AN INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY BY PAUL J. GLENN, Ph.D., S.T.D. Professor of Philosophy in the College of St. Charles Borromeo, Columbus, Ohio B. HERDER BOOK CO. 15 & 17 SOUTH BROADWAY, ST. LOUIS 2, MO. AND 33 QUEEN SQUARE, LONDON, W. C. 1944 Mt. Angel Abbey Library St. Benedict, Oregon 973/i ALL RIGHTS RESERVED Printed in U.S.A. IMPRIMATUR 4* James J. Hartley, D.D. Bishop of Columbus Dec. 16, 1943 Copyright 1944 B. HERDER BOOK CO. Vad-Ballou Press, Inc,, Binghamton and New Norte THIS VOLUME IS DEDICATED WITH AFFECTION AND REVERENCE TO MY FIRST TEACHERS AND MY LIFELONG FRIENDS, THE MOTHER SETON SISTERS OF CHARITY of Seton Hill, Greensburg, Pennsylvania PREFACE An Introduction to Philosophy ought to live up to its name. It should tell the young collegian, and the presumably older non­ collegian who takes it up with serious intent, a number of im­ portant things. It should answer the questions naturally to be expected of the person who wishes to be introduced,-—questions such as these : What is philosophy ? How did it come into exist­ ence ? What interesting things have happened to develop it or to hinder its development? What great names are identified with its effort? What have the bearers of these names done for philosophy? Is there a single true philosophy? Can there be a really false philosophy ? Can one know true from false ? What, in outline, are the things philosophy speaks of? Some such litany of inquiries, duly adapted, would be recited, —at least inaudibly in his own mind and heart,—by any nor­ mally curious human being about to be introduced to a Person­ age. And philosophy is as interesting and as exciting as any Personage, even if he were spelled in capitals throughout. This book attempts to introduce the reader or student to philosophy by answering the sort of questions just listed. It tells, in the somewhat dry and dusty fashion exacted by the needful compression of much in small space, the story of philosophy: its birth, its experiences, and even discusses its ancestry. It sets forth numerous samples of the language of philosophy, and in­ sists upon a clear understanding of these terms. It tells of true philosophy, and of many a system of doctrines that tries to justify itself as true philosophy. It follows the winding course of philosophy through the centuries and down to our own. Then it sets forth the content of philosophy, the seven master sciences which are the departments of philosophy in its rounded and V vi PREFACE complete form. All this the present manual attempts to do. Such value as the book may have lies all in this attempt. The intro­ duction may be a stumbling and half-inarticulate thing, but if it brings minds into familiar and appreciative communion, it can claim value despite its defects and stutterings. It is hoped that this Introduction will really introduce many minds to the Queen of Human Sciences. After that is done, the personal efforts of each individual must determine whether he is to retire to the remembrance of a regal smile, or to be held as a favored courtier close to the queenly throne. P.J.G. College of St. Charles Borromeo, Columbus, Ohio. CONTENTS FAGE Preface ........ ............................................................... Introduction....................................... v i PART FIRST The Origin and Growth of Philosophy CHAPTER The Beginnings of Philosophy....................................................... 27 Article 1. The Roots of Philosophy.................................................. 27 Article 2. The Emergence of Philosophy............................................ 36 II. The Development of Philosophy...................................................... 47 Article I. The Philosophy of Socrates and Plato .... 47 Article 2. The Philosophy of Aristotle............................................ 65 Article 3. The Course of Philosophy after Aristotle .... 82 III. The Perfecting of Philosophy . *. ..................................................... 93 Article 1. The Factors of Perfection in Philosophy .... 93 Article 2. Some Great Philosophers of the Age of Perfection . 101 IV. The Course of Philosophy to Our Times..................................... 118 Article I. Transition from Medieval to Modern Philosophy . .118 Article 2. The Philosophy of the Last Three Centuries . . .131 I. PART SECOND The Questions of Philosophy I. The Logical Question....................................................................... 161 Article 1. The Operations of the Mind........................................... 161 Article 2. Ideas and Terms............................................................ 168 Article 3. Judgments and Propositions ........ 174 Article 4. Reasoning and Argument....................................... . 182 II. The Critical Question....................................................................... 194 Article I. Truth and Certitude...................................................... 194 Article 2. Various Doctrines on Certitude..................................... 199 Article 3. The Sources of Certitude................................................ 214 Article 4. Scientific Certitude and its Acquisition..........................223 vii viii CHAPTER CONTENTS PAGE III. The Ontological Question................................................................. 227 Article 1. The Nature of Being.......................................................227 Article 2. The Properties of Being................................................ 237 Article 3. The Classificationof Being............................................. 246 Article 4. The Emergence of Created Being..................................... 251 IV. The Cosmological Question............................................................258 Article 1. The Nature of the Bodily World..................................... 258 Article 2. The Origin and Development of the Bodily World . 278 Article 3. The Fact of Finality in the Bodily World .... 28s V. The Psychological Question.......................................................... 294 Article 1. Life in Plants and Animals...........................................294 Article 2. Life in Human Beings...................................................... 308 VI. The Theological Question......................................................... 331 Article 1. The Existence of God...................................................... 331 Article 2. The Nature of God............................................................347 Article 3. The Activity of God...................................................... 355 VII. The Ethical Question..................................... 367 Article 1. General Ethics................................................................. 367 Article 2. Individual and SocialEthics.............................................381 Index.................................................................................................................... 397 AN INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY INTRODUCTION I. The Name Philosophy ; 2. Definition of Philosophy; 3. Object of Philosophy; 4. Importance of Philosophy; 5. Identification of the True Philosophy; 6. Division of This Treatise. I. The Name Philosophy: The word philosophy is a com­ bination of two Greek nouns, philia which means “love” or “friendship,” and sophia which means “wisdom.” We may there­ fore translate the word philosophy as “the love of wisdom.” A philosopher, consequently, is “a lover of wisdom.” Translating a word is one way of expressing its nominal definition. For a nominal definition (called so from the Latin nominalis which means “having reference to a nomen or name”') tells what a name means. A nominal definition explains a name, but sometimes it tells very little about the thing which has the name. Of much greater value and importance is real definition (called so from the Latin realis which means “having reference to a reality or thing”). For while nominal definition explains the name of a thing, real definition explains the thing itself. Still, there is sometimes much enlightenment to be found in studying aptly formed names. This is so in the case of philosophy. We shall therefore pause briefly to consider the nominal definition of philosophy. Afterwards we shall study its real definition. We have legend, if not history, to tell us that the word philoso­ phy was coined by Pythagoras in the 6 century B.c. This ancient Greek teacher is praised for his humility or his clear-sightedness, I 2 INTRODUCTION —which cornes to much the same thing,—in recognizing the fact that a man, by the use of his unaided natural powers, can never attain to wisdom pure and simple. He can be, and should be, a lover of wisdom, a seeker after wisdom. But he may never presume to call himself absolutely wise. And hence Pythagoras called his own deep studies, not wisdom, but the love or the quest of wisdom; that is, he called these studies philosophy. Not long after Pythagoras there appeared in Greece men of wide influence but of inferior mind who proudly called them­ selves “the enlightened” or “the wise” (as who should say “the intelligentsia”) ; the name in Greek is sophoi. History has per­ mitted these persons to keep the name thus usurped, and knows them as The Sophists. But it is a tidy piece of irony that the name Sophist has come to mean, not a man truly wise, but a pretender and a quack. “Thus the whirligig of time brings in his revenges.” We wonder what lies in store for the prideful modern “intellec­ tuals” who make a religion of the latest apparent findings of ma­ terial science. Doubtless their place is already set among the antic-comedians on the stage of coming time, and futurity will use them for its mirth, yea, for its laughter. Philosophy, nominally or by virtue of the word as a name, means the love of wisdom. The words love and wisdom call for a moment’s attention. Love, in its fundamental meaning, is the tendency or drive of the will towards an object. It is an act and a state of the will, not a tender sentiment or affection. Sometimes, indeed, the will-act and the will-state of love are attended by soft feeling, but this is not always or necessarily the case. It is important to notice and to remember this fact in a day when the cinema and light fiction have distorted and almost destroyed the true meaning of the word love.—Love is of two types, called by the learned desiring Jove and well-wishing love (or, in the ancient Latin terminology, amor concupiscentiae and amor benevolentiae'). Desiring love tends to possess its object ; well-wishing love tends to do good to its object. Manifestly, the love of wisdom which we call philoso- INTRODUCTION 3 phy is desiring love. It is love which finds expression in effort, in quest, in striving to possess and to retain wisdom. And what is this wisdom which philosophy seeks ? Wisdom is not the same as knowledge, for a person might know much and still be unwise. Wisdom indeed involves knowledge, but it also includes the ability, the inclination, and the steady purpose of putting knowledge to good use. St. Thomas Aquinas (12251274) says in his book Summa Contra Gentiles that a man is to be called wise when he knows what he has to do and plans and manages to do it well. Thus wisdom involves several things: an end or purpose to be attained ; an appreciative knowledge of this purpose ; an ability, an inclination, and a steadfast effort to achieve the known purpose in the best possible manner. Thus it is wisdom to work for a known good purpose in a steady, de­ voted, and enlightened way. Such is wisdom considered sub­ jectively, that is, in its subject, in the person who possesses it. Taking the term wisdom in an objective sense (that is, as a thing in itself, independent of a possessor) and regarding it in a most general way, we may say that wisdom is the sum-total of the things worth knowing and working for, which can attract the best efforts of the best minds and wills. This is the wisdom which philosophy pursues. This is that deepest knowledge, that altissima scientia, of which philosophy is the love and the untir­ ing quest. 2. Definition of Philosophy : The real definition of phi­ losophy, as contrasted with the nominal definition already dis­ cussed, tells us that philosophy is the science of all things natu­ rally knowable to man’s unaided powers, in so far as these things are studied in their deepest causes and reasons. We shall pres­ ently ponder each phrase of this definition. But first it will be well to inspect the meaning of the term philosophy as it is loosely employed in casual speech. r We often hear such expressions as these : “the philosophy of education,” “the philosophy of religion,” “business philosophy,” 4 INTRODUCTION “the philosophy of history,” “the American philosophy of life,” “the philosophy of style.” Now what does the term philosophy mean in all these uses, or what, at least, does it suggest ? It sug­ gests, first of all, a body of reasoned truths or of conclusions re­ garded as truths. Further, it suggests that these truths are the background, the basis, and the ultimate explanation of the thing to which they are referred as “a philosophy.” Thus the expression “the philosophy of education” suggests a body of reasoned truths (or principles, or “values”) which give meaning to the word education, which show the worth of education, and which indi­ cate, in a basic way, the best means of achieving and imparting it. Again, the expression “the philosophy of style,”—that is, of literary style,—means, as it does in Herbert Spencer’s little book which bears that title, the root-reasons which are back of all the rules of grammar and rhetoric. Therefore, “the philosophy” of anything suggests the sum-total and system of reasoned truths which are back of the thing and give it meaning. Of any activity or procedure, of any plan, of any programme, of any “way of life,” the reasoned basis is called its philosophy. Here, of course, we have the term philosophy in a very restricted meaning, even a metaphorical meaning ; philosophy thus restricted comes close to what people usually mean when they use that horrible misnomer ideology. We have no quarrel with such a restricted use of the term, but it is not in this sense that we employ it in the present treatise. In this study we use the term philosophy to indicate the science of all things knowable, the science which is “man’s ulti­ mate effort to interpret the universe” ; we do not use the term to mean the basis of some one effort or some one phase of human activity or interest. We do not speak of the philosophy of this or that; we speak of philosophy. Our concern is philosophy in its first meaning as the universal science, not in its restricted or metaphorical meaning as a special or particularized science. Reverting now to the real definition of philosophy, we find that we have called it the science of all things naturally knowable to man’s unaided powers in so far as these things are studied in INTRODUCTION 5 their deepest, their ultimate, causes and reasons. This definition must be learned with care ; we must be sure of the precise mean­ ing of its every phrase. a) Philosophy is a science.·—Science, considered objectively, is a body of related data, set forth systematically, expressed with completeness, and presented together with the evidence (proofs and explanations) which justifies and establishes these data as certain and true. Science, considered subjectively, is scientific knowledge in the mind of a person; it is knowledge that is rounded, systematic, evidenced, and complete. A science is (objectively) any branch or department of things knowable which presents related data with certitude, prooj, sys­ tem, completeness. A science (subjectively) is a person’s certain, evidenced, systematic, rounded knowledge of things knowable. When we say that philosophy is a science, we take the term science objectively. We mean that philosophy is a body of re­ lated data that is systematic, complete, evidenced, and certain. It is to be noted in passing that the evidence or proof requisite for a science is not merely experimental or laboratorian evidence. Evidence may also be (as in the case of pure mathematics) reasoned or rational evidence. This point is important because many teachers- of our times have presumed to limit science to the domain of the laboratorian and the statistician, arbitrarily ruling out rational evidence from the realm of true science. Such a ruling is blind and brazen impudence ; it is also self-contradic­ tory. For no amount of laboratorian data, no number of experi­ ments, no catalogue of statistics, can amount to scientific evidence unless reason reduces them to unity and order and draws con­ clusions from them. And neither the nature and value of reason­ ing nor the basic force of the conclusions drawn by reason can be tested by laboratorian devices or proved by experimental methods. We therefore reject the positivistic, sensistic, material­ istic, and empiricist doctrine that pure reasoning is of no scien­ tific value. Philosophy is a rational or reasoned science, not a laboratorian science. Philosophy does indeed use the findings 6 INTRODUCTION of the laboratorian sciences, but it is not confined or hampered by their limitations. It sheds its great light upon the data of the laboratory sciences, serving the scientist as daylight serves the laborer or the mechanic, and, in its turn, it draws from them il­ lustration and even direction for its efforts. But it is not fettered by their methods or subjected to their special requirements. b) Philosophy is the science of all knowable things.—In a day of intense specialization, it seems silly to say that there is a single science of everything. Nearly all the sciences we know of, and notably the positive sciences which keep our laboratorians busy, are partial or departmental sciences. Each of these deals with a branch of knowledge, and each is divided into almost endless departments and sub-departments. In the face of this bewildering maze of sciences, how can we think of one science which em­ braces in its scope every possible object of human knowing? Yet there inevitably is such a science. Even those who scoff at the assertion of its bare possibility are forced to assume its existence and to build their findings upon it as a necessary base. A little thought will convince anyone that there must be such a science ; the difficulty suggested by the variety and multiplicity of partial sciences is merely a seeming difficulty. Cardinal Mercier has an enlightening word to say on this point in his Manual of Modern Scholastic Philosophy (p. 2) : “Philosophy does not profess to be a particularized science with a place alongside other such sciences and a restricted domain of its own for investigation ; it comes after the particular sciences and ranks above them, deal­ ing in an ultimate fashion with their respective objects, inquiring into their connections and the relations of these connections, until it finally arrives at notions so simple that they defy analysis and so general that there is no limit to their application. So under­ stood, philosophy will exist as long as there are men endowed with the ability and energy to push the inquiry of reason to its furthest limit. So understood, it is a living fact, and it has a his­ tory of more than two thousand years.” Indeed, as the Cardinal goes on to point out, it is impossible INTRODUCTION 7 to have any particularized science without some fundamental grasp or some assumption of universal truths. The very existence of particularized or partial sciences affirms the existence of a non-particularized science, that is, of philosophy. For it is as impossible to have a partial science without reference to a uni­ versal science as it is impossible to have words without reference to a language, or even to have parts without reference to a whole. Not that philosophy is the simple sum-total of partial sciences. No, the relation of the particular sciences to philosophy is not the relation of constituent parts or elements to a totality which is their sum; rather, it is the relation of elements to a reality which is other and greater than themselves. Somewhat similarly, a building which is called a triumph of architecture is something other and something greater than any or all of the bricks and beams used in constructing it. A living plant is something more than a simple sum of parts. A language is more than a list of words ; a literature more than a sum of sentences. The glorious harmonies of a musical masterpiece make something other and greater than a sum of notes. To dwell for a moment on the last illustration, we may notice that the harmonies of a musical com­ position “come after and rank above” the individual notes that make it up. The composition is not a simple addition of note to note; it involves more than single notes or chords sounded in sequence; it involves notes and chords in their relations, their interpretations, their fusions in a reality which is both other and greater than themselves. So philosophy which is the science of all things, and therefore includes all other sciences and their ob­ jects, comes after and ranks above the partial sciences, and is other and greater than the sum-total of all these. Philosophy achieves its place by drawing into basic unities the vast and be­ wildering world of knowables with which all other sciences deal piecemeal. c) Philosophy is the science of all things naturally knowable to man.—Philosophy investigates all that man can know by the use of his unaided knowing-powers; that is, by the use of his 8 INTRODUCTION intellect or reason working upon the data gathered by his senses. Philosophy does not investigate what man has come to know by Divine Revelation, except, indeed, in so far as he could have known this without such revelation. For this reason philosophy is called a human science in contrast with the divine science of Chris­ tian Theology. Philosophy, indeed, is the queen of human sci­ ences. Sometimes philosophy is described as “the handmaid of the­ ology.” This title is most honorable, and it is thoroughly justi­ fied. For the truths which philosophy discovers, discusses, and proves are in perfect alignment with truths divinely revealed. Philosophical truths, moreover, help a person to grasp and ap­ preciate revealed truths. Further, the systematic procedure of philosophy suggests itself as the best and noblest instrument for setting forth the truths of theological science. Thus, in these several ways, philosophy serves theology, or, more precisely, serves man in his study and appreciation of theology. Since this service of philosophy to theology is the service of the human to the divine science, it is aptly described as the service of a hand­ maid. Now, certain mistaken minds,—some of which are mali­ cious as well as mistaken,·—interpret the phrase “the handmaid of theology” to mean “the slave of theology.” These minds, out of an abundance of ignorance which misses the clearest truths of history, suggest that Catholic philosophers, in times past, have bent and twisted philosophy to make it support revealed truth. Nothing could be further from the fact. True philosophy does support Revelation. Naturally so. For the power of reason by which man discovers and proves truths is a gift of the same God who has supernaturally revealed certain truths. There is no con­ tradiction in God; hence there can be no contradiction in His manifestations of truth, whether these be made naturally through the activity of sound minds or supernaturally through His re­ vealed Word. No twisting or bending of philosophy is required to make it serve theology. Philosophy is by nature the devoted handmaid of theology, not its shackled and tortured slave. INTRODUCTION 9 d) Philosophy is the science of all things naturally knowable to man inasmuch as these are studied in their deepest causes and reasons.—The quest of philosophy is an ultimate one. Philoso­ phy seeks bed-rock for the edifice of human knowledge. Every science looks for causes and reasons to evidence its data ; philoso­ phy seeks the last, the ultimate, the deepest causes and reasons. Philosophy, therefore, stands unique among human sciences. The partial or particularized sciences,—such as physics, chemis­ try, biology,—must be satisfied with proximate causes and reasons, that is, with those that are more or less ready to hand. For each of the partial sciences works in a very restricted field, and must find justification for its data within that field or in im­ mediately related fields. Philosophy, however, is not so re­ stricted ; philosophy is not immediately or necessarily concerned with proximate causes ; it wants the ultimate, the root-deep evi­ dence for its truths. To illustrate the contrast between the particular sciences and philosophy, consider a block of limestone. Mathematical science is interested in it solely as quantity. Physics looks to its mass and and inertia. Chemistry wants to know the substantial bodily constituents (the elements) that compose it. Now, philosophy ignores quantity, physical properties, and chemical constitution (although it does not deny these things). Philosophy poses an. ultimate question; it asks, “What, in the deepest sense of the inquiry, is this thing called a block of limestone?” Philosophy does not, like mathematics, inquire about the size or measure­ ment of the limestone. It does not, like physics, investigate quali­ ties or properties of limestone. It does not, like chemistry, seek to know which other bodily realities (called elements) make up this bodily reality called limestone. Philosophy asks what this limestone is. The other sciences accept the basic fact, the deepest reality, of the block of limestone ; they take this for granted ; they do not seek to investigate it. But it is precisely this deepest reality, ignored or blindly assumed by the partial sciences, that focusses the inquiry of philosophy. Philosophy asks, “What, ulti­ ίο INTRODUCTION mately, is this limestone?” Well, it is a thing or reality; it is a substantial reality; it is a bodily reality. Fundamentally, ulti­ mately, this limestone is a substantial reality of the bodily order; more briefly, it is a body. And as such, as a body, the limestone block engages the attention of philosophy. Notice here what an immense world of knowable things is drawn into unity in the one concept or idea of body. Notice too how truly ultimate is the quest of philosophy as contrasted with the effort of partial sci­ ences to gain proximate justification for their conclusions. We have here something that should give us a grasp of the truth that philosophy can be, and is, a science of all things knowable (despite the endless variety and multiplicity of these things), and that philosophy penetrates as deeply as the human mind can go in its investigation of reality. Philosophy seeks to trace things actual and things possible to their last discernible causes and reasons. Now a cause is anything that contributes in any way to the producing or the maintaining of a reality. A reason is whatever helps in any way to explain a reality to the inquiring mind. A cause contributes to the becom­ ing or the being of a reality; a reason contributes,to a person’s understanding of a reality. In a word, a cause produces or main­ tains, a reason explains. All reality must be either produced or unproduced. If pro­ duced, it is caused, it is an effect. One effect may, in turn, become the cause of a further effect. But the chain of cause-and-effect is not endless, nor can it be endless. Working back along this chain, we inevitably must come to a First Cause which is not produced, not an effect of a prior cause (for it is first). There must be a First Cause, existing of its own necessity, by its own unbounded and supreme excellence. And this Cause is, and must be, one. There is only one First or Primary Cause. All other causes in the universe, whether actual or merely conceivable, are effects before they are causes. As causes then they are not pri­ mary, but secondary. The one First or Primary Cause is God. God is First ; He has no cause or causes of Himself ; He is un- INTRODUCTION II produced; He is not an effect. Yet God is somehow knowable (even as He is here shown to be knowable in the present train of argument) ; God is recognizable; God is explainable to the in­ quiring mind. All of which proves that while there are no causes of God, there are reasons which explain to the mind the existence and the excellence of God. Notice and remember this truth : All reality other than God has both causes and reasons; God has no causes but only reasons. Now, when we know the cause of anything we have at least a partial explanation of that thing; therefore, every cause is a reason. But there are reasons other than causes; therefore, not every reason is a cause. Further, a reality, even if it lack causes (as does God) cannot lack reasons; for reality as such is know­ able, graspable, understandable. Hence, everything is explain­ able ; everything has its reasons; this is true even if the reasons elude the grasp of man’s imperfect mind. In a word nothing can exist without a sufficient or fully-accounting reason for its exist­ ence. This is the meaning of the familiar Latin axiom Nihil sine ratione sufficienti existentiae suae. Literary folk like to refer to this truth as the necessity for a raison d’être. Causes are of four chief types; these are called, respectively, material, formal, effecting, final. A bodily reality is the product or effect of all four types of cause ; a spiritual reality is the effect of the last three types, for a spirit has no material cause. A ma­ terial cause is the bodily stuff out of which a body is made. A formal cause gives “form” or character or definiteness or deter­ minateness to a reality, making it that thing formally or as such; and this, whether one considers a substantial or an accidental reality ; hence a formal cause is either a substantial formal cause (such as that which makes a silver statue silver) or an accidental formal cause (such as that which makes a silver statue six inches high). An effecting cause produces an effect by its activity or operation. A fined cause is the goal which invites dr indicates the aim of the activity of the effecting cause. Philosophy is interested in all types of causes and in all reasons, 12 INTRODUCTION but only in so far as these are ultimate or serve as means to the discovery of the ultimate explanation of reality. Herein we notice once more one of the unifying characteristics of philoso­ phy, and we are enabled to grasp something of the possibility of a single science which deals with all knowables. For the multitude of sciences that exist today to amaze us with their endless variety are largely a tissue of proximate causes and effects, and of reasons immediate and often provisional. Philosophy, by entering the ultimate realms of investigation, is able to unify, clarify, and en­ hance the many and various findings of the particular sciences. 3. Object of Philosophy : When we speak casually of “an object” we may mean a reality or thing, as when we talk of “visible objects” or “objects of value” or “objects of art.” Or we may mean the end, aim, or purpose of an action, fact, or event, as when we speak of “the object of a visit” or “the object of a plan or programme” or “the object of a meeting.” Now, when we speak of the object of a science we employ the term object in an ancient technical sense. First of all, the object of a science is what the science treats of; it is what we loosely call “the subject-matter” of the science. In this sense the object of a science is known as the material object. Thus, for example, the material object of the science of geology is the earth; the material object of the science of physiology is the human body ; the material object of the science of astronomy is the world of heavenly bodies. Hence when we speak of the material object of a science we name, in general, the field in which the science works.—In a second and more penetrating meaning, the object of a science is what gives the science its precise character, its “form” as the ancients would say. It is that which makes a sci­ ence this determinate science, formally or as such, and marks it off from other sciences in the same general field. In this sense the object of a science is called the formal object. Now, that which gives a science its accurate and determinate character is its point of approach, its aim and purpose, and the principles INTRODUCTION 13 which guide it or light its way. Thus geology which studies the earth as its material object is concerned with the rocky structure of the earth, and not with the shape or size of fertility or divisions of the earth. We say : the material object of geology is the earth; the formal object of geology is the rocky structure of the earth. Many sciences may work in the same field; therefore many sciences may have the same material object. But no two sciences deal with the material object in precisely the same way and with the same end in view ; should they do so they would coalesce as one science. Hence no two sciences can have the same formal object. Sciences are distinguished one from another by their objects, and, in last analysis, by their complete formal objects. To illustrate this, consider the sciences of anatomy, physiology, and hygiene. All three of these sciences have the same material object, namely, the organs of the human body. But these three sciences have not the same formal object. Anatomy studies its material object for the purpose of knowing structure; physiology studies the same material object for the purpose of knowing function; hygiene studies the same material object for the pur­ pose of knowing how to maintain normality and health. The material object of philosophy is reality, that is, “all things knowable.” The formal object of philosophy is reality in its final explanation, that is, “studied in its deepest, its ultimate causes and reasons.” Philosophy is at one with all sciences in its material object, for all sciences deal with reality, although each particular science has but a limited part of reality in its scope while philoso­ phy has all. But philosophy stands alone, stands unique, in its quest of ultimate causes and reasons. Philosophy is distinguished from every other science by its formal object. There was once great confusion on the question of the distinc­ tion between philosophy and theology. The difficulty was this: Philosophy deals with all knowables in an ultimate manner. So does theology. For all knowables may be summed up in two words, Creator and creature, or in two equivalent words, God and the universe. It would seem then, since both theology and 14 INTRODUCTION philosophy deal with God and the universe in an ultimate way, that these two sciences coalesce as one. St. Thomas Aquinas (1225—1274) cleared up the difficulty. He showed that the for­ mal object is itself twofold : the formal object as aim, purpose, or special aspect, and the formal object as guiding principle or light. The former he called “the formal object which” (objectum formale quod) ; the latter he called “the formal object whereby” (objectum formale quo). Now, philosophy deals with all knowables (its material object) in an ultimate manner (formal object which) under the unaided light of the human mind (formal ob­ ject whereby). Theology, on the other hand, deals with its material object (all knowables—God and creatures) in an ulti­ mate manner (formal object which) under the light of Divine Revelation (formal object whereby). Stating the principle: sciences are distinguished one from another by their respective formal objects and ultimately by the formal object “whereby,” St. Thomas drew a clear line of distinction between philosophy and theology. We may state the object of philosophy as follows : Material Object : all things knowable; all reality; Formal Object Quod: reality as knowable in its ultimate explanations ; Formal Object Quo: reality knowable in its ultimate ex­ planations under the light and effort of man’s unaided reasoning power. 4. Importance of Philosophy: On the face of things, it is unquestionably important for us to know what man has accomplished through the centuries by the closest and most intense use of his mind. It is manifestly important to know some­ thing of man’s quest into the heart of reality and to read some of the results of that quest. We all acknowledge the importance of knowing man’s deeds, his dreams, his plans and policies, his management of affairs, his aspirations. Still greater must be the importance of knowing INTRODUCTION 15 man’s achievements in the high domain of the intellect. To follow the course of human efforts to learn ultimate truth; to be cul­ turally enriched by a knowledge of what these efforts have won ; to be helped by this knowledge to avoid the calamitous mistakes of the past ; to achieve in all this a real enlightenment of mind,— surely this is to pursue most noble aims. Now, the earnest study of philosophy and its course through history is the one direct means of pursuing such aims. Can there be any doubt then that philosophy is a science of tremendous importance ? Father Stanislaus Lortie in his Elementa Philosophiae Chris­ tianae (Vol. I, p. 4 f. ) says that philosophy is of great importance (a) to individual persons, (&) to human society, (c) to the Christian Faith, and (d) to all the particular sciences.—(a) The individual finds in the study of philosophy a splendid means of exercising-both understanding and will : the understanding is stimulated by the quest of ultimate truth; the will is stirred by basically known truth to choose what is truly good, (δ) Hu­ man society finds its condition improved as its members advance in the knowledge of truths fundamental to the social order, to sound economics, to solid political science, (c) .The Christian Faith is benefited by philosophy inasmuch as this science demon­ strates the truths which the Fathers of the Church called “The Preamble of the Faith” ; further, philosophy is a splendid instru­ ment for the scientific exposition of the truths of Faith, and it illuminates sacred doctrine by apt analogy and telling similitude. Philosophy also defends the Faith against those who presume to attack it in the name of reason ; for true philosophy shows that there is, and must be, completest harmony between faith and reason, between religion and science, (d) The particular sci­ ences find in philosophy,—as M. Jacques Maritain points out,— their judge, their defender, and their governor. Yet, though philosophy uses the particular sciences as instruments, and fur­ nishes to them their requisite basis of reasoned principles, it never loses its queenly independence; it remains ever superior to the particular sciences and is “pre-eminently free.” 16 INTRODUCTION These, then, are the points in which philosophy shows its tre­ mendous importance : its intrinsic character ; its necessity to man in individual and social life; its service to religion and to scientific study; its rank and independence as the queen of hu­ man sciences. No one should go unwillingly to the study of philosophy, sur­ rendering reluctantly to its imperious claims and taking up the work as a dull and heavy duty. For philosophy is not only in­ escapably important for the person who seeks education and culture ; it is also one of the most attractive and absorbing studies that can engage the attention of any mind. 5. The Identification of True Philosophy: We have defined philosophy as the science of all things naturally know­ able viewed in their last discernible causes and reasoiis. Ponder­ ing this definition, we conclude that a considerable amount of time must have been required for the necessary viewing and discerning. Philosophy, the greatest of human sciences, was not developed in a day. It must have come to whatever objective perfection it may now possess through the expenditure of great effort long sustained. Now, it is hardly conceivable, in this clamoring, arguing world, that the development of philosophy has been a manifest and steady growth, like that of a tree in a garden, a thing to be recognized by every observer, and not to be mistaken or denied. No, there must have been in ages past, there must be still today, many and various philosophical efforts, some copiously fruitful, some largely futile and false. Man has been slow of mind since the original Fall; he has been in ignorance, subject to pride and prejudice; he has been wildly capricious and wilful. Even the story of man’s most serious and studious thinking cannot be a simple record of steady achievement and constant agreement. Quite the contrary, in fact. Hence there have been, and there are now, multitudes of theories and of systems of theories which are not true philosophy at all. There are, to use a graceless phrase, INTRODUCTION 17 many “false philosophies.” Grains of truth are everywhere, of course; no system of thought, however mistaken, can be so wholly false as to exclude altogether every element of truth. But there are endless systems and theories in the world (many of them exhumed from ancient books and presented as sparklingly new “interpretations of the universe”) which, in general charac­ ter, and in their speculative and practical conclusions, are false and harmful to minds and souls. On the other hand, however, much of man’s philosophical effort through the ages has led to the discovering of ultimate truth; much of man’s mental labor has been successful labor. And, since the effort to systematize findings has been as continuous as the effort to know root-causes, we must reasonably expect to find, somewhere in the world, a comparatively complete and ultimate system which alone is en­ titled to the name of philosophy. In a word, there must be avail­ able now for the mind a true philosophy. It may not be wholly perfect ; indeed, we cannot expect it to be that, since it is a human achievement and will necessarily bear the mark of human limita­ tions. But, after two thousand years of tireless questing, there must be now available a system of ultimate thought, of reasoned truths, of which we say, “This is the best that the mind of man has been able to achieve ; this system, more than any other, meets at all points the requirements of fact, and of reason in its most penetrating investigation of reality.” The philosophy of which these words can justly be said is the true philosophy. Nor is it true in any mere metaphorical sense, true because it seems ac­ ceptable, true because it is comparatively better than other sys­ tems. It must be true in fact, true actually, true in very truth. If it be not so, then truth is simply not attainable by man’s mind. For if two thousand years of the best efforts have produced a best and tested system which is not a true system, how can we hope that truth will be attained in two thousand years more, or in two million ? How can we hope that man’s mind can achieve philosophy at all? Unless we are prepared to accept the selfcontradiction and the insanity of complete skepticism, we must i8 INTRODUCTION admit, on the one hand, that the mind is capable of attaining truth, and, on the other hand, we must acknowledge some success where that capability has been exercised for studious centuries. That man can go on learning is certain, but that man can utterly change the pattern of his knowing, and can abandon all the most certain and fundamental principles and data of his knowledge, is so impossible as to be inconceivable. The true philosophy, then, imperfect but still true and relatively perfect, must be here in the world for the energetic and adequate mind to discover and em­ brace. The modern mind is subject to a benighting influence in the steady advance of experimental science. It is likely to conclude that light and truth lie all ahead, and that the past was all a grop­ ing and mistaken time. One thought should serve to correct this sort of blindness. If there is no eternal, unchanging, unaging meaning in the words truth, knowledge, certitude, how do we even know what we are after in all our splendid experiments? How do we even know our aims, however far off in a glorious future we choose to set their attainment? This thought should lead to another : that philosophy is a system of ultimate truths which must stand up, and stand unchanged, under all the new findings of all the new sciences. True philosophy will throw its light around the findings of the partial sciences, and will take illustration of ultimate truths from what they offer. But this is only saying what has already been said : “True philosophy must meet at all points the requirements of fact and of reason.” True philosophy welcomes and fosters the development of all sciences ; the light of its ultimate truth finds new glories in them, as the light of the sun flashes with new beauty when the prisms which refract its ray are multiplied in number and variety. We assert then that true philosophy exists in the world, and that it is available to the human mind. Y et much “false philoso­ phy” is here too. How shall the true philosophy be known? What criteria have we for identifying the true philosophy ? First of all, true philosophical doctrine must exhibit itself as INTRODUCTION 19 enduring, as historically continuous. Truth endures; error tends to fall away, although it tends also to recur and reappear in new guises. A doctrine which has managed to last, to weather storms of skepticism and direct attack, to stand up and stand firm under all the advances and extensions of human knowledge, has a claim on our attention as true doctrine. It has proved its mettle ; it is authentic ware. Further, doctrine which involves a necessity of truth in itself, and has endured because it cannot be rationally doubted or denied, is necessarily part of the true philosophy. Again, in addition to lastingness, a true philosophical doc­ trine will fit in with others of its kind in a sort of interlocking security, so that there is a true consistency in the system of such truths. Philosophical truths cannot be like individual survivors riding individual planks ; they must rather be amicable and mutu­ ally helpful survivors in a single boat,—the one ark of intellectual salvation. Still again, in addition to lastingness and interlocking con­ sistency, true philosophical doctrines must be changeless in them­ selves; they are not to be trimmed or shaded, contracted or expanded. As the world grows older, as the sum of human knowl­ edge is extended, as science opens new doors and windows, the truths of philosophy must show themselves over and over again, and in more and more detail, to be the rays of a single glorious sun. Truth is always truth. There is no such thing as a doctrine becoming more true or less true, although, of course, there is always the possibility of man’s learning more about what is in itself changelessly true. Truth is eternally there. It may be dis­ covered in successive and increasingly larger views, but, in itself, it neither grows, nor does it fade into falsity. Further, no truth can be in conflict with any other truth. Where such conflicts seem to exist, they are apparent, not real conflicts, or one of the con­ flicting things is falsity and not truth. The course of human history shows a successive discovery and application of ultimate truths. We discern, moving down through the centuries, the stream of man’s philosophical achieve- 20 INTRODUCTION ment. Sometimes the stream is clear and clean; sometimes it is muddled with intermingled error. In one place its course is straight and plain; in another it moves through bewildering loops and curves. Here it is open, there it lies concealed by some rank growth that obscures its channel. But the stream flows on, flows ever, continuous, consistent, enduring. Now, of all the doctrines propounded and defended by many men of many ages, which are those that constitute this ever­ flowing stream of true philosophy? Which are the truths that make the perennial philosophy, the philosophia perennis, the philosophy which runs a course unbroken through the centuries ? Well, we shall find that this philosophy is mainly Greek in its origins, and mainly Aristotelian in its Grecian character. We shall find that this philosophy has come, in the main, from Soc­ rates, Plato, and Aristotle,—but chiefly from Aristotle,—and that it moved into Christian times to take new light and power in the day of Christianity which succeeded the night of pagan antiquity. We shall find it enriched by the genius of St. Augus­ tine in the 4 century; carried forward by religious men,—sole preservers of things of the mind during the true Dark Ages,— into the 9 century and the Revival of Learning under Charle­ magne and Alcuin. We shall find it taking more complete form under the labor of the eloquent Roscelin, the deeply learned St. Anselm, the keen but hesitant William of Champeaux, the fiery and erratic Abelard. We shall find it rounding into perfection under the power of the unequalled genius of the 13 century when the greatest minds gave it their best efforts,·—William of Au­ vergne, Alexander of Hales, St. Bonaventure, St. Albert the Great, St. Thomas Aquinas, John Duns Scotus. After the 13 century, the philosophia perennis,—henceforth known as the Scholastic philosophy or the philosophy of the schoolmen,— moved through the years to our own day, often obscured, often ignored, often and for long periods despised as outmoded by those who knew little or nothing of its doctrines and their com­ pelling evidence. Despite continued and recurring obstacles and INTRODUCTION 21 obscurities, this philosophy has ever been coming newly into view, ever striving to assume and maintain its rightful place of pre-eminence and control. Today it challenges the attention of the best minds, and its influence widens hourly. Many of its most notable modern exponents are called, perhaps regrettably, the Neo-Scholastics,—the “neo” being a concession to current fash­ ion and a call for attention which, without it, would hardly be bestowed. The Scholastic philosophy, or, more precisely the GrecoScholastic philosophy, survives in the world today as the only continuously existent and consistent system of philosophic thought that man may find in all the records of his race. It rep­ resents the best that man has been able to do in his tireless quest of root-reality. It is the one system that has any roundness or completeness in its expression of the human philosophic effort, that is, of the effort of the deepest and most earnest human thought upon the ultimate unities which embrace all knowable reality within their mighty scope. This blunt statement is ever provocative of indignation and denial among non-Scholastics with their broken and partial philosophies. But there the thing stands. Like it or hate it, it is fact and not fiction. This is no dictum of partisan minds, but the irrefutable declaration of hu­ man history. Nor is this perennial philosophy, this acme of human achieve­ ment in “interpreting the universe,” a dry and dusty system of statistical truths, set in an iron fixity that leaves nothing for the student but the task of memorizing, and balks constructive think­ ing or advance in philosophic knowledge. No one who knows anything of the Scholastic philosophy could so utterly miscon­ ceive it or so slanderously misrepresent it. The Scholastic phi­ losophy has been likened to a stream ; it is no stagnant pool. It is a running, living, vitalizing stream, and its springs are ever­ flowing, fresh, clear, new as well as old. Indeed, it is the non-Scholastic welter of philosophies that resembles the stale standing water that can do no more than dry away and leave but 22 INTRODUCTION fruitless and hardened clay. These futile “philosophies,” with their opinions, their views, their approaches to this subject and to that, can never give the human mind the certainty it requires for constructive thinking; they can never bring knowledge to flower or truth to glorious fruitfulness. It is these, and not the perennial philosophy, which give a show of reason to the lay­ man’s notion that philosophers are mere idlers and misty-eyed dwellers in a world of unreality. Now, why should there be indignation and denial when the unique claims of the Scholastic philosophy are presented ? There are many minor reasons: the resentment of prideful minds against any claim to uniqueness; the current substitution of fashion for thought, which finds anything with the mark of the past upon it an object for scoffing and derision; the ineptitude that ignores history, and reduces knowledge to a set of charts on the walls of a laboratory. Plain, brazen, unblinking ignorance is another reason. But the major reason for modern resentment against the claims of Scholasticism lies in this fact : the great Scholastics of the past were Catholics and, for the most part, churchmen, who, finding that divinely revealed truth may have in philosophy a noble instrument for exposition and scientific elaboration, applied their philosophic doctrines in the realm of theology. Because, as a fact, Scholastic philosophy stands in agreement with Catholic doctrine (and how could it be other­ wise, since both are true?) biassed minds have declared that the Scholastics forced and twisted their philosophy to fit with their religion ; that they warped its tenets into place as “Catholic phi­ losophy” ; that they shackled and enslaved philosophy to serve a set system of theology. All this is, of course, quite untrue. The philosophia perennis has not been warped or twisted ; it fits natu­ rally and nobly into its place as the free-serving and devoted ancilla theologiae. Just as grace supposes nature and builds upon it, so does Revelation suppose reason and ennobles and enlarges its efforts and its scope. Y et the modern non-Scholastic will have none of this. To him, Scholastic philosophy is Catholic philoso- INTRODUCTION 23 phy. And Catholic philosophy is theological philosophy. Now, nothing is more distasteful to the modern mind than theology. For the first mark of pride is that it resents God, and the modern mind is sadly tainted by pride. Strictly speaking, there is no such thing as Catholic philoso­ phy. That is to say, there is no system of philosophical doctrines built up for the purpose of supplying a reasoned basis for Cath­ olicity. True philosophy actually supplies such a reasoned basis, but it has not been elaborated for that purpose. True philosophy is naturally and inevitably the reasoned basis for true theology. But, as it is the fate and the glory of the Catholic religion to resemble its Divine Founder in being the object of hatred, abuse, contempt, and misrepresentation on the part of those who do not know and will not investigate its character, claims, and history, so it is the fate and glory of the true philosophy which naturally supports Catholicity to be the object of like evil sentiments and activities on the part of persons who reject, with the smallest and most cursory investigation, its irrefutable claims upon the human mind. At the outset of our study we assert the claims of Scholastic philosophy to be the true philosophy. As we have said, there are elements of truth scattered through many doctrines and many systems and schemes of theories. But in the Scholastic phi­ losophy we find truths systematized, correlated, set forth in a rounded completeness which covers the whole ground of ra­ tional inquiry. We do not assert that the Scholastic philosophy is wholly perfect. We must admit that certain departments of it, and notably that called Natural Philosophy or Cosmology, are subject to development and improvement. But in its basic principles, in its rounded character, in its coherence and continu­ ity, in its reasoned conclusions, it is a unique thing in the world. If there can be true philosophy at all, and surely there can be, then this is the true philosophy. Our studies, as we advance, will help to show the justice of this claim. From the standpoint of Scholastic philosophy we shall view INTRODUCTION 24 and criticize the development of philosophic thought as we en­ deavor to trace, in an elemental and sketchy manner, the progress of the philosophia perennis through human history. 6. Division of This Treatise: The first part of the pres­ ent study is descriptive and historical. We shall, in this part, look into the beginnings of philosophy, its development, its com­ ing of age. The second part of our study turns upon the essential questions of philosophy; it turns upon what may be called the diversified function of philosophy. If we choose, we may say that the first part of this study is historical, the second part functional. The treatise is therefore divided into two Parts. These, with their subjoined Chapters are set forth in the following scheme : PART FIRST The Origin and Growth of Philosophy Chapter I. The Chapter II. The Chapter III. The Chapter IV. The Beginnings of Philosophy Development of Philosophy Perfecting of Philosophy Course of Philosophy to Our Times PART SECOND The Questions of Philosophy Chapter I. The Logical Question Chapter II. The Critical Question Chapter III. The Ontological Question Chapter IV. The Cosmological Question Chapter V. The Psychological Question Chapter VI. The Theological Question Chapter VII. The Ethical Question PART FIRST The Origin and Growth of Philosophy The Part gives some account of the roots of philosophic endeavor, and of the emergence and development of philosophy. It gives a summary description and criticism of notable philosophical doc­ trines from the most ancient times to the present day. These matters are discussed in four Chapters, as follows : Chapter I. The Beginnings of Philosophy Chapter II. The Development of Philosophy Chapter III. The Perfecting of Philosophy Chapter IV. The Course of Philosophy to Our Times CHAPTER I THE BEGINNINGS OF PHILOSOPHY The present Chapter discusses the roots of philosophy found in man’s rational nature and in some primeval manifestation to man of the meaning of reality, particularly of his own existence. Further, the Chapter studies the first emergence of philosophy among the ancient Orientals and the early Greeks. The Chapter is accordingly divided into two Articles : Article i. The Roots of Philosophy Article 2. The Emergence of Philosophy Article 1. The Roots of Philosophy a) Man’s Rational Nature; b) Primitive Revelation and Tradition. a) Man’s Rational Nature Philosophy, the loving quest of wisdom, the tireless pursuit of knowledge to its deepest origins and roots, comes into being, first and foremost, because the human mind is forever seeking to know, and to grasp the ultimate how’s and why’s of what it knows. Man has a quenchless thirst for knowledge. Nor is this a desire for mere data, for bare facts and events; it is a desire for data with their explanations, their justifications, their evi­ dence, their proofs. And if a proof or explanation is not in itself an evident and inescapable reality, the mind looks for proof of that proof. So the search for solid and reliable knowledge,—for truth, in a word,—is carried forward, or naturally tends to be carried forward, towards fulfillment. The mind proves truth by truth ; it holds truths in relation and connection ; it delves deep to unify and clarify its findings in an ultimate understanding. Thus man is, by his very nature, philosophical. 27 28 THE BEGINNINGS OF PHILOSOPHY The incessant questions of a child are manifest proof of the natural thirst for knowledge in which philosophy finds its first root. And though the child, unspoiled and trusting, will accept any explanation as satisfactory, and will find, for instance, no difficulty in the story of a fat Santa Claus coming down a narrow chimney or in the leap that carried the cow over the moon, the young mind will presently inquire further for evidence as ex­ tended experience makes its first willing acceptance give place to doubts. In its immaturity, in its lack of time and experience to draw into understandable unity the endless wonders of the world about it, the child accepts any explanation of any fact, and accepts fantastic tales quite casually as no more wonderful than the reality of this most wonderful world. But the child accepts each explanation, each wondrous tale, because it regards these things as true. Truth is what the mind is after ; truth is what the mind desires; truth is what the mind is for. And the quest of truth, down to its last foundations, is a philosophical quest. Here is discerned the first root of philosophy. Nor can it be successfully objected that many minds are indif­ ferent, careless, unconcerned about the quest for truth and the explanation of facts. Such an objection is far from exact. No normal mind, however incurious, is without special interests in which it has the tendency to know and to understand, even though enervation or lack of energy hinders the full exercise of this tendency. There are indeed countless persons who have no direct or conscious interest in what are loosely called “the things of the mind,” that is, deep reasonings upon abstract truths, such as are the delight of the practised philosopher. There are many who have no sympathy with such things ; who regard effort spent upon them as idleness and waste of time ; who consider all “phi­ losophizing” as silly vaporizing in a world of unreality. It is re­ markable that this should be, since the philosopher, above all others, is most thoroughly and exclusively concerned with real­ ity. It is remarkable, but it is so. But the point we make here is THE ROOTS OF PHILOSOPHY 29 that even those who regard professed philosophers as fools who wear out their minds (and their readers and hearers) in mean­ ingless discussions of “the whichness of what” and “the whatness of which,”·—even those scoffers to whom there is no important reality beyond machines and microscopes and bread and sport, even these are seekers after facts with their causes and reasons, their how’s and their why’s. Your “practical” person, full of scorn for philosophy, is none the less an ardent admirer of the man who knows his job ; it is his own proudest boast that in his special sphere of interest and activity he “knows all the answers.” So even this “practical” person is proof sufficient of our assertion that the human mind wants knowledge, and wants the how’s and why’s of what it knows. But we have no need to pause and argue with the inept, the lazy, the incurious. Our statement that the human mind is natu­ rally philosophical in its effort is manifestly true of the mind at its unspoiled best. That some minds are ill-directed and spend their energies amiss ; that some are thwarted by incapacity ; that some are quickly weary in the quest of truth,—these facts are in no sense an argument against the native tendency of the human mind for ultimate truth. Indeed, they are rather a proof of that tendency. There is an explanation for the fact that many human beings fail to seek out ultimate causes and reasons, fail to realize or to concern themselves about the meaning of existence, and are content with second-best and third-best explanations of the world about them, of life, of duty, of effort. There is an explana­ tion, and only one. It is the fact that something has, in human origins, gone wrong with man; something has hurt his mind, darkening it and making it subject to sudden weariness, willing to surrender its effort under the stress of exacting labor. The name of this fact is Original Sin. And of that we may not pause to speak further in this place. We come back to our statement that the first root of philos­ ophy is found in man’s native tendency to know truths with their 30 THE BEGINNINGS OF PHILOSOPHY evidence. This statement is given with technical accuracy in the following formula : the first root of philosophy is found in the rational nature of man. . Now, the nature of a thing is its working essence. And the essence of a thing is that which constitutes it and makes it what it is. Essence regarded as the source of operations is called na­ ture; thus we are justified in our description of nature as “work­ ing essence.” To illustrate: the essence of a man (physically considered) is his body and soul; these are the elements which constitute a human being, and make him what he is in his funda­ mental actuality. But the nature of a man is the essence looked at as the source and font of human operations. So we say that it is according to man’s nature that he feels and sees and thinks and wills. Man’s essence works that way. That is his mode of operation. That is his nature. When we say that the nature of man is rational we use the term in its original Latin meaning, not in its current meaning of “conscious” or “normal.” A rational nature means a nature fundamentally equipped for understanding and freely choosing. We do not say that a being of rational nature can think or will at any instant; no, we say that such a being is fundamentally equipped for thinking and willing, even though some obstacle should prevent the exercise of these activities. Thus a baby, even a baby yet unborn ; a madman ; a man unconscious, each of these is a being of rational nature as truly as is the alert, mature, and normal man who is consciously exercising his powers of thinking and willing. This is a point of boundless importance for many reasons which lie outside the scope of our present study. But one of these reasons is of such vital character that it must be allowed to obtrude itself even here; we shall pause upon it for a brief paragraph. One great reason for stressing the true meaning of the phrase “rational nature” lies in the fact that current usage makes the word "rational” practically synonymous with the word “con­ scious,” or the word “lucid,” or the word “normal.” Thus we ! THE ROOTS OF PHILOSOPHY 31 speak of one recovered from the stress of high emotion, or of one who has emerged from delirium or coma, or of one who has achieved normality after a temporary lapse into insanity, as one who “is quite rational again.” This is a sad, nay a disastrous use of the word. For it has in it the suggestion,—which grew up and grew strong together with the materialistic and pagan view of things which we call “modern” and sometimes “scien­ tific,”—that one who is not “rational” (that is, one who is not in adequate and active awareness and management of himself) is something less than hitman. Especially is this so with reference to the unborn child, the insane, the more be­ nighted sort of criminal, the senile, the immature,—the “un­ fit,” in a word. And out of this evil sense of the term “rational” has come, in a measure far greater than most of us realize, our easy tolerance, our sober acceptance, of “scientific” discussions and justifications of abortion, of sterilization, of euthanasia or “mercy killing.” No one would listen for a moment to the pro­ posal, however sober and “scientific,” that we should murder or mutilate a great number of perfectly normal men. But many of us will listen patiently, perhaps with half-assent, to the proposal that the abnormal, the subnormal, or the outworn should be eased gently out of life or mutilated and made impotent to prop­ agate. It is, in large measure, our false grasp of the word “ra­ tional” that prevents us from seeing that the one proposal is precisely the same as the other. Each is a proposal to maim or murder human beings, every one of whom is a being of rational nature. Here we recall an important Scholastic distinction. A being fundamentally equipped for an operation is said to possess in actu primo the perfection which that operation indicates or be­ stows. A being that exercises the operation is said to possess its perfection in actu secundo. Literally, the Latin phrases mean, respectively, “in first actuality” and “in second actuality” ; we may, however, translate them freely as “in basic fact” and “in actual exercise.” Thus a baby is a thinking and a walking be­ 32 THE BEGINNINGS OF PHILOSOPHY ing in actu primo or in basic fact, because it is fundamentally equipped for the operations of thinking and walking, even though lack of experience and of development balks the actual exercise of these operations. After a time, the child will both think and walk, and, in exercising these operations, it will be a thinking and a walking being in actu secundo or in actual exer­ cise. It will think and walk in the second place, given the exist­ ence of the basic equipment for thinking and walking in the first place. Now, the point here to remember is that every rational creature is rational by reason of the fact that it possesses in actu primo the powers of understanding and free choice. That every human being is a being of rational nature is a truth discussed in the department of philosophy called psychology. For the present, we merely notice the fact that man is rational, that he has the natural equipment and tendency to think, to appre­ hend, to understand, to think things out, to correlate and inte­ grate his findings and to bring them into unity. In all this man shows himself to be cast m the image of God who knows all things in the unity of eternal understanding. And this connatu­ ral human power and tendency for understanding, reasoning, unifying,—this rational nature of man,—is the first root of phi­ losophy. It must be noticed that a rational nature is more than a know­ ing nature. All animals have a knowing nature, but man alone, of all animals, is rational. Animals are equipped for sense­ knowledge ; man is equipped for intellectual knowledge, that is, for rising from the individual findings of the senses to the suprasensible and universal grasp of reality and for will-acts in the light of this superior knowledge. Sense-knowledge is knowledge of concrete and individual things; mental or intellectual knowledge is knowledge of es­ sences (expressed in the mind as concepts or ideas) and of the relations of essences (expressed in the mind as judgments and reasonings). The sense of sight, for example, beholds individual objects, say a tree or a group of trees. But the mind, taking the THE ROOTS OF PHILOSOPHY 33 findings of sight, rises from these data to an understanding of what tree means, not this tree or these trees only, but any tree and every tree. Further, the mind rises to concepts or ideas of things which the senses cannot possibly grasp,—things such as substance, or symmetry, or beauty. Inevitably, out of its findings and their unions, their compari­ sons, their relations, their connections, the mind becomes aware of truths which it enunciates within itself as judgments and expresses outwardly as propositions. And out of judgments, aligned in their proper relations, the mind will draw conclusions or further judgments. Thus does the mind reason or think things out. Among reasoned conclusions of the mind there are, by natural necessity, certain clearly recognized truths involving duty, obli­ gation, rightness or wrongness ; in a word, morality. The fact that a man can define a reality, that he can discuss things in a general way, that he can do a sum in arithmetic or prove a theorem in geometry; the fact that he is aware of duty and recognizes the need of law and order,—all these facts are proof inescapable that man is a being of rational nature, and, by that same token, that he is by nature philosophical. Philosophy exists because, first of all, man has a nature that makes him pursue the philosophical quest. Such is the meaning of the dec­ laration that the first root of philosophy is the rational nature of man. b) Primitive Revelation and Tradition The fact that man is of rational nature, and therefore funda­ mentally philosophical, does not mean that all human beings are actively interested in the deep and determined process of think­ ing things out which we call philosophical speculation. No, all we may say, and must say, is that man is equipped by nature for such speculation. It is to be expected, however, that man’s natu­ ral equipment for speculation would manifest itself in the forma­ tion of some system of thought about reality. Special tastes and 34 THE BEGINNINGS OF PHILOSOPHY talents, together with favoring circumstances, must have come into play, sometimes in man’s history, to put him to the task of using his natural equipment in the developing of philosophy. None the less, the fact of philosophy in the world is not en­ tirely explained in terms of rational nature, tastes, talents, and circumstances. There is ample evidence in the history of human thought that all men, from the earliest times, have had some common store of knowledge to draw upon. The ancients, despite wide variations in their cultures, had many notions in common. They all had some knowledge of the emerging of the earth out of a chaos of waters. They all believed that man was made, directly or indirectly, out of the clay of the earth. They all held that man is meant to serve God. They all were convinced that the human race had somehow gone wrong in its very origins, and that man­ kind had suffered a fall. They all felt that the business of life involves some sort of cleansing and refining of self, and the attainment of a more perfect state here or hereafter. They all taught that man is, in one way or another, to work for reunion with his Primal Source. Further, all the ancients had the story of a destructive flood of waters which laid waste the world, and the story of the dispersion of human tribes. We must conclude that mankind came to a knowledge of these things through the medium of some primitive revelation. Christians find this conclusion consonant with their belief that God instructed our first parents; that He spoke with them fa­ miliarly ; that He doubtlessly gave them information about their material origins even as He imparted knowledge of the creation and inbreathing of their spiritual souls which gave them their perfected being as images of God. This primitive revelation of man’s nature, dignity, duty, and destiny, together with the ear­ liest and most striking experiences of the human race, must have been a matter of common discussion. All these facts must have been narrated again and again by the human voice as the story was handed on from generation to generation. In a word, the primitive revelation and the first great experiences of mankind THE ROOTS OF PHILOSOPHY 35 must have been perpetuated through early times by human tra­ dition. Now, tradition, unless it is divinely protected and conserved (as is the case with Sacred Tradition which is a source of Divine Revelation), is a stream that inevitably gathers alien matters as it flows along. Man is imaginative, and his fancy tends to dress fact with such abundance of adornment that the fact itself is sometimes obscured and even forgotten. For this reason, modern man, driven by the same imaginative impulse, is too ready to dismiss old traditions as “mere folk-lore.” But there is always a reason for folk-lore ; there is always a living truth in the wrap­ pings of fanciful detail ; there is no such thing as mere folk-lore. And so, while it is undoubted that the primitive revelation and the earliest events of human history have come down the stream of human tradition in an imperfect and progressively obscured condition, we are none the less on solid historical ground in our conclusion that these two things (primitive revelation and re­ membered events of early history) are factual and not fanciful. The primitive revelation and human tradition come together to constitute a true source of philosophical concepts and speculation. They may justly be regarded as the second root of philosophy. Summary of the Article In this Article we have discerned the fact that the first root of philosophy is the rational nature of man. We have defined nature as “essence viewed dynamically,” that is, essence regarded as the font of operations. And rational nature means nature equipped in actu primo (or “in basic fact”) for understanding and free self-directive choice. We have noticed the fact that man has some common original storehouse of knowledge which can be ac­ counted for only by a primitive revelation and an esssentially reliable human tradition; these two agencies constitute the sec­ ond root of philosophy. Our study thus far has given us the meaning of certain philo- 36 THE BEGINNINGS OF PHILOSOPHY sophical terms, such as: essence, nature, sensation (i.e., sense­ knowledge}, intellection (i.e., intellectual knowledge}, concept, judgment, proposition, reasoning, actus primus, actus secundus. Article 2. The Emergence of Philosophy a) First Efforts; b) The Ancient Orientals; c) The Early Greeks. a) First Efforts Since man is by nature philosophical, it is inevitable that the earliest records of his thinking should manifest something of that human quest of ultimate causes and that human effort to make a deep unification of knowledge which we call by the name philosophy. As soon as man begins to think he begins to think things out ; he begins to speculate or reason deeply ; he begins to philosophize. As soon as he records his thinking, philosophy be­ gins, however imperfectly, to take form. Philosophy emerges the moment the mind comes to grips with reality and begins to draw conclusions and unify findings. Some writers speak of a period of human history and of hu­ man thinking as “pre-philosophic.” With all reverence for great learning, we dare to reject this term as inaccurate. It is true that the earliest records of man’s thinking offer us no rounded and systematized interpretation of “all things knowable.” But it is equally true that these records show a real approach to the realm of knowables. Such an approach is not pre-philosophical, but simply philosophical. There is no warrant for cramping the meaning of the word philosophical to exclude all early reasoning on the subjects of God and duty. For theology and ethics (that is, the philosophy of God, and the philosophy of duty) are as truly philosophical as cosmology (the philosophy of the bodily world) or metaphysics (the philosophy of reality as such). Hence we need not apologize for applying the high name of philosophy to the religious and moral conclusions of the ancient THE EMERGENCE OF PHILOSOPHY 37 oriental peoples who have left us the earliest records of human thinking. The philosophical efforts of man, from earliest to most recent, are efforts to find the true answers to one or other of certain fundamental questions. These questions may be listed as seven : (1) The Logical Question, that is, the question of correct procedure in reasoning, in thinking things out ; (s) The Critical Question, that is, the question of the extent and reliability of human knowledge ; the question of the possibil­ ity and method of achieving truth and certitude ; (5) The Cosmological Question, that is, the question of the ultimate constitution of bodies, and of their nature and proper­ ties ; (4) The Psychological Question, that is, the question of the meaning of life, especially human life, and of the nature and powers of the human life-principle or soul ; (5) The Theological Question, that is, the question of the existence, nature, operations, and perfections of God ; (d) The Ontological Question (or, if one prefer, The Meta­ physical Question'), that is, the question of the meaning and prop­ erties of being as such ; (7) The Ethical Question, that is, the question of morality in human conduct, of right and wrong, of human duty and human destiny. These seven questions delineate the field of philosophy. They frame the discussion of “all things knowable.” b) The Ancient Orientals The ancient oriental peoples were the Hebrews, the Chaldeans, the Egyptians, the Chinese, the Hindoos, the Persians. To the records of these early peoples we turn to discern the emergence of philosophy. I. The Hebrews, whose name is probably a derivation from Heber who was one of the ancestors of Abraham, had, from their 38 THE BEGINNINGS OF PHILOSOPHY earliest recorded times, a belief in one God (monotheism). They believed in the immortality of the human soul, and in a life to come which involves retribution for the good or evil practised in this earthly existence. Evidence for these statements is found in the most ancient books of Holy Scripture. After the 6 century b.c., distinct groups of religious philosophers appeared among the Hebrews : (a) The Pharisees held the doctrines already men­ tioned (one God; immortality of the soul; rewards and punish­ ments of a life to come), and they claimed to be the only authorized interpreters of the moral and ceremonial law. (&) The Sadducees denied the existence of anything spiritual (material­ ism) ; they acknowledged the existence of God but denied His government and providence in the world (deism) ; they found the true goal of human life in earthly pleasures and enjoyments (hedonism), (c) The Essenes were a cloistered group who held the necessity of self-denial to loose the soul from its body-prison into the happiness of heaven. They taught that the soul existed before it was joined to the body (pre-existence of souls), and that it was imprisoned in the body for some fault. The Hebrew philosophy deserves its name; it must not be brushed aside as pre-philosophical. It deals, however brokenly, with the theological question, the psychological question, and the ethical question. An important point to notice is that this early philosophy had the idea of one only God; that is, it held the doc­ trine of monotheism. Here we see that monotheism is a really primitive doctrine, and not the development of cruder beliefs as some materialists and evolutionists of our day would like us to think. 2. The Chaldeans (that is to say, the Babylonians and the Assyrians) at first held by monotheism·; they believed in one su­ preme God called El. Later they degraded this pure belief into a system of polytheism, that is, a theory of a plurality of gods. They held that man exists for the worship and service of divin­ ity; to fulfill his destiny he must practise virtue, he must be a lover of peace, and must be just in his dealings with his fellows. THE EMERGENCE OF PHILOSOPHY 39 Again we find monotheism, that pure and elevated doctrine, as a really primitive form of belief, indeed of reasoned knowl­ edge. Evolutionists would like to have it that crude and polythe­ istic beliefs were gradually refined into monotheism, but history has not a single instance of such a refinement. Monotheism pre­ cedes polytheism, and, among peoples not divinely protected from the lapse, monotheism degenerates into polytheism. Notice that the Chaldeans dealt with the theological question and the ethical question. 3. The Ancient Egyptians were, at first, monotheists; they lapsed into polytheism at an early period of their history, and deified the elements and parts of the universe. About the 7 cen­ tury b.c. there was a mighty religious revival among the Egyp­ tians, and the very animals of sacrifice came to be worshipped. But animal worship (zoolatry) was unknown to the most ancient Egyptians. The Egyptians believed in the immortality of the soul, and, about the 7 century b.c., they came to believe in the transmigration of souls (metempsychosis'). They taught the necessity of virtuous living as the means to happiness in a life to come. Here we find the elements of a philosophy which dealt with the theological question, the psychological question, and the ethical question. ' 4. The Ancient Chinese believed in one God called Shang-ti, a personal deity, distinct from the world, and all powerful. This pure belief quickly degenerated, especially after the 12 century b.c. when ancestor worship came strongly into vogue. Worship of the sun, moon, and stars (sabaeism) also appeared. After the 6 century b.c., the Chinese were much influenced in thought and conduct by their philosophers, especially Kun-fu-tse (Confucius) and Lao-tse. Confucius preached faithful observance of ancestral customs ; he discouraged the natural tendency of men to pry into causes and reasons ; his was a philosophy to kill philosophy. Laotse taught the existence of a Supreme Being called Tao (hence his doctrine is called Taoism') who produced the world. Tao is 40 THE BEGINNINGS OF PHILOSOPHY ever serene, untroubled; man must model himself on Tao; man must cultivate serenity of mind, caring nothing for riches or honors, or even for learning or for laws ; man must follow quietly and unexcitedly his own natural bent. The ancient Chinese dealt with the theological question, and, in a measure, with the psychological question ; their great philoso­ phers were concerned chiefly with the ethical question. 5. The Ancient Hindoos had sacred books called Veda, that is, science. These show traces of an original monotheism, but only traces, however plain. Polytheism came into being among the Hindoos at an early period. The Hindoo philosophy is very vague, but it contains unmistakable evidence of some belief in human immortality, in man’s duty to worship divinity and to avoid sin. Between the 8 and the 5 century b.c. certain books (called Brahmanas and Upanishads') were written to explain the Vedas. These hint at a supreme and personal God called Prajapati, but this notion is quickly submerged in a welter of poly­ theistic doctrine. The theory developed in the Brahmanas is that the world and all things in it are maya or illusion. There is only one reality called Brahma. Man must rid himself of the deceiving idea that he exists as an individual ; he must strive to merge him­ self consciously in Brahma with whom all things are really one {pantheism}. Aligned with this doctrine of Brahma is Buddhism which holds the world unreal and illusory and teaches man to seek changelessness and peace in a state of Nirvana in which all desire is dead, all emotion extinguished. The Hindoo philosophy deals slightly with the theological question, largely with the ethical question. Notice that it is pessimistic in character ; it holds that man’s lot is one of decep­ tion and pain, and teaches him that his sole ethical effort is to be rid of pain. 6. The Ancient Persians were monotheists at the first, but about the 8 century b.c. there appeared a mighty teacher called Zarates or Zarathustra (whom the Greeks called Zoroaster) who taught the existence of two warring gods {religious dual­ THE EMERGENCE OF PHILOSOPHY 4i ism) ; one of these was the Supreme Good, the other the Supreme Evil. The good deity was called Ahura-Mazda (the Greeks named him Ormuzd or Ormazd) ; to him we attribute all good things, fire, light, stars and planets, summer, fertility, the human race. The evil deity was called Angra-Mainyu (the Greeks made the name Ahriman) ; to him are to be attributed all evil things, darkness, cold, bad spirits, disease, death, poisonous plants, fero­ cious animals, storms, and all destructive forces. These two divinities wage ceaseless war. One of the followers of AhuraMazda is the great spirit Mithras who will captain the forces of good to the final defeat of Angra-Mainyu. Perhaps, after the evil divinity and his followers have been hurled into the pit of punishment, Mithras will intercede for them, and they will ulti­ mately be admitted to the paradise of delights in which AhuraMazda reigns.—Man was created pure by Ahura-Mazda ; he ate certain forbidden fruits and, in consequence, lost the love of his creator and was numbered with the hosts of Angra-Mainyu. Human nature was thus soiled at its source, and each individual feels within himself the war of good and evil. Man must rid him­ self of the evil and seek his original perfection. Man’s soul is immortal ; it will be brought to purification and happiness either by strong efforts for virtue in this life or by suffering hereafter. The ancient Persians discussed the theological question and the ethical question with incidental discussion of the psycholog­ ical question. We notice in their strange mélange of doctrines some vestiges of the primitive revelation in the somewhat dis­ torted account of man’s creation and original sin. c) The Early Greeks Most accounts of philosophy begin with the speculation (that is, the deep philosophical studies) of the Greeks, dismissing the ancient orientals as pre-philosophic. We have noticed the un­ fairness of this practice. The Greeks had a natural liking for things of the mind. They were inclined to dwell upon what they saw in the world about 42 THE BEGINNINGS OF PHILOSOPHY them and to think out causes and reasons. Among the Greeks, far more than among any other pre-Christian people, philosophy was steadily cultivated. It reached a state of rounded develop­ ment in the Golden Age of Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle. The earliest Greek philosophers attacked the cosmological question ; they sought the explanation of the bodily world. Other questions of philosophy were only incidental to their studies. For convenience, we group the philosophers of this period into “schools,” that is, classifications of philosophers who studied the same matters or held similar views. The “schools” we are to notice are : the lonians, the Pythagoreans, the Eleatics, the Atomists, and the Sophists. I. The lonians, taking up the cosmological question, asked what is the original matter of which the bodily world is made, (a) Thales, of the 7 and 6 centuries b.c., taught that the world­ stuff is water, for the world is a mixture of solids, liquids, and gases, and water is the only substance which we commonly find in all three forms. (£>) Anaximander, of the 7 and 6 centuries b.c., thought the original world-stuff is a kind of spray or mist which is an infinite and living substance (he called it “the Bound­ less”). Out of this substance all bodily things emerge, and, under the action of heat which is inherent in it, they merge into it again, and this process goes on continuously (theory of an infinite series of worlds'). The earth is a cylinder poised in the center of the universe. All matter is alive (hylozoism) ; plants and ani­ mals come by progressive upward stages from the slime of the heated earth (evolution or transformism). (c) Anaximenes, of the 6 century b.c., regarded the original world-stuff as a kind of vapor, infinite and alive, which, by thickening and thinning (con­ densation and rarefaction) causes different things to emerge; these bodies float in the infinite vapor like leaves in an autumn breeze, (d) Heraclitus, of the 6 century b.c., made the primal world-stuff a kind of fire, infinite, alive, intelligent. This fire is not a mass of matter but a kind of all-pervading reason which operates by its inherent power (dynamism) to produce bodies; THE EMERGENCE OF PHILOSOPHY 43 the production of bodies goes on by blind necessity {determin­ ism'). (e) Empedocles, of the 5 century b.c., held that the world­ stuff is a compound of air, earth, water, fire ; these jour elements, by their various comminglings, make up the bodily world and all things in it. Two forces play upon the elements, a unifying force called love and a separating and diversifying force called hate. The bodily world is alive jhylozoism), and has the power of sensing, (f) Anaxagoras, of the 5 century b.c., taught that the world-stuff is a mass of particles of every kind of body found in the universe. This mass was motionless and inert; it was put into a whirling movement by the action of a Divine Mind which is no part of the mass of matter. The whirling motion caused different bodies to “separate out.” The Divine Mind knows all and rules all. In general, the lonians taught a cosmogony, or theory of the emergence of the world, rather than a cosmology, or theory of the nature of the world; still, they dealt proximately (and not philo­ sophically) with the constitution of the bodily universe, and hence deserve to be called cosmologists. Their doctrine is hylozoistic, dynamistic, evolutionistic, deterministic, and sometimes (as in Heraclitus) pantheistic. Of all the philosophers of this school Anaxagoras is by far the most notable, for he alone achieved the idea of an independent Divine Mind as the original mover and ruler of the world. 2. The Pythagoreans (called so from their leader Pythagoras who lived in the 6 century b.c.) were of mathematical mind ; they were charmed by the order and harmony of the universe, by its regularity and proportion. They felt that the world is not only expressible in mathematical terms, but that it is mathematical in nature. They taught that all things are numbers, and number is expressed in harmony. The Pythagoreans believed in an all­ pervading divinity. They taught that man’s soul (which is a number) is imprisoned in the flesh for some primordial sin; un­ less it be purified by virtuous living, it will pass, when a man dies, into another body, and into another and another, until 44 THE BEGINNINGS OF PHILOSOPHY purification is attained or the soul is found hopelessly vile. Here we have the first appearance among the Greeks of metempsy­ chosis or the transmigration of souls. The Pythagoreans are a step higher than the lonians. The lonians achieved a physical idea to explain the world; the Py­ thagoreans a mathematical idea. This idea is very vague, but it is more abstract than that of the lonians, and hence more suit­ able to serve as a focussing-point for a philosophy of the world. Philosophy could not come into its own, however, until man had achieved a metaphysical idea (the idea of being as such) ; this was first set forth and satisfactorily discussed by Aristotle in the 4 century b.c. 5. The Eleatics (called so from the city of Elea where nota­ ble members of this group lived and taught) were impressed by the variety and changeability of the world. They concluded that change is incompatible with substantial reality. Hence they taught that there really is no change ; all change is illusion. “All is; nothing becomes.” All bodies are of the same essential nature. The Eleatics (important among whom were Xenophanes, Parmenides, Zeno of Elea, Melissus of Samos, of the 6 to 4 century b.c.) were monists, that is, they taught that there is only one kind of bodily substance. By implication they were panthe­ ists, for they made the matter of the world self-explaining, hence necessary and eternal, and therefore divine. 4. The Atomists thought of the world-stuff as a great mass of particles like a dust storm. All the particles have the same nature (monism) ; they differ only in shape, size, and weight. The particles do not cling together; they are held apart by vacuoles or intervals of vacuum. They are eternal, and have been in motion from eternity. Out of their motion come various ar­ rangements of differently shaped atoms which we know as bodies. Man has knowledge of sense and of thought. The atomconstituted bodies throw off images of themselves, like shells, and these somehow enter man’s senses and produce sense-knowl­ edge. This knowledge is not trustworthy. The knowledge of THE EMERGENCE OF PHILOSOPHY 45 thought is reliable. Man must find his true good in tranquillity of soul ; he is to obtain this by cultivating pure thought and by using all material things with great moderation. The atomists were materialists for they acknowledged no real­ ity but the bodily world. They were monists for they taught that matter is “all of a piece.” They were mechanicists (or mecha­ nists) for they explained the variety and multiplicity of the world by mechanical movement of atoms. By implication, they were pantheists, for if matter is all, then matter is self-existing and divine. In addition to the cosmological question, the Atomists discussed the critical question (nature and reliability of man’s knowledge), and the ethical question (man’s purpose in exist­ ing, the means he is to use). Notable Atomists were Leucippus, whose times are doubtful, and Democritus who lived in the 5 century b.c. 5. The Sophists (in Greek, sophoi or “the wise ones”) took up the critical question. They concluded that no one can know anything with certainty {skepticism). {a) Protagoras, of the 5 century b.c., said that everything is in a state of becoming ; there is no stable being. Man’s knowledge is never absolute ; it is rela­ tive to the subject, that is, the person who possesses it {relativism and subjectivism), so that what is regarded as true for one per­ son at one time may be false to another person or to the same person at another time. The individual man is thus the measure of truth; “man is the measure of things.” {b) Gorgias, of the 5 century b.c., declared that nothing exists, and if anything did exist it could not be known with certitude {nihilism and skepti­ cism). The sophists were skeptics, and their influence degraded the philosophical effort. They have to their credit, however, that they raised the critical question. Summary of the Article In this Article we have investigated the earliest records of human thinking to discover the sources of philosophy. We have 46 THE BEGINNINGS OF PHILOSOPHY noticed the doctrines,—inaccurately called pre-philosophic,—of the ancient Hebrews, Chaldeans, Egyptians, Chinese, Hindoos, Persians. In the records of all these people we have discovered one constant note—monotheism. Thus we see that the evolu­ tionists are wrong when they try to persuade us that the pure idea of one supreme God is a progressive development and growth out of cruder notions. Monotheism definitely came first ; polytheism and other debased religious philosophies came later as a lapse and retrogression due to man’s original fall and the consequent darkening of the human mind.—We have noticed various groups or schools of early Greek thinkers among whom philosophy began to take more perfect form. We have discussed the lonians, the Pythagoreans, the Eleatics, the Atomists, the Sophists. We have seen that the chief interest of the early Greeks centered on the world about us; their main discussion turned upon the cosmological question. Incidentally, we have learned many valuable terms used in every treatise on philosophy: speculation, monotheism, poly­ theism, materialism, hedonism, deism, pre-existence of souls, metempsychosis, zodlatry, sdbaeism, pantheism, pessimism, reli­ gious dualism, hylozoism, infinite-series-of-worlds, determinism, a physical idea, a mathematical idea, a metaphysical idea, mon­ ism, skepticism, relativism, nihilism, subjectivism. CHAPTER II THE DEVELOPMENT OF PHILOSOPHY The present Chapter studies the growth of philosophy after its emergence in the early Greek schools, and traces the develop­ ment of philosophic thought to its relatively full expression in the magnificent synthesis of Aristotle in the 4 century b.c. The Chapter also discusses the retrogression of philosophy after Aristotle. These matters are studied in three Articles : Article I. The Philosophy of Socrates and Plato Article 2. The Philosophy of Aristotle Article 3. The Course of Philosophy after Aristotle Article 1. The Philosophy of Socrates and Plato a) The Essential Question; b) Theories of Socrates; of Plato. c) Theories a) The Essential Question It is useless to employ human reason in the quest of truth un­ less it can be known beyond doubt or quibble that the mind is capable of attaining truth and holding it with certitude. Man cannot attain to all truth, for the scope of the intellect, while tremendous, is not infinite. But there is a vast domain of truth which man is competent to investigate and within which his natural" mental powers can bring him to unwavering certitude. If this fact be not recognized at the outset, no development of philosophy is possible. Without a recognition of human power capable of knowing things with certitude, philosophy becomes silly vaporizing and the baseless fabrication of a dream. There­ fore, the essential question of philosophy is the critical question, 47 48 THE DEVELOPMENT OF PHILOSOPHY that is, the question of the value and extent of the human knowing­ power ; the question of knowledge, truth, and certitude as avail­ able to man’s connatural and unaided efforts. When Socrates came upon the scene, in the 5 century b.c., the ability of man to know things for certain was being cast into doubt by the Sophists. The doctrine of these teachers was skepti­ cism, that is, the doctrine that man cannot be certain of anything and that all his knowledge is valueless or, at best, of dubious value. It is, of course, impossible to formulate a direct proof by reason for the reliability of reason. Such a proof would involve the fallacy of “begging the question,” that is, assuming at the outset the point to be established by the proof. Nor is a proof necessary. A proof is always a careful and methodical unfolding of a thing which is complicated ; it is a simplifying ; it is a bring­ ing to light and evidence what is not evident in itself. But when a thing is simple to begin with, no simplifying is called for. When a thing is uncomplicated, no unfolding of complications is pos­ sible. When a thing is self-evident, external evidence is not needed. One does not need a lighted lamp to discover the noon­ day sun. One does not demand proof that the eyes can see. One simply beholds the sunlight and uses one’s eyes. That a man can think, and think things out by putting two and two together, is as direct and evident an experience as seeing with the bodily eyes in daylight. Proof is neither possible nor necessary. Still it is possible to formulate an indirect proof of the selfevident truths of man’s existence and man’s ability to think and by thinking to arrive at certitude and reliable knowledge. Such proof is found in the impossible and self-contradictory charac­ ter of the opposed doctrine called skepticism. For skepticism is the total paralysis of philosophy ; it is, as G. K. Chesterton once remarked, “the suicide of thought.” Like suicide, is it an insane thing. Skepticism asserts that it is certain that nothing is certain. It uses reason to show that there is no use using reason. The THE PHILOSOPHY OF SOCRATES AND PLATO 49 skeptic cannot speak without affirming his own existence as a certain fact, without affirming certain meaning in the words he he utters, without affirming the certain existence of those to whom he speaks, without affirming the truth of his own theory that no truth of theory is possible. Therefore, the skeptic cannot open his mouth without contradicting himself and denying his own philosophy even as he states it. The skeptic has no recourse but to remain forever silent. Socrates did not pause to analyze the error of the skeptical Sophists. To their doubts and denials he opposed a human and manly acceptance of the power of man’s mind to attain truth and to hold it with certitude. This he took for granted, as every sane man must. Starting with this premise, he developed his philoso­ phy of the critical question, giving his theory of knowledge, its character, its value, its purpose. He tied in his studies of the critical question with the ethical question, and, to some extent, with the psychological question and the theological question. But the main mark and characteristic of Socrates’ philosophy is that it is critical and ethical; it deals with human knowing and with virtue, and indeed it brings these two things together in one. In much this theory is erroneous, but it marked a splendid step for­ ward in the development of true philosophy (or true speculation}, and it was a needed brake upon the ruinous course of the Sophists. b) Theories of Socrates Socrates lived from 469 to 399 b.c. He has left us no writings, and it is likely that he wrote nothing to leave. He taught only orally, and his teachings have come down to us through the writings of his pupils, Plato and Xenophon. Thus our “sources” are secondary, since only a man’s own writings are primary sources of his teachings. But these secondary sources are, in the present case, reliable. Socrates felt a divine call to teach and to improve the lives of men. Teaching was for him a religious duty. He recognized the 50 THE DEVELOPMENT OF PHILOSOPHY fact that no improvement in men’s lives and morals is possible without a solid philosophy of knowledge. For why speak of duties to men who cannot be sure of anything, and hence cannot certainly know that they have duties at all ? Why talk of morals if there is no reliable knowledge that morals exist or are desir­ able? So intimate indeed is the relation of knowledge to right living that Socrates declared that knowledge is virtue. He main­ tained that to know thoroughly what is right is to make the do­ ing of wrong impossible. Now, Socrates must have known very well that we often act in contradiction to our knowledge. With the poet Ovid, he must have had experience of “seeing and approving the better things, yet doing the worse.” Nor did he excuse sin and crime as the product of sheer ignorance. No, he held that when a man knows thoroughly and realizes all the implications of what he knows he cannot act in such a way as to make practical denial of his knowledge. Yet Socrates stressed the knowing-power too strongly. He should have stressed free-will as well. Man’s mind is not like the all-embracing daylight. What a person knows, in full setting, with all implications clearly evident, is not present to the casual mental glance as a wide and varied landscape is present to the glance of the eye. The human mind is, in its action, rather like a narrowly focussed spotlight which throws its light on one small space and leaves many available areas in darkness. And the hand behind the spotlight, turning it this way or that, to take in this consideration or to omit that other, is the free-will. What­ ever proposed course of action is illuminated by the spotlight of the mind has aspects of attractiveness and aspects of unattractive­ ness, and the mind dwells on whichever of these two things the will decides it shall consider. No matter how good an object of consideration may be, the will can focus the mind on features of it that are unattractive and repellant. And no matter how bad an object may be, the will may turn the light of the mind upon some real or apparent phases of it that are attractive. Hence, sin THE PHILOSOPHY OF SOCRATES 51 is possible, even when the sinner “knows better.” To put this technically: “Man is capable of objectively indifferent judg­ ments.” Perhaps Socrates stressed knowledge so strongly because he earnestly wished to root out the pernicious error of the Soph­ ists who made knowledge of no value at all. At all events, he did make knowledge the one thing necessary for man’s mental and moral well-being. And he held that of all knowledge knowledge of self is the core and the essence. “Know thyself!” was the sum­ mary of his teaching. Why should a person strive to know himself? Because, said Socrates, all knowledge is in him as planted seeds are in the earth. He must labor, as the gardener labors with hoe and waterpot, to bring this germinal knowledge to birth, growth, fruitful­ ness. Is this latent knowledge inborn in the mind? It is not certain that Socrates held this doctrine (innatism). If he did, he was utterly wrong, for all our natural knowledge is acquired; it be­ gins with the action of the senses on the bodily world around us ; from sense-findings the mind or intellect arises to knowledge that is quite beyond the reach of the senses, and forms ideas or con­ cepts, judgments, and reasonings. But perhaps Socrates did not teach innatism. He may have taught that the seed-knowledge with which the mind is endowed was implanted by the action of the senses upon the material and sensible universe. Whatever he taught about the origin of knowledge, it is clear that he held that the finished product is to be worked out of the mind itself. How shall a person set to work to bring to fruitfulness,—that is, to clear, certain, scientific understanding,—the seed-knowl­ edge of the mind? By following the Socratic Method. This method consists of two processes, the ironic and the maieutic.— (a) When a youth came to Socrates for instruction, the great teacher would receive him with every mark of respect, and would ask him questions, seeming to be himself a pupil rather than a teacher. Invariably the newcomer would grow expansive under 52 THE DEVELOPMENT OF PHILOSOPHY this treatment, and presently he would begin to “show off.” Now, the questions of Socrates seemed innocent, but they were most shrewdly put. Sooner or later the over-confident newcomer would involve himself in contradictory answers. Again and again he would be led into conflicting and impossible statements. Soc­ rates would gently point out this distressing state of affairs, and before long the poor victim would be forced to make shamefaced admission that he did not know what he was talking about. This was what Socrates was working for. The confession of igno­ rance is, he taught, the first essential step in the work of achieving knowledge of self. Thus far the Socratic irony. It cleared and loosened the mental soil.—(&) Then came the maieutic process, that is, the process of “bringing to birth” the ideas and judg­ ments of the mind. This process amounted to study and dis­ cussion,—“dialogue,” it was called. If, for example, the question, “What is virtue?” was posed for his students, Socrates would use,—if necessary,—the ironic process to disabuse the pupils’ minds of hazy, inept, inadequate preconceptions. Then he would call for examples of virtue. He would require a pupil to explain why he had named each example virtue. He would institute com­ parison of example with example, noting similarities and differ­ ences. At length, the pupils would be prepared to formulate a clear and precise definition of virtue. Now, once a person can clearly define a thing, he knows that thing. Thus, by the maieutic process, is knowledge “brought to birth.” This method of working out a concept by studying various instances or examples is known as the inductive method or simply as induction. Socrates is rightly regarded as “the father of induction.” The concepts or ideas worked out by the maieutic process are used by the mind in forming judgments and arriving at conclu­ sions by reasoning. Such judgments and reasonings, said Soc­ rates, are unchangeably true; they constitute science; they are known with certitude. Thus did Socrates contradict the doubts THE PHILOSOPHY OF SOCRATES 53 and denials of the Sophists with a ringing assertion of the pos­ sibility of achieving truth, certitude, science. We see, in all this, that Socrates was concerned with the critical question; we also notice that this question is intimately bound up in the Socratic system with the ethical question, since Socrates held that knowledge is virtue. Dealing directly with the ethical question, Socrates says that man is made for happiness, and that happiness is the fruit of goodness, that is, of virtuous living. And, since knowledge is virtue, and is to be attained by striving to develop the contents of the mind, man’s great moral effort must be directed to knowledge, especially self-knowledge. “Gnothi s’auton, Know thyself !” was the constant cry of Socrates. As to the theological question, it is fairly clear that Socrates believed in one supreme God. But for the sake of avoiding po­ litical troubles,—which came upon him notwithstanding,—he conformed to the polytheistic practices of his times. On the cosmological question, it is likely that Socrates taught the production of this world out of eternal matter, and that he regarded the world as the best that could possibly be made {cos­ mological optimism). On both scores he was wrong. He did not identify the world with God {pantheism), but held that God is present everywhere in the world, ruling it in all things {divine providence and government). Discussing the psychological question, Socrates held that man has a soul which is distinct from the body. The human soul, he taught, is like God inasmuch as it is simple (that is, not made of parts), immortal, and endowed with understanding and memory. It seems, however, that Socrates failed to realize that the cause of the soul’s immortality is its spirituality. It will be noticed, too, that Socrates failed to mention free-will as a faculty of the soul, and one that makes it like to God. And he mentions understand­ ing and memory as though they were two faculties, whereas they are one ; the intellectual memory is but one function or service of the understanding (i.e., the intellect) itself. 54 THE DEVELOPMENT OF PHILOSOPHY What Socrates taught about the union of soul and body in man, is not clear. He may have held, as did Plato later, that the soul is in the body as a hand is in a glove ; that is, he may have taught a merely accidental union of soul and body. The truth is that soul and body in man are substantially united ; soul and body constitute a single substance, the human substance. Such in briefest outline were the teachings of Socrates. Despite incompleteness and errors, these theories constitute a developing philosophy which is immeasurably superior to anything accom­ plished by thinkers of preceding ages. The fame of Socrates as a teacher and his widening influence over minds, especially the minds of the young, brought him to the unfavorable notice of the politicians. These fine gentlemen managed to have him condemned to death. He drank the deadly hemlock in the year 399 b.c. In passing, we must contradict the sentimental opinion that the suicide of Socrates was a noble deed. If it were not for the artistic and touching account of it we have from the pen of Plato, we should probably never think of it as something fine and full of dignity. Suicide is never noble. It is, in itself, a contemptible and a cowardly deed. Of course, Socrates, despite his magnifi­ cent mind, was under the sway of pagan opinion and custom; without doubt he regarded the taking of his life as a thing justi­ fied and even necessary in the circumstances. We make no at­ tempt to fix his personal guilt. We simply point out the truth of sane ethics that a man may never take his life by direct means. No man may justly be compelled to be his own executioner. Even if he be willing to spare the hangman an ugly job, he may not kill himself. For it is manifestly an unnatural thing (and hence con­ trary to the natural law) for a man to take his own life, even if that life be forfeit. One final word. While Socrates was wrong in identifying knowledge and virtue, he deserves the highest praise for his ef­ forts to put ethics on a reasoned basis, and to show that many things are good or bad in themselves. He made moral science THE PHILOSOPHY OF PLATO 55 more than a set of rules of etiquette, or a programme of whims, or a code of fads, or a list of likes and dislikes. A great many of our modern intellectuals would do well to ponder and to imitate this notable Socratic effort. c) Theories of Plato The name Plato is familiar to everyone, even to Macaulay’s schoolboy. But many are unaware that the word Plato is a nick­ name. The real name of this philosopher was Aristocles. It is said that he was of stocky build, and that his broad shoulders earned him the nickname Plato, for platos is Greek for breadth. Perhaps the famous name Plato was the invention of some com­ panion who fixed it upon the young Aristocles as a schoolboy of our day labels a comrade by reason of physical appearance and knows him thenceforth as “Shorty” or “Stumpy” or “Slim.” Plato was of noble descent. He was a splendidly gifted man, and he used his gifts with studious diligence. He was a poet, a playwright, an observant traveller, a philosopher, and,—most important of all,—a literary stylist of the first rank. Plato de­ stroyed his plays and poems, but he retained his splendid style, and this fact (together with the other fact that many of his works survive intact to our day) has a great deal to do with his enduring fame. Many of his theories are exalted and attractive, but it may be questioned whether his essential philosophy would have lived if it had been clothed in less artistic expression. Does anyone doubt that a masterly style can be so effective as to “put a man over”? Let such a person consider Renan. Let him consider Pascal. Let him even consider Will Durant. Then let him con­ sider Plato. Plato (427-347 b.c.) studied under the philosopher Cratylus and then for eight years he was the pupil of Socrates. His own period of teaching was a long and notable intellectual reign. He died in Athens at the ripe age of eighty. We have thirty-five dialogues attributed to Plato. Many of these are unquestionably genuine ; some are spurious ; some are 56 THE DEVELOPMENT OF PHILOSOPHY of doubtful authenticity. Among the important ones commonly accepted as genuine are: Gorgias, The Banquet, Phaedo, Phaedrus, The Republic, Timaeus, Laws, Theaetetus, and most of his Letters. Like Socrates, Plato was interested, first and foremost, in the critical question, but this question was, for him, intertwined with the psychological question rather than with the ethical question as in the Socratic system. The basic and unifying doctrine of Plato’s philosophy is his theory of knowledge. This is a famous theory, and it served Plato well in his efforts to bring into a harmonious system the notable teachings of his predecessors and contemporaries. But, for all that, it is a false and futile theory. Plato taught that each man was originally a soul. He was a spirit living in a world of things-in-themselves ; a world of sub­ stantial universal ideals or forms. The world about us is a world of individual things. We see individual trees, we speak to individual men, we hear individual sounds, we notice individual instances or expressions of beauty. And yet our intellectual knowledge is not individual ; it is uni­ versal. The eye can see only individual trees, but the mind or intellect knows what tree means. We have knowledge of tree-initself or tree-as-such. We can write the definition of tree, and it defines each and every tree that has ever existed, or exists now, or will exist, or can exist. For we know and define an essence; we are not confined to the sense-knowledge of individual things that have that essence. How can it be that, in a world made up exclusively of individual things, we have this universal knowl­ edge of essences in the abstract ? Aristotle was presently to give the right answer to this im­ portant question. He was to teach that the mind has the power of peering beneath the trappings of individuality and getting at the essences of things. This abstractive power of the human intellect was something that Plato neither recognized nor sus­ pected. Plato thought that the only explanation of the universal THE PHILOSOPHY OF PLATO 57 ideas in our minds is found in the fact that those minds once con­ fronted universal things. So he taught that we have had a previ­ ous existence in a spiritual realm {pre-existence of souls'). There we confronted and beheld not trees, but tree-in-itself ; there we saw, not a beautiful object or scene, but beauty-subsisting-initself ; there we knew, not something good, but substantial good­ ness itself. Now man, the soul, somehow sinned. The spirit that dwelt in the world of things-as-they-are, or things-substantially-subsisting-in-themselves, was somehow contaminated, and this by its own fault. For this offense, the soul was imprisoned in a body and put here on the earth. As the soul was thrust into its body­ prison, it forgot all its splendid knowledge. But the body is equipped with channels of knowledge; we call them the senses. These can deal only with the externals of individual things, but still they do give us knowledge. And this individual knowledge garnered by the senses stirs the soul, prods it to recall what once it knew. And so, stirred by the objects of sense, a man dimly and imperfectly remembers what things are. T0 know is to re­ member. Here we see that Plato taught these things: (1) the pre­ existence of souls; (2) the innate or inborn character of knowl­ edge; (5) the purely accidental (that is, non-substantial) union of soul and body; (4) the existence of a supernal realm where things exist in universal and not as individuals; (5) by im­ plication, he denied the abstractive power of the human mind or intellect. And in all five teachings Plato was calamitously wrong. The previous existence of souls (or pre-existence, as it is tech­ nically called) is both philosophically untenable and theologically reprobated. The moment that God creates the soul (and God immediately and directly creates each human soul) He joins it substantially with its body, though the body be but a micro­ scopic reality in the bosom of a mother. One identical instant, unbroken, undivided, is the instant of the creation and the sub­ stantial. uniting (or infusion) of the soul. The very first moment 58 THE DEVELOPMENT OF PHILOSOPHY in which a human soul exists without its body is the moment that comes immediately after a man’s death. There is no such moment before conception or birth. Innatism or the doctrine of inborn knowledge is a theory wholly indefensible, as philosophers of all ages have shown, from Aristotle to Locke. We acquire our knowledge. Starting with the experiences of the senses which bring us knowledge of things in their concrete and material individuality, we rise, by the abstractive power of the mind, to the recognition of what kind of things we sense; we recognize essences; we form uni­ versal ideas or concepts. And these are the elements of our intel­ lectual knowledge. As we have seen in discussing the theories of Socrates, the union of soul and body in man is a substantial union, not an accidental one. The soul is not merely in the body. Soul and body are so united as to form one single, if compound, substance. Man is not a body alone, nor a soul alone ; neither is he merely a soulin-a-body. Plato said that the soul is in the body controlling it as a rower is in a boat moving it at will by his efforts at the oars. This is wholly false. Man is an animated body, a soul-infused body, a soul-and-body compound. Union of soul and body is not accidental but substantial. The soul is indeed the most important part or element of a man ; it is what the Scholastics call the sub­ stantial form of the living body ; yet it is not the whole man. And while the soul, which is a spirit, can exist alone, and does exist alone when it leaves the body at death, it has a kind of connatural need for the body because it cannot exercise all the functions of which it is the natural principle or source unless it be joined in substance with its body. Hence we see that sane philosophy finds entirely acceptable the Christian truth of the ultimate resurrec­ tion of the body. Plato’s notion of a supernal realm where things exist as uni­ versal substances is a fanciful conception, highly poetic, pleasingly imaginative, but it is a wholly gratuitous assumption and is in no sense a philosophical truth. Indeed, reason cannot admit the pos­ THE PHILOSOPHY OF PLATO 59 sibility of any finite thing existing in universal. Plato’s vague theory seems to imply the notion that all the subsisting universal forms or ideals are unified and identified in the Subsistent Ideal of The Good. A sympathetic interpreter could, with a bit of straining, bring this theory into some agreement with the majes­ tic truth that the Infinite Goodness, God Himself, is the only Being which exists eternally and necessarily, and that in Him, identified with His Undivided Essence, are the archetypal ideas or forms of all things creatable. But, could such an interpretation of Plato’s theory of ideas (or ideals) have been suggested to him four hundred years before Christ when he walked the groves of Academe, it would doubtlessly have been to him tire occasion of no little astonishment. Of the abstractive power of the human intellect which Plato implicitly denies without having heard of it or thought of it, we have already spoken briefly and we shall have occasion to speak again in a later Article. Plato’s theory of knowledge supports, however vainly and shallowly, the important doctrines of the changelessness of truth, the possibility of man’s achieving certitude, and the possibility of science. Like Socrates, Plato, despite his purpose of harmonizing and unifying all notable theories of philosophers, turned his face steadily ^gainst the destructive and self-contradictory skepticism of the Sophists. '“In discussing the cosmological question, Plato teaches that the bodily universe and all the bodily things in it are ultimately made of some primordial world-stuff which has the elemental , forms of air, earth, fire, and water. Thus Plato borrows from the lonians, particularly from Empedocles. We must ever remem­ ber that he was a harmonizer; he had the avowed purpose of bringing all acceptable philosophies into unity and system. The primordial world-stuff (which first appears as air, earth, fire, water) is sometimes called the Platonian prime matter. This term is apt to be misleading, for Plato’s world-stuff was a definite kind of matter, and hence was not primary but secondary. We 6o THE DEVELOPMENT OF PHILOSOPHY shall discuss the true meaning of “prime matter” in our study of Aristotle’s cosmology. Plato believed, with Socrates, that the world is the best of all possible worlds (cosmological optimism) since God could make nothing inferior. And, since life is superior to non-life, the world must be alive (hylozoism). God,—the Subsistent Idea or Ideal of The Good,—created the world. As Creator, God is called Demiurge. Before the bodily universe was made, God created certain spirits ; to these He com­ mitted the work of creating the bodily world. Yet He reserved to Himself the creation of man’s soul. Plato’s cosmology is full of errors. Neither his primal matter (which turns out to be secondary and not primal) nor his ele­ ments are ultimate explanations of bodies. Both are bodies them­ selves, and hence offer the same problem to the philosopher as the universe taken at face value. As for his cosmological opti­ mism, the world is not the absolutely best world, else the inex­ haustible power of the Creator would be exhausted in its making ; it is relatively the best inasmuch as it is most admirably suited for its purpose. Nor is anything to be called inferior or imperfect which fits into its place and service for the achieving of purpose. Hence Plato’s argument for optimism and for hylozoism are gratuitous and valueless. As we have seen, much psychological doctrine is bound up with Plato’s fundamental philosophy, his famous Theory of Knowledge. Coming directly to the psychological question, Plato teaches that man’s soul (directly created by God) is spiritual, rational, self-moving, immortal. The body-prison in which the soul is enclosed was originally a male body. From this was drawn a female body and also the bodies of animals. Once produced, living bodies proceeded to multiply by the process of generation. In addition to the spiritual soul, man has a sensing-soul and a soul which is the source of courage. Only the spiritual soul is immortal. If a man properly purifies himself in this life and casts off the guilt of the offense that led to the imprisonment of his THE PHILOSOPHY OF PLATO 61 soul in the body, the soul will return at his death to the realm of substantial ideals or forms from which its primal fault banished it. If, however, a man have lived ill, his soul will pass at his death into a female body (transmigration of souls or metempsychosis'). If the female existence be badly spent, the soul will next appear in an animal, and eventually, if evil endures, in a plant. Hope­ lessly incorrigible souls will be put in a place of torment. At times Plato speaks of this hell as eternal ; again he seems to sug­ gest that all souls will eventually be purified and sent to the heaven of substantial ideals. The idea of a primal fall of man is common to all the ancients and can be explained only as a surviving remnant of the Primitive Revelation. All the world remembers Original Sin, and that, as Mr. Chesterton points out, is one reason why so many modern intellectuals are anxious to deny it. Plato’s theory of three souls in man is fantastic ; perhaps we might interpret this doctrine to mean that man’s soul has three notable modes of action. The doctrine of a spiritual, immortal, rational soul in man is true, and is demonstrated in the department of philosophy called Rational Psychology. The notion of transmigration of souls is oriental rather than Grecian, yet it had won the approval of those Greeks who followed Pythagorean doctrine, and so Plato puts it into his harmonized system. It is utterly false, however, and lacks every vestige of scientific or philosophical proof. The notion that existing females are only reincarnations of unworthy males should scarcely endear Plato to the devout female sex. The Platonian doctrine of heaven and hell falls short of reality but suggests it. Plato shrinks from the bald assertion of the eternity of hell as many persons do today under the mistaken impression that they are being fair and merciful. Anything short of an eternal sanction for the moral law cannot satisfy reason, nor can it meet the requirements of sane feeling. The eternity of hell is not only a fact, but a truly sane fact, a merciful fact, not a cruel conception involving mere revenge. In discussing the ethical question, Plato holds that sin is in­ 62 THE DEVELOPMENT OF PHILOSOPHY evitable because of the dullness of the mind which guides the will. But, says Plato, the inevitable sin is to be laid to man’s charge ; he is responsible for it in cause, inasmuch as he freely committed the primal sin which brought imprisonment in the body and con­ sequent dullness of mind. The ultimate goal of human effort is happiness. Man does not find happiness in things that serve his earthly use (utilitarianism'), nor in things which flatter the senses (hedonism), but in the steady effort to live virtuously and to know The Good, that is, God. Earthly man is meant for life with his fellows, and human society takes on a necessary form in the State. The individual is necessarily a citizen. As such he exists for the State. The civil power (that is, the State) must take control of each child early in life ; it must discover the child’s special aptitudes and train him in accordance with them, so that the State may be a harmonious and smoothly functioning organ­ ism. The best form of government is that in which a few wise men hold the place of control (aristocracy or sophocracy). The next best form of government is military rule (timocracy). Less desirable and even bad forms of government are : oligarchy or the rule of certain families ; democracy or the rule of the rank and file of common people ; and tyranny or the rule of an absolute sovereign who lacks wisdom, foresight, and kindness. Plato rightly declares that the goal of human conduct is hap­ piness, and, surprisingly enough for a man unenlightened by Christian Revelation, he is right in teaching that happiness is to be sought in the knowledge of God and the practice of virtue. That man sins inevitably, at least venially, sometimes in life (un­ less he be kept from it by a special Providence) is true; it is not true, however, that man cannot avoid mortal sin if he uses the grace of God which is made available to all without exception. Of course, it would be unfair to expect Plato to know this truth for it is a matter of the Christian Faith. Plato is entirely wrong in his theory that the citizen exists for the State. Strictly speak­ ing, the State exists for the citizen. And while the State must control the citizen in many things and exact obedience to its THE PHILOSOPHY OF PLATO 63 laws, it does so in the interest of the body of citizens, not in its own interest as though it were a thing independent of the citi­ zens and superior to them. For, while the State is a natural society and not an artificial one founded on some compact or agreement of men (as Hobbes, Rousseau, and others were to teach later in their theories of Social Compact or Social Contract'), it is not the owner of its citizens but their servant ; it is not their superior but their inferior. Of course, it is not for the individual man to say that, since the State is his servant, he may order it about as he chooses ; the State is not his personal servant, but the servant of all citizens together. And, while the individual man is the im­ portant thing (since he, not the State, not society, is the image of God), he must remember that there are many other individuals with rights equal to his own and of the same sort as his own. Hence the individual must be prepared to make willing 'personal sacrifice, to endure inconvenience, to curb anti-social impulses ; he must obey civil laws, and must expect and accept punishment for the violation of these laws,—which really means the viola­ tion of other men’s rights. Sane ethics thus avoids two evil extremes which actually meet in their enslavement of the indi­ vidual : it avoids exaggerated individualism (with its inevitable enslavement of the many in the interest of the few who happen to have power), and it avoids totalitarianism or State absolutism (with its inevitable enslavement of the citizens in the interest of civil power, or, more precisely, in the interest of evil politicians who manipulate the civil power). The root of Plato’s calami­ tously mistaken doctrine of State absolutism is found in his view of the State as an organism of which the citizen is but a cell, that is, a thing dependent, inferior, existing only for the well-being of the larger organism of which it is but a tiny part. This view (which was later to be developed by Herbert Spencer, who taught that all humanity is one organism) is full of damage to the human race. One type of such damage appears in the cry for State control of education,—a thing which Plato himself openly favored. It must be kept steadily and clearly in mind that parents 64 THE DEVELOPMENT OF PHILOSOPHY have the right and the duty of educating their children. And the aim of true education is the producing of good men and women, not the producing of good citizens. Of course, good men and women will be good citizens, but that is incidental to their char­ acter as good men and women. The function of the State in edu­ cation is to guard the rights of parents in the matter, to supply opportunity for the realization of this right, and to help in vari­ ous ways in its actual exercise. But State control of education is an unqualified evil ; it works always to the ruin of sound govern­ ment and peaceful social life ; inevitably so, since it is a contra­ diction of the natural law. Summary of the Article In this Article we have noticed that the first and fundamental question of all philosophy is the critical question, that is, the question of the extent and reliability of human knowledge. We have seen that the truth that man can know, can reason, can have certitude, is a self-evident truth which neither requires nor ad­ mits direct proof. We have studied, in brief outline, the doctrines taught by Socrates and by Plato, finding in them both truth and falsity, sometimes strangely commingled, but discerning in them a new and penetrating philosophical effort, a more thorough and complete speculation, than the pagan world had yet known. In a word, we find in these two sets of theories a developing philoso­ phy; we find that here the true and perennial philosophy begins to take form. Our vocabulary of philosophical terms and phrases has been enriched as we learned the meaning of: the Socratic Method (with ironic and maieutic processes) ; induction; optimism; innatism; sensation; intellection; substantial union; accidental union; simplicity; Platonic subsistent universal ideas, or ideals, or forms; essence; Platonic prime matter; utilitarianism; indi­ vidualism; totalitarianism; State; State absolutism; Social Con­ tract Theory (or Le Contrat Social). THE PHILOSOPHY OF ARISTOTLE 65 Article 2. The Philosophy of Aristotle a) Aristotle; b) Logic; c) Physics; d) Metaphysics; e) Ethics. a) Aristotle Aristotle was born in 384 b.c. at Stagira (and hence he is called “The Stagirite”) in ancient Chalcis. His was perhaps the finest mind, in natural gifts, that the world has ever known. For twenty years he was a pupil of Plato, carrying on meanwhile his private researches in philosophy and in physical science. He had an interest in biological study, and it is likely that he did some dissecting under the eye of his father, Nichomachus, who was court-physician to the king of Macedon. Aristotle spent some time in travel, and afterwards he was tutor to the young Alexan­ der whom the world was to know as “the Great.” Then he set up as a teacher at Athens. His pupils about him, he lectured as they all walked slowly up and down the shaded walks of the Lyceum of Apollo. And thus his school came to be known as “the peri­ patetics,” a name derived from the Greek peripatein “to walk about.” After a dozen years of teaching, Aristotle incurred the displeasure of the politicians, for he had acquired far too much influence with the young men of Athens to be a safe person to have about. He quietly slipped away, and died a natural death in Euboea in 322 b.c. when he was sixty-two years of age. We have some of Aristotle’s writings, although certain critics think these are but notes taken by his more gifted pupils. No such masterful style appears in these works as graces the writings of Plato. If Aristotle really wrote them, he did not take time to edit them and set them in finished order. Yet, for all that, these writ­ ings are among the most precious pages that the world possesses. We group the writings of Aristotle under four heads : Logic (the Organon, or, as he called it, Analytic') ; Physics; Meta­ physics; Ethics. 66 THE DEVELOPMENT OF PHILOSOPHY b) Logic Logic is the science of correctness in the human knowing­ process. For thinking must be correct if it is to lead one securely to knowledge that is true and certain. Today we distinguish in Logic a twofold science : one, the science of correct thinking, of legitimate procedure in reasoning ; we call this Formal Logic or Dialectics ; the other, the science of truth and certitude as achiev­ able by thinking, that is, by reasoning; we call this Major Logic or Criteriology. Aristotle, with perfect scientific acumen, as­ signed the study of truth and certitude to metaphysics. Aristotle invented the science of Formal Logic or Analytic, and he developed it into a rounded and relatively perfect thing. Of few men and of few achievements may such a statement be made. The mind has three major operations : it directly knows things (that is, it grasps essences in an abstract manner) ; it compares its findings and judges their agreements and disagreements (that is, it pronounces upon what it knows) ; finally, it works out further judgments by reasoning upon judgments already formed. The first of these operations is called apprehending ; the second, judging; the third, reasoning. The purpose of Formal Logic or Dialectics (or of Analytic) is to discern the mode of procedure which the mind must follow to insure a reliable result ; it is to discern the “laws of thinking” ; it is to know how and wherein the three operations, and especially the last (i.e., reason­ ing), are legitimate and justified. Aristotle analyzed the mental processes with enlightened ac­ curacy. Discerning the fact that the mind, by its native power, rises from the findings of the senses to reality that lies beyond sense-grasp, and abstracts from the individual character of sense­ objects to know things in universal, he goes on to set forth and prove the existence of three grades of mental abstraction, the physical, the mathematical, the metaphysical. These three grades or degrees of mental abstraction are important in themselves and THE PHILOSOPHY OF ARISTOTLE 67 also as the proper bases of the classification of the sciences which deal with extramental reality. Apprehending supplies the mind with elemental knowledge, that is, ideas or concepts which are the mental representations of essences. Then the mind goes to its proper work of judging, pronouncing, recognizing truths, connecting subject-idea and predicate-idea. Judging is the fundamental thought-process. The operation called reasoning is but a series of judgings, connected, related, leading to a final act of judging and pronouncing some agreement,-—that is, bringing together some subject and some predicate,—or disagreement,—that is, denying some predicate of some subject. In a word, reasoning is a roundabout way of ar­ riving at a judgment which is not immediately manifest to the mind. Judging is the basic, the essential process of thinking. Now, in judging, the mind pronounces on the agreement or disagreement of ideas or concepts ; the mind associates or dis­ severs a predicate-idea and a subject-idea; the mind affirms or denies a predicate of a subject. Thus judging is predicating. Ar­ istotle discerns five ways in which predicating takes place ; every judgment is necessarily made according to one of these five ways. The Five Modes of Predicating are called the predicates (in Greek, categoremataj. These are: Genus, Species, Difference, Property or Attribute, and Accident. To explain and illustrate : (a) Genus—When the mind predicates one idea of another (applies predicate-idea to subject-idea) in such wise that the predicate expresses that part of the essence of the subject which the subject has in common with other things from which it is none the less essentially distinguished, the predicate-idea is called the genus of the subject-idea, and the judging or predicating is called generic. Thus, in the judgment, “Man is animal,” the predicate-idea “animal” expresses part of the essence “man,” but not all of that essence for man is more than animal ; the predicate­ idea expresses that part of the essence “man” which man has in common with other things, namely, non-rational animal beings. (&) Species—When the mind predicates one idea of another 68 THE DEVELOPMENT OF PHILOSOPHY (i.e., predicate of subject) in such wise that the predicate ex­ presses or defines the entire essence of the subject perfectly and exclusively, the predicate-idea is the species of the subject-idea, and the judging or predicating is called specific. Thus, in the judgment, “Man is rational animal,” the predicate-idea expresses completely, perfectly, and exclusively the essence of the subject­ idea. This predicate applies to no other subject. The predicate is an essential definition of the subject. The predicate is the species of the subject. (c) Difference—When the mind applies predicate-idea to subject-idea in such wise that the predicate expresses that part of the essence of the subject which marks the subject off from other things with which it has a common genus, the predicate is called the difference (or the ultimate difference or the specific difference) of the subject. Thus, in the judgment “Man is rational,” the predicate-idea expresses what distinguishes the subject-idea from another idea which has with it a common genus, that is, from non-rational animal. The judging or predi­ cating here is called differential. (d) Property or Attribute—When the mind applies predi­ cate-idea to subject-idea in such wise that the predicate expresses what belongs to the subject by natural necessity but is no con­ stituent element or part of its essence, the predicate is called the property or the attribute of the subject, and the judging or pred­ icating is called proper. Thus, in the judgment, “Man is a-beingthat-can-laugh” the predicate-idea expresses what belongs by nature to the subject although it is no part of the essence of the subject. (