BOOK IV
Lecture 1
Place, its existence
406. After treating in Book III of motion, and the infinite, which belongs intrinsically to motion insofar as it is in the genus of continuous things, the Philosopher now intends, in Book IV, to deal with the things that are extrinsically connected with motion.
First, of things that are connected with motion extrinsically as measures of mobile things:
Secondly, of time which is the measure of motion itself, at no.558 (L.15,1.
As to the first he does two things:
First, he studies place;
Secondly, the void, at no. 494 (L.9).
About the first he does two things:
First, he shows that it is the business of the natural philosopher to study place;
Secondly, he carries out his proposition, at no. 411.
As to the first he does two things:
First, [277] he proposes what he intends and says that just as it is the business of the natural philosopher to determine about the infinite; namely, whether it exists or not, and how it exists, and what it is, so also about place;
Secondly, at no. 407, he proves what he had said:
First from the viewpoint of place itself;
Secondly, from our viewpoint [i.e., that of the ones studying place] at no. 409.
407. About the first he gives two reasons, of which the following is the first [278]. Whatever things are common to all natural things pertain especially to the considerations of the natural philosopher; but place is such, for all generally maintain that whatever exists is in some place. They prove it by a sophistic argument consisting of positing the consequent. They argue thus: What does not exist is nowhere, i.e., in no place, for there is no place where the goat-stag or the sphinx exist, which are certain fictions after the manner of chimeras. They argue therefore that if what is found in no place does not exist, then whatever exists is in a place.
But if to be in place belongs to all beings, it seems that place pertains rather to the consideration of metaphysics then that of physics.
And it must be said that Aristotle here argues from the opinion of those who posit that all beings are sensible, on account of their inability to go beyond their imaginations. According to them, natural science is first philosophy, common to all beings, as is mentioned in Metaphysics IV (L.5).
408. Then [279] he gives the second reason: The consideration of motion belongs to the natural philosopher; but the motion which is according to place and is called “change of place” is the most general of all motions. For some things namely, the heavenly bodies, are moved solely according to this motion and nothing is moved with other motions without being moved by this one. Moreover, this motion is more properly so because it alone is truly continuous and perfect, as will be proved in Book VIII. But notion according to place cannot be known without knowing place. The natural philosopher therefore should consider place.
409. Then [280] he arrives at the same conclusion from our viewpoint: Wise men should settle matters about which there is doubt; but there are many doubts about what place is. The cause of these doubts is twofold. One is based on place itself: because not all the properties of place lead to the same opinion about place, but from certain properties of place it seems that place is one thing and from other properties that it is something else. The other cause is based on men, for the ancients neither proposed their doubts about place well nor pursued the truth of the matter well.
410. Then [281] he begins to determine about place.
First in a dialectical manner;
Secondly, by determining the truth, at no. 434.
As to the first he does two things:
First he discusses dialectically whether place exists;
Secondly what it is at no. 422.
About the first he does two things:
First he gives reasons showing that place exists;
Secondly, showing that it does not exist, at no. 415.
As to the first he does two things:
First he shows that place exists, by using reasons based on the truth of things;
Secondly, by reasons based on the opinions of others, at no. 413.
411. In regard to the first, he gives two reasons. In the first of these he proceeds thus: That place is something, is clear from the very transmutation of bodies that are moved according to place. For just as the transmutation which is according to form led men to the knowledge of matter, because there had to be a subject in which the forms could succeed one another, so transmutation according to place led men to a knowledge of place, for there had to be something where bodies could succeed one another. And this is what he adds, namely, that when water goes out from where it now is, i.e., from some vessel, air re-enters. Since, therefore, another body sometimes occupies the same place, it is clear that place is something different from the things that are in place and which are moved according to place. For where air now is there was previously water, and this would not be if place were not something different from both the air and the water. Consequently, place is something: it is a sort of receptacle distinct from any of the things located in it, and it is the term “from which” and “unto which” of local motion.
412. He gives the second reason [282], saying that since the motion of any body whatsoever shows that place exists, as has been said, then the local motion of natural simple bodies, such as fire and earth, and such like heavy and light bodies, not only shows that place is something, but also that place has a certain power and force.
For we observe that each of these bodies is carried to its proper place when it is not prevented, i.e., the heavy are carried down and the light upward. This shows that place has a certain power of pre-serving the thing that is in place. For this reason, an object tends to its own place by a desire of self-preservation. This, however, does not prove that place has the power to attract, except in the sense in which the end is said to attract.
“Up” and “down” and the other directions, namely, “before” and “behind,” “right” and “left,” are the parts and species of place. These directions are determined in the universe according to nature and not merely in relation to ourselves. This is clear from the fact that when we speak of them in relation to ourselves, the same thing is not always “up” or “down,” “right” or “left,” but varies according to our various relations to it. Hence it frequently happens that an immobile object which was “on the right” comes to be “on the left.” The same is true of the other directions, depending on our different relations to them.
But in nature there is a definite “up” and “down” according to the motion of heavy and light bodies, and the other [four] directions are determined by the movements of the heavens, as was said in Book III. It is not just any part of the universe that is “up” and just any part that is “down,” but “up” is always whether light bodies are carried and “down” is whether heavy bodies tend. Now whatever things have according to themselves definite positions must have powers by which they are determined, for in an animal the power of the right is distinct from the power of the left. Accordingly, place exists and has definite powers.
Now, that in certain things the position is assigned only in relation to us is shown in mathematical objects, which, although they are not in place, yet have a position attributed to them solely in relation to ourselves. Hence they have no position according to nature but only according to the intellect, inasmuch as they are understood in some relation to ourselves, either as above or below, or to the right or left.
413. Then [283] he appeals to the opinions of others to show that place exists. First, to the opinion of those who posit a void. For whoever asserts that the void exists must admit that place exists, since the void is nothing more than a place devoid of body. And so from this and from the reasons given above, it is possible to conceive that place is something other than bodies and that all sensible bodies exist in place.
414. Secondly, [284] to confirm the same point he uses the opinion of Hesiod, who was one of the ancient theological poets. It was he who taught that the first thing made was chaos. For he said that the first of all things made was chaos, it being a sort of confusion and a receptacle for bodies; later the extended earth was made to receive various bodies—as if first a receptacle of things had to exist before the things themselves could exist. And he and others posited this because, with many others, they believed that all things that exist are in place. And if this is true, it follows that place not only exists but that it has a remarkable power in that it is the first of all beings. For that can exist without other things but they not without it, seems to be first. But according to them place can exist without bodies—a conjecture they made by observing that place remains even when the things occupying it are destroyed. But things cannot exist without place. It follows, therefore, according to them, that place is the first among all beings.
Six dialectical reasons showing place does not exist
First he gives dialectical reasons showing that place is form or matter;
Secondly, he gives reasons to the contrary, at no. 429.
As to the first he does three things:
First he gives a reason showing that place is form;
Secondly, that place is matter, at no. 425.
Thirdly, from these he draws a corollary, at no. 428.
Prerequisites to determining the truth about place.
First he lays down certain things necessary to the consideration of the truth:
Secondly, he determines the truth, at no. 445.
As to the first he does three things:
First he points out the ways in which one thing is said to be in another;
Secondly, he asks whether anything can be in itself, at no. 437;
Thirdly, he settles some difficulties previously raised, at no. 443.
435. He lists [299] eight ways in which something is said to be in something.
The third way is as “man” is said to be in “animal,” and any species in its genus.
And thus it is evident that all the other ways are derived from the last, which is the most proper.
438. Secondly [302] he answers this;
First he shows how something can be in itself;
Secondly, how it cannot, at no. 439.
439. Then [302] he shows that nothing can be primarily in itself.
Secondly, he proves his proposition, at no. 440.
First he shows that nothing is primarily in itself per se;
Secondly, per accidens, at no. 442.
Finally he concludes that the things said above about place were said as contesting it. Some of these oppositions have now been solved; others will be solved after the nature of place is manifested.
Necessary previous notions for the definition of place.
First he gives some presuppositions to be used in determining about place;
Secondly, he shows what qualities a definition of place should have, at no. 447;
Thirdly, he begins to determine about place, at no. 448.
First, that one show what place is, for a definition is an expression indicating what a thing is.
448. Then [310] he determines about place;
Secondly, at no. 487, he settles the doubts previously mentioned;
Thirdly, he assigns the cause of the natural properties of place, at no. 492.
About the first he does two things:
Secondly, how something exists iu place, at no. 472(L.7).
As to the first he does two things:
First he mentions some facts preliminary to his hunt for the definition;
Secondly, he begins to investigate the definition of place, at no. 455 (L.6).
452. He gives the fourth reason [313]. First, he mentions it; secondly, he proves it, at no. 453.
First, he looks into each part of the definition;
Secondly, he shows that it is a good definition, at no. 471
As to the first he does two things:
First, he searches for the genus of place;
Secondly, for the differentia that will complete the definition, at no.467.
In searching for the genus of place he divides. In connection with this he does three things:
Secondly, he excludes three members of the division, at no. 457;
Thirdly, he concludes to the fourth member, at no. 466.
457. Then [317] he excludes three members of this division.
Secondly, he pursues his intention, at no. 458.
Secondly, that it is not space, at no. 460;
Thirdly, that it is not matter, at no. 464.
460. Then [320] he takes up the question of space.
First he sets down why space seems to be place;
Secondly, he shows that it is not place, at no. 461.
464. Then [323] he continues by considering matter.
First he shows why matter seems to be place;
Secondly, that it is not place, at no. 465.
First, he shows that an error arose from improperly considering this difference;
Secondly, how we must understand the immobility of place, at no. 468.
First he shows how something is absolutely in place and how not;
Secondly, how a thing not absolutely in place. is in place in a certain respect, at 482.
481. For in regard to this he does two things:
First he shows how the outermost sphere is in place;
Secondly, he draws-a conclusion from what has been said, at 485.
About the first he does three things:
First, he shows that the outermost sphere is in place through its parts;
Secondly, how its parts are in place, at no. 481,
Thirdly, how the parts make the whole to be in place, at no. 434.
In this connection note that according to Aristotle “the heavens” are to be taken in two senses here: first, they are taken for the entire universe of bodies and especially of the heavenly; secondly, for the outermost sphere. He says therefore that those things are in place per se which are in motion according to place, whether they are in motion according to their totality or according to their parts, as are the heavens, i.e., the universe; in place per accidens are the soul and the heavens, i.e., the outermost sphere. For it is necessary to say that all the parts of the universe are somehow in place: the outermost sphere per accidens and other bodies per se, inasmuch as they are contained by a body outside of them. And he manifesto this up to the end.
The definition of place is used to solve the original problems;
the properties of place are justified.
492. Then [338] he uses his definition to give a reason for the properties of place.
First, as to the fact that a body is naturally borne to its proper place;
Secondly, as to the fact that a body naturally rests in its own place, at no. 493.
Finally he concludes in summary that it has been stated that place exists and what place is.
The void—reasons for and against
First he manifests his intention:
Secondly, he executes it, at no. 497.
As to the first, he does too things:
First he shows that it is proper for the natural philosopher to deal with the void;
Secondly, he shows what order should be followed in determining the matter of the void, at no. 495.
496. Then [342] he begins to follow this program:
First sets down preliminary notions that are necessary for discovering the truth about the void;
Secondly, he begins to search for the truth, at no. 520 (L.11).
About the first he does two things:
First he gives the reasons of those who posit or deny the existence of the void;
As to the first he does two things:
First he gives the reason of those who deny the existence of the void;
Secondly, the reasons of those who affirm it, at no. 499.
499. Then [343] he sets forth the reasons of those who posited a void.
First, those who spoke of the void naturally;
Secondly, of those who spoke of it non-naturally, at no. 505.
As to the first he does two things:
First he mentions the reason given by those who held that the void is a space separated from bodies;
Secondly, by those who held for a void in bodies, at no. 502.
Concerning the first he does two things:
First he gives the reason of those who posited a void;
Secondly, how Melissus used that reason conversely, at no. 501.
The meaning of “void”—refutation of those positing the void
Concerning this he does three things:
First he shows what is meant by the word “void”;
Secondly, how some thought that the void exists, at no. 513;
Thirdly, he rejects the reasons given by those who posit that a void exists, at no. 515.
As to the first he does two things:
First he reveals his intention;
Secondly, he executes it, at no. 509.
508. Then [350] he shows that it meant by the word “void”.
First he gives the more common meaning;
Secondly, what the Platonists took it to mean at no. 512.
As to the first he does three things:
First he shows what the word “void” means;
Secondly, what should be added to that meaning at no. 510;
Thirdly, he clears up a doubt, at no. 511.
513. Then [354] he tells how some posited existence of a void;
First, what they said the void was;
Secondly, why they posited it, at no. 514.
First therefore he rejects the reasons given by those who posit a separated void;
Secondly, the arguments of those who posit a void existing in bodies, at no. 517.
From motion there is shown to be no separated void
First, he shows that the void does not have a separate existence;
Secondly, that there is no void in bodies at no. 544 (L.14).
Concerning the first he does two things:
First he used motion to show that a separate void does not exist;
Secondly, by considering the void in itself, at no. 541.
As to the first he does two things:
First, from the fact of motion he shows there is no void;
Secondly from the fact of faster and slower motions, at no.527 (L.12).
From the fastness and slowness of motion, a separated void is disproved
About this he does two things:
First he assigns the causes of fastness and slowness in motion;
Secondly, he uses these reasons to argue to his point, at no. 529.
528. Then [367] he argues to his point from the aforesaid causes.
First from the differences of the medium;
Secondly, from the differences in the mobile object, at no. 539,
As to the first he does two things:
Secondly, he recapitulates, at no. 533.
Concerning the first he does two things:
Secondly, he shows that the conclusion follows from the premises, at no. 532.
And so from a consideration of the velocity of motion, it is evident that the void does not exist.
Non-existence of the void from the void itself
From all this it appears that there is no separate void either within or outside the universe.
There is no void within bodies
First he gives the reason proposed by those who posit such a void;
Secondly, he disproves their position, at no. 546;
Thirdly, he dissolves their argument, at no. 551.
546. Then [379] he rejects this position:
First according to one interpretation;
Secondly, according to another interpretation, at no.547.
551. Then [385] be answers a previous argument:
First he repeats it, explaining it more extensively;
Secondly, he solves it, at no. 552.
This then is the argument which prompted some to posit the void.
First, he reveals his proposition;
Secondly, he introduces the conclusion be mainly intends, at no. 557.
As to the first he does three things:
First he explains his proposition by an argument;
Secondly, by examples, at no. 555;
Thirdly, by the effects of rarity and density, at no. 556.
As to the first he does two things:
First he premisses certain things necessary for his proposition;
Secondly, he proves his proposition, at no. 554.
The second is that whatever is in act had to come into being from what was in potency.
Does time exist, and is there the same “now” in the whole of time?
First he tells what his intention is and the order he will follow;
Secondly, he carries out his proposal, at no. 559.
Then [391] he begins the discussion of time:
First by arguing against [existence of time];
Secondly, by presenting the truth, at no. 571 (L.17).
In regard to the first he does two things:
First he inquires whether time exists, arguing against it;
Secondly, what it is, at no. 565 (L.16).
As to the first he does two things:
First he gives two reasons which show that time does not exist;
First, he raises the question;
Secondly, he objects to one side of the question, at no. 562;
Thirdly, he objects to the opposite side, at no. 563.
Dialectical inquiry into what time is, and how related to motion
565. After inquiring whether time exists, the Philosopher now inquires dialectically what it is.
First he disproves the opinions of others;
About the first he does two things:
First he gives various opinions of others about time;
Secondly, he disproves them, at no. 566.
566. Then [398] he disproves their opinions, first of all, the first; then the second, at no. 567.
568. Then [401] he inquires how time is related to motion.
First he shows that time is not motion;
Secondly that time does not exist independently of motion, at no. 570.
In summary he concludes that time is not motion, nor is it without motion.
The definition of time, given and explained
571. After treating of time dialectically, the Philosopher here begins to determine the truth.
First, he determines the truth concerning time;
In regard to the first he does two things:
First he determines concerning time absolutely.
Secondly, in relation to things measured by time, at no. 600 (L.20).
As to the first he does three things:
First he makes clear what time is;
Secondly, what the “now” of time is, at no. 582 (L.18);
About the first he does two things:
First he gives the definition of time;
Secondly, he explains it, at no. 581.
First he shows how “before and after” are found in motion;
Secondly, how they are related to motion, at no. 578;
Thirdly, he shows that time follows motion according to “before and after,” at no. 579.
About the first he does two things:
First he shows that the continuity of time is due to the continuity of motion and magnitude;
Secondly, that the same is true of the “before and after” of time, at no.577.
How the same “now” is or is not in a whole time
582. After explaining what time is, the Philosopher here explains the “now.”
Secondly, after settling this he gives the reason for what is said above the “now,” at no. 588.
As to the first he does three things:
First, he declares that the “now” is somehow always the same and somehow not;
Secondly, he explains this, at no. 584;
Thirdly, he proves it, at no. 585.
588. Then [416] he explains the reason for the things which are said of the “now”:
First, why it is said that nothing of time exists but the “now”;
Secondly, why the “now” is said to separate and continue the parts, of time, at no. 590;
Thirdly, why it is said that the “now” is not a part of time, at no. 592.
First he explains it by considering motion and the mobile;
Secondly, by considering a line and a point, at no. 591.
From the definition of time certain things are clarified
Fourthly, how time to known through motion and vice-versa, at no. 597.
596. Then [422] he shows how time is the same and how not the same.
First, how it is the same or not the same absolutely;
Secondly, how it is the same in a certain respect, at no. 597.
598. Then [424] he shows that just as we know motion from time, so also time from motion.
First, by reason of number and the thing numbered;
Secondly, from the likeness existing between magnitude and motion, at no. 599.
How things are, and are not, in time
First he compares time with things that exist in time;
Secondly, with things that exist in the “now,” at no. 612 (L.21).
Concerning the first he does two things:
First he compares time to motion;
Secondly to other things that are in time, at no. 602.
602. Then [427] he shows how it is related to other things:
First, how other things are in time;
Secondly, what things belong in time, at no. 603.
603. Then [428] he shows to what things it belongs to be in time;
First he shows that not all beings exist in time;
Secondly, that not all non-beings do, at no. 611.
As to the first he does two things:
First he shows that things which are always do not exist in time;
Secondly, that nevertheless things that are at rest are, as such, in time, at no. 606.
As to the first he does two things:
First he mentions the facts from which he proceeds to the manifestation of his proposition;
Secondly, he concludes to the proposition, at no. 605.
The meaning of “now” and related terms
First he explains the meaning of “now”;
Secondly, the meaning of certain other words that are determined by the “now, “ at no. 615.
As to the first be does two things:
First be gives the proper and principal meaning of “now”;
Secondly, be gives a secondary meaning, at no. 614.
Secondly, he raises a difficulty, at no. 616.
How Corruption is attributed to Time—All Motion and Change are in Time.
First, how corruption is attributed to time;
Secondly, how every motion and change exist in time, at no. 623.
Concerning the first he does two things:
First he makes his proposition clear by an argument;
Secondly, by a sign, at no. 622.
The Problems are Solved as to the Existence and Unity of Time.
625. After determining the truth about time, the Philosopher now settles certain doubts about time:
First in regard to the existence of time;
Secondly, in regard to the unity of time, at no. 630.
As to the first he does two things:
Secondly, he solves them, at no. 626.
626. Then [452] he answers these questions:
First he answers the second question, because it is easier;
Secondly, he answers the first one, at no. 627.
627. Then [453] he answers the first question, and as to this he does three things:
Secondly, he gives an objection to the question, at no. 628;
Thirdly, he resolves the question, at no. 629.
The question, therefore, is this: Would time exist if no mind existed?
Secondly, he answers it, at no. 631;
Thirdly, he explains something he took as a presupposition, at no. 637.
First he rejects a false solution;
Secondly, he gives the true one, at no. 634;
In regard to the first he does three things:
First he gives the false answer;
Secondly he disproves it by leading to a discrepancy, at no. 632;
Thirdly, he shows that this discrepancy is really an Impossibility, at no. 633.
634. Then [460] he gives the true solution. Concerning this he does three things:
First he prefaces certain facts required for the solution;
Secondly, from these he arrives at the solution, at no. 635;
Thirdly, he makes the solution clear by appealing to the statements of others, at no. 636.