creature is the total cause of the effect, and, in another way, God is the total cause of the effect. God and creature do not conspire together to produce the effect, each giving out a part of the efficacy which produces the effect. No, God the Primary Cause, and the creature which is a secondary cause (since God alone is Primary Cause) produce the effect, each wholly, in respectively differ­ ent ways. When,—to employ a very crude example, —two horses pull one wagon, each horse contributes part of the power that is required to move the wagon; the horses are partial causes of the effect which is the moving of the wagon. But when a man uses a pen to write a letter, both the man and the pen, each in TRANSIENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 267 its own way, is a total cause of the letter; the whole letter comes from the man, and the whole letter is written with the pen. Man and pen are not partial causes which stand on a plane, so to speak, and work together, each contributing a part of the effect. The man writes the whole letter ; so does the pen. But the man writes as the principal cause, the pen as the instrumental cause, and from the principal cause through the instrumental cause the finished effect emerges. In an analogous manner, the effects pro­ duced by creatures in action are wholly ascribed to creatures, and wholly ascribed to God; to the crea­ tures as secondary causes, and to God as Primary Cause. For creatures are contingent beings; contin­ gency extends to everything in fact or function in the realm of creatures ; creatures have nothing of their own which can stand independent of the First Cause as the basis of their existence or of the existence of their smallest operation. Hence, creatures require the active influence,—the inpouring of power, force, di­ rection, support,—of God in all that they do as well as in all that they are; they require the Divine Co­ operation as well as the Divine Conservation. And, as we have said, the word concurrence (or even the word cooperation') is a weak word in this connection. St. Thomas Aquinas used the expressions, “the in­ fluence or inpouring of God,” “the action of God,” “the Divine Motion,” “the operation of God” (in­ fluxus Dei, actio Dei, motio divina, Dei operatio') to 268 THEODICY express the activity of God which we consider here. These terms arc accurate, but usage .-vcnis to have established the term concurrence (or the Latin con­ cursus) as the acceptable one. We may well use this word if we keep dear minds about its meaning and are not led by its etymological structure into misun­ derstanding its true force. Divine Concurrence means the Divine Power actively exercised upon the creature (that is, secondary cause) to elicit operations, to determine and direct them, and to support them in being, in such wise that these operations are wholly ascribable to the creature as their secondary cause, and wholly ascribable to God as the sole Primary Cause. b) THE FACT OF DIVINE CONCURRENCE I. It is a truth established in Ontology that noth­ ing can act except in so far as itself is actual. A thing cannot operate unless it be there to operate, unless it be equipped to operate, unless it be determined in operation, unless it be stirred or moved to operate. Now, creatures depend entirely upon the First and Necessary Being (that is, upon God) and they have no actuality whatever independently of that Being. This does not mean that creatures are identified with God (for to say so would be to profess pantheism which is a debased and an absurd doctrine) but that creatures have an entire dependence upon God for their being and operation ; it means that creatures in TRANSIENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 269 themselves and in their operat ions arc entirely con­ tingent upon God. In other words, creatures can act only in so far as the Divine Power concurs in their action, that is, only in so far as the}- arc made. are made capable of action, are determined in action, are moved to action, arc supported in action, by the exer­ cise of the Divine Power. I'or all these points (exist­ ence, equipment or nature, determination, movement, support) are points of actuality, and no actuality is wholly independent of the Pure and First Actuality which is God. Therefore, creatures cannot exist and function unless Divine Concurrence is a fact. But it is manifest that creatures do exist and do function. Therefore Divine Concurrence is a fact. 2. The order of effects manifests the order of causes whence these effects come. Now, in any effect which comes from a creature-cause (or secondary cause, to use the technical term) we discern an effect that is proper to the Creator-cause or God. For it is God’s own proper Being to exist of Himself, and it is God’s own proper operation to give existence where it is not to be found of itself. And in every effect that comes from a secondary cause we have some­ thing that really exists; every such effect is a real existence, and one that does not account for itself ; it is an existence but not a self-existence; it is an exist­ ence that can be explained only as an existence given, and only God can give existence. The creature-cause, or secondary cause, truly produces the effect as this 270 THEODICY or that sort of thing; but that it is an existing thing at all, and not self-existent, indicates the action of creative power, the power of God alone. The creature­ cause produces the effect in such a way that it is the creature’s work; it is wholly his operation and pro­ duction ; yet radically it is a thing, an existence, which is also wholly the production of God. Therefore, every effect produced by a creature-cause is also an effect produced by the Creator-cause. Every creatural effect has both God and creature as total cause, from respectively distinct viewpoints; it has God as total Primary Cause, and it has the creature as total secondary cause. Now, the effects produced by the operations of creatures actually do exist in the world. These effects manifest an order or alignment or a presence of causes, the Primary, and the secondary. And the manifestation of Primary Causality in the effects of secondary causes is neither more nor less than the manifestation of Divine Concurrence in the operations of creatures. Hence, as the existence and operation of secondary causes is a fact, so also is the existence and operation of Divine Concurrence a fact. 3. Nothing has being or perfection except in so far as it has reference to, and dependence on, Being and Perfection, that is, except in so far as it funda­ mentally rests in God. Now the capacity or equipment of a nature for operation is being and perfection; so also is the actual exercise of operation. Therefore, TRANSIENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 271 the capacity of a creature for action, and the actual exercise of action, rests in God. In other words, such capacity and such action requires the Divine Concur­ rence. Therefore, Divine Concurrence is a fact. c) THE MODE OR MANNER Ol·' DIVINE CONCURRENCE God acts or concurs in all the operations of crea­ tures as First Efficient Cause, as Ultimate Final Cause, and as Radical Formal Cause, (n) God is the First Efficient (or “actively producing”) Cause of creatural action because God alone gives to creatures their being, their existence, their power to act, and God alone applies the operating power of creatures to its connatural function. Nothing is moved, says the adage, except it be moved by something other than itself, and ultimately by the First Mover Himself Unmoved, that is, by God. Hence all movement, all operation, has its radical origin in God ; God is truly the First Efficient Cause of all. (&) God is the Ul­ timate Final Cause (or “Last End”) of all creatural action. For God is the Creator, the Framer of every nature ; He sets all creatures in being and directs to Himself as to the ultimate Goal all the acts and opera­ tions of creatures. Hence God is the Ultimate Final Cause of creatural operation, (c) God is the Radical Formal Cause of all creatural action. A formal cause gives specific character to anything which proceeds from it as an effect; it makes the effect the precise kind of thing that it is. Now God is the Creator and 2 72 THEODICY Determiner of creatures in their specific structure and powers, and hence He is the Determiner of what proceeds from such structures and powers. Therefore God is truly the fundamental Formal Cause oi all creatural operation. “God,” says St. Thomas, “is the cause of every action inasmuch as 1 Ic gives the power to act, conserves it, applies it to function; and inas­ much as by His power every other power operates.” There is no difficulty in understanding the mode of Divine Concurrence, that is, the causal activity of God in the actions and operations of creatures, until the special question is raised about those operations which proceed from the free-will of man. On this score there is a notable controversy among philoso­ phers. All agree, of course, on the fad of Divine Con­ currence in man’s free activity, but there is no general agreement about the precise manner in which the Divine Concurrence is here exercised. The question is one that calls for clear minds and clean distinctions, for, if the doctrine be stated inadequately (and it can hardly be stated with full adequacy for it is not without deeps of mystery) it may easily lead the un­ wary to false conclusions. If the Divine Concurrence in free-wdll acts be too lightly taken, it may seem to endow man with creative power and to make human freedom an independence of God, the sole Author of all actual being. On the other hand, if too rigidly conceived, Divine Concurrence may seem to make man but an inert instrument of God, and to ascribe TRANSIENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 273 all man’s acts and operations (including his sins!) to God as their true Author. We shall presently list the more notable opinions on this difficult point, but be­ fore coming to that we ask the student to keep steadily in mind the following inevitable truths about which there is not, nor can be, any controversy whatever : (a) God is the sole Creator ; He is the only Author of being or perfection; nothing has positive actuality except from God the Pure Actuality; God is a true and total Cause in every actual operation of every creature, (b) Man is truly endowed with free-will, and by its exercise he is the responsible author of his moral acts, (c) God is in no sense the cause of sin, which is not being or perfection but the lack of perfection, the defection from being; man alone is responsible for that lack and defection which we call moral evil or sin. Keeping these truths clearly and fixedly in mind, we may indicate the doctrines offered by philosophers about God’s concurrence in man’s free acts. As a preliminary to that statement we offer a brief description of various possible types of con­ currence : (a) Mediate concurrence is that whereby God con­ serves creatures in existence as beings endowed with the power to act or operate. Immediate concurrence is that whereby God actually operates with the crea­ ture in exercising an action. (ό) Physical concurrence is the active and effec­ tive physical influence of the Primary Cause upon the 274 THEODICY secondary. By this concurrence the creature (or secondary cause) is moved to action, applied to func­ tion, actuali)' set in operation. Moral concurrence is a persuasion, exhortation, allurement, whereby the .Primary Cause draws the secondary free cause to determinate action. (c) Previous concurrence is the influence of the Primary Cause upon the secondary antecedently to the creatural operation. Simultaneous concurrence is the influence of the Primary Cause concomitantly producing the effect together with the secondary cause. The force of previous concurrence falls directly on the secondary cause; the force of simultaneous con­ currence falls directly upon the effect, that is, on the operation exercised. (d) Efficacious concurrence is that which, of its very nature, infallibly has its effect. Indifferent con­ currence has its effect dependently on the cooperation of the secondary cause. (e) General (or indeterminate') concurrence is a supporting causal influence which is not directed to one definite effect to be produced. Special (or deter­ minate) concurrence is directed to one definite and determined effect. (/) Intrinsic concurrence (or concurrence ab in­ trinseco) is entwined, so to speak, in the very being of the action of the secondary cause. Extrinsic concur­ rence (or concurrence ab extrinseco) is an influence which is, so to say, applied from without, or exter- TRANSIENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 27.5 nally, and so supports, moves, and directs the second­ ary cause in operation. The more notable philosophies of concurrence may be reduced to two, namely, that of the Molinists, and 'that of the Physical-Premotionists. I’roponcnts of 'cachot these theories claim harmony with the doctrine of St. Thomas Aquinas, but the name Thomists is generally applied to the Prcmotionists only. We shall merely outline the theories here. I. The Molinist Theory (cf. Book Third, Chap. I, Art I, a and b) holds that God gives to man’s free­ will a concurrence that is immediate, moral, indiffer­ ent in itself, simultaneous, extrinsic. God, by Plis scientia media, clearly foresees how man will choose to act in given circumstances, and accordingly makes His concurrence (which is in itself indifferent and indeterminate) an efficacious and determinate con­ currence which comes into actuality simultaneously with man’s free-action, to support it and give it being. The Molinists admit that God “pre-moves” all crea­ tures to their connatural operations by creating them with definite natures and conserving them in the ex­ ercise of their natural powers. Tn the realm of man’s free-action, God’s “premotion” consists in the fact that He has created the will of man for good in gen­ eral, has impelled it infallibly in the direction of such good, and, in every exercise of human choice, Fie 216 THEODICY allures it by moral influence towards flic actual good. For the rest, man’s individual will-acts (which are ever choices of means towards the general and pre­ determined end or universal good) are determined by man alone, God simultaneously concurring in man’s choice. God is a true cause, and a total cause, of the human act of free-willing, for lie is not only the Creator and Conserver of free-will, but actual­ izes, by His simultaneous concurrence (eternally de­ creed in accordance with His perfect knowledge through scientia media of what man will freely choose) the action of His human creature, and is the support and guarantee of true freedom in the action itself. Thus God’s simultaneous concurrence in hu­ man free-acts is a true cause of such acts without making them, by the very force and nature of Divine Concurrence, imperative upon man as inevitably to be performed.—The opponents of this theory object that, while the doctrine is a manifestly agreeable ex­ planation of human freedom, it slights the absolutely supreme and necessary operation of God in every creatural action. It even seems to suggest, say the objectors, that man, in the moment of free-choice, is either independent of God or is the actual deter­ miner of God’s own action, thus reversing the true order of things and putting man in God’s place. 2. The Physical-Premotionist Theory holds that God moves every secondary cause (including human TRANSIENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 277 free-wills) to connatural action by a concurrence aptly called physical premotion or even physical pre­ determination. This concurrence is physical, previous, immediate, special, intrinsic. In the actual exercise of free-will acts, there is also a simultaneous concur­ rence of God which rounds out and brings to com­ pleteness the previous concurrence or promotion whereby God physically moves and applies the free­ will to determinate action. Now, while the free-will in infallibly and inevitably moved (or pre-moved) to determinate action, its choice remains truly free, be­ cause God moves every being in a manner consistent with its nature, and therefore moves free-beings in such a way that they act freely. This doctrine, say the Premotionists, is so far from destroying human free­ dom that it is its only safeguard and sane explana­ tion. For the human will is in itself a potentiality or power, and, like all creatural powers, it is incapable of absolute ^//-determination; all creatural move­ ment must have its absolute source in the First Mover Himself Unmoved. God moves the free-will by an infallibly effective and immediate predetermination which does not take away the freedom of the will, but moves the will to determine itself freely, and thus renders free-choice both possible and actual. Nor is God thereby the Author of man’s sinful acts; sin, like all evil, is a defection and a lack, and is ascribable to the bad dispositions of the will which is moved by God to good. The matter of evil, the 278 THEODICY material clement of action which is itself good, is indeed ascribable to the premotion of Cod ; the fonn, or formal element of evil action (i. e., that which makes evil such) is ascribable solely to the bad will of man, so that God is not even its accidental cause (of. Hook Third, Chap- I, dirt. 2, d). The same sun­ light which makes damp earth hard, makes wax soft. The same object is reflected in a clear mirror as beau­ tiful, and in a faulty mirror as distorted and ugly. In a somewhat analogous manner, the same Divine Movement, and the one action to which it infallibly moves the free-will, are morally good or evil accord­ ing as the free-will is well or badly disposed, that is, according as the free-will which is moved to the ac­ tion measures up or falls short. Inasmuch as the free­ will measures up to the possibilities of reflecting and expressing the force of the Divine premotion, the result is good, and finds its true and total cause in God, even as it finds its true and total secondary cause in the will itself ; inasmuch as the free-will freely falls short of reflecting and expressing the true force of Divine premotion, the result is moral evil, and its only cause is the bad disposition of the free will itself. —The opponents of Premotionism declare that this doctrine makes the explanation of human freedom needlessly mysterious, while they admit that it ad­ mirably vindicates the necessary place of the First Mover Himself Unmoved in every creatural activity. TRANSIENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 279 With this brief outline of the two chief theories on Divine Concurrence we are disposed to leave the matter. The point controverted is one for the special­ ist. Students who have the capacity for a penetrating study of the arguments offered by the proponents of the respective theories will find instructors glad to direct their further reading. For others, great elabo­ ration of argument, a setting up of points and re­ buttals, of claims and objections, would be but tedious and profitless labor. The thing to be remembered is this : all controversialists agree perfectly upon the fact and the necessity of Divine Concurrence in hu­ man free-acts ; all admit the absolute sovereignty and requisite efficacy of God in every creatural operation ; all unreservedly teach the true freedom of choice with which the human will is endowed. The question is not whether God concurs in the free operations of man, but hozv God concurs in these activities. We have here a question, not of fact, but of manner or mode. For the rest, if we dare to express an opinion in the face of most deep and learned argument on both sides of this controversy, we must say that reason seems strongly to favor the Premotionist posi­ tion. For, despite its depths of difficulty and of mys­ tery, this doctrine rests squarely on the metaphysical principle that only the movement, the premotion, of the Creator and First Mover can be assigned as the absolute beginning and the absolute continuing sup­ 28ο THEODICY port anti the absolute determining direction of any creatural movement whatsoever, even that of a will that is truly free. Quidquid movetur ab ab io movetur: anything· thaï is moved is moved by something other than itself, and ultimately by the First Mover Him­ self Unmoved. SUMMARY OF THE ARTICLE In the Article we have learned the meaning of concurrence in general, and of Divine Concurrence in particular. We have noticed the etymological in­ adequacy of the term concurrence in this connection, and we have therefore learned to use it with caution lest its surface-meaning lead us astray. We have proved that Divine Concurrence is a fact in the world, basing our arguments upon the contingency of crea­ tures, the order of causes reflected in creatural effects, and the reference of being to the All-Perfect. We have discussed the manner in which God and crea­ tures are, each in respective order, total causes of creatural operations, and we have found that God operates in every activity of creatures as First Efficient Cause, as Ultimate Final Cause, and as Radical Formal Cause. We have briefly explained the controversy which exists among philosophers on the manner in which God concurs with human free­ will activities, and we have outlined the doctrine of the most important of the controversialists, the Molinists and the Premotionists. ρΜΜ7ΤΓ'ΓΤΤ —. TRANSIENT OPERATIONS OF GOD Article 4. The Divine Operation Governance and Providence 281 of a) Meaning of Terms b) The Fact of Divine Providence c) Certain Difficulties a) meaning of terms Providence is a term derived from the Latin pro “for; before,” and videns “seeing.” Thus it means “a looking before,” “a looking out for.” It means seeing beforehand what is required and planning to meet the requirement. We call a man provident if he carefully manages his affairs, looking to the fu­ ture, estimating his income and computing necessary expenditures; we call a man improvident if he lives for the moment, without plan or policy for the future. It thus appears that the term providence is aptly used to designate a plan of action, a way (that has been worked out before being put into execution) of di­ recting things to a goal or end. Now, Divine Provi­ dence is God’s Understanding and Will (that is, the Divine Reason) inasmuch as It eternally and infal­ libly directs things towards their last end or purpose, meeting with boundless wisdom every situation in its every detail. The result of Divine Providence in the world is the fact that creatures are governed, each in accordance with its nature, towards their ultimate end, which is God Himself, that is, the manifestation of God’s glory. Thus goverance and providence go to­ gether. The one operation of God is Divine Provi- 282 THEODICY deuce when we consider it in God, and it is the Divine Governance of creatures when we consider it in its application and workings in the world of linite things. St. Thomas Aquinas puts the point thus: “Two things belong to the domain of providence : the know­ ing how to direct and arrange things, and this is providence properly speaking; and, secondly, the actual directing and arranging of things in accord­ ance with this knowledge, and this is called govern­ ment. The first is eternal ; the second, temporal.” In a word, providence in God becomes government in creatures. b) THE FACT OF DIVINE PROVIDENCE We assert that there is a Divine Providence which effectively extends its governing influence to every­ thing in the world, not only in a general way, but in particular, so that it touches all reality in its minutest details. That this must be so is evident from the fol­ lowing arguments : I. In God there is a Providence. Providence, as we have seen, is the understanding of how to manage and direct things to their due ends. Now, as we have elsewhere proved, God is Infinite Understanding; in God there is the most perfect knowledge of how to manage and direct things to then- ends. Therefore, it is manifest that in God there is a Providence, or, more exactly, that God is Infinite Providence. TRANSIENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 283 2. In God there is all First Causality and Infinite Wisdom. Creatures are wholly dependent or contin­ gent upon God for their existence and for their opera­ tions; hence, they are dependent upon God for the achievement of their goal or end, for this is to be attained by the exercise of their operations. Now, it would not be wise for God to create without a pur­ pose, nor to create beings in themselves helpless to achieve their purpose and leave them so. It follows that, since God is the sole Creator infinite in Wisdom, He has made creatures for a purpose and directs them in its achievement. Therefore God is Provider and Governor; there is Providence in God and provi­ dential Divine Government in creatures. 5. Things different in nature are not drawn into one harmonious force except under the direction of one master-director and master-plan. Now, the uni­ verse is made up of a staggering multitude and variety of objects that not only differ in nature but are frequently contrary, one to the other. Yet it is very manifest that there is here a world-order, a great and magnificent harmony. Therefore there must exist an Orderer and GoAærnor; there must be a provident and governing God. In other words, in God there must be Providence, and in creatures providential Governance. 4. This Providence must extend its influence to everything in the world not only in general, but in 284. THEODICY particular. For the First Causality of God reaches all reality, and individual things, in their smallest parts and movements, are realities. Therefore God’s providence is no general plan, hut a most detailed plan which leaves nothing out. It follows that all creatures, down to the last and least, come under the application of Divine Providence and are divinely governed. C) CERTAIN DIFFICULTIES Those who deny the existence of God as Provi­ dence (and among these we count the Fatalists who contend that everything is subject to the inevitable action of a blind drive or force ; and the Deists who declare that God, having made the world, has aban­ doned it now to get on as best it may) are deceived by the apparent difficulties which lie in the way of the true doctrine. These difficulties are reducible to two: the fact that so many things appear to happen by chance, and, secondly, the fact that there is evil in the world. We must pause upon these difficulties for a brief space. i , nil <1 I. The Question of Chance. If things in the world happen by chance and not by plan ; even if only a few events, or even one, were to occur by sheer chance, then, certainly, our whole doctrine of Divine Provi­ dence and Governance is done for. But let us be clear on what we mean by the phrase by chance. We do not Μ» TRANSIENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 285 mean without cause. Chance cannot be conceivably the cause of anything, nor does it mean the absence of cause. Chance merely means some unexpectedness or “unforeseenness” in an effect. And, however un­ foreseen by finite minds, however unexpected, the ef­ fect which we call chance-effect has its adequate accounting cause in every case. Nor can the fact that an effect is unexpected or unforeseen by finite minds carry unexpectedness or “unforeseenness” to the In­ finite Mind. In a word, what happens by chance in our view, does not happen by chance in God’s view. What is no part of our plan, is certainly a part of God’s plan, and this must be so even when God’s plan is not wholly, or even partially, revealed to us, but is wrapped in mystery. Every normal adult has had enough experience of life and its happenings to un­ derstand that apparent evils often turn out to be bless­ ings. Everyone knows that his little mind can take in but a small part of the universe of possibilities, and that the complexities of detail in this vast cosmos, complexities of events, of movements, of effects, must, in the main, be mysterious to him and full of unexpectedness and so-called chance. But a man does wrong to attribute his own limitations to the Infinite Being. He is guilty of gross “anthropomorphism” in putting upon God the limitations of under­ standing and of will, and those of time and space, which characterize human existence. God’s plan is an eternal plan, eternally viewed in its entirety and 286 THEODICY in full detail; it is not something that unfolds to God as it unfolds to creatures. Therefore, the notion that things happen by chance, as though (hey hap­ pened in a manner surprising and even balding to the Almighty, is a false and unreasonable notion. And to allege the fact that we do not always understand the design of God in I I is government of events as a reason for denying the existence of that design, is a proud and stupid thing to do. Now, reason com­ pels us to the acknowledgment of an existing Infinite First Cause upon Whom all things utterly depend. Reason, following up that first fact, compels us to recognize the Infinite Being as boundlessly capable, so to speak; as perfectly able and willing to take full charge of the universe and to manage it most thoroughly in its every fact and movement and event. Further still, reason compels us to acknowl­ edge that this Infinite Adequacy is infinitely effec­ tive. In a word, pure and unclouded reason makes manifest to us the existence and effectiveness of Divine Providence and Governance in the world. And that fact, once known, must not be allowed to slip from notice. If events seem in conflict with it, then this must be only seeming and not fact. For reason compels us to recognize Providence, but it does not enable us to explain in full, and in every event, the actual working-out of Providence. The right attitude of mind, the philosophical attitude, is that of humility and calm recognition of the limi- TRANSIENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 287 tations of the human mind. It is not only piety, it is true philosophy, that enables a man to know that “all things work together unto good.” Nor does this mean a fatalistic acceptance of all that happens as inevitable, and as inevitably the best that could hap­ pen. No; as we have seen in discussing the concur­ rence of God with free-wills, man is a true and total cause of his own free-acts, and man may be perverse. And yet, as we shall see, man is wholly unable to upset Divine Providence or to distort its plan, how­ ever much damage he may do to himself. We shall touch this point in our consideration of the next dif­ ficulty, namely, that of Divine Providence and ex­ isting evil. 2. The Question of Existing Evil. In an earlier part of this manual (c/. Book Third, Chap. I, Art. 2, d) we have defined evil, distinguishing it as physical and as moral evil, and we have proved that God wills physical evil accidentally (or per accidens) but does not will moral evil (or sin) in any way whatever. But the point we have to consider here may be raised in this question : How does God, if He is the Infinite Provider and Governor, even tolerate evil, especially moral evil, in the world which Pie rules so absolutely? To find the true answer to this ques­ tion we must bring to our study a clear recognition of two truths : first, that God’s Providence and Gov­ ernance is an infinitely wise and absolutely effective 288 THEODICY direction of things to their true end; secondly, that human freedom is a fact which involves (he possi­ bility of abuse. With these two truths held steadily in mind, we attack the problem of Divine .Providence and existing evil. Providence directs realities and events to their true end. What is this end? Manifestly, it is the ul­ timate end, the last end, the absolutely final end, for this end it is that gives meaning to all subordinate and partial ends. Now, the final or ultimate end of all creatures is the manifestation of the external glory of God. And this end is absolutely achieved. We call the end of creation the external glory of God, for nothing internal or intrinsic can be af­ forded to the Infinite Being which already possesses the fulness of all perfection. And by objective ex­ ternal glory, we mean the character of creatures as an expression of God's power and wisdom and good­ ness and beauty. Just as a well executed painting, or a finely sculptured statue, is a credit to the artist who made it, so is God’s world of creatures a credit to God; the work of art manifests the power and skill of the artist, his intelligence, his taste, his ability; the world of creatures manifests the perfections of the Creator. Such is the external and objective glory of God revealed in His works. Revealed? Yes, but to what or to whom? To intelligences, to minds, to persons. And here comes in the second note, the sec­ ond determinant, in the final end of creatures; they "5 TRANSIENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 289 exist to manifest God’s perfections to mankind, and thus to win mankind to a recognition of what they express. And we call that glorv, that credit, that ex­ pressed perfection in a work which is recognized for what it is, the formal glory of him who wrought the work. The work of art is a credit to the artist in itself whether anyone ever sees it or not ; it expresses his glory objectively. Yet the artist has not formal glory unless the work of art be known and in some sense appreciated. Now, creatures exist for the ob­ jective and formal glory of God; they exist to ex­ press this glory. And this they infallibly do. For in themselves, by their very being, they are expressions of God’s objective external glory; and men must al­ ways recognize that objective glory and make it formal, even when they do not turn the recognition to their own account and through it obtain happi­ ness. For man will forever render objective and formal glory to God, and in himself, his works, his mind, he will eternally manifest God’s glory by ■ showing forth the Divine Perfections; the souls in heaven manifest God’s mercy, love, goodness; the souls in hell manifest God’s justice. Thus, whether a man save his soul or lose it, the ultimate end of creation is absolutely achieved, and man is power­ less to defeat it. It appears, therefore, that moral evil (that is, sin) which leads human lives to ruin and to endless misery, does not stand in the way of the attainment of the absolutely ultimate end of all créa- 290 THEODICY tion towards the attainment of which all I kings are guided by Divine Providence and Governance. In a word, moral evil docs not come in conflict ilh the fact of Divine Providence al all. Nor does physical evil conflict with Providence. The defects that we call physical evils (sickness, suffering', harsh, climate, etc.) are really a kindness to fallen man, who, with­ out them, would never turn to God or to the practice of virtue. Even in a world that is marked by so many hardships, or physical evils, multitudes of men are constantly looking for a temporary heaven and an earthly Paradise, uncaring for that true and eternal beatitude for which they are meant to labor in the brief workday of earthly life. All men would do so were it not for the presence and pressure of physical evils which keep us reminded that we have not here a lasting city. Further, physical evils bring out the best in men ; without them, there would be no occasion for the development of that stamina, that character, that heroism, which all men justly admire. It is mani­ fest, without further argument, that physical evils, far from being in conflict with Divine Providence, are not in contact with its main character and pur­ pose, and are apt instruments for the achievement of its secondary end which is the happiness and eternal well being of mankind. It is when we forget that man’s welfare is the secondary end of Divine Providence, and not the primary and absolutely ultimate end, that we find the TRANSIENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 291 existence of moral evil a difficulty. With this second­ ary end of Iwovidence, moral evil is indeed in con­ flict, for it works the ruin of men. But here we must recall the fact that moral evil, like every sort of evil, is ίΐιι absence and a lack, a defection ami a and not something with its own positive and failure, formal constitution. And the failure and lack, the defec­ tion and fault, which we call sin or moral evil, is clue to the non-conforming of free man with the full measure of God’s concurrence and premotion to good. Human freedom is a fact, and, as we have seen, it is something of its very nature subject to abuse in a finite creature which has not yet attained its final end or goal. Given to man for his own good, as well as for the expression of God’s formal and objective glory, freedom of choice (or freedom of will) is incapable of missing the ultimate end of Providence, but quite capable of missing the sec­ ondary end. It can be misused to harm man, although it cannot be misused to harm God or to upset the ultimate plans of God. God does not will its misuse, even indirectly or accidentally, or even in so far as such misuse harms man ; Ide wills its proper use. But he wills that man act freely, and if man freely falls short of what nature and grace enable him to do, the failure is man’s own entirely, and it touches man alone, and in no wise conflicts with the ultimate end of Providence. And even in its secondary end the Providence of God is often indirectly served by i 2Q2 THEODICY moral evil. Out of the evil of persecution came the glory of the martyrs; out of the hardships vilely im­ posed upon the poor come nobility of life, strength of character, and the field for the exercise of the splendid social virtues that we call the spiritual and corporal works of mercy. To a thoughtful man.— and especially to one who is “of the household of the Faith” with that understanding of the family­ life of Christendom which an outsider has never experienced and cannot rightly know,-—it is abun­ dantly evident that the Providence of God is con­ stantly drawing good out of evil. Such a man requires no great effort of mind, as he traces in memory the course of his own life, and weighs the facts and events that have shaped it, to see God’s “good and gracious purpose working in all the evils” that have come upon him. It appears, then, that there is no real conflict between the fact of Providence and the fact of evil; no, not even when the evil is that moral evil which brings man to an eternal mis­ ery and an endless suffering. SUMMARY OF THE ARTICLE In this Article we have defined providence in gen­ eral, and Divine Providence in particular. We have noticed that Providence on the part of God means Divine Governance exercised over creatures. We have proved the existence of Providence as a fact, TRANSIENT OPERATIONS OF GOD 293 drawing our arguments from the Infinite Under­ standing of God, from ilis essential First Causality, from His Wisdom, from the world-order. And we have indicated, as an inevitable conclusion of rea­ son, that Divine Providence and Governance arc ex­ tended to the last and least details in the universe of realities, and are 110 mere general movement or control in the wide direction of ultimate good. We have considered certain difficulties that assail the unthinking mind when the subject of Providence is considered in the face of a world in which so much seems to happen by chance, and in which there are manifest imperfections (or physical evils) and much moral evil (or sin).