BOOK VIII
Lecture 1
Opinions on the beginning and end of motion
965. After showing in the preceding book that it is necessary to posit a first mobile, and a first motion, and a first mover, the Philosopher intends in this present book to inquire after a description of the first mover, and first motion, and first mobile, The book is divided into two parts:
In the first he premisses something necessary to the following investigation, namely, that motion is sempiternal;
In the second he proceeds to investigate what is proposed, (L. 5).
About the first he does three things:
First he raises a problem;
Secondly, he states the truth according to his own opinion, (L. 2);
Thirdly, he answers possible objections to the contrary, (L. 4)#
In regard to the first he does three things:
First he proposes his problem;
Secondly, he gives opinions for both sides, at 968;
Thirdly, he shows the usefulness of this consideration, at 970.
About the first he does two things:
First he proposes the problem he intends to investigate;
Secondly, he responds to a tacit question, at 967.
966. In regard to the first it should be known that Averroes says that Aristotle in this book does not intend to inquire whether motion is sempiternal universally, but limits his question to the first motion.
But if one considers both the words and procedure of the Philosopher, this is entirely false. For the words of the Philosopher speak of motion in a universal sense. He says in effect: “Was there ever a becoming of motion before which it had no being and is it perishing again so as to leave nothing in motion?” From this it is clear that he is not inquiring about one definite motion but about motion universally, asking whether at any time there was no motion.
The falseness of Averroes’ statement appears also from the very procedure of Aristotle. First, it is Aristotle’s custom always to argue to his proposition from proper causes. Now, if anyone will consider the arguments he adduces, he will see that in none of them does Aristotle argue from a middle term that refers properly to the first motion, but he argues rather from a middle proper to motion in general. Hence this alone shows that he intends to inquire here about the sempiternity of motion in general.
Secondly, if he had already proved that there is one or a number of sempiternal motions, he would have been foolish to ask below whether anything is eternally in motion, for that question would have been already answered. It also is ridiculous to say that Aristotle would repeat from the start his consideration of a problem he had already settled, and act as though he had omitted something, as the Commentator pretends. For Aristotle had the opportunity to correct his book and fill in at the proper place any section he had omitted, so as not to proceed in a disorderly way. For if this chapter had been treated in the way charged by the Commentator, everything that follows would be confused and disorderly. This is not strange, for, having supposed an initial impossibility, others then follow.
Furthermore, the correctness of our view is shown by the fact that Aristotle later on uses what he proves here, as a principle to prove the eternity of the first motion. He would never have done this, had he already proved that the first motion is eternal.
The reason which moved Averroes is wholly frivolous. For he says that if Aristotle is here intending to inquire into the eternity of motion in common, it will follow that the consideration of Aristotle has been diminished, because it is not evident from what he proves in this place, how motions could be always continued one to the other.
But this has no weight, because it is enough for Aristotle to prove in this chapter in a general way that motion has always been. But how the eternity of motion is continued—whether it is because all things are always in motion, or because all things are sometimes in motion and sometimes at rest, or because some things are always in motion and others sometimes in motion and sometimes at rest—is a question he raises immediately after the present one.
Thus the present chapter must be explained according to this intention, namely, that he intends to inquire about motion in common. According to this, therefore, he asks: “Did motion in common begin to be at some time, so that previously there had never been any motion, and so that at some time it will perish so as to leave nothing in motion, or, on the other hand, did it never begin and will it never cease, so that it always was and always will be?
And he gives an example taken from animals, for some philosophers have said that the world is a certain large animal. For we see animals as alive so long as motion is apparent in them, but when all motion ceases in them they are said to be dead. Accordingly, motion in the whole universe of natural bodies is taken as a kind of life. If, therefore, motion always was and always will be, then this sort of life of natural bodies will be immortal and never-failing.
967. Then at (749) he answers a tacit question. For in the preceding books Aristotle had discussed motion in common, without applying it to things; but now, inquiring whether motion has always existed, he applies his general doctrine about motion to the existence it has in things. Therefore, someone could say that in this consideration the first question should have been about whether motion has existence in things rather than whether it is eternal, especially since there are some who have denied that motion exists.
To this he responds that all who have spoken about the nature of things admit that motion exists. This is evident from their statements that the world was made, and from their consideration of the generation and ceasing-to-be of things, which cannot occur without motion. It is therefore a common supposition in natural science that motion has existence in things. Hence there is no need to raise this question in natural science any more than in other sciences are raised questions about the suppositions of the science.
968. Then at (750) he presents opinions for both sides of the question he proposed.
First he gives the opinions which declare that motion is eternal;
Secondly, those who declare that motion is not eternal, at 969.
In explanation of the first part (750), therefore, it should be known that Democritus supposed that the first principles of things are bodies that are per se indivisible and always mobile and that the world came to be by the chance aggregation of these bodies—not only the world in which we exist but an infinitude of other worlds, since these bodies congregated to form worlds in diverse parts of infinite void. Still he did not posit these worlds as fated to endure forever; rather, some came into existence as a result of atoms combining, and others passed out of existence as a result of the same atoms scattering. Therefore all the philosophers who agree with Democritus assert the eternity of motion, because they say that the generation and ceasing-to-be of certain worlds i’s always going on-and that necessarily involves motion.
969. Then at (751) he gives the opinions of the other side. And he says that whoever declare that there is just one world which is not eternal, also declare what reasonably follows with respect to motion, namely, that it is not eternal.
Therefore, if there be supposed a time in which nothing was in motion, this could happen in two ways, just as it is in two ways that this world could be supposed not always to have been: in one way, that this world began in such a way that previously it never existed at all, as Anaxagoras held; in another way, that the world so began to be that it did not exist for some time previously, but that it again had existed before that time, as Empedocles held.
In like manner with respect to motion, Anaxagoras said that at one time all things were a mixture of one thing with another and nothing was segregated from anything else—in which mixture it was necessary to posit that all things were at rest, for motion does not occur without separation, since whatever is in motion separates from one terminus in order to tend to another. Therefore Anaxagoras posited the pre-existence of this mixture and rest in infinite time, in such a way that at no time before (the present world) had there been any motion at all, and that it was Mind, which alone was unmixed, that caused motion in the first instance and began to separate things one from another.
Empedocles, on the other hand, said that in one period of time some things are in motion, and again in another period all things are at rest. For he posited Friendship and Discord as the first movers of things: Friendship’s property was to make a unity of all things, and Discord’s to make many things from the one. But because the existence of a mixed body requires a mingling of the elements so as to form one thing, whereas the existence of a world required that the elements be dispersed in orderly fashion, each to its respective place, he posited that Friendship is the cause of the coming-to-be of mixed bodies, and Discord the cause of their ceasing-to-be; but that, contrariwise, in the whole world Friendship was the cause of its ceasing-to-be and Discord the cause of its coming-to-be.
Accordingly, he posited that the whole world is being moved, when either Friendship makes one from the many or when Discord makes many of the one; but during the intermediate times, he supposed there was rest—not in the sense that there was no motion at all, but none with respect to the general change of the world.
Because Aristotle had mentioned the opinion of Empedocles, he also gave the very words, which are difficult to interpret because they are in metre.
Thus, therefore, did Empedocles express his opinion in this arrangement of words: “It has learned to be born,” i.e., it is customary for something to be generated, “the one from the manifold”; “and again,” i.e., in another way, “from the one commingled,” i.e., composed of a mixture, “the manifold arises,” i.e., the many come to be through separation—for some things are generated by combining with others, and others by separating.
And according to what we observe in regard to particular instances of coming-to-be, so “thus do things come to be,” i.e., the same must be understood in the universal coming-t-o-be of things with respect to the whole world. “Nor is their era one,” i.e., there is not just one period of duration of things; but at one time a world is generated, at another it is destroyed, and in between there is rest: for “era” is taken to mean the measure of the duration of a thing..
He expresses the distinction of these eras when he adds, “Thus are they changed,” i.e., as though stating that the time in which things pass through the cycle of combining or separating is called one era. And lest anyone suppose that the generation of a world does not require an era, i.e., a period of time, but that the universe comes to be in an instant, Empedocles adds, “nor are they made perfect all at once,” but after a long interval of time.
Then speaking of the other era he adds, “thus are they always immobile,” i.e., in the time between the generation and corruption cycle, he supposed that things are at rest.
And lest anyone believe that before there was always change, and that later there will be continual rest, he excludes this by saying “alternately,” i.e., as though saying that this happens in cycles, namely, that things change and then rest, and then change again, and so on ad infinitum.
Then the words of Aristotle are added to explain the foregoing words of Empedocles, especially the expression, “thus they change.” He says therefore that following the words, “thus they change,” must be understood the addition, “from then hence,”, i.e., from a definite beginning up to the present—not in the sense that motion always was, or that after it began it had been interrupted.
970. Then at (752) he shows the usefulness of considering the question he has proposed. And he says that we must consider just what is the truth about this question, for to know the truth about it is most necessary not only for natural science but the science of the first principle as well, since both here and in the Metaphysics he uses the eternity of motion to prove the first principle.
This method of proving the existence of a first principle is most efficacious and irresistible. For if on the supposition that both motion and the world existed forever, it is necessary to posit one first principle, then, if the eternity thereof should be rejected, it is all the more necessary, for it is clear that every new thing requires a principle bringing it into being. Now the only reason why it could seem that no first principle would be necessary, would be if things were ab aeterno. But if the existence of a first principle follows even on that supposition, i.e., that the world existed ab aeterno, it is clear that the existence of a first principle is absolutely necessary.
Arguments for the eternity of motion
In the first he explains his proposition;
In the second he solves objections contrary to his proposition, (L.4).
About the first he does two things:
First he presents arguments to show the eternity of motion;
Secondly, he answers opinions to the contrary, (L. 3).
About the first he does two things:
First he shows that motion always has been;
Secondly, that it always will be, at 895.
About the first he does two things:
First he explains his proposition with an argument from motion;
Secondly, with an argument from time, at 979.
About the first he does three things:
First he premisses something needed for his proposition;
Secondly, he presents a proof that manifests his proposition, at 976;
Thirdly, he shows that his argument proceeds necessarily, 977,
First he premisses something needed for his proof;
Secondly, he presents the proposed proof, at 978.
979. Then at (757) he explains his proposition with an argument from time.
Arguments against Anaxagoras and Empedocles
First he gives an argument against their position;
Secondly, against the argument they presupposed, at 992.
First he suggests that their argument is unsuitable;
Secondly, that it was more unsuitable to Anaxagoras’ position than to that of Empedocles, at 993;
Thirdly, he shows that even according to Empedocles’ opiniont it is unsuitable, at 994.
First he explains the proposition;
Secondly, he rejects a false interpretation, at 995.
Solution of arguments concluding motion was not always
Secondly, he answers them, at 1000.
1000. Then at (770) he answers these arguments in order.
Five ways in which things may be disposed with respect to motion or rest.
The first is divided into three parts:
In the first he gives a division having five members;
In the second he excludes three members of this division, at 1006;
1006. Then at (774) he excludes three members of the division.
First he posits that not all things are always at rest;
Secondly, that not all things are always in motion, at 1007;
1008. Thirdly, at (777) he forms the arguments against this position.
First with respect to the motion of growth;
Secondly, with respect to the motion of alteration, at 1009;
Thirdly, with respect to local motion, at 1012.
A third member of the division is rejected
1016. Then at (785) he studies the other two members of his division.
First he reveals his intention;
Secondly, he pursues it, (L. 7).
About the first he does three things:
First he shows to which opinion the fourth member pertains;
Secondly, he summarizes what has been said in this chaptert at 1017;
Thirdly, he states what remains to be said, at 1020.
1017. Then at (786) he sums up what has been said in this chapter.
First he recalls the divisions previously made;
Secondly, he recalls the rejection of the first member which posited all things at rest, at 1018;
Thirdly, the rejection of the other two members, at 1019.
Universally, whatever is moved is moved by another
In the first he shows that the first mover is immobile;
In the second that the first mobile is always being moved, (L. 13).
The first part is divided into two sections:
In the first he shows the immobility of the first mover from the order of movers and mobiles;
In the second, from the eternity of motion, (L. 13).
The first is divided into two parts:
In the first he shows that the first mover is immobile;
In the second that the first mover is eternal, (L. 12).
About the first he does two things:
Secondly, he shows the proposition, (L. 9).
In the first he gives a division of movers and mobiles;
In the second he explains his proposition in individual cases, at 1024.
About the first he does two things:
First he divides movers and mobiles;
Secondly, he explains the division, at 1023.
1024. Then at (792) he proves that everything that is moved is moved by another.
First he manifests it in cases that are evident;
Secondly, in cases about which there is doubt, at 1025.
Secondly, he shows that they do not move themselves, at 1026;
Thirdly, he shows by what they are moved, (L. 8).
What moves the heavy and light. Everything moved, moved by another.
First he shows by what they are moved;
Secondly, he concludes to his main intention, at 1036.
About the first he does two things:
First he shows that they are naturally moved by something;
Secondly, he investigates by what they are moved, at 1030.
First he distinguishes potency;
Secondly, from this he shows by what such things are moved, at 1035.
About the first he does three things:
First he shows that it is necessary to know the ways in which something is said to be in potency;
Secondly, he explains this at 1031;
Thirdly, with this he solves a question, at 1033.
1031. Then at (800) he distinguishes “being in potency”:
Secondly, in quality, at 1032;
Thirdly, in local motion, at 1033.
No process to infinity in movers. Not every mover need be moved.
In the first he shows that it is necessary to reach a first that is either immobile or moves itself;
About the first he does two things:
First he shows that it is not possible that things be moved by another ad infinitum;
Secondly, he shows that not every mover need be moved, at 1042.
About the first he does two things:
First he explains the proposition by ascending in the order of mobiles and movers;
Secondly, by descending, at 1041.
About the first he does two things:
First he premisses things needed for manifesting his proposition;
Secondly, he gives an argument that shows the proposition, 1040.
First he proves that not every mover is being moved;
Secondly, from this and from the previous arguments he concludes to his main proposition, at 1049.
Secondly, he rejects one member$ at 1043;
Thirdly, he rejects another, at 1046.
In that which moves itself, one part moves and the other is moved.
In the second how these parts are mutually related, (L. 11);
In the third that it is necessary to come to a first which is immobile, (end of L, 11).
About the first he does two things:
About the first he does three things:
First he proposes that what moves itself does not totally move itself as a whole;
Secondly, he proves the proposition, at 1052;
Thirdly, he concludes to the main conclusion intended—end of 1053.
Secondly, that with respect to a thing which moves itselfg one part does not move itself, at 1059.
About the first he does two things:
First he proposes what he intends;
Secondly, he proves his proposition, at 1055..
First he proposes what he intends;
Secondly, he proves his proposition, at 1060.
How the parts of something moving itself are related.
First he proposes what he intends;
Secondly, he shows his proposition, at 1063;
Thirdly, he reaches the conclusion chiefly intended by all the foregoing, at 1068.
1063. How this happens he shows at (832). About this he does two things:
First he explains his proposition;
Secondly, he solves a doubt, at 1066.
About the first he does two things:
First he shows how the parts of a thing that moves itself are related;
Secondly, how with respect to them a whole is said to move itself,1065.
About the first he does two things:
Secondly, how these two parts are joined to one another, at 1064.
1064. Then at (833) he shows how these two parts are mutually related.
1066. Then at (835) he raises a doubt about the foregoing.
Secondly, he solves it, at 1067.
1067. Then at (836) he resolves this doubt.
The first mover is not moved, but is one and perpetual.
First he proposes what he intends;
Secondly, he proves it, at 1072.
About the first he does three things:
First he reviews what has been previously manifested;
Secondly, he omits something that seemed useful for his proposition, at 1070;
Thirdly, he explains his proposition, at 1071,
First he proves this through self-movers that at one time exist and at another time do not;
Secondly, through moving principles which sometimes are causing motion and sometimes not, (L. 13).
About the first he does three things:
First he shows that there must be a first mover that is eternal;
Secondly, that such a mover should be one rather than many, at 1075;
Thirdly, he shows both at once, i.e., that there is one first mover and that it is eternal, at 1076.
About the first he does two things:
First he rejects an argument by which some could try to prove this proposition;
Secondly, he goes on to explain his proposition, at 1074.
The first mover perpetual and wholly unmoved, as shown from moving principles
First he reviews things said from the beginning of this treatise;
Secondly, from these he forms an argument for his proposition, at 1081;
Thirdly, he finishes the solution of a doubt mentioned above, at 1085.
1081. Then at (848) from the foregoing he proves his proposition.
First that the first mover is immobile;
Secondly, that the first motion is perpetual, at 1083.
About the first he does two things:
First he proves the proposition;
Secondly, he dismisses an objection, at 1082.
Many reasons why local motion is the first motion
In the first he shows which is the first motion;
In the second, what kind of being the first mover is, (L. 21).
About the first he does two things:
First he states his intention;
Secondly, he carries out his proposal, at l087.
1087. Then at (854) he proves the proposition.
Secondly, by referring to the sayings of the ancients, (L. 20).
About the first he does two things:
First he shows that local motion is the first;
Secondly, which local motion, (L. 15).
The first he proves in three ways:
First through the properties of motions;
Secondly, through the difference between rior and subsequent, 1090;
Thirdly, by reason of the order of mobiles, at 1096.
Secondly, as to the second, at 1092;
Thirdly, as to the third, at 1094.
Local motion alone can be continuous and perpetual.
First he shows which motion can be always continuous;
Secondly, he shows that such a motion is the first, (L. 19).
The first part is divided into three sections:
In the first he shows that no motion but local can be continuous;
In the second that no local motion but a circular one can be continuous, (L. 16);
In the third that a circular motion can be continuous, (L. 19).
About the first he does two things;
First he proposes what he intends;
Secondly, he proves his propositiont at 1098.
1098. Then at (864) he proves the proposition. And about this he does two things:
About the first he does two things:
First he proves the proposition;
Secondly, he excludes some objections, at 1100.
About the first he does two things:
First he proves the proposition in motions;
Secondly, in changes, at 1099.
No change of place can be continuous and perpetual except the circular
First he proves his proposition by a demonstration;
Secondly, dialectically, (L. 18).
About the first he does two things:
First he proves his proposition;
Secondly, from the proven truth he solves some doubts, (L. 17).
About the first he does three things:
The second part begins at 1115;
About the first he does two things:
First he sets forth the doubt;
Secondly, he solves it, at 1114.
1115. Then at (876) he presents the second doubt. About this he does three things:
Secondly, he rejects a solution given in Book VI, at 1116;
Thirdly, he gives the true solution, at 1118.
1116. Then at (877) he rejects the solution he had presented above in Book VI.
Secondly, he sets it aside, at 1117.
1119. Then at (880) he resolves the third doubt. About this he does three things:
First he mentions the doubt and its solution;
Secondly, he explains each with an example, at 1120;
Thirdly, he draws a corollary from the foregoing, at 1122.
Dialectical reasons to show reflex motion is not continuous
First he expresses his intention;
Secondly, he proves his proposition, at 1124.
1124. Then at (885) he proves the proposition.
First, for reflex local motion only;
Secondly, in common for all motions, at 1126.
Proper reasons why circular motion can be continuous, and why it is the first
First of all he shows this with proper arguments;
Secondly, with logical and common arguments, (L. 20).
About the first he does two things:
First he shows that a circular motion is continuous;
Secondly, that it is the first, at 1134.
About the first he does two things:
First he gives two arguments to prove that circular motion can be continuous;
Secondly, from the same arguments he concludes that no other motion can be continuous, at 1132.
First he proves the proposition;
Secondly, he draws a corollary from what was said, at 1133.
Dialectical reasons why circular motion is continuous and first.
Confirmation from the ancients
First he mentions his intention;
Secondly, he carries out his proposal, at 1142.
1142. Then at (902) he carries out his proposal:
About the first he does three things:
First he shows that an infinite motion supposes an infinite power;
Secondly, that an infinite power cannot exist in a magnitude, at 1146;
Thirdly, that the first mover must be one which causes a continuous and undying motion, (L. 22).
Secondly, that on the other hand, in an infinite magnitude there cannot be a finite power, at 1156.
Diversity of movers annuls continuity of motion
Secondly, he shows from this that the first mover is necessarily one, (L. 23).
About the first he does three things:
First he raises a doubt about projectiles;
Secondly, he resolves the doubt, at 1162;
Thirdly, from this he shows that the motion of a projectile is not continuous, at 1163.
About the first he does two things:
Secondly, he rejects one solution, at 1161.
1163. Then at (911) he concludes from the foregoing that a motion of projection is not continuous.
The first mover can have no magnitude
First he states his proposition;
Secondly, he raises a doubt and solves it, at 1170.
About the first he does three things:
First he proves the unity of the first mover through the continuity of motion;
Secondly, he shows how a continuous motion comes from one mover, 1166;
Thirdly, where the principle of a continuous motion is, at 1168.
First he shows how from one mover there can be a motion ever continuous;
Secondly, how it is regular, at 1167.
1170. Then at (916) he raises a doubt about the foregoing.